Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

The majority choice in this problem is

risk averse: the prospect o f certainly


saving 200 lives is more attractive than a
risky prospect o f equal expected value,
that is, a one-in-three chance o f saving
600 lives.
The Framing of Decisions and the A second group o f respondents was
given the cover story o f problem 1 with a
Psychology of Choice different formulation o f the alternative
programs, as follows:

Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman Problem 2 [N = 1551:


If Program C is adopted 400 people will die.
[22 percent]
If Program D is adopted there is 113 probabil-
ity that nobody will die, and 213 probabili-
Ecxplanations and predictions o f tional choice requires that the preference ty that 600 people will die. [78 percent]
people's choices, in everyday life as well between options should not reverse with Which of the two programs would you favor?
as in the social sciences, are often found- changes o f frame. Because o f imperfec-
ed on the assumption o f human rational- tions o f human perception and decision, The majority choice in problem 2 is
ity. The definition o f rationality has been however, changes o f perspective often risk taking: the certain death o f 400
much debated, but there is general agree- reverse the relative apparent size o f ob- people is less acceptable than the two-in-
ment that rational choices should satisfy jects and the relative desirability o f op- three chance that 600 will die. The pref-
some elementary requirements o f con- tions. erences in problems 1 and 2 illustrate a
sistency and coherence. In this article W e have obtained systematic rever- common pattern: choices involving gains
are often risk averse and choices in-
volving losses are often risk taking.
Summary. The psychological principles that govern the perception of decision prob- However, it is easy to see that the two
lems and the evaluation of probabilities and outcomes produce predictable shifts of problems are effectively identical. The
preference when the same problem is framed in different ways. Reversals of prefer- only difference between them is that the
ence are demonstrated in choices regarding monetary outcomes, both hypothetical outcomes are described in problem I by
and real, and in questions pertaining to the loss of human lives. The effects of frames the number o f lives saved and in problem
on preferences are compared to the effects of perspectives on perceptual appear- 2 by the number o f lives lost. The change
ance. The dependence of preferences on the formulation of decision problems is a is accompanied by a pronounced shift
significant concern for the theory of rational choice. from risk aversion to risk taking. W e
have observed this reversal in several
groups o f respondents, including univer-
we describe decision problems in which sals o f preference by variations in the sity faculty and physicians. Inconsistent
people systematically violate the re- framing o f acts, contingencies, or out- responses to problems I and 2 arise from
quirements o f consistency and coher- comes. These effects have been ob- the conjunction o f a framing effect with
ence, and we trace these violations to the served in a variety o f problems and in contradictory attitudes toward risks in-
psychological principles that govern the the choices o f differentgroups o f respon- volving gains and losses. W e turn now
perception o f decision problems and the dents. Here we present selected illustra- to an analysis o f these attitudes.
evaluation o f options. tions o f preference reversals, with data
A decision problem is defined by the obtained from students at Stanford Uni-
acts or options among which one must versity and at the University o f British The Evaluation of Prospects
choose, the possible outcomes or con- Columbia who answered brief question-
sequences o f these acts, and the contin- naires in a classroom setting. The total The major theory o f decision-making
gencies or conditional probabilities that number o f respondents for each problem under risk is the expected utility model.
relate outcomes to acts. W e use the term is denoted by N , and the percentage This model is based on a set o f axioms,
"decision frame" to refer to the deci- who chose each option is indicated in for example, transitivity o f preferences,
sion-maker's conception o f the acts, out- brackets. which provide criteria for the rationality
comes, and contingencies associated The effect o f variations in framing is o f choices. The choices o f an individual
with a particular choice. The frame that a illustrated in problems 1 and 2. who conforms to the axioms can be de-
decision-maker adopts is controlled part- scribed in terms o f the utilities o f various
Problem 1 [ N = 1521: Imagine that the U.S.
ly by the formulation o f the problem and outcomes for that individual. The utility
is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual
partly by the norms, habits, and personal Asian disease, which is expected to kill 600 o f a risky prospect is equal to the ex-
characteristics o f the decision-maker. people. Two alternative programs to combat pected utility o f its outcomes, obtained
It is often possible to frame a given de- the disease have been proposed. Assume that by weighting the utility o f each possible
cision problem in more than one way. the exact scientific estimate of the con- outcome by its probability. When faced
sequences of the programs are as follows:
Alternative frames for a decision prob- with a choice, a rational decision-maker
lem may be compared to alternative per- If Program A is adopted, 200 people will be
saved. [72 percent]
will prefer the prospect that offers the
spectives on a visual scene. Veridical highest expected utility (1, 2 ) .
If Program B is adopted, there is 113 probabil-
perception requires that the perceived ity that 600 people will be saved, and Dr. Tversky is a professor of psychology at Stan-
relative height o f two neighboring moun- 213 probability that no people will be ford University, Stanford, California 94305, and Dr.
tains, say, should not reverse with saved. 128 percent] Kahneman is a professor of psychology at the Uni-
versity of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada
changes o f vantage point. Similarly, ra- Which of the two programs would you favor? V6T 1W5.
SCIENCh, VOL. 211, 30 JANUARY 1981 0036-807518110130-0453$01.5010 Copy1-ight Q 1981 AAAS 453
As will be illustrated below, people ex- The Framing of Acts
hibit patterns of preference which appear
incompatible with expected utility theo- Problem 3 [ N = 1501: Imagine that you Face
the following pair of concurrent decisions.
ry. We have presented elsewhere (3) a First examine both decisions, then indicate
descriptive model, called prospect theo- the options you prefer.
ry, which modifies expected utility theo- Decision (i). Choose between:
ry so as to accommodate these observa- A. a sure gain of $240 [84 percent]
tions. We distinguish two phases in the B . 25% chance to gain $1000, and
choice process: an initial phase in which 75% chance to gain nothing [ 16 percent]
acts, outcomes, and contingencies are Decision (ii). Choose between:
C. a sure loss of $750 113 percent]
framed, and a subsequent phase of eval- D. 75% chance to lose $1000, and
uation (4). For simplicity, we restrict the Fig. 1 . A hypothetical value function. 25% chance to lose nothing [87 percent]
formal treatment of the theory to choices
involving stated numerical probabilities The majority choice in decision (i) is
and quantitative outcomes, such as mon- has the following properties. First, im- risk averse: a riskless prospect is pre-
ey, time, or number of lives. possible events are discarded, that is, ferred to a risky prospect of equal or
Consider a prospect that yields out- n(0) = 0, and the scale is normalized so greater expected value. In contrast, the
come x with probability y , outcome y that n ( l ) = 1, but the function is not well majority choice in decision (ii) is risk tak-
with probability q, and the status quo behaved near the endpoints. Second, ing: a risky prospect is preferred to a
with probability 1 y - - q. According for low probabilities n(p) > p , but riskless prospect of equal expected val-
to prospect theory, there are values v(.) TO)) + n ( l - p) 5 1 . Thus low proba- ue. This pattern of risk aversion in
associated with outcomes, and decision bilities are overweighted, moderate and choices involving gains and risk seeking
weights n(.) associated with probabili- high probabilities are underweighted, in choices involving losses is attributable
ties, such that the overall value of the and the latter effect is more pronounced to the properties of v and n . Because the
prospect equals n(p) v(x) + n(q) v(y). A than the former. Third, n(pq)/n(p) < value function is S-shaped, the value as-
slightly different equation should be ap- n(pqv)/nQ?v)for all 0 < y , q , r 5 1 . That sociated with a gain of $240 is greater
plied if all outcomes of a prospect are on is, for any fixed probability ratio q , the than 24 percent of the value associated
the same side of the zero point (5). ratio of decision weights is closer to with a gain of $1000, and the (negative)
In prospect theory, outcomes are ex- unity when the probabilities are low value associated with a loss of $750 is
pressed as positive or negative devia- than when they are high, for example, smaller than 75 percent of the value asso-
tions (gains or losses) from a neutral ref- n(. l)/n(.2) > n(.4)/n(.8). A hypothetical ciated with a loss of $1000. Thus the
erence outcome, which is assigned a val- weighting function which satisfies these shape of the value function contributes
ue of zero. Although subjective values properties is shown in Fig. 2. The major to risk aversion in decision (i) and to risk
differ among individuals and attributes, qualitative properties of decision weights seeking in decision (ii). Moreover, the
we propose that the value function is can be extended to cases in which the underweighting of moderate and high
commonly S-shaped, concave above the probabilities of outcomes are subjective- probabilities contributes to the relative
reference point and convex below it, as ly assessed rather than explicitly given. attractiveness of the sure gain in (i) and
illustrated in Fig. 1 . For example, the dif- In these situations, however, decision to the relative aversiveness of the sure
ference in subjective value between weights may also be affected by other loss in (ii). The same analysis applies to
gains of $10 and $20 is greater than the characteristics of an event, such as am- problems 1 and 2.
subjective difference between gains of biguity or vagueness (Y). Because (i) and (ii) were presented to-
$110 and $120. The same relation be- Prospect theory, and the scales illus- gether, the respondents had in effect to
tween value differences holds for the trated in Figs. 1 and 2, should be viewed choose one prospect from the set: A and
corresponding losses. Another property as an approximate, incomplete, and sim- C, B and C, A and D, B and D. The most
of the value function is that the response plified description of the evaluation of common pattern (A and D) was chosen
to losses is more extreme than the re- risky prospects. Although the properties by 73 percent of respondents, while the
sponse to gains. The displeasure associ- of v and n summarize a common pattern least popular pattern (B and C) was
ated with losing a sum of money is gener- of choice, they are not universal: the chosen by only 3 percent of respondents.
ally greater than the pleasure associated preferences of some individuals are not However, the combination of B and
with winning the same amount, as is re- well described by an S-shaped value C is definitely superior to the combina-
flected in people's reluctance to accept function and a consistent set of decision tion A and D, as is readily seen in prob-
fair bets on a toss of a coin. Several stud- weights. The simultaneous measurement lem 4.
ies of decision (3, 6) and judgment (7) of values and decision weights involves Problem 4 [ N = 861. Choose between:
have confirmed these properties of the serious experimental and statistical diffi- A & D. 25% chance to win $240, and
value function (8). culties (10). 75% chance to lose $760. [0 per-
The second major departure of pros- If n and v were linear throughout, the cent]
pect theory from the expected utility preference order between options would B & C. 25% chance t o win $250, and
model involves the treatment of proba- be independent of the framing of acts, 75% chance to lose $750. 1100 per-
cent]
bilities. In expected utility theory the outcomes, or contingencies. Because of
utility of an uncertain outcome is weight- the characteristic nonlinearities of n and When the prospects were combined
ed by its probability; in prospect theory v, however, different frames can lead to and the dominance of the second option
the value of an uncertain outcome is mul- different choices. The following three became obvious, all respondents chose
tiplied by a decision weight n(p), which sections describe reversals of preference the superior option. The popularity of
is a monotonic function of p but is not a caused by variations in the framing of the inferior option in problem 3 implies
probability. The weighting function n acts, contingencies, and outcomes. that this problem was framed as a pair of
SCIENCE, VOL. 211
separate choices. The respondents ap- The first stage of problem 6 yields the
parently failed to entertain the possibility same outcome (no gain) for both acts.
that the conjunction of two seemingly Consequently, we propose, people eval-
reasonable choices could lead to an un- uate the options conditionally, as if the
tenable result. second stage had been reached. In this
The violations of dominance observed framing, of course, problem 6 reduces to
in problem 3 do not disappear in the problem 5 . More generally, we suggest
presence of monetary incentives. A dif- that a decision problem is evaluated con-
ferent group of respondents who an- ditionally when (i) there is a state in
swered a modified version of problem 3, which all acts yield the same outcorne,
with real payoffs, produced a similar pat- such as failing to reach the second stage
tein of choices (11). Other authors have of the game in problem 6, and (ii) the
S t a t e d probability: p
also reported that violations of the rules stated probabilities of other outcoines
Fig. 2. A hypothetical weighting function.
of rational choice, originally observed in are coiiditioiial on the nonoccurrence of
hypothetical questioris, were not elimi- this state.
nated by payoffs (12). The striking discrepancy betweell the
We suspect that nlariy concu~rentde- Let us examine the structure of these responses to problems 6 and 7, which are
cisions in the real world are framed inde- problems. First, note that problems 6 identical in outcomes and probabilities,
pendently, and that the preference order and 7 are identical in terms of probabili- could be described as a pseudocertainty
would often be reversed if the decisions ties and outcomes, because prospect C effect. The prospect yielding $30 is rela-
were combined. The respondents in offers a .25 chance to win $30 and pros- tively more attractive in problem 6 than
problem 3 failed to combine options, al- pect D offers a probability of .25 x in problem 7, as if it had the advantage of
though the integration was relatively .80 = .20 to win $45. Consistency there- certainty. The sense of certainty associ-
simple and was encouraged by instruc- fore requires that the same choice be ated with option C is illusory, however,
tions (13). The complexity of practical made in problems 6 and 7. Second, note since the gain is in fact contingent on
problems of concurrent decisions, such that problem 6 differs from problem 5 on- reaching the second stage of the game
as portfolio selection, would prevent ly by the introduction of a preliminary (15).
people from integrating options without stage. If the second stage of the game is We have observed the certainty effect
computational aids, even if they were in- reached, then problem 6 reduces to prob- in several sets of problems, with out-
clined to do so. lem 5; if the game ends at the first stage, comes ranging from vacation trips to the
the decision does not affect the outcome. loss of human lives. In the negative do-
Hence there seems to be no reason to main, certainty exaggerates the aversive-
The Framing of Contingencies make a different choice in problems 5 ness of losses that are certain relative to
and 6. By this logical analysis, problem 6 losses that are merely probable. In a
The following triple of problems illus- is equivalent to problem 7 on the one question dealing with the response to an
trates the framing of contingencies. Each hand and problem 5 on the other. The epidemic, for example, most respond-
problem was presented to a different participants, however, responded simi- ents found "a sure loss of 75 lives" more
group of respondents. Each group was larly to problems 5 and 6 but differently aversive than "80% chance to lose 100
told that one participant in ten, pre- to problem 7. This pattern of responses lives" but preferred "Im chance to lose
selected at random, would actually be exhibits two phenomena of choice: the 75 lives" over "8% chance to lose 100
playing for money. Chance events were certainty effect and the pseudocertainty lives," contrary to expected utility theo-
realized, in the respondents' presence, effect. ry.
by drawing a single ball from a bag con- 'I'he contrast between problenls 5 and We also obtained the pseudocertainty
taining a known proportion of balls of the 7 illustrates a phenomenon discovered effect in several studies where the de-
winning color, and the winners were paid by Allais (14), which we have labeled the scription of the decision problerris fa-
immediately. certainty effect: a reduction of the proba- vored conditional evaluation. Pseudo-
bility of an outcome by a constant factor certainty can be induced either by a se-
Problem 5 [N = 771: Which of the following
options d o you prefer'? has more impact when the outcome was quential formulation, as in problem 6, or
A. a sure win of $30 [78 percent]
initially certain than when it was merely by the introduction of causal contin-
B. 80% chance to win $45 [22 percent] probable. Prospect theory attributes this gencies. In another version of the epi-
effect to the properties of T. It is easy to demic problem, for instance, respond-
Problem 6 [N = 851: Consider the following
two.stage game. In the first stage, there is a verify, by applying the equation of pros- ents were told that risk to life existed on-
75% chance to end the game without winning pect theory to problems 5 and 7, that ly in the event (probability .lo) that the
anything, and a 25% chance to move into the people for whom the value ratio v(30)l disease was carried by a particular virus.
second stage. If you reach the second stage v(45) lies between the weight ratios Two alternative programs were said to
you have a choice between: ~ ( . 2 0 ) / ~ ( . 2 5and
) ~ ( . 8 0 ) / ~ ( 1 . 0will
) pre- yield "a sure loss of 75 lives" or "80%
C. a sure win of $30 [74 percent] fer A to B and F to E, contrary to ex- chance to lose 100 lives" if the critical
D. 8% chance to win $45 [26 percent]
pected utility theory. Prospect theory virus was involved, and no loss of life in
Your choice must be made before the game
starts, i.e., before the outcome of the first does not predict a reversal of preference the event (probability .90) that the dis-
stage is known. Please indicate the option you for every individual in problems 5 and ease was carried by another virus. In ef-
prefer. 7. It only requires that an individual who fect, the respondents were asked to
Problem 7 [N = 811: Which of the following has no preference between A and B pre- choose between 10 percent chance of
optiotns d o you prefer? fer F to 6. For group data, the theory losing 75 lives and 8 percent chance of
E. 25% chance to win $30 [42 percent] predicts the observed directional shift losing 100 lives, but their preferences
P. 2Wh chance to win $45 [58 percent] of preference between the two problems. were the same as when the choice was
30 JANUARY 1981
between a sure loss o f 75 lives and 80 provide is an illusion o f conditional fram- ing o f credit-card purchases, representa-
percent chance o f losing 100 lives. A ing. It appears that insurance is bought tives o f the credit-card industry re-
conditional framing was evidently as protection against worry, not only quested that the price difference be la-
adopted in which the contingency o f the against risk, and that worry can be ma- beled a cash discount rather than a
noncritical virus was eliminated, giving nipulated by the labeling o f outcomes credit-card surcharge. The two labels in-
rise to a pseudocertainty effect.The cer- and by the framing o f contingencies. It is duce differentreference points by implic-
tainty effectreveals attitudes toward risk not easy to determine whether people itly designating as normal reference the
that are inconsistent with the axioms o f value the elimination o f risk too much or higher or the lower o f the two prices. Be-
rational choice, whereas the pseudo- the reduction o f risk too little. The con- cause losses loom larger than gains, con-
certainty effect violates the more funda- trasting attitudes to the two forms o f pro- sumers are less willing to accept a sur-
mental requirement that preferences tective action, however, are difficult to charge than to forego a discount. A simi-
should be independent o f problem de- justify on normative grounds (16). lar effect has been observed in
scription. experimental studies o f insurance: the
Many significant decisions concern ac- proportion o f respondents who preferred
tions that reduce or eliminate the proba- The Framing of Outcomes a sure loss to a larger probable loss was
bility o f a hazard, at some cost. The significantly greater when the former
shape o f rr in the range o f low probabili- Outcomes are commonly perceived as was called an insurance premium (19,
ties suggests that a protective action positive or negative in relation to a refer- 20).
which reduces the probability o f a harm ence outcome that is judged neutral. These observations highlight the labil-
from I percent to zero, say, will be val- Variations o f the reference point can ity o f reference outcomes, as well as
ued more highly than an action that re- therefore determine whether a given out- their role in decision-making. In the ex-
duces the probability o f the same harm come is evaluated as a gain or as a loss. amples discussed so far, the neutral ref-
from 2 percent to 1 percent. Indeed, Because the value function is generally erence point was identified by the label-
probabilistic insurance, which reduces concave for gains, convex for losses, and ing of outcomes. A diversity o f factors
the probability o f loss by half, is judged steeper for losses than for gains, shifts o f determine the reference outcome in
to be worth less than half the price o f reference can change the value dif- everyday life. The reference outcome is
regular insurance that eliminates the risk ference between outcomes and thereby usually a state to which one has adapted;
altogether (3). reverse the preference order between it is sometimes set by social norms and
It is often possible to frame protective options (6). Problems 1 and 2 illustrated expectations; it sometimes corresponds
action in either conditional or uncon- a preference reversal induced by a shift to a level o f aspiration, which may or
ditional form. For example, an insurance of reference that transformed gains into may not be realistic.
policy that covers fire but not flood could losses. We have dealt so far with elementary
be evaluated either as full protection For another example, consider a per- outcomes, such as gains or losses in a
against the specific risk o f fire or as a re- son who has spent an afternoon at the single attribute. In many situations, how-
duction in the overall probability o f race track, has already lost $140, and is ever, an action gives rise to a compound
property loss. The preceding analysis considering a $10 bet on a 15 : 1 long shot outcome, which joins a series o f changes
suggests that insurance should appear in the last race. This decision can be in a single attribute, such as a sequence
more attractive when it is presented as framed in two ways, which correspond o f monetary gains and losses, or a set o f
the elimination o f risk than when it is de- to two natural reference points. I f the concurrent changes in several attributes.
scribed as a reduction of risk. P. Slovic, status quo is the reference point, the out- T o describe the framing and evaluation
B. Fischhoff,and S. Lichtenstein, in an comes o f the bet are framed as a gain o f o f compound outcomes, we use the no-
unpublished study, found that a hypo- $140 and a loss o f $10. On the other tion of a psychological account, defined
thetical vaccine which reduces the prob- hand, it may be more natural to view the as an outcome frame which specifies (i)
ability o f contracting a disease from .20 present state as a loss o f $140, for the the set of elementary outcomes that are
to .10 is less attractive i f it is described as betting day, and accordingly frame the evaluated jointly and the manner in
effectivein half the cases than i f it is pre- last bet as a chance to return to the refer- which they are combined and (ii)a refer-
sented as fully effective against one o f ence point or to increase the loss to $150. ence outcome that is considered neutral
two (exclusive and equiprobable) virus Prospect theory implies that the latter or normal. In the account that is set up
strains that produce identical symptoms. frame will produce more risk seeking for the purchase o f a car, for example,
In accord with the present analysis o f than the former. Hence, people who do the cost o f the purchase is not treated as
pseudocertainty, the respondents valued not adjust their reference point as they a loss nor is the car viewed as a gift.
full protection against an identified vi- lose are expected to take bets that they Rather, the transaction as a whole is
rus more than probabilistic protection would normally find unacceptable. This evaluated as positive, negative, or neu-
against the disease. analysis is supported by the observation tral, depending on such factors as the
The preceding discussion highlights that bets on long shots are most popular performance o f the car and the price o f
the sharp contrast between lay responses on the last race o f the day (17). similar cars in the market. A closely re-
to the reduction and the elimination o f Because the value function is steeper lated treatment has been offered by Tha-
risk. Because no form o f protective ac- for losses than for gains, a differencebe- ler (18).
tion can cover all risks to human welfare, tween options will loom larger when it is We propose that people generally
all insurance is essentially probabilistic: framed as a disadvantage o f one option evaluate acts in terms o f a minimal ac-
it reduces but does not eliminate risk. rather than as an advantage o f the other count, which includes only the direct
The probabilistic nature of insurance is option. An interesting example o f such consequences o f the act. The minimal
commonly masked by formulations that an effect in a riskless context has been account associated with the decision to
emphasize the completeness o f pro- noted by Thaler (18). In a debate on a accept a gamble, for example, includes
tection against identified harms, but the proposal to pass to the consumer some the money won or lost in that gamble and
sense o f security that such formulations o f the costs associated with the process- excludes other assets or the outcome o f
SCIENCE, VOL. 211
previous gambles. People commonly other group (N = 88) the values shown consistencies were traced to the inter-
adopt minimal accounts because this in brackets. action of two sets of factors: variations
mode of framing (i) simplifies evaluation in the framing of acts, contingencies, and
and reduces cognitive strain, (ii) reflects Problem 10: Imagine that you are about to outcomes, and the characteristic non-
purchase a jacket for ($125) [$15], and a calcu-
the intuition that consequences should lator for ($15) [$125]. The calculator salesman linearities of values and decision
be causally linked to acts, and (iii) informs you that the calculator you wish to weights. The demonstrated effects are
matches the properties of hedonic expe- buy is on sale for ($10) [$I201 at the other large and systematic, although by no
rience, which is more sensitive to desir- branch of the store, located 20 minutes drive means universal. They occur when the
away. Would you make the trip to the other
able and undesirable changes than to store? outcomes concern the loss of human
steady states. lives as well as in choices about money;
There are situations, however, in The response to the two versions of they are not restricted to hypothetical
which the outcomes of an act affect the problem 10 were markedly different: 68 questions and are not eliminated by mon-
balance in an account that was pre- percent of the respondents were willing etary incentives.
viously set up by a related act. In these to make an extra trip to save $5 on a $15 Earlier we compared the dependence
cases, the decision at hand may be eval- calculator; only 29 percent were willing of preferences on frames to the depen-
uated in terms of a more inclusive ac- to exert the same effort when the price of dence of perceptual appearance on per-
count, as in the case of the bettor who the calculator was $125. Evidently the spective. If while traveling in a mountain
views the last race in the context of ear- respondents do not frame problem 10 in range you notice that the apparent rela-
lier losses. More generally, a sunk-cost the minimal account, which involves on- tive height of mountain peaks varies with
effect arises when a decision is referred ly a benefit of $5 and a cost of some in- your vantage point, you will conclude
to an existing account in which the cur- convenience. Instead, they evaluate the that some impressions of relative height
rent balance is negative. Because of the potential saving in a more inclusive ac- must be erroneous, even when you have
nonlinearities of the evaluation process, count, which includes the purchase of no access to the correct answer. Similar-
the minimal account and a more in- the calculator but not of the jacket. By ly, one may discover that the relative at-
clusive one often lead to different the curvature of v , a discount of $5 has a tractiveness of options varies when the
choices. greater impact when the price of the cal- same decision problem is framed in dif-
Problems 8 and 9 illustrate another culator is low than when it is high. ferent ways. Such a discovery will nor-
class of situations in which an existing A closely related observation has been mally lead the decision-maker to recon-
account affects a decision: reported by Pratt, Wise, and Zeckhauser sider the original preferences, even when
(21), who found that the variability of the there is no simple way to resolve the in-
Problem 8 [N = 1831: Imagine that you
have decided to see a play where admission is
prices at which a given product is sold by consistency. The susceptibility to per-
$10 per ticket. As you enter the theater you different stores is roughly proportional to spective effects is of special concern in
discover that you have lost a $10 bill. the mean price of that product. The same the domain of decision-making because
Would you still pay $10 for a ticket for the pattern was observed for both frequently of the absence of objective standards
play? and infrequently purchased items. Over- such as the true height of mountains.
Yes [88 percent] N o [12 percent] all, a ratio of 2 : 1 in the mean price of two The metaphor of changing perspective
Problem 9 [N = 2001: Imagine that you products is associated with a ratio of can be applied to other phenomena of
have decided to see a play and paid the admis- 1.86 : 1 in the standard deviation of the choice, in addition to the framing effects
sion price of $10 per ticket. As you enter the respective quoted prices. If the effort with which we have been concerned here
theater you discover that you have lost the that consumers exert to save each dollar (19). The problem of self-control is natu-
ticket. The seat was not marked and the ticket
cannot be recovered.
on a purchase, for instance by a phone rally construed in these terms. The story
Would you pay $10 for another ticket? call, were independent of price, the dis- of Ulysses' request to be bound to the
Yes [46 percent] N o [54 percent] persion of quoted prices should be about mast of the ship in anticipation of the ir-
the same for all products. In contrast, resistible temptation of the Sirens' call is
The marked difference between the re- the data of Pratt et al. (21) are consistent often used as a paradigm case (22). In
sponses to problems 8 and 9 is an effect with the hypothesis that consumers this example of precommitment, an ac-
of psychological accounting. We pro- hardly exert more effort to save $ I5 on a tion taken in the present renders inopera-
pose that the purchase of a new ticket in $150 purchase than to save $5 on a $50 tive an anticipated future preference. An
problem 9 is entered in the account that purchase (18). Many readers will recog- unusual feature of the problem of inter-
was set up by the purchase of the original nize the temporary devaluation of money temporal conflict is that the agent who
ticket. In terms of this account, the ex- which facilitates extra spending and re- views a problem from a particular tem-
pense required to see the show is $20, a duces the significance of small discounts poral perspective is also aware of the
cost which many of our respondents ap- in the context of a large expenditure, conflicting views that future perspectives
parently found excessive. In problem 8, such as buying a house or a car. This will offer. In most other situations, deci-
on the other hand, the loss of $10 is not paradoxical variation in the value of sion-makers are not normally aware of
linked specifically to the ticket purchase money is incompatible with the standard the potential effects of different decision
and its effect on the decision is accord- analysis of consumer behavior. frames on their preferences.
ingly slight. The perspective metaphor highlights
The following problem, based on ex- the following aspects of the psychology
amples by Savage (2, p. 103) and Thaler Discussion of choice. Individuals who face a deci-
(IN), further illustrates the effect of em- sion problem and have a definite prefer-
bedding an option in different accounts. In this article we have presented a se- ence (i) might have a different preference
Two versions of this problem were pre- ries of demonstrations in which seem- in a different framing of the same prob-
sented to different groups of subjects. ingly inconsequential changes in the for- lem, (ii) are normally unaware of alterna-
One group (N = 93) was given the val- mulation of choice problems caused sig- tive frames and of their potential effects
ues that appear in parentheses, and the nificant shifts of preference. The in- on the relative attractiveness of options,
30 JANUARY 1981 457
(iii) would wish their preferences to be dictive orientation encourages the deci- D. Ellsberg, Q. J. Econ. 75,643 (1%1); W. Fell-

ner, Probability a n d Prt?fit-A Study qf' !+-

independent of frame, but (iv) are often sion-maker to focus on future experience nomic Behavior Along Boyc>sian Lines (Irw~n,

uncertain how to resolve detected incon- and to ask "What will I feel then?" Homewood, Ill., 1965).

The scaling of v and rr by pair comparisons re-

sistencies (23). In some cases (such as rather than "What do 1want now?" The quires a large number of observations. The pro-

former question, when answered with cedure of pricing gambles is more convenient for

problems 3 and 4 and perhaps problems 8 scaling purposes, but it is subject to a severe an-

and 9) the advantage of one frame be- care, can be the more useful guide
- in dif- choring bias: the ordering of gambles by their

cash equivalents diverges systematically from

comes evident once the competing ficult decisions. In particular, predictive the preference order observed in direct com-

frames are compared, but in other cases considerations may be applied to select parisons [S. Lichtenstein and P. Slovic, J. Exp.

Psychol. 89, 46 (1971)l.

(problems 1 and 2 and problems 6 and 7) the decision frame that best rewesents A new group of respondents (N = 126) was pre-

it is not obvious which preferences the hedonic experience of outcomes. sented with a modified version of problem 3, in

which the outcomes were reduced by a factor

should be abandoned. Further complexities arise in the nor- of 50. The participants were informed that the

These observations do not imply that mative analysis because the framing of gambles would actually be played by tossing a

pair of fair coins, that one participant in ten

preference reversals, or other errors of an action sometimes affects the actual would be selected at random to play the gambles

of his o r her choice. To ensure a positive return

choice or judgment (24), are necessarily experience of its outcomes. For ex- for the entire set, a third decision, yielding only

irrational. Like other intellectual limita- ample, framing outcomes in terms of positive outcomes, was added. These payoff

conditions did not alter the pattern of prefer-

tions, disct~ssedby Simon (25) under the overall wealth or welfare rather than in ences observed in the hypothetical problem: 67

heading of "bounded rationality," the tenns of specific gains and losses may at- percent of respondents chose prospect A and 86

percent chose prospect D. The dominated com-

practice of acting on the most readily tenuate one's emotional response to an bination of A and D was chosen by 60 percent of

available frame can sometimes be justi- occasional loss. Similarly, the experi- respondents, and only 6 percent favored the

dominant combination of 5 and C.

fied by reference to the mental effort re- ence of a change for the worse may vary S. Lichtenstein and P. Slovic, J . Exp. I'sychol.

101, 16 (1973); D. M. Grether and C. R. Plott,

quired to explore alternative frames and if the change is framed as an uncompen- Am. Econ. Rev. 69, 623 (1979); I. 1,ieblich and

avoid potential inconsistencies. How- sated loss or as a cost incurred to A. Lieblich, Pcrcc,pt. Mot. Skills 29, 467 (1969);

D. hf. Grether, Social Science Working I'aper

ever, we propose that the details of the achieve some benefit. The framing of No. 245 (California Institute of Technology,

phenomena described in this article are acts and outcomes can also reflect the Pasadena, 1979).

Other demonstrations of a reluctance to in-

better explained by prospect theory and acceptance or rejection of responsibility tegrate concurrent options have been reported:

by an analysis of framing than by ad for particular consequences, and the de- P. Slovic and S. Lichtenstein, J . Exp. I'sychol.

78, 646 (1968); J. W. Payne and M. L. Braun-

hoc appeals to the notion of cost of liberate manipulation of framing is com- stein, ibid. 87, 13 (1971).

M. Allais, Economc,trica 21, 503 (1953); K.

thinking. monly used as an instrument of self- McCrimmon and S . Larsson, in Expc>cted Util-

The present work has been concerned control (22). When framing influences ity Hypothe.se.s and the Allais Paradox, M. All-

ais and 0. Hagan, Eds. (Reidel, Dordrecht,

primarily with the descriptive question the experience of consequences, the 1979).

of how decisions are made, but the psy- adoption of a decision frame is an ethi- Another group of respondents ( N = 205) was

presented with all three problems, in different

chology of choice is also relevant to the cally significant act. orders, without monetary payoffs. The joint fre-

normative question of how decisions quency distribution of choices in problems 5, 6,

References and Notes and 7 was a s follows: ACE, 22; ACF, 65; ADE,

ought to be made. In order to avoid the 4; ADF, 20; BCE, 7; BCF, 18; BDE, 17; BDF,

1. J. Von Neurnann and 0. Morgenstern, Theory of 52. These data confirm in a within-subject design

difficult problem of justifying values, the Games a n d Economic Behavior (Princeton the analysis of conditional evaluation proposed

modern theory of rational choice has Univ. Press, Princeton, N.J., 1947); H. Raiffa, in the text. More than 75 percent of respondents

Decision Analysis: Lectures on Choices Under made compatible choices (AC or BD) in prob-

adopted the coherence of specific prefer- Uncertainty (Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass., lems 5 and 6, and less than half made compatible

ences as the sole criterion of rationality. 1968); P. Fishburn, Utility Theory for 1)ecision choices in problems 6 and 7 (CE or DF) or 5 and

Making (Wiley, New York, 1970). 7 (AE or RF). The elimination of payoffs in these

This approach enjoins the decision- 2. L. J. Savage, The Foundations of S t ~ t i s t i c s questions reduced risk aversion but did not sub-

maker to resolve inconsistencies but of- (Wiley, New York, 1954). stantially alter the effects of certainty and

3. D. Kahneman and A. Tversky, Econometrics pscudocertainty.

fers no guidance on how to do so. It im- 47, 263 (1979). For further discussion of rationality in pro-

4. The framing phase includes various editing oper- tective action see H. Kunreuther, Disortur In-

plicitly assumes that the decision-maker ations that are applied to simplify prospects, for surcmce Protection: Public Policy Lessons

who carefully answers the question example by comb~ningevents or outcomes o r by (Wiley, New York, 1978).

discarding negligible componrnts (7). W. H. McGlothlin, Am. J . I'.sychol. 69, 604

"What do I really want?" will eventually 5. I f p + y = I a n d e i t h e r x > y > O o r x < y < O , (1956).

achieve coherent preferences. However, the equation in the text is replaced by R. Thaler, J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 1 , 3 9 (1980).

vb) + r r b ) [v(x) v ( y ) l , so that decision


-
B. Fischhoff, P. Slovic, S. Lichtenstein, in ('og-

the susceptibility of preferences to varia- weights are not applied to sure outcomes. nitive Prt,cc~.s.sesin Choice and 1)ecision Brhov-

6. P. Fishburn and G. Kochenberger, Decision Sci. ;or, T. Wallsten, Ed. (Erlbaum, Hillsdale, N.J.,

tions of framing raises doubt about the 10, 503 (1979); D. J. Laughhunn, J. W. Payne, 1980).

feasibility and adequacy of the coher- R. Crum, Manage. Sci., in press; J. W. Payne, J. C. Hershey and P. J. H. Schocmaker, J . Risk

D. J. Laughhunn, R. Cmm, ibid., in press; S . A. Insur.. in Dress.

ence criterion. Eraker and H. C. Sox, Med. 1)ecision Making, A.


J. ~ r a t t , Wise, R. Zeckhauser, Q. J. Econ.

Consistency is only one aspect of the in press. In the last study several hundred clinic 93, 189 (1979).

patients made hypothetical choices between R. H. Strotz. Rev. Econ. Stud. 23. 165 (1955): G.

lay notion of rational behavior. As noted drug therapies for severe headaches, hyperten- Ainslie, Psychol. Bull. 82, 463 (1975); J. Elster,

by March (26), the common conception sion, and chest pain. Most patients were risk Uly.ssc~.s a n d the Sirens; Studies in Rationality

averse when the outcomes were described a s and Irrntionolity (Cambridge Univ. Press, Lon-

of rationality also requires that prefer- positive (for example, reduced pain or increased don, 1979); R. Thaler and H. M. Shifrin, J. Polit.

life expectancy) and risk taking when the out- Econ., in press.

ences or utilities for particular outcomes comes were described as negative (increased P. Slovic and A. Tversky, Behav. Sci. 19, 368

should be predictive of the experiences pain or reduced life expectancy). No significant (1974).

differences were found between patients who A. Tversky and D. Kahneman, Science 185,

of satisfaction or displeasure associated actually suffered from the ailments described 1124 (1974); P. Slovic, B. Fischhoff, S. Lich-

with their occurrence. Thus, a man could and patients who did not. tenstein, Annrr. Rev. Psychol. 28, 1 (1977); R.

7. E. Galanter and P. Pliner, in Sensation a n d Nisbett and L . Ross, Numcm 1nfi.rc.nce: Strate-

be judged irrational either because his Measurement, H. R. Moskowitz 6.t a / . , Eds. gies a n d Shortcomings qf Social Judgmcwt

preferences are contradictory or because (Reidel, Dordrecht, 1974), pp. 65-76. (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1980);

8. The extension of the proposed value function to H. Einhorn and R. Hogarth, Annu. Rev. Psy-

his desires and aversions do not reflect multiattribute options, with or without risk, de- chol. 32, 53 (1981).

serves careful analysis. In particular, indif- H. A. Simon, Q. J . Econ. 69,99 (1955); P.sycho1.

his pleasures and pains. The predictive Rev. 63, 129 (1956).

ference curves between dimensions of loss may


criterion of rationality can be applied to be concave upward, even when the value func- J. March, Bell J . Econ. 9, 587 (1978).

tions for the separate losses are both convex, This work was supported by the Office of Naval

resolve inconsistent preferences and to because of marked subadditivity between di- Research under contract No014-79-C-0077 to

improve the quality of decisions. A pre- menslons. Stanford University.

458 SCIENCE, VOL. 211

You might also like