Yes, The Baby Should Live - A Pro-Choice Response To Giubilini and Minerva

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.

com

Response

Yes, the baby should live: a pro-choice response


to Giubilini and Minerva
Bertha Alvarez Manninen

Correspondence to ABSTRACT 1. The moral status of the newborn is equivalent


Dr Bertha Alvarez Manninen, In their paper 'After-birth abortion: why should the baby to that of a fetus; neither can be considered a
School of Humanities, Arts,
and Cultural Studies, Arizona
live?' Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva argue that ‘person’ in a morally relevant sense because
State University, 4701 W because there are no significant differences between a fetus neither possesses an interest in continued
Thunderbird Road, Phoenix, AZ and a neonate, in that neither possess sufficiently robust existence.
85306, USA; bertha. mental traits to qualify as persons, a neonate may be 2. Preventing a newborn from becoming a
manninen@asu.edu justifiably killed for any reason that also justifies abortion. To person—that is, thwarting her potential—
Received 9 March 2012 further emphasise their view that a newly born infant is more does not harm her.1
Revised 29 November 2012 on a par with a fetus rather than a more developed baby, I will argue that their defence of the first premise
Accepted 29 January 2013 Giubilini and Minerva elect to call this 'after-birth abortion' equates two senses of the term ‘interest’ (ie, posses-
rather than infanticide. In this paper, I argue that their thesis sing an interest in something, in this case possessing
is incorrect, and that the moral permissibility of abortion does an interest in continued existence, versus taking an
not entail the moral permissibility of 'after-birth' abortion. interest in something) and therefore fails to show
that neonates, or fetuses, do not possess an interest
in their continued existence The argument they
In their paper ‘After-birth abortion: why should the offer in favour of premise 2 is rather unclear, and
baby live?’ (published in Journal of Medical Ethics, subject to three interpretations that are all problem-
2012), Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva atic. The most charitable interpretation of their
argue that because there are no significant differences argument in favour of the second premise employs
between a fetus and a neonate, in that neither possess a very controversial position about diachronic per-
sufficiently robust mental traits to qualify as persons, sonal identity (ie, the persistence conditions of
a neonate may be justifiably killed for any reason that persons over time) that they make no attempt to
also justifies abortion. In particular, Giubilini and defend. After detailing how their arguments falter,
Minerva are concerned with cases where fetal defects I will offer an alternative interpretation of abortion
are not known until after birth, or if an unfortunate rights that does not entail the permissibility of
event happens during labour and delivery that renders ‘after-birth abortion’ or infanticide.
the fetus impaired (eg, if the fetus suffered from peri-
natal asphyxia). However, they also argue that even THE MORAL ARGUMENT
social reasons—for example, job loss or a change in According to Giubilini and Minerva, a person is
the status of a couple’s relationship—would justify
killing a neonate because such reasons are sufficient an individual who is capable of attributing to her own
existence some (at least) basic value such that being
for justifying abortion. To further emphasise their
deprived of this existence represents a loss to her… all
view that a newly born infant is more on a par with a individuals who are not in the condition of attributing
fetus rather than a more developed baby, Giubilini any value to their own existence are not persons.1
and Minerva elect to call this ‘after-birth abortion’
rather than infanticide. This definition of personhood, and using this
Giubilini and Minerva’s article1 has garnered much definition to argue that only those who meet
attention, and has been, unsurprisingly, criticised by these criteria possess a right to life, is not a new
members of the pro-life community.2 I am not pro-life one among philosophers and ethicists.i To be
—I do believe that women have a right to obtain an clear, according to Giubilini and Minerva, it is
abortion because I believe that every person has a right
to decide if they wish to use their body to sustain the
i
life of another. Nevertheless, I find Giubilini and See, for example, Warren,3 Singer4 and Tooley.5 Also see
Minerva’s thesis deeply troubling. Having an immedi- Chappel.6 Here Chappel argues against what he calls
‘criterialism,’ the view that possession of certain properties
ate visceral reaction against a position, however, is not (eg, sentience or rationality) is necessary and sufficient for
sufficient for concluding that there is something wrong personhood. Rather, he argues, we antecedently grant
with that position. (I am sure that 50 years ago many personhood to a being and then deduce from this that she is
people had a strong visceral reaction against miscegen- likely to be the kind of creature who displays sentience,
ation, but this does not entail that miscegenation is rationality, self-consciousness and so on. Moreover, Chappell
argues that treating certain beings, for example infants, as
wrong.) Therefore, it is necessary to carefully explore persons is a necessary prerequisite for them developing the
Giubilini and Minerva’s arguments in favour of this capacities of persons: ‘By years of treating her children as
very contentious conclusion. This is the aim of this creatures who “have the person properties”—in the sense
paper, and I submit that they have not successfully that interest the criterialist—she makes it true that they are
creatures who have the personal properties in just that sense
To cite: Manninen BA. argued that after-birth abortion is permissible. (p. 9). Giubilini and Minerva fail to really engage the vast
J Med Ethics The success of Giubilini and Minerva’s argument amounts of philosophical literature that exists about the issue
2013;39:330–335. rests on two premises: of personhood, much to the detriment of their thesis.

330 Manninen BA. J Med Ethics 2013;39:330–335. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-100656


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.com

Response

not necessary for an individual to actually take an interest in simply does not possess an interest in continued existence at
her welfare in order to have one. As they note, if I abscond all. Painlessly euthanising the dog for such trivial reasons
with a person’s winning lottery ticket, one she has no idea would be no different from depriving any other organic
she even possessed, I have harmed her even if she never dis- material of its life—this action would be on a par with
covers the crime. This is because, although she never happens pulling out weeds. Another example comes from bioethicist
to take an interest in her winnings because of her ignorance, Bonnie Steinbock: a dog cannot take an interest in being vac-
she is nevertheless capable of appreciating that she has been cinated, since it does not possess robust enough mental traits
harmed if she were to discover my theft. As Giubilini and to understand the concept of health and therefore is not ‘in
Minerva put it, such a person is ‘in the condition to value the the condition of attributing any value’1 to its health.
different situation she would have found herself in if she had Nevertheless, it seems absurd to deny that the dog possesses
not been harmed.’1 It is the capacity to take an interest in X, an interest in adequate medical care regardless of its inability
according to Giubilini and Minerva, that is necessary in order to appreciate it. Steinbock7 writes:
to maintain that one has been harmed by being deprived of X
and, consequently, if one can be said to have a right to It is in the owner’s interest to have his animal vaccinated, since
X. Specifically, in order for a person to have a right to life, it owners usually want healthy animals. But it is also in the dog’s
own interest, since a dog that gets distemper will experience con-
is necessary that the loss of her life constitute a harm for her,
siderable discomfort and probably die. We might reasonably
and the only way that the loss of life can constitute a harm approach an owner who neglected to have his dog vaccinated by
for an individual is if she is able to value and take an interest saying: “It isn’t fair to the dog. Even if you don’t care if the dog
in her life. For the sake of argument, I will grant that an indi- dies, you should vaccinate him for his own sake. ( p18)
vidual can only have a right to X if the deprivation of X con-
stitutes a loss for her. (Although this, too, is a controversial Consider yet another example. Let’s say a 6-month-old infant
contention. If I own a fleet of 1000 cars, it may not harm me has contracted an illness that would painlessly kill him unless he
if a single one is stolen (I may not even notice my loss), but I is medicated. The baby is certainly not ‘in the condition to
nevertheless have a right to that car because it is my prop- value the different situation (he) would (find himself ) in had
erty.) The problem comes with Giubilini and Minerva’s con- (he) not been harmed.’ A 6-month-old, though more mentally
tention that it is necessary that one be capable of valuing X capable than a newborn in several respects, is still not so men-
in order to be harmed by its deprivation, or, specifically for tally capable that he is self-conscious, values his life, and is dis-
our purposes, that an individual must be capable of attribut- tressed at the thought of his death. Indeed, I am not even sure
ing value to her own existence in order for her to actually whether my 3-year-old daughter meets these criteria.
possess an interest in continued existence. Nevertheless, I suspect many would agree that the 6-month-old
It is vital to emphasise that, according to Giubilini and has an interest in the medication, that it would benefit him
Minerva’s argument, an individual cannot really appreciate because it extends his life, even if he is incapable of appreciating
that she is a victim of harm without possessing some rather it. Moreover, many would certainly agree that it is the infant
robust mental traits: she must be capable of seeing herself as himself that has this interest, not just his parents or the people
a subject of benefit and harm (ie, a certain amount of self- who love him; the baby would retain that interest even if he
consciousness is in order) and she must be able to reason that were an unwanted orphan. Indeed, if Giubilini and Minerva are
certain things harm or benefit her. When discussing the right correct, a severely mentally handicapped individual (who never
to life in particular, Giubilini and Minerva’s argument entails develops any robust form of self-consciousness, and therefore is
that only rational, self-conscious beings can possess a right to unable to see himself as a subject of harm or benefit) would
life, since it is only these kinds of beings who can perceive have no interests at all outside of not being subjected to pain
themselves as entities who exist over time and who can appre- (given his sentience). He would certainly lack a right to life on
ciate that their death would constitute a loss of value for the same grounds as fetuses and neonates do, and would prob-
them. This entails that most non-human animals cannot be ably lack a right to medical treatment, for the same reason the
harmed by being killed (if it is done so painlessly, given their 6-month-old does. Suppose the subject here was an autistic
sentience). More generally, their argument entails that one child who, at the age of 5, is utterly incapable of appreciating
cannot actually have an interest in X unless one is capable of the impact certain forms of education could have on her ability
consciously taking an interest in X—that, in order to have a to become a more verbal, rational, and self-sufficient human
welfare, or things that are in one’s own good, it is necessary being. According to Giubilini and Minerva’s above-mentioned
to possess the capacity to take an interest in one’s welfare and criteria for moral rights, such a child would have no interest at
one’s own good. all in acquiring this education, and therefore would not be
In order to begin to see why Giubilini and Minerva’s con- harmed by not obtaining it, because this child is also not in a
tention is problematic, let’s take a look at the following exam- position to attribute any value to her education. But certainly
ples where it seems acceptable to hold that a being has been this is wrong. If the autistic child could become a more product-
harmed by a deprivation of X even though she is utterly ive member of society, and even attain more robust forms of
incapable of appreciating X. Suppose a dog owner requests self-consciousness and reasoning abilities as a result of this edu-
that his dog be painlessly euthanised for no other reason cation, then it is undoubtedly in the child’s best interest to
other than he is only allowed to have one pet and his dog has receive that education, regardless of whether she is capable of
passed the point of puppy-cuteness. Since the dog cannot per- taking an interest in it.
ceive of itself as a continuing entity existing over time (the Therefore, there is clearly a marked distinction between pos-
dog is not self-conscious), it does not have the capacity to sessing the capacity to take an interest in X and actually having
value its life, or contemplate a possible world in which he is an interest in X. Steinbock,7 acknowledging this distinction,
not living and be distressed by that idea. Because the dog denotes two senses of the word ‘interest’: interest1 denotes
cannot take a conscious interest in its continued existence, things that are in a being’s interest, whereas interest2 denotes
Giubilini and Minerva are committed to saying that the dog things an individual can take an interest in (p16). Having

Manninen BA. J Med Ethics 2013;39:330–335. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-100656 331


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.com

Response

interests in the first sense of the term is certainly sufficient for there is a significant difference between a later-term fetus and
being a subject of harm if such interests are violated. In this an embryo/early-term fetus. Therefore, from this perspective,
sense, the autistic child lacks an interest2 in being educated, but abortion is permissible in the earlier stages of pregnancy but not
certainly possesses an interest1 in it because she stands to benefit later ones. A person who holds this position would deny that it
from that education. Consequently, she would be a victim of is permissible to kill a later-term fetus because it is impermissible
harm by being deprived of her education. Similarly, the dog and to kill an infant, given that there is no substantial difference
the 6-month-old baby lack an interest2 in receiving medical care between the two. Such a person would, of course, disagree with
but both have an interest1 in it, and therefore being deprived of Giubilini and Minerva’s conclusion that neonates and later-term
medical care would harm them both. Possessing interests1 is suf- fetuses are not harmed by their death. But Giubilini and
ficient to render an individual a possible subject of harm if those Minerva take for granted that acknowledging there is no signifi-
interests are violated. cant difference between a later-term fetus and a neonate logic-
All these examples illustrate that a being can benefit from X ally leads one to the conclusion that ‘after-birth abortion’ is
even if he is utterly incapable of taking an interest in X. One permissible, rather than to the conclusion that later-term abor-
need not be capable of appreciating that one has been harmed tions are impermissible (or all abortions for that matter, if one
in order to actually be harmed. Indeed, if one takes a closer also believes that embryos and early-term fetuses are not signifi-
look at Giubilini and Minerva’s wording, one can see that this is cantly different from neonates).
tacitly acknowledged by even them. When discussing the case of Second, if neonates aren’t persons in the sense that they
the ignorant lottery winner who has nevertheless been harmed possess limited moral status and no right to life, then what are
by having her ticket stolen, they maintain that the reason she is they; what is their moral standing? If they can be killed as wan-
still a victim is because she ‘is in the condition to value the dif- tonly as Giubilini and Minerva suggest, this seems to relegate
ferent situation she would have found herself in if she had not them to the status of mere property. If the only interest new-
been harmed.’1 The implication here is that the harm done unto borns have, given their sentience, is the interest in not being
her is antecedent to her being aware of it; if it were otherwise, subjected to physical pain, then it is permissible to do almost
what would she be aware of? If a person can reflect on a coun- anything at all to them so long as it is done painlessly. This
terfactual state of affairs, and can appreciate that a deprivation means that parents can kill them, or deprive them of medica-
of X constitutes a loss for her, it is not that awareness (or even tion, love and attention, as long as they are not causing any
the capacity to have that awareness) that constitutes the loss; pain. And, given the robustness of the mental traits necessary
rather, the loss, the harm, must exist prior to her being aware in order to be worthy of moral rights according to Giubilini
(or even having the capacity to be aware) of it. The capacity for and Minerva, this status lasts beyond the first few weeks of life
being aware of the harm is necessary in order for her to subject- —quite possibly into the toddler years. Although they claim
ively suffer, but that is quite distinct from saying that no harm that their argument is only supposed to cover the first few days
at all exists by being deprived of X unless one is capable of sub- of the infant’s life, this is simply a refusal to acknowledge the
jectively suffering from the loss of X. If the loss of X didn’t logical implications of their view. The mental traits they claim
already constitute a harm, there would be nothing there to serve are necessary in order to possess a right to life do not yet exist
as the cause for the individual’s suffering once she is capable of in children until the later toddler stages. As philosopher
understanding her loss. Timothy Chappell6 writes: ‘If rationality is a necessary condi-
What follows from this, then, is that one can still be tion for counting as a person, that is, a member of the primary
harmed by being deprived of X even if one is utterly incap- moral constituency, then all children under a certain age will
able of appreciating that loss. An individual is harmed by an fail to count as persons.’ (p3). The implications of Giubilini
action if that action constitutes an attack on her welfare; and Minerva’s arguments are more far-reaching than they
that attack can occur regardless of whether the individual admit.
possesses the capacity to appreciate that her welfare has been
compromised. Consequently, Giubilini and Minerva’s reasons
for not attributing an interest in continued existence to THE METAPHYSICAL ARGUMENT
fetuses and neonates are simply unsuccessful. The most they In responding to the objection that fetuses and neonates are
have shown is that fetuses and neonates are utterly incapable harmed by not being allowed to realise their potential person-
of taking an interest in their continued existence. But this is hood, Giubilini and Minerva1 write:
trivially true, and it has no bearing whatsoever on whether If a potential person, like a fetus and a newborn, does not
they actually have an interest in continued existence. That is, become an actual person, like you and us, then there is neither
all Giubilini and Minerva have shown is that fetuses and an actual nor a future person who can be harmed, which means
neonates lack an interest2 in continued existence. But this that there is no harm at all. So, if you ask one of us if we would
has no bearing on whether they have an interest1 in contin- have been harmed, had our parents decided to kill us when we
ued existence, and it is this interest that matters when deter- were fetuses or newborns, our answer is ‘no’, because they would
mining whether someone has been wronged by being have harmed someone who does not exist (the ‘us’ whom you
are asking the question), which means no one. And if no one is
deprived of continued existence. In order for their argument
harmed, then no harm occurred.
to be successful, Giubilini and Minerva would have to show
that Steinbock is incorrect to draw a distinction between This is a convoluted passage, and it can have at least three
interests1 and interests2, or that interests1 cannot exist possible interpretations (that I can see). The first one is that
without interests2. They have not shown that either is the killing a non-person is acceptable because only persons can be
case. harmed by being killed, since only persons can take, and there-
I want to now call attention to two important points that fore possess, an interest in continued existence. Above, I have
Giubilini and Minerva fail to address. First, it is possible to shown that this claim is not just contentious (and probably false)
agree with their point that there is no intrinsic difference but also not well supported by their argument. A second inter-
between a later-term fetus and a neonate, but still contend that pretation is that we could not claim that we were harmed if we

332 Manninen BA. J Med Ethics 2013;39:330–335. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-100656


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.com

Response

had been killed as neonates; in such a case we would not have to this account of diachronic personal identity argue that
existed to be able to make the complaint at all. But this is tanta- persons are persons essentially—that is, that persons only
mount to arguing that killing has no victim because it gets rid of exist as long as they are persons and therefore have no iden-
the victim, and this is obviously absurd. tity connection to any part of their lives when they existed as
A third, and most charitable, interpretation is to construe non-persons (in purely metaphysical terms, according to this
Giubilini and Minerva as making a metaphysical claim about the account, personhood is a substance sortal that picks out a
nature of diachronic personal identity: killing the fetus or certain ontological kind of being). This means that I would
neonate would not have harmed you because you didn’t exist as cease to exist upon becoming a non-person, which need not
a fetus or neonate; killing such beings would have prevented happen at physical death or even at conscious death; if I were
your existence, but it would not have killed you because you to become severely demented, say at the advanced stages of
had not yet come into existence. Evidence of this interpretation Alzheimer’s disease, I would cease to exist altogether because
can be found when they write that one reason it is permissible I would not (at that point) be a self-conscious, rational indi-
to kill a neonate is because ‘merely potential people cannot be vidual with a continuous stream of memories. Similarly, I
harmed by not being brought into existence’. In other words, never existed as a fetus or even a baby, since neither are
you, as a person would not have been harmed had you been persons yet. Because one must possess rather robust traits of
killed as a neonate because you did not yet exist. If this is, character to be a person in this sense of the term, I didn’t
indeed, the argument they mean to give, Giubilini and Minerva come into existence until sometime during the toddler years,
appeal to a position known as the Psychological Account of and neither did you. Philosopher Mary Ann Warren, who also
Personal Identity.8 subscribes to this view of personal identity, puts it this way:
Questions such as when did you begin to exist, when do you
die, and under what conditions does your self persist over time [W]e are essentially people if we are essentially anything at all.
constitute the main issues when discussing diachronic personal Therefore, if fetuses and gametes are not people, then we were
identity. In an earlier essay, I argued that philosophers and never fetuses and gametes, though one might say that we
emerged from them. The fetus which later became you was not
bioethicists often, sometimes unwittingly, assume certain posi-
you because you did not exist at that time…[s]o if it had been
tions on the issue of personal identity in many of their ethical
aborted nothing whatever would have been done to you, since
arguments.9 I further argued that addressing the plausibility of you would have never existed.15
those underlying metaphysical assumptions is a necessary pre-
requisite for assessing the success of the ethical arguments that Because Giubilini and Minerva share the language that
are built upon them. For example, in his famous article ‘Why Warren uses, it seems reasonable to hold that they also share her
abortion is immoral,’10 Don Marquis argues that abortion is assumptions in this regard.
wrong for the very same reason that killing most any other Yet this position is loaded with complications. It difficult to
human being is wrong: abortion deprives the fetus of its valuable believe I was never a baby—that the pictures of the 6-month-old
future. Among other things, a vital component of the success of that I have always thought were me was not really me. It is also
Marquis’ argument is that the embryo or the fetus is the same hard to believe that I would cease to exist in an advanced stage of
individual over time, for depriving it of a future cannot constitute Alzheimer’s disease or any other progressive dementia; indeed,
a loss for a particular embryo or fetus unless that future rightfully the fact that many people take great pains to ensure that they will
belongs to it—if it is the same being now that it would be in the be well taken care of in such a state illustrates a strong identifica-
future. This is necessary so that we can properly attribute all of tion with this stage of existence. Of course, just because people
those future valuable experiences to the embryo or fetus while in feel that they were identical with a neonate or will be identical
utero. Because Marquis argues that abortion does constitute such with a demented individual is not in itself sufficient to conclude
a loss for even an early-stage embryo, and because the only thing that they are, in fact, identical with that neonate or demented
a future person can have in common with a past embryo is that individual. However, because this is such a deeply pervasive view
both are the same human organism, Marquis tacitly assumes in of identity, and one that most people are going to be unwilling to
his argument that the persistence conditions of humans over time surrender, the burden of proof lies with Giubilini and Minerva to
lies in enduring as the same human organism (and, indeed, I have present a very convincing argument in favour of such a view (if,
heard him confirm that this is his view). This position has been indeed, this is what they mean to argue). Most people will hold
dubbed ‘Animalism’ by Eric Olson11 12 and the ‘Biological View’ that had they’d been killed as a baby, they would have been
by David DeGrazia.13 harmed because you were, in fact, killing them at an earlier stage
Giubilini and Minerva seem to be invoking the of their existence.
Psychological Account of Personal Identity, which maintains I have illustrated some philosophical problems in Giubilini
that there is a distinction between ‘human’ and ‘person,’ in and Minerva’s argument that, I believe, cast doubt as to
that the former is a biological denotation (Homo sapiens) whether it is necessary to have the robust mental traits of a
while the latter describes, as John Locke puts it, ‘a thinking, person in order to possess a right to life. But there are also
intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can con- puzzling, and troubling, practical consequences to their pos-
sider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different ition. The mental traits they argue is a prerequisite to posses-
times, and places; which it does only by that consciousness sing a right to life do not appear overnight, and they are not
which is inseparable from thinking, and, as it seems to me, lost instantaneously either. Is the right to life a gradient right?
essential to it’14 (Giubilini and Minerva affirm this distinction Does a 1-year-old have just a little bit of that right—less than
in their paper.) Clearly, many biological human beings a 5-year-old, but more than a neonate? If an elderly individ-
(including fetuses, neonates, the severally mentally disabled, ual begins the degeneration into Alzheimer’s disease, does her
and those in persistent vegetative states) are not persons in right to life become gradually weaker? Giubilini and Minerva
this sense of the term. In addition, individuals who subscribe attempt to sidestep these questions by passing the buck to

Manninen BA. J Med Ethics 2013;39:330–335. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-100656 333


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.com

Response

neurologists and psychologists, but it is up to them to clearly advocates have used against abortion rights for decades. Finally,
denote the logical consequences of their views. Moreover, deriding fetal and infant life does not accord with the phenomen-
such a litmus test for attributing the right to life to individuals ology of many women who have themselves obtained abortions
excludes a huge subset of the human (and non-human) popu- but, nevertheless, regard intrauterine life as worthy of moral
lation: not just embryos, fetuses, and neonates, but certain value and respect.17–19
mentally impaired individuals, individuals in either temporary Instead, I maintain that an appeal to Judith Jarvis
or permanent comas, and elderly individuals in the advanced Thomson’s argument in her ‘A defense of abortion,’ that no
stages of dementia. In other words, Giubilini and Minerva one person’s right to life entails that another person has an
take what makes individuals such as these the most vulnerable obligation to surrender her body to sustain that life, is a
(ie, that they have an underdeveloped capacity for rational much more promising route to take, albeit not one entirely
thought) and use it to argue that they are not worthy of the devoid of difficulties.iii 20 Such a stance does not require one
most basic of all rights. It seems to me that the very contrary to assert that the fetus is not a person or that the fetus is
is the case: their vulnerability in this regard makes them can- devoid of moral rights or moral status; rather, even if we
didates for our care and protection.ii grant the fetus every single right we would grant an extrauter-
ine person, because no extrauterine person possesses the right
to use another person’s body for the sustainment of life, the
A DIFFERENT PRO-CHOICE PERSPECTIVE fetus would not possess this right either. A pregnant woman,
In another essay, I argued that pro-choice advocates should cease
therefore, has a right to decide she does not want to use her
building their arguments in favour of abortion rights upon the
body to sustain the fetus’ life, just like I have a right to
premise that human fetuses are not persons.16 The reasons I
decide whether I want to use my body to save your life via
argue this are fourfold. First, given the vast amounts of ink spilt
the donation of a non-vital organ or bodily fluids. While
on this question, and given the unlikelihood of ever reaching a
Thomson’s argument has been subject to much critical scru-
consensus on the issue of moral (or even metaphysical) person-
tiny,22–24 I do believe that it can ultimately survive that scru-
hood, we will never come close to achieving consensus on the
tiny, although arguing for this is beyond the scope of this
abortion issue by relying on such a deeply controversial premise.
paper. What I want to do, rather, is show how, if Thomson’s
Second, doing so is imprudent. Given the various attempts in the
argument is accepted, this goes a long way to drawing a
USA of late by pro-life advocates to pass a Human Life/
marked distinction between a fetus and a neonate—one that
Personhood Amendment in their respective state (which, many
does not entail the permissibility of ‘after-birth abortion’.
have admitted, is an attempt to directly challenge the validity of
Thomson argues that the right to an abortion is not the right
Roe v Wade), pro-choice advocates need to be armed with argu-
to kill the fetus per se but, rather, that it is the right to withdraw
ments in favour of abortion rights that remain unscathed in the
sustenance from the fetus at the woman’s request. The right to an
event that human fetuses are granted the rights of persons.
abortion, from a Thomsonian standpoint, is an incarnation of the
Third, constantly deriding the lives of human fetuses, and in this
broader right to bodily autonomy—a right that all persons, male
case newborn infants, paints pro-choice advocates as callous and
or female, pregnant or not, possess. Throughout the majority of
heartless extremists, and therefore results in our losing the public
pregnancy, a woman cannot withdraw aid from the fetus without
relations battle—not just with pro-life advocates, but also with
causing its death, but that is not to say that, if the fetus could
abortion moderates and even pro-choice advocates themselves,
survive without her sustenance, she then has an additional right
many of whom hold fetal life in high regard despite their support
to kill it. Thomson writes:
of abortion rights. Given the recent onslaught of new policies
designed to restrict abortion access for women, the voice of the [W]hile I am arguing for the permissibility of abortion in some
pro-choice community cannot afford to be further marginalised cases, I am not arguing for the right to secure the death of the
in public consciousness. Arguing that, essentially, a pro-choice unborn child. It is easy to confuse these two things in that up to
stance leads to the permissibility of infanticide not only obfus- a certain point in the life of the fetus it is not able to survive
cates the intents and goals of the pro-choice movement, but outside the mother’s body; hence removing it from her body
essentially serves to confirm many of the arguments pro-life guarantees its death… But they are importantly different… there
are some people who will feel dissatisfied by this feature of my
argument. A woman may be utterly devastated by the thought of
a child, a bit of herself, put out for adoption and never seen or
Although this may appear to be, at first, incompatible with a pro-choice
ii
heard of again. She may therefore want not merely that the child
perspective (in that it can be argued that this entails that embryos and
be detached from her, but more, that it die. Some opponents of
fetuses should also be entitled to care and protection given their
vulnerability), it need not be. My own particular reason for being abortion are inclined to regard this as beneath contempt—
pro-choice is mentioned below—that is, I am largely convinced by thereby showing insensitivity to what is surely a powerful source
Judith Jarvis Thomson’s argument that no person (whether intrauterine of despair. All the same, I agree that the desire for the child’s
or extrauterine) has a right to use the body of another for sustenance. In death is not one which anybody may gratify, should it turn out to
this sense, embryos and fetuses would be entitled to the same care and be possible to detach the child alive.20
protection as any other person—while the vulnerable need care and
protection, that protection can never extend to the point that the bodily Suppose that you are dying of a blood disorder and need a
autonomy of another may be violated. A sick patient in need of a bone bone marrow transplant to survive. I am not required to donate
marrow transplant, for example, should be cared for and protected as
much as possible, and every avenue available to secure him a bone bone marrow to you, even if my failure to do so results in your
marrow transplant should be pursued. However, it would never be death.25 However, I do not have a right to kill you if it happens
permissible to forcibly extract bone marrow from an unwilling ‘donor’, that you can survive without my bone marrow. Notice, nothing
and our refusal to do so is not typically interpreted as a refusal to care changes about you as a person, or as a bearer of moral status.
for the patient. Similarly, if it were possible to care for an embryo or
fetus without encroaching on another person’s bodily autonomy, then I
would favour pursing that option and, if a fetus survives an abortion,
iii
then I do believe the infant should be given the same level of care and For an analysis of Thomson’s argument, as well as an extensive
protection as any comparable newborn. defence of it, see Boonin.21

334 Manninen BA. J Med Ethics 2013;39:330–335. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-100656


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.com

Response

You do not lose your personhood when you are in need of my Their conclusion was based on rational argumentation, rather
bone marrow, or gain it when you are no longer in need of it. than immediate visceral and violent responses. None of the arti-
Your status as a person does not change in either case, but what cles I have read condemning them have studied their essay in an
is owed to you in order to sustain your life does. attempt to follow their logic and see where they went wrong (as
Giubilini and Minerva are arguably right that there are no sig- I have tried to do in this paper). It is concerning how quick we
nificant cognitive differences between a later-term fetus and a are to protest the idea that the vulnerable may be killed by
newborn. Like most people, I suspect, this inclines me against threatening to kill others.
approving later-term abortions rather than toward approving I believe Giubilini and Minerva’s arguments are flawed, and I
‘after-birth abortion.’ However, even if one accepts the permissi- welcome a dialogue with them and others about my response.
bility of later-term abortion, this still does not entail that they However, I defend their right to write it and the Journal of
must accept the permissibility of ‘after-birth abortion.’ Rather, Medical Ethics’s right to publish it, and I condemn the threats of
one can argue that, while in the womb, the fetus’ interest in violence against them. If we cannot debate each other civilly,
continued existence stands at odds with a person’s bodily auton- with respect, and with the use of reason in lieu of death threats,
omy. Because of the physical, mental and emotional enmesh- then we have to wonder about the kind of world we are building
ment of pregnancy between the woman and the fetus, and for the fetuses and infants whose right to life so many champion.
because even the best pregnancies require a lot from a woman,
Acknowledgements Many thanks to my student, Michael Gooch, who first
and may even pose a threat to her health, the woman’s interest
brought Giubilini and Minerva’s article to my attention, and to my husband
in her bodily autonomy supersedes the fetus’ interest in contin- Dr Tuomas Manninen for his comments and editing skills. Many thanks, also, to the
ued existence. However, once the fetus is born, its interest in reviewers and editors of the Journal of Medical Ethics for their very helpful
continued existence is no longer at odds with anyone’s right to comments, and for encouraging civil and respectful debate and dialogue.
bodily autonomy, in which case the neonate’s interest in contin- Competing interests None.
ued existence should prevail. That is, the fetus/neonates’ loca- Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
tion does nothing to change its nature, but it can indeed have
an impact on how to cash out what is owed to it and, therefore,
location does matter in certain respects. Persons may have fewer
REFERENCES
rights in prison than they would in the outside world, even 1 Giubilini A, Minerva F. After-birth abortion: why should the baby live? J Med Ethics
though their moral status does not change. Children may have 2013;39:261–3.
fewer rights while living in their parents’ house than they would 2 Teahan M. Ethicists call for killing of newborns to be made legal. Catholic Herald,
if they lived in their own home, but they still remain persons. 29 Feb 2012. http://www.catholicherald.co.uk/news/2012/02/29/
ethicists-call-for-killing-of-newborns-to-be-made-legal/ (accessed 4 Mar 2012).
Similarly, the fact that the fetus is situated in the body of
3 Warren MA. On the moral and legal status of abortion. The Monist 1973;57:43–61.
another person means that respecting its interest in continued 4 Singer P. Practical ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
existence entails infringing upon the rights of another (if the 5 Tooley M. Abortion and infanticide. Philos Public Aff 1972;2:37–65.
woman does not want the fetus in her body). No such infringe- 6 Chappell T. On the very idea of criteria for personhood. South J Philos 2011;49:1–27.
ment exists once the fetus emerges from the womb. If the right 7 Steinbock B. Life before birth: the moral status of embryos and fetuses. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1992.
to an abortion is regarded thusly, then this provides a reason for 8 McMahan J. The ethics of killing: problems at the margins of life. Oxford: Oxford
concluding that, while the fetus may die as an inevitable conse- University Press, 2002:39–66.
quence of a woman’s decision to retract continued sustenance, 9 Manninen BA. The metaphysical foundations of reproductive ethics. J Appl Philos
the infant may not be killed because its existence infringes on 2009;26:190–204.
10 Marquis D. Why abortion is immoral. J Philos 1989;86:183–202.
no one’s bodily rights.
11 Olson E. Was I ever a fetus? Philos Phenomenological Res 1997;57:95–110.
Giubilini and Minerva have not provided any sufficient 12 Olson E. The human animal: personal identity without psychology. New York:
reasons for concluding that ‘after-birth abortion’ is permissible. Oxford University Press, 1997.
Given that the prospect of approved infanticide is profoundly at 13 DeGrazia D. Human identity and bioethics. New York: Cambridge University Press,
odds with our deeply entrenched moral intuitions, the burden is 2005.
14 Locke J. An essay concerning human understanding. Amherst, NY: Prometheus
on them to present an extremely convincing argument. Until they Books,1690, Book II, chapter 27.
do so, we can conclude that yes, indeed, the baby should live. 15 Warren MA. Do potential persons have rights? In: Partridge E, ed. Responsibilities
to future persons. Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1981:264.
A POSTSCRIPT ON CIVILITY 16 Manninen BA. Rethinking Roe v. Wade: defending the abortion right in the face of
contemporary opposition. Am J Bioeth 2010;10:33–6.
Giubilini and Minerva’s article has received far more attention
17 Kushner E. Experiencing abortion: a weaving of women’s words. New York:
in the non-academic realm than most of us ever expect to get Harrington Park Press, 1997.
with our publications. All of the essays I have encountered have 18 Cannold L. The abortion myth: feminism, morality, and the hard choices women
been highly critical, and from my understanding the authors make. Hanover: Wesleyan University Press, 2001.
have received death threats. Journal editor Julian Savulescu has 19 McDonnell K. Not an easy choice: a feminist re-examines abortion. Toronto: The
Women’s Press, 1984.
defended the publication of this piece and the authors, and has 20 Thomson JJ. A defense of abortion. Philos Public Aff 1971;1:47–66.
rightly condemned the negative attacks that Giubilini and 21 Boonin D. A defense of abortion. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
Minerva have received: ‘What is disturbing is not the arguments 22 Beckwith F. Personal bodily rights, abortion, and unplugging the violinist. Int Philos Q
in this paper nor its publication in an ethics journal. It is 1992;32:105–18.
23 Wilcox J. Nature as demonic in Thomson’s defense of abortion. In: Baird R, Rosenbaum S
the hostile, abusive, threatening responses that it has elicited.’26
(Eds). The ethics of abortion. Amherst: Prometheus Books, 1989:257–71.
I disagree with Savulescu that the conclusions of this essay are 24 Kaczor C. The ethics of abortion: women’s rights, human life, and the question of
not concerning, and I disagreed with it as strongly in its previ- justice. New York: Routledge, 2011.
ous incarnations in the writings of Peter Singer, Michael Tooley 25 McFall v. Shimp, 10th Pennsylvania District Court. 1978, http://www.ucs.louisiana.
and Mary Ann Warren (who, in her later years, retracted her edu/~ras2777/judpol/mcfall.html (accessed 14 Feb 2013).
26 Savulescu J. “Liberals are Disgusting”: In Defence of the Publication of “After-Birth
argument that infanticide is intrinsically morally permissible). Abortion.” J Med Ethics (blog), 28 Feb 2012. http://blogs.bmj.com/medical-ethics/
However, I completely agree with him that the violent responses 2012/02/28/liberals-are-disgusting-in-defence-of-the-publication-of-after-birth-
to Giubilini and Minerva are just as, if not more, concerning. abortion/ (accessed 26 Apr 2012).

Manninen BA. J Med Ethics 2013;39:330–335. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-100656 335


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on May 24, 2015 - Published by group.bmj.com

Yes, the baby should live: a pro-choice


response to Giubilini and Minerva
Bertha Alvarez Manninen

J Med Ethics 2013 39: 330-335


doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100656

Updated information and services can be found at:


http://jme.bmj.com/content/39/5/330

These include:

References This article cites 10 articles, 2 of which you can access for free at:
http://jme.bmj.com/content/39/5/330#BIBL

Email alerting Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article. Sign up in the
service box at the top right corner of the online article.

Topic Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections


Collections Ethics of abortion (153)
Ethics of reproduction (289)
Sex and sexuality (153)

Notes

To request permissions go to:


http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions

To order reprints go to:


http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/reprintform

To subscribe to BMJ go to:


http://group.bmj.com/subscribe/

You might also like