Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Philosophical Hermeneutics

and Biblical Exegesis

Edited by
Petr Pokorny
and
Jan Roskovec

Mohr Siebeck
82 Michael Kirwan

of the' lost traveller' cited by Foster at the beginning of this article - "we have
become explorers of human possibility, but unable to return home and unsure Apophatic Elements in Derrida's Deconstruction
of where and how to end our journey" - begins to look limited, as i f our
problem were simply one of collective disorientation, an abence of maps. Ivana Noble
What is disturbing and new for many is the discovery we are indeed lost, but
in a war-zone with an unknown enemy.
It is possible to detect throughout Habermas' Peace Prize speech a sense
of frustration at the rudeness of a conversation having been violently 1. Introduction
interrupted. Ancient issues concerning the tension between society and
religion have to be addressed once more, while the theme of biotechnology To speak about apophaticism in Derrida runs two risks. The first would be to
which has a most pressing urgency and interest for him has been 'hi-jacked' dismiss the theme completely and say that Derrida explicitly distances himself
(literally) by current events. This is a question of timing, of course, but it is from the apophatic tradition and sees it as a 'rhetoric of negative determina-
possible also that we have here a parable of the real limitation of hermeneu- tion' or only as another type of theology, which aims at strengthenning claims
tics, a parable which poses questions to Gadamer and Habermas alike. How by which we can grasp divine essence. Derrida calls this hyperessential
1

can the claim to the universality of hermeneutics be sustained in situations theology, which restores the order it puts into question. He remains critical of
where there is an outright refusal of dialogic conversation? And is the any determination, whether positive or negative. He argues that what is based
description of fundamentalism as a situation of distorted comunication within in a negative determiner still attempts to give an identity (non-entity) to who
a modernity divided against itself (and the genetic explanation of religion we are and what we do and how we relate to one another and our world and
which this implies) simply a way of'domesticating' the problem, leaving vital to God. Thus, it remains a 'negative' mirror image of the positive determina-
aporias untouched? Despite the amount of work still to do, however, the tion. The second risk is to consider Derrida a proponent of apophaticism too
2

Gadamer - Habermas discussion remains a fascinating initial exploration of quickly. There are overlapping themes in Derrida's deconstruction and in the
large and vital themes around the nature of modernity and tradition, and while apophatic tradition, as will be demonstrated, but there are also Derrida's
the terms of the debate have been considerably altered by political and criticisms of apophaticism. Here an important question arises, namely, what
cultural transformations, the seeming insolubility of many key questions exactly Derrida considers apophaticism to be. Drawing on Dionysius and
means that it will continue to be a valuable point of reference. Meister Eckhart in particular, Derrida seems to make little distinction, i f any,
between the Western via negativa and Eastern apophaticism. He also does 3

not take into account criticisms of apophatic hyperessentialism, which, as can


be found, for example, in Gregory of Nyssa, is found in the apophatic
4

tradition itself. And finally, we cannot fit him too easily into a Christian
theological framework as his own background is in Judaism.
The aim of this article is to shed more light on the relation of Derrida's
deconstruction to apophatic method. In order to do that, I will first examine
Derrida's concept of deconstruction and its targets: the logic of identity and
the metaphysics o f presence. Here I will trace Derrida's arguments for not

See T. FOSHAY, Introduction to: H. COWARD, T. FOSHAY (eds.), Derrida and Negative
1

Theology, Albany 1992, 2 - 4 .


Compare to the role Eunomius gave to the concepts of 'unbegotten', 'uncreated' or
2

'ungenerated', dealt with in another article in this collection, 'The Apophatic Way in
Gregory of Nyssa', part 2: Two key controversies.
3 Cf. J . D E R R I D A , HOW to Avoid Speaking: Denials, in: C O W A R D - F O S H A Y , 7 4 - 1 4 2 .
4 See my essay 'The Apophatic Way of Gregory of Nyssa' in this collection.
84 Ivana Noble Apophatic Elements in Derrida's Deconstruction 85

treating deconstruction as yet another approach claiming to give access to with the 'proper', the 'distinguished', the 'literal', the 'exclusively clean', 7

a more certain (non-)knowledge. It will be argued that - perhaps, similarly to which contrasts with the always changing living speech.
Gregory of Nyssa - Derrida attempts to challenge the claims to possibilities Deconstruction has as its main target the logic of identity, which is derived
of any final and unchangeable determination of meaning and truth in our from Aristotle. It consists of three laws: (i) the law of identity: whatever is,
language about the world in which we live, about ourselves or even about is; (ii) the law of contradiction: nothing can both be and not be; and (iii) the
God. This will give me a base on which to examine Derrida's explicit relation law of exclusion: everything must either be or not be. This logic of identity,
8

to the apophatic tradition and to which aspects of apophatic thinking are to be according to Derrida, lies at the heart of Western metaphysics and its main
found in Derrida's deconstruction, which ones he distances himself from, and fault is that it approaches life as a theory, where everything can be fitted into
which ones are missing, and thus where a Christian theologian employing the prescribed categories. Derrida claims that the logic o f identity is an
Derrida's method has to rely on other sources. exclusivist system disregarding differences and depriving life of creative
power. It treats reality as static, homogeneous, logically coherent and
essentially simple. The whole dualist metaphysical vocabulary is, according
to Derrida, a result of the process of excluding the different. Concepts like
2. Two targets of Derrida's deconstruction
sensible-intelligible, ideal-real, internal-external, fiction-truth, na-
ture-culture, speech-writing, activity-passivity, etc. propose that there is
Where does Derrida's concept of deconstruction come from? What is it
a fixed 'objective' structure of reality, which does not change. Such credulity,
related to? These are the main questions of this part. In order to be able to
according to him, has to be deconstructed. Then a creative unboundedness of
answer these questions I have at least to sketch a development of his thinking.
reality can be rediscovered, where the different is no longer excluded or
Derrida's early period of writings is strongly influenced by the rigor of
imprisoned in fixed metaphysical rules. For this purpose he introduces the
phenomenological analysis. His first two works are directly dedicated to
notion of differance. This neologism attempts to combine the two meanings
Husserl; an 'Introduction' to Husserl'sZ 'Origine de la geometrie (1962) and
of the French verb differer - to 'differ' and to 'defer'. Derrida's differance
La Voix et le phenomene: Introduction au probleme du signe dans la
points to the 'finitude of reason' and 'the permanent impossibility of absolute
phenomenologie de Husserl (1967). In the same year he published two other
5
knowledge'. Concerning the differance, Derrida goes back to Saussure's
9
works, a collection of essays L'Ecriture et la difference {Writing and
structuralist theory, where "language in its most general form could be
Difference), and De la grammatologie (Of Grammatology). In these writings
understood as a system of differences, 'without positive terms' ." Saussurian 10
we can trace the roots of Derrida's deconstruction. He approaches themes of
analysis brings Derrida to the recognition of an "unconceptualisable [sic!]
violence in metaphysics, representation and misrepresentation, assumptions
dimension" i n language. Lechte concludes: "Difference without positive
of rationally structured meaning and the radicality of metaphorical language.
terms implies that this dimension in language must always remain unper-
His deconstruction starts in literary criticism. He sees language as radically
ceived, for strictly speaking, it is unconceptualisable. With Derrida,
metaphorical, deprived of any literal meaning and claims that we have to do
difference becomes the proto-type of what remains outside the scope of
away with any idea that a text discloses any single truth value which is there
Western metaphysical thought... Difference is not an identity [we can add, not
to be discovered: "The 'rationality' - but perhaps that word should be
even a negative identity]; nor is it the difference between two identities.
abandoned ... inaugurates the deconstruction, not the demolition but the de-
Difference is difference deferred." 11
sedimentation, the de-construction, of all the significations that have their
source in that of logos. Particularly the signification of truth.'''' Concentration
6

on logos led to logocentrism, the 'impurity' of writing, to the preoccupation 7 Cf. G . C . SPIVAK, 'Translator's Preface' to Derrida's O f Grammatology, 1976,
lxxxiii-lxxxiv.
8Cf. B . R U S S E L L , The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford 1973,40.
9 Cf. M. W E S T P H A L , J.M. M A R S H , J.D. C A P U T O , Modernity and Its Discontents, New

In English translation: Speech and Phenomena and Other Essays on Husserl's Theory
5
York 1992, xiii.
of Signs, Evaston (111.) 1973. J. L E C H T E , Fifty Key Contemporary Thinkers, London, New York 1994, 107.
10

J. D E R R I D A , Of Grammatology, Baltimore, London 1976, 10.


6
11 L E C H T E , 107.
86 Ivana Noble Apophatic Elements in Derrida '.v Deconslruction 87

John D. Caputo explains Derrida's differance in terms of meaning as 'an between presence and absence in Derrida's terms is not grasped in an
effect produced by the spacing between signifiers', and points out that 'the immediate experience, but in a reflective reconstitution of presence. We posit
'system' of such meanings is not a system, does not close over, but remains presence through an interpretation, through a fiction about it, where an
in a permanently open-ended condition'. Differance 'makes it possible both original lack of something makes possible an appreciation of its presence.
to say something and impossible to nail it down definitively, decidedly.' 12 And on the other hand, presence provides us with a permanent destruction of
Caputo puts it as follows: such fictions and their principles. 17

Paul Ricoeur states that deconstruction as opposed to identity faces the


"We never get a chance to write from on high, we never win the transcendental high ground.
We write from below, slowly and painfully forging unities of meaning from the flow of problem, "but what about absolute difference?"; for deconstruction as
signifiers... unities about which we keep our fingers crossed that they will get us through the opposed to presence, the problem is, "but what about [the] impossibility to
day. We are always inside and outside truth, unable to stop the rush of truth, yet unable, too, 'recognize the same'?" He asks further, "Can deconstruction be identified or
to hold truth in place and stop its rushing off." 13 presented!" He points out that there is no way of answering the question of
'what do you mean' by deconstruction, and no way to 'experience' decon-
Derrida's emphasis on not reducing language to the identity of its concepts
struction. "Deconstruction has to be deconstructed reflexively," says Ricoeur,
is attractive; however, this also means that words do not have any sharp
and contrasts it with positions, that built a system on the initial critique they
boundaries, they can become circular, which makes communication incredibly
represented. Thus, deconstruction is not nihilism, atheism, meaninglesness or
difficult. Here is the vulnerability of Derrida's approach: when the fixed
pure vacuity, as a Buddhist approach might propose. The question of the
objective structure of reality is gone, the conceptualisable truth is deconstruc-
degree to which it can be compared to apophatic thinking remains open. If as
ted, what is left? Gregory of Nyssa, like Derrida, argued for an awareness that
I want to propose in the following section it can be so compared, Ricoeur
language can never grasp the essence of things, yet we can acknowledge 14
says, "then it is constructed by the love of God and our love to God." lg
things in their effects. Derrida's deconstruction is left with the problem of
15

missing reference. Both Gregory and Derrida emphasized the constant striving
and straining of humankind on the never-ending journey, yet for Gregory this
is a never-ending journey towards God, while this is absent in Derrida. 4. Derrida on Apophaticism
Derrida's deconstruction is, in the final analysis, addressed to a 'metaphy-
sics of presence'. Presence is perceived as particular and temporal. Derrida When we deal with Derrida's relation to apophaticism, we have to be aware
speaks about 'positing' presence in events. He points out, however, that that he does not make a distinction between the Eastern apophasis and the
events have a paradoxical structure. Jonathan Culler presents Derrida's view Western via negativa. He uses the concepts as synonymous and places them
in the following way: "for presence to function as it is said to, it must have the under the one heading of negative theology. Thus, his references to negative
19

qualities that supposedly belong to its opposite, absence." The difference 16


theology are relevant for the analysis of his explicit relation to the apophatic
tradition as well. His most detailed consideration of the subject is contained
12 J . D . C A P U T O , On Being Inside/Outside Truth, in: M A R S H - C A P U T O - W E S T P H A L , 51 f.
in his essay 'How To Avoid Speaking: Denials'. But his relation to the
20

13 C A P U T O , 52.
apophatic tradition (negative theology) as a question has been with him for
14 In the previous essay on Gregory of Nyssa's apophaticism this position was described some considerable time. Already in his essay 'Differance' (1968) he gives
in three steps. First, Gregory argues that no single human word (or combination of them) can
hope to grasp the essence of God. Second, and perhaps even more relevant for comparison
with Derrida, Gregory points out that in fact it is doubtful if any human word can fully
express the essence of a thing. Finally, he denies that unbegottenness, uncreatedness, 17For a relationship between deconstruction and negative theology in Derrida see
ungeneratedness, is the most adequate way to name God. Cf. L . K A R F I K O V A , Rehof z Nyssy H. COWARD, T. F O S H A Y (eds.), Derrida and Negative Theology, Albany (N.Y.) 1992.
[Gregory of Nyssa], Praha 1999,279. 18In a personal communication from P A U L R I C O E U R , November 3rd 2001.
15 Gregory applies this primarily to our knowing God, we cannot know God in his 19For the terminological confusion, see D E R R I D A , How to Avoid Speaking: Denials,
essence (ouoia), but what we can do is to acknowledge God's effects (evepyeiai). 74-76.
16 i . C U L L E R , On Deconstruction - Theory and Criticism after Structuralism, London 20 The French version of this essay,' Comment ne pas parler: Delegations', first appeared
1983,95. in D E R R I D A ' S Psyche: Inventions de l'autere, Paris 1987, 535-595.
88 lvana Noble Apophatic Elements in Derrida's Deconstruction 89

a considerable account of why his work is close to negative theology and yet negate; you affirm nothing." This objection leads to charges, justified or
cannot be identified with any form of it: unjustified, of nihilism and atheism; (ii) You speak for nothing, "only for the
"So much so that the detours, locutions, and syntax in which I will often have to take sake of speaking, in order to experience speech." Here Derrida says that to
recourse will resemble those of negative theology, occasionally even to the point of being experience speech itself is not saying nothing, and nor is speaking to no one;
indistinguishable from negative theology. Already we have to delineate that differance is (iii) It leads to the negative manifestation of God. "[F]rom the moment the
not, does not exist, is not present-being (on) in any form; and we will be led to delineate also proposition takes a negative form, the negativity that manifests itself need
everything that it is not, that is, everything; and consequently that it has neither existence only be pushed to the limit," and the hyperessentiality of God is reestablished,
nor essence. It derives from no category of being, whether present or absent. And yet those
"Every negative sentence would already be haunted by God or by the name of
aspects of differance which are thereby delineated are not theological, not even in the order
of the most negative of negative theologies, which as one knows are always concerned with God." An "inversion has always already taken place ... in order to say that
disengaging a hyperessentiality beyond the finite categories of essence and existence, that divinity is not produced but productive." This third objection captures most
26

is, of presence, and always hastening to recall that God is refused the predicate of existence, of Derrida's attention. He says that when the apophatic discourse is analysed
only to acknowledge His superior, inconceivable, and ineffable mode of being." 21
in its
From here onwards Derrida charges negative theology with attempts to "logico-grammatical form... it perhaps leads us to consider the becoming-theological of all
reestablish yet even stronger form of hyperessentiality by means of a negative discourse. [...] God would be not merely the end, but the origin of this work of the negative.
definition, something, which can be already seen with Eunomius's attempt to Not only would atheism not be the truth of negative theology; rather, God would be the truth
of all negativity. One would thus arrive at a kind of proof of God - not a proof of existence
find a name for God which is descriptive of divine essence. In spite o f 22
of God, but a proof of God by His effects, or more precisely a proof of what one calls God,
criticisms from Jean-Luc Marion, of which Derrida gives a detailed account,
23
or of the name of God, by effects without cause, by the without cause." 21

he does not change his position, and in his later essay 'How To Avoid
Speaking: Denials' gives the folloving definitions of the negative theology: And it is here where Derrida distances himself from the apophatic
(negative) theology: "No, what I write is not 'negative theology'." Yet, this 28
"Under the very loose heading of 'negative theology' as you know, one often designates
refusal springs from a similar insight to that of Gregory when he sought to
a certain form of language, with its mise en scene, its rhetorical, grammatical, and logical
modes, its demonstrative procedures - in short a textual practice attested or rather situated refute Eunomius' arguments. The negative can prove as rigid a determiner as
'in history', although it does sometimes exceed the predicates that constitute this or that the positive - what we cannot say about God being as limiting and destructive
concept of history." 24 as any positive theology. Derrida is unwilling to accept a place among the
negative theologians i f that means accepting that the 'not-saying' of God is
A couple of lines further on he states that, although there is not one single
simply a variant on the 'saying' of God. For, in his reading of Dionysius and
negative theology, but a variety of different ones, they still have in common
Meister Eckhart, but also of Augustine, he finds repeated reference to
a 'rhetoric of negative determination' considering that "every predicative
'hyperessentiality', to being beyond being. But such reference is not so
29
language is inadequate to the essence, in truth to the hyperessentiality (the
much subverting a positive theology as replacing i t . ' Hyperessentiality' is still
being beyond Being) of God," and consequently claim that "only a negative
fundamentally an ontological statement, one which is rooted firmly within
('apophatic') attribution can claim to approach God, and to prepare us for
a neo-Platonic metaphysics. The problem is not solved, merely transposed.
a silent intuition of God." Then, Derrida lists three types of usual objections
25
Derrida also refers to more contemporary discourses resembling the one of
against "everything that resembles negative theology": (i) "You prefere to
negative theology, to Wittgenstein and Heidegger in particular. Derrida
21 J . D E R R I D A , Differance, in: Margins of Philosophy, Chicago 1 9 8 2 , 6 . (French original
came out in 1 9 6 8 ) .
2 6 lb id, 75-77.
2 2 Cf. G R E G O R Y OF N Y S S A , Contra Eunomium libriletll. Ed. W . J A G E R , G N O I I , Leiden Ibid, 76.
27

1960, 3 - 3 1 1 , 1 . 6 7 3 , 1 1 . 3 .
lb id, 7 7 .
28

23 Cf. J . - L . M A R I O N , L'idole et la distance: cinq etudes, Paris 1977, 318; quoted by 29See D E R R I D A , op. cit., 7 8 - 8 1 . It is interesting that Derrida does not refer to the
D E R R I D A in How to Avoid Speaking: Denials, footnote 2 on p. 132. apophatic tradition before Dionysius, where more common features would be found. He
24 D E R R I D A , HOW to Avoid Speaking: Denials, 7 3 . confesses his fascination with negative theology (p. 82), but persistently refuses to be
2 5 D E R R I D A , op. cit. 14. associated with it.
90 Ivana Noble Apophatic Elements in Derrida's Deconstruction 91

recalls the end of Wittgenstein's Tractatus: "The inexpressible, indeed, God's revelation, a place of human prayer. But whether such a place is
exists. It shows itself; it is the mystical" and "Concerning that about which possible, Derrida leaves as an open question. 35

one cannot speak, one must remain silent." Derrida examines the necessity
30 Here another term of Derrida's comes into play, that of'denegation', which
Wittgenstein speaks about, the necessity of 'the trace', as Derrida puts it, is sometimes translated into English as 'denial', but which is perhaps best left
a trace in speech, a promise for future when "one must speak" of "what is as as 'denegation'. The French term (a translation of the German Verneinung)
yet unpresentable." Wittgenstein provokes Derrida to give an account of his
31 operates as an affirmative of negation, or a double movement of negation.
silence in the face of this promise. Derrida states that "this promise is older This is for him an unconscious movement prior to speech or action, as well
than I am," it is a "destination toward speech, this silence yet remains as a conscious movement within speech. Until the unconscious motivation for
a modality of speech: a memory of promise and a promise of memory." But 32 our words and deeds is felt, they remain un-words and un-deeds. With the
then, there is Derrida's somewhat odd conclusion: motivation, we can become conscious of them, though always as past or
'"how to avoid speaking' since I have already started to speak and have always already future.
started to promise to speak? That I have already started to speak, or rather that at least the It is in this context that Derrida understands negative theology. It both
trace of speech will have preceded this very speech, one cannot deny. Translate: one can constitutes a form of theology, a conscious movement within speech towards
only deny it. There can only be denial of what is undeniable."" a clearer explication or (not-)speaking about God, but at the same time it
Thus, we are left with a response as a kind of a response to a provocation deconstitutes that theology, by the unconscious recognition of the impossibili-
or to being asked to do an impossible task. And yet there are ways in which ty of the task it has set itself. To arrive at an understanding of God, to have
Derrida does want to retain something of the insight of negative theology, knowledge of God is necessarily to see in God the incomprehensible, the
precisely of the unspeaking of God which it at least implies: hence the title of unknowable. It is to become aware of the lack of understanding and igno-
his essay. In other words, at stake for him is not so much the negative rance.
understanding, a negative epistemology or metaphysics to substitute Derrida also raises the question about which 'place', which ground, one
a previous more positive one. Instead, he is interested in not-saying, in how avoids speaking from. Is it because one wants to keep a secret? Or is it
it is possible to not-speak God, in what precedes such not-speaking. because one does not have the secret, that in a way what is expected to be
Does it mean, then, that Derrida argues for a kind of metaphysics of uncovered is still found as hidden? Or is it because of holding on to the secret
silence, which would take him back to where he started with his critique of that there is no secret? He states that his place is not that of Greek or Christian
the metaphysics of presence? He addresses this issue, when dealing with the tradition of negative theology, but, i f anything, then that of Jewish and Islamic
contribution of Heidegger. Heidegger's What is Metaphysics, Derrida argues, thought. But he does not want to thematize this place:
36

can be read as an example of a negative discourse. Heidegger, according to "I thus decided not to speak of the negativity or of apophatic movements in, for example,
him, points out the strangeness of what is as the wholly other, of what the Jewish or Islamic traditions. To leave this immense place empty ...was this not the most
transcends Dasein. But Heidegger does not solve the problem of how to avoid
speaking of Being. Derrida writes that Heidegger claims that a certain
'topology of Being' is necessary, which can help us to avoid 'objectifying 35 Cf. M. H E I D E G G E R , Einfiihrung in die Metaphysik, Tubingen 1953: 50-51. D E R R I D A ,
representation', including a negative objectifying representation. Even 34
op. cit. 123-131.
God's essence cannot be expressed by means of Being, and faith has no need 36 Cf. D E R R I D A , op. cit., 100. In a footnote he raises the question as to why does he hide
to do so. Faith has a need of a place where one can encounter God, a place of himself behind the 'negative theology of others' and admits: "[I]f one day I had to tell my
story, nothing in this narrative would start to speak of the thing itself if I did not come up
against this fact; for the lack of capacity, competence, or self-authorization, I have never yet
30 L . WITTGENSTEIN, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London 1990, 6.552 and 7. been able to speak of what my birth, as one says, should have made closest to me: the Jew,
the Arab." (Footnote 13, p.135) In his later biographical commentary Derrida emphasizes
31 D E R R I D A , op. cit., 81.
especially the background of Judaism, see Jacques Derrida par Geoffrey Bennington et
32 Ibid, 84-85.
Jacques Derrida, Mars 1991. This theme was developed by U L R I C H E N G E L ' S paper
33 Ibid, 86.
' Religiose (Nicht-)Identitat' at the 3rd International L E S T Congress hold in November 6-9
3 4 See D E R R I D A , op. cit. 125. 2001 in Leuven, which will be published by Leuven University Press.
92 Ivana Noble Apophatic Elements in Derrida's Deconstruction 93

consistent possible apophasis? Concerning that about which one cannot speak, isn't it the God, and i f we never arrive it is because the not arriving is part of our
best to remain silent?" 37
(un)knowing of who God is. This is what gives hope, since God is always
God, close and infinitely other, and i f our journey is never-ending, it also
means that ultimately no obstacle can stand in our way. The apophatic way as
found in the Fathers has the need of conversion at its heart, which is explicit
5. Conclusion in its inclusion of thoughts, words as well as deeds. It gives space to
anamnesis, the living memory, which we posit in tradition and which helps
This essay has, I hope, demonstrated that Derrida is in some senses dealing
us to interpret our experience, and its reference is participatory, perhaps in the
with similar kinds of questions to these of apophatic theology and responds
sense, which Derrida criticised, that it takes God as the beginning and the end
to them with remarkably similar probings to those I pointed out in my essay
of all our activity, of all our living and moving and resting. Such apophati-
'The Apophatic Way in Gregory of Nyssa' presented in this collection. Yet
cism also gives space to the symbolic kataphatic theology as a complement
Derrida rejects apophatic (negative) theology as he sees it as hyperessential.
of the apophatic critique, making it possible to acknowledge God in his
It reestablishes and strengthens the order it puts into question, perhaps in
effects. Derrida's deconstruction is left with the problem of missing reference.
a similar fashion to Eunomius's negative names of God, such as unbegotten,
Although, he also emphasizes the constant striving and straining of human-
uncreated or ungenerated, which in the end become the absolute names o f
kind on the never-ending journey, this journey is not given a direction and an
God, giving access to divine essence. What Derrida does not reflect is the
aim, not even from a Jewish and Islamic perspective. Here Ricoeur's remark,
critique of the hyperessentiality of the negative approach to be found in the
that i f deconstruction was to be compared with apophatic thinking, it would
apophatic tradition itself. His rejection of apophaticism is motivated by
need to be rooted in the love of God, is relevant. For an explicit recognition
similar reasons to those we find in the apophatic tradition of the Fathers, of
of that, a theologian who searches in Derrida for inspiration has to rely on
which Gregory is a striking example. Derrida is in agreement with this
other sources.
tradition in his emphasis on the impossibility of grasping the essence of
Finally, as I noted at the beginning, Derrida confuses the Western and the
things, including the essence of God, in the stress on permanent movement,
Eastern approaches, the via negativa and the aphophasis. His method o f
on things being always in process, and on our participation in this process,
deconstruction does indeed resemble some of the pre-Dionysian apophatic
which cannot be reduced to either positive or negative speaking.
emphases. But apophaticism offers much more than a speculative approach
Yet, for all that, there is a clear divide between the two. This divide is not
to the unspoken, than a side way to the ungraspable. It is a way of ongoing
given by the hyperessentiality or non-hyperessentiality of the approach, but
conversion, rather than of resting in a static image of reality and of God,
simply by the problem of reference. Derrida attempts to substitute the empty
38
whether positively or negatively defined.
space between the signifiers for reference, yet it does not open up equal
possibilities. As I pointed out in my essay on Gregory, the latter refuses to
reduce God to any name, even to that of 'unbegottenness' or 'ungenerated-
ness' (and today we might replace those terms with little damage to the
integrity of Gregory's thought by the concept of 'Being'). He allows God to
remain God, infinite, transcendent, incomprehensible. Yet it is precisely this
God whom we are able to encounter on our journey, who reveals himself to
us, in whom we live and move and have our being. He is a God of history, too,
beyond yet within, and human response to this God is a response which must
therefore be rooted within history. It is as human beings that we approach

3 7 D E R R I D A , op. cit., 122.


1 think that MARION'S critique of Derrida's accounts of hyperessentiality is justified.
38

See note 23.

You might also like