Desinterstedness and Desire in Kant's Aesthetics

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

Disinterestedness and Desire in Kant's Aesthetics

Author(s): Paul Guyer


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 36, No. 4 (Summer, 1978), pp. 449-
460
Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/430485
Accessed: 11/11/2008 19:13

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

The American Society for Aesthetics and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.

http://www.jstor.org
PAUL GUYER

Disinterestedness
and Desire
in Kants Aesthetics

SOME PHILOSOPHICAL THEORIES arouse our spatial and temporal forms of things, as
suspicion because of the nature of their opposed to both such material properties of
arguments, even though their conclusions objects as their color or tone as well as such
do not actually conflict with widely held be- more abstract properties as their content,
liefs. Thus, for instance, Descartes's method meaning, or conceptual significance. This
of clear and distinct ideas concludes by war- opinion conflicts with such natural beliefs
ranting a fairly ordinary set of empirical as that the beauty of a sunset lies in its
beliefs, but because of such problems as magnificent display of colors, or that of a
the obscurity of its criterion for clearness Pieta in its deep expression of emotion. If
and distinctness and its foundation in argu- Kant's basic principles really do conflict
ments for the existence of a non-deceitful with such intuitions, then his theory of taste
God, it can hardly persuade us to accept surely would merit our suspicion.
those beliefs. Some theories, however, suffer Kant's interpretation of the disinterested-
in our estimation because, quite apart from ness of judgments of taste also discourages
the plausibility of their foundational con- our serious consideration of his theory. Kant
cepts and arguments, or even despite such asserts that such judgments - judgments
plausibility, their conclusions conflict with that particular objects are beautiful - and
well-entrenched beliefs and intuitions. the experiences on which they are based are
Kant's theory of aesthetic judgment, at least free of any connection to interest, either
as traditionally interpreted, is such a theory. antecedent to or consequent upon the judg-
To be sure, his Critique of Judgmentl has ment. That is, aesthetic judgments must not
had many admirers and much influence. only be made independently of any prior
But a generally favorable appreciation of interest in the existence of their objects, but
the basic theory of this work has been hin- "also in themselves ground no interest at
dered, I think, by the fact that some of its all" (?2, 205n.). And this seems a damning
most prominent conclusions are apparently conclusion. It may be true that, as Kant
in profound conflict with some of our most says, "One must not be in the least pre-
widely held views about the nature and possessed in favor of the existence of a
significance of our experience of natural thing, but must be quite indifferent in this
beauty and artistic accomplishment. regard, in order tol play the part of a judge
Thus, Kant took it to be a key conclusion in matters of taste" (?2, 205). It is cer-
of his theory of taste that the only proper tainly true that if one is already disposed in
objects of aesthetic appreciation are the favor of an object for a reason such as its
monetary value or a personal attachment
PAUL GUYER is assistant professor of philosophy at to its creator, one cannot make a fair assess-
the University of Pittsburgh. ment of its aesthetic merits without ignor-
450 GU Y ER

ing these dispositions; and it may sometimes Such doctrines as that only form is aes-
be the case that one cannot ignore them, thetically significant, that beauty can gen-
and so cannot make a fair judgment of erate no interest, and that natural beauty
taste. But that the beauty of an object can- is more significant than artistic beauty, pro-
not engender a genuine desire or concern duce much of our discomfort with Kant's
for it, for further experience of it, for its aesthetics. In fact, however, a proper inter-
maintenance and preservation, even, cir- pretation of Kant's basic theory of aesthetic
cumstances permitting, for ownership of it response and judgment can show that some
- in short, an interest in it - is absurd. of Kant's most disagreeable beliefs - in-
Rather, we all assume that the beauty of cluding those just mentioned - are not
an object is one of the best reasons we could really consequences of it at all. In some
have for taking an interest in it, and we cases, such as that of Kant's formalist pref-
justify a wide range of desires and activ- erence of design to color or composition to
ities - such as wanting to visit museums, tone (?14, 225), his opinions are in no way
travelling to do so, and spending money to direct consequences of his theory, whatever
gain admission to them - simply by ref- he himself may have thought. In others,
erence to the beauty (or other aesthetic such as the case of the thesis that aesthetic
merits) of objects. If Kant's theory of taste judgment can create no interest, the actual
is in fundamental conflict with this, surely consequences of Kant's theory are not quite
it must be wrong. what they appear to be, nor quite what he
Nor do our difficulties with Kant's theory takes them to be.
of disinterestedness end with its apparent Obviously, I cannot demonstrate all of
denial that the experience of beauty can this in a single paper.2 This article will be
have any direct effect on our desires, or confined to one problem in Kant's theory
generate any interest in the existence of of the disinterestedness of aesthetic judg-
beautiful objects. For in attempting to ment. I will argue that if Kant's thesis that
compensate for his exclusion of any direct the judgment of beauty itself grounds no
connection between the judgment of taste interest in its object is interpreted so as to
and any interest in the existence of beauti- conflict with our ordinary beliefs about the
ful things with a theory of an indirect at- reasonable consequences of aesthetic experi-
tachment between the two, Kant only com- ence, then it does not actually follow from
mits another assault on our beliefs, this time Kant's theory of aesthetic judgment, but
our beliefs about the significance of art. He that if, by means of a special Kantian no-
grounds an indirect and "intellectual" inter- tion of "interest," it is understood so as to
est in beauty on an analogy between aes- follow from Kant's basic theory, then it
thetic response and moral feeling, by means does not actually conflict with our usual
of practical reason's interest in the existence beliefs about interest in beauty. To put the
of objects conforming to the conditions of point another way, Kant's explanation of
our wholly disinterested delight, and then aesthetic response does imply that we can-
maintains that this foundation justifies not take a certain form of interest in beauti-
interest in the beauty of nature but not of ful objects, but this does not mean that we
art. This conclusion is expressed in his be- must look beyond the phenomenon of aes-
lief that "virtuosi of taste are not merely thetic response itself to explain our desires
often, but rather customarily, vain, selfish, with respect to natural and artistic beauty.
and given to injurious passions," and thus In fact, far from precluding such desires,
"interest in the beautiful of art . . . affords Kant's own explanation of our pleasure in
no proof of a manner of thinking attached the beautiful shows why they arise, and that
or even inclined to the morally good," is one of its great virtues.
whereas "an immediate interest in the My claim, then, is that, in the only sense
beauty of nature is always a mark of a good in which it does follow from his theory of
soul," and thus a sound basis for an intellec- taste, Kant's thesis that the judgment of
tual interest (?42, 298). beauty grounds no interest in its object is
Disinterestedness and Desire 451

not incompatible with the supposition that the beginning of the Second Moment,
the experience of beauty can naturally and where he argues that if anyone is conscious
directly generate certain desires with respect that his delight in an object is without any
to beautiful objects. Thus, it is simply not interest, he "cannot but estimate [the ob-
necessary for Kant to resort to a theory of ject] except as containing a ground of de-
indirect and "intellectual" interest in beauty light for everyone." More specifically,
to explain such desires, and his claim that . . . since the delight is not grounded on any
natural but not artistic beauty can generate inclination of the subject (nor on any other con-
such an interest may be ignored. But even sidered interest), but rather the judging subject
if it is not - even if Kant's basic theory of feels himself completely free with respect to the
aesthetic response can be supplemented by delight that he directs to the object, he can find
no private conditions, to which his own subject
a theory of a further intellectual or moral alone might be party, as ground for his delight,
interest in beauty - it can also be shown and consequently must regard it as grounded in
that his distinction between natural and that which he may presuppose in everyone . . .
artistic beauty in this regard is unjustified; Accordingly he will speak of the beautiful as if
on Kant's own account, paradigmatic cases beauty were a property of the object . . . (?6,
211).
of artistic beauty have just as much claim
to our intellectual interest as cases of nat- But while it is quite plausible to suppose
ural beauty. As this point can only be made that if one cannot find any private grounds
with an excursus into Kant's theory of for one's pleasure in an object, one will take
genius, however, its treatment must be re- that pleasure to be publicly valid, this para-
served for another occasion.3 graph does not employ a plausible concept
of interest. It simply equates interest with
I any partial or private ground for delight.
Does the disinterestedness of aesthetic The requirement that aesthetic judgment
judgment entail that the experience of a be disinterested is then trivial, for it is
beautiful object can create no interest in merely equivalent to the requirement that
its existence? Kant's discussion of disinter- it be intersubjectively valid. No inde-
estedness in the First Moment of the Ana- pendent criterion of disinterestedness is
lytic of the Beautiful includes the assertion implied here.
of such a view. But this discussion is neither In ?2 of the First Moment, however, Kant
clear nor convincing; and when we support does offer a more informative account of
its contentions by the more powerful argu- disinterestedness. In this section, which he
ments of the Second Moment of the Ana- presents as the beginning of the argument
lytic and an appropriate definition of in- of the Analytic of the Beautiful, Kant de-
terest, we shall see that the thesis that aes- fines an interest as a kind of pleasure,
thetic judgment creates no interest in its namely any "delight which we connect with
object can have only limited force. the representation of the existence of an
Kant starts his analysis of taste with the object" - or, as it is sometimes translated,
"quality" of disinterestedness "because it is with the representation of the "real exist-
this which the aesthetic judgment on the ence" of an object (?2, 204) .4 Interest is
beautiful first regards" (?1, 203n.). It is not also more simply defined as "pleasure in the
clear that this remark actually offers a good existence of an object" (?41, 296). And
reason for beginning the analysis with dis- pleasure in the existence of an object is
interestedness, but it does suggest that con- contrasted with pleasure in the "mere repre-
sidering whether one's pleasure in a given sentation of it" (205). Apparenltly, then, an
object is interested or not is the first step to interested pleasure is pleasure in the actual
be taken in deciding whether or not that existence of an object, and a disinterested
feeling of pleasure licenses calling the ob- pleasure is pleasure in its mere representa-
ject beautiful, that is, in making a particu- tion, "no matter how indifferent I may be
lar judgment of taste. Kant displays the to the real existence of the object of this
criterial significance of disinterestedness at representation."
452 GU Y ER

Kant supports his claim that aesthetic distinction between existence and repre-
pleasure is disinterested with a traditional sentation, or some further analysis of in-
sort of example.5 Asked whether a palace terest, it cannot be clear that any pleasure
before me is beautiful, I might say no, on connected in any way with the actual ex-
the ground that I do not care for things istence of an object is an interest, or that
made merely to be gaped at, or that a good an interest is any kind of pleasure at all.
restaurant would please me more, or I might (Nothing in Kant's example necessitates
dismiss the building by condemning the defining interest as itself a kind of pleasure,
vanity of the great who exploit the popu- rather than as a kind of ground or reason
lace to build such things. However, all such for pleasure, which would be more
responses are irrelevant to the question of natural.) 6
beauty. Obviously, they manifest utilitarian The definition of interest as any delight
or moral concerns, rather than a purely connected with the existence of an object,
aesthetic concern with the beauty of the then, involves an obscure distinction be-
building itself. And according to Kant, each tween existence and representation and a
of the irrelevant replies manifests a concern vague conception of the connection between
with the real existence of the object rather pleasure and existence. If Kant's assertions
than with its mere representation. This is that pleasure in the beautiful is not found-
why they are irrelevant to aesthetic judg- ed on any interest, and that it creates none,
ment. The example seems meant to supply are based solely on the argument of ?2 -
evidence for interpreting interest as delight and both assertions are made by the end of
connected with real existence, and pleasure this section, which contains no more argu-
in the beautiful as delight connected with ment than what I have described - then
mere representation, as well as for the thesis their justification is far from clear.
that aesthetic judgment is disinterested. Kant's development of the theme of dis-
Kant's argument, however, is unconvinc- interestedness in the next two sections does
ing. While we all undoubtedly do find it not advance our understanding of either
intuitively correct to dismiss those replies just what the contrast between representa-
to the question of beauty which Kant sug- tion and real existence involves or just what
gests we reject, it is not obvious that any connection between pleasure and real ex-
contrast between existence and mere repre- istence must actually be proscribed in the
sentation must be our basis for doing so. case of taste. These sections contrast aes-
We may contrast the utility of an object thetic response with the two basic categories
with its beauty, or the moral justifiability of interested pleasure, the pleasure of sens-
of a building's having been built in the way ory gratification in agreeable objects (?3,
it was with the beauty of the structure that 207), and the pleasure of esteem or ap-
resulted, but it is not obvious that we must proval (?5, 210) of objects which are good
distinguish between existence and represen- either for something or in themselves (?4,
tation to make such distinctions. On the 207). Pleasure in the beautiful differs from
face of it, at least, distinguishing between mere pleasure in sensation because the for-
such properties as beauty and utility, or mer is disinterested and the latter is inter-
such interests as the aesthetic and the moral, ested. But the reason why mere sensory
is enough to explain Kant's example. gratification in the agreeable is interested,
Nor is it clear what Kant's distinction according to Kant, is that the object of
actually amounts to, or what it would mean such pleasure
for a kind of pleasure to be connected to through sensation excites a desire for objects of
representation rather than existence; it the same sort; thus, the delight presupposes not
certainly seems that our pleasure - our the mere judgment on such an object, but the
actually taking pleasure - in the beauty of relation of its existence to my condition, insofar
as [the latter] is affected by it (?3, 207).
the palace depends as much on its existence
as does any possible pleasure in its utility. No contrast with the beautiful is explicitly
Without either some further analysis of the made, but we can only infer that it, unlike
Disinterestedness and Desire 453

the agreeable, does not provoke such a de- existence of something. Indeed, one might
sire, and that it is disinterested for that suppose that just because pleasure in the
reason. This argument, however, is unsatis- good may be had through a "mere concept,"
factory for two reasons. First, it is not ob- it does not require the real existence of
vious that a delight in the existence of a anything.
particular object is identical with a desire Still, there is a link between pleasure and
for experience of further objects of the real existence in the case of the good. The
same sort, or even entailed by such a desire; concept of a good is the concept of a pos-
so it is not clear that the desire which Kant sible end, that is, something for the sake
describes as being aroused by the agreeable of which we might act. It thus implies "the
must be connected with an interest as he has relation of reason to (at least possible)
defined it. This argument does not clarify willing, and consequently contains a delight
the notion of taking pleasure in the ex- in the existence [Dasein] of an object or an
istence of something, nor does it establish action, that is, some interest" (?4, 207). The
that the pleasure in the beautiful is not concept of a good is a concept of a thing
such a pleasure. Secondly, insofar as it con- which offers some reason to will it, because
trasts pleasure in the beautiful and that in this concept either promises pleasure in its
the agreeable by reference to the fact that existence or represents it as morally desir-
the latter creates a desire for the existence able (in which case pleasure will follow
of certain objects, this section presupposes from willing it). But to will an object just
rather than proves that the experience of is to will its existence; to will is to try to
beauty does not provoke any such desire or actualize a concept. Thus, the concept of
interest. the good is connected to the notion of the
In ?3, then, Kant does not show that the existence of an object, and pleasure in a
pleasure in the beautiful presupposes no good is connected to its real existence,
interest in its object, and that it is not a either as an incentive for willing existence
pleasure in any way connected with the lat- or as a consequence of such willing. So
ter's existence. Nor does he actually prove pleasure linked to a concept of a good is
that either aesthetic experience or judgment connected to real existence as well, and is
can create no interest in the existence of an interest on Kant's definition.
objects. In ?4, Kant advances his case even But from this it simply does not follow
less. He contrasts the beautiful and the that when a feeling of pleasure cannot be
good by arguing that the latter pleases "by linked to an object by a mere concept, that
means of reason through a mere concept." pleasure is not connected in any way with
Thus, "to find something good, I must the real existence of the object, or that it is
always know what sort of thing the object not an interest. In the case of the good, a
should be, that is, have a concept of it"; prior promise of pleasure in the existence
but to find something beautiful, Kant as- of an object - given by a concept of it -
serts, no concept is necessary. Thus, he is a reason for willing its existence. If
maintains that an object can please as pleasure in the beautiful is not linked to
either useful or morally good only if it is its object by any such concept - which
subsumed under some concept (of use or is all that Kant asserts in ?4 - then no such
moral requirement), but that such beauti- promise may be given, and there may be no
ful things as "flowers, free drawings, . . . prior incentive for willing the existence of
[and] foliage signify nothing, depend on no a beautiful object, at least under any deter-
determinate concepts, and yet please" (?4, minate conceptualization or description of
207). The basic contrast which this section it. But this does not entail that pleasure
makes, in other words, turns on the factor in the beautiful does not depend in some
of connection to a concept rather than on way on the existence of its object. Nor does
connection to real existence. Yet it is surely it imply that once an object is found beau-
not evident that a pleasure which requires tiful, we cannot desire its continued exist-
a concept must be a pleasure in the real ence, and act toward this end - in an ordi-
454 GUYER

nary sense, take an interest in a beautiful beauty be founded on a feeling of pleasure


object. for which "universal subjective validity" -
Neither ?3 nor ?4, then, clearly estab- or intersubjective validity - can reasonably
lishes that pleasure in the beautiful is not be claimed, and argues that if our pleasure
connected with the existence of an object, in a beautiful object is explained as due to
nor that the experience of a beautiful ob- the fact that the manifold of sensibility
ject cannot create an interest in its exist- which it provides occasions a harmony be-
ence. Kant claims that interest or delight in tween imagination and understanding
real existence "always has relation to the without any determinate concept being
faculty of desire, either as its determining applied to the object, this condition will
ground or as necessarily connected with its be fulfilled. Kant first attempts to deduce
determining ground" (?2, 204), and so by the requirement of universal validity from
separating interest and aesthetic response the disinterestedness of aesthetic judgment
he clearly means to deny that the latter it- (?6, 211). Such an inference, however, is
self has any effect on the faculty of desire. either circular, if an interest is simply
But ?3 merely implies that the experience identical to any source of partiality, or in-
of a beautiful object does not create a de- valid, if interest is not so defined. More-
bsire for experience of a type of object, over, such an inference might also be
which does not entail that it can produce thought of as an attempt to derive norma-
no desire for the existence of the particular tive conclusions from factual premises.7 For
object actually experienced. And ?4 only these reasons, it is better to regard the
suggests that a beautiful object cannot be claim that aesthetic judgment requires in-
seen as desirable (or pleasurable) through tersubjective validity as a fundamental
the medium of a concept, which does not premise of Kant's theory, supported not by
imply that it must be without any effect at arguments within the theory, but by an
all on desire. extra-systematic appeal to what we all
The First Moment of the Analytic of the recognize to be the correct use of the lin-
Beautiful thus establishes no clear contrast guistic form ". . . is beautiful." Kant makes
such an appeal in ?7 (212-213); and in ?7,
between representation and real existence,
unlike ?2, Kant makes his appeal to our
nor does it prove that pleasure in the beau-
intuitions without the damaging introduc-
tiful has no interest as its consequence. In
tion of any such mechanism as his own
fact, if his discussion of disinterestedness is
contrast between representation and exist-
his true starting-point, then Kant's attempt
ence. I will assume that this condition on
to construct any aesthetic theory, let alone
judgments of taste is familiar, and turn to
one with counter-intuitive conclusions, is
Kant's explanation of aesthetic response as
doomed to failure. If, however, we take the
Second Moment rather than the First as a pleasure due to the harmony of our
higher cognitive faculties. It is on this
the basis of the Analytic, and treat the
aspect of Kant's theory that the interpre-
thesis of disinterestedness as a consequence
tation of disinterestedness as anything more
rather than as a premise of Kant's theory
than mere impartiality must depend, and
of aesthetic response, two gains will result.
from which any explanation of the disin-
First, we will then be able to see how the
requirement that aesthetic judgment be terestedness of aesthetic response must
emerge.
disinterested can in fact be defended. Sec-
ondly, we will also see just how limited Kant's explanation of pleasure in the
beautiful is founded on a general theory of
the force of Kant's claim that such a judg-
ment creates no interest must be. pleasure according to which the "attain-
ment of every aim is accompanied with a
II feeling of pleasure" (vi, 187; cf. ?22, 242),
but which also supposes that such pleasure
In the Second Moment, Kant both lays is actually felt only when the attainment
down the requirement that a judgment of of the objective in some way appears con-
Disinterestedness and Desire 455

tingent rather than necessary (188). The "the cognitive faculties, which are set into
First Introduction to the Critique of Judg- play by [a given] representation, are here
ment suggests how this general theory is in a free play, since no definite concept re-
applied to the case of aesthetic response. stricts them to a definite rule of cognition"
In any act of judgment, the faculties of (?9, 217). Kant applies the term "free" to
imagination and understanding are united. the imagination alone as well as to the har-
Ordinarily, their connection is objective, mony between imagination and understand-
and is recognized in the application of a ing; thus, the conclusion of the Analytic
concept to an object. But we may also con- describes taste as a "faculty for estimating
sider the relationship between these two an object in relation to the free lawfulness
cognitive faculties from a merely subjective [Gesetzmdssigkeit]of the imagination" (?22,
point of view, or notice "how one helps or 240).
hinders the other in [a given] representa- Two points must be noted about this ex-
tion, and thereby affects one's mental state"; planation of aesthetic response. First, while
in this case, Kant maintains, the relation it links pleasure to the absence of constraint
between imagination and understanding is by a concept, the imagination is not free of
sensible [empfindbar] (FI, 223). To con- all constraints whatever. Kant's theory is
nect this with Kant's theory of pleasure, that the imagination and understanding are
and explain why it is in fact a feeling of disposed to the state of harmony by the
pleasure which manifests a harmony be- manifold presented by an object, or, specifi-
tween our cognitive faculties, we may define cally, by the form of an object. As Kant
our objective in the use of these faculties argues, it is when
in two ways: objectively, as finding a con-
the imagination (as the faculty of intuitions a
cept for a given object, or subjectively, as priori) is unintentionally set into harmony with
finding the subjective condition for the the understanding (as the faculty of concepts)
application of a concept, that is, as finding through a given representation, and a feeling of
unity in the manifolds apprehended by pleasure thereby aroused, [that] the object must
be regarded as final for the reflective judgment
sensibility and presented by imagination (vii, 190) .
to the understanding. Kant's theory of
pleasure then implies that we feel pleasure That is, when the representation of an ob-
when this latter goal of cognition is attained ject disposes the imagination and under-
in the absence of its ordinary guarantee, standing to a harmonious state of free
namely, the use of an empirical concept as play, we take pleasure in the beauty of that
a rule for unifying a manifold, and is thus object. This harmony is "unintentional," in
attained contingently. that it is not produced by following the
This is just what the First Introduction rule provided by a particular concept, but
describes as resulting, is otherwise similar to a normal state of
... if (even before it regards the comparison [of cognition. Thus, the harmony of the fac-
an object] with others), the judgment, which has ulties, like an ordinary cognitive state, does
no concept ready for the given intuition, unites depend upon a representation of an object,
the imagination (which merely apprehends the
or a manifold of sensibility, being furnished
object) with the understanding (which presents
a concept in general) and perceives a relation of to the mind. There is nothing in Kant's
the two cognitive faculties, which in general con- account to suggest that this manifold is not
stitutes the subjective, merely sensible condition furnished in the ordinary way - by the
of the objective use of judgment-namely, the effect of an external object on the faculty
harmony of the two faculties with each other of sensibility. The freedom of the imagina-
(FI, 223-224).
tion lies in its freedom from constraint by
This harmony produces pleasure because it concepts, and not in any freedom from the
is at least like the synthesis of a manifold, other usual circumstances of perception. In
though without a determinate concept, and this regard, aesthetic response is as depend-
is thus contingent. For the same reason, it ent upon the existence of an object as is
may also be called free. As Kant puts it, ordinary cognition. (Naturally, this account
456 G U Y ER

must be modified in order to accommodate claims that although pleasure in the beauti-
the judgment of objects of taste which are ful resembles
not ordinary physical objects or events,
. . . neither that from the pathological ground
such as literary works, and to take care of of agreeableness nor that from the intellectual
such judgments of taste as are made in the ground of represented good . . . still it has in-
course of the creation of works of art. In trinsic causality, namely, that of presenrving the
fact, Kant eventually shows how to make condition of representation itself and the occu-
such modifications, but not in his initial pation of the cognitive faculties without further
purpose (p. 12, 222).
exposition of his theory, where he takes as
paradigmatic the aesthetic judgment of Like any other pleasure, our response to
natural objects or else of such relatively the beautiful is accompanied with - in
concrete objects of art as paintings and fact, Kant writes as if it were identical-
particular musical performances.) with - a tendency to preserve the repre-
Secondly, there is nothing in Kant's ex- sentation which occasions it.
planation of our pleasure in the beautiful But if pleasure in the beautiful resembles
which entails that it differs from other cases other pleasures in this regard, in spite of its
of pleasure, except in the way in which it is various peculiarities, then several conclu-
aroused and in the intersubjective validity sions follow. First, while the faculty of de-
which it enjoys. Kant himself states that sire may not be involved in the origin of
the agreeable, the beautiful, and the good aesthetic response, this does not entail the
are not the objects of three different kinds conclusion that such response is without
of feelings, but rather only "denote three effect on desire. Rather, a tendency to pre-
different relations of representations to the serve a mental state will ordinarily mani-
feeling of pleasure and displeasure" (?5, fest itself as a kind of desire - namely, a
209-210). Pleasure has different objects be- desire to remain in a given condition. Thus,
cause it may be caused in different ways the very nature of aesthetic response as a
(by an object's physiological effect on the kind of pleasure, on Kant's own account,
senses, by its subsumption under a concept leads to its connection with desire. Further,
of the good or useful, or by its disposing if aesthetic response naturally produces a
the imagination and understanding to their desire for its own preservation, then it is
harmonious accord); but the feeling of also natural to think of it as leading to a
pleasure is always the same, and, at the most desire for at least the continued existence
general level, so is the form of its explana- of its object. For if the existence of a given
tion. Pleasure in the beautiful, like pleasure object is the condition of our having a
in any other object, is subject to Kant's representation or experience of it, then that
transcendental characterization8of pleasure, existence will be a condition of our enjoying
"in terms of the effect that the sensation of that representation. In that case, the tend-
our state produces on our mind" (APV, ency to preserve one's state of mind - the
?60, 231) .9 Thus, according to the Anthro- enjoyment - will certainly extend to the
pology, pleasure is "what directly prompts condition of that state of mind, or the de-
me to maintain [my] state (to remain in sire will extend to the existence of the ob-
it) ," or, in the words of the third Critique, ject; for if it is analytically true that to
it is "the consciousness of the causality of a will an end is to will the necessary means
representation in respect of the state of the to it (FMM, 417),1O then it should also be
subject as one tending to preserve that true that to desire an end is to desire the
state" (?10, 220). Indeed, Kant goes out means to it.11 But a desire for the continued
of his way to make it clear that this char- existence of an object we have found beau-
acterization applies to aesthetic response. tiful is certainly one thing we could mean
The Anthropology offers its explanation as by an interest in the beautiful; thus, the
subsuming both pleasure "through the fact that our response to beauty is pleasure
senses" and that "through imagination must itself lead to an interest in the con-
(taste)," and the Critique of Judgment tinued existence of its object.
Disinterestedness and Desire 457

If this is so, then Kant's explanation of ence of an object is an interest only when
aesthetic response entails rather than pre- that object can be represented as an object
cludes the creation of an interest in its of desire under some concept, and thus by
object. How could Kant deny this, let alone the faculty of reason.
conclude that the complete disinterestedness Adopting this definition of interest allows
of aesthetic response is actually a conse- us to interpret Kant's thesis of disinterested-
quence of his theory of aesthetic response? ness without denying either our intuitions
As long as we are confined to the definition about beauty or the implications of Kant's
of interest which Kant offers in the Critique own theory of pleasure. For on this defini-
of Judgment, there is no answer to this tion, Kant's explanation of aesthetic re-
question. If, however, we consider the defi- sponse does indeed imply that our pleasure
nition of interest employed in the Critique in the beautiful is neither an interest, nor
of Practical Reason, we can see that Kant's caused by an interest, nor the cause of an
denial of a consequent interest in beautiful interest. The key to Kant's theory is that
objects is entailed by his explanation of aesthetic response is free of the constraint
aesthetic response, although its significance of any determinate concept. Thus, it is not
is then not quite what it appears to be. produced by the subsumption of the mani-
fold under any determinate concept. More-
over, aesthetic judgment does not produce
III
any determinate concepts to which pleasure
In the second Critique, Kant defines an can be linked, or which can be used to
interest as "an incentive of the will so far promise pleasure. It is Kant's thesis that "in
as it is presented by reason" (CPR, 79). A their logical quantity all judgments of taste
"determining ground of the will," which on are singular judgments" (?8, 215), that is,
this definition is equivalent to an interest, is are valid only of the particular objects
similarly defined as "the conception of an which occasion them, in spite of whatever
object and its relation to the subject, where- general terms might occur in our expres-
by the faculty of desire is determined to seek sion of the judgment. If no classification of
its realization" (CPR, 21). Here, an in- an object by an empirical concept - for
terest is not itself a feeling of pleasure, but instance, "rose" - produces our pleasure in
rather a kind of concept of an object. A its beauty, then, Kant believes, we cannot
feeling of pleasure is, in a way, a possible connect "the predicate of beauty with the
incentive for the will, but for a will deter- concept of the object taken in its entire
mined by reason, the feeling of pleasure logical sphere," or infer that any other ob-
must be linked to a concept to serve as an ject properly identified as a rose, or sub-
incentive. sumed under any other determinate concept
Now, such an interest does preserve a applying to the given object, will share its
connection between pleasure and existence. beauty. But if an interest is a concept of an
A conception of an object promising pleas- object which presents it as an object of the
ure in its existence is one kind of incentive will, or promises pleasure, then we cannot
for the will, and as an incentive for the will, have an interest in the case of the beautiful.
such a conception leads to the willing of an No concept which can be applied to an
object's actual existence. But more im- object can promise that we will take pleas-
portantly, on this definition an interest is ure in its beauty, and no empirical concept
not just any pleasure connected with the applicable to it can be used to formulate
existence of an object, and not embodied an interest even subsequently to the ex-
in just any representation of an object perience of the given case.
which affects the faculty of desire. An in- The judgment of taste must be disinter-
terest in an object is present only when ested, because it is free of any dependence
there is a concept of it, by means of which on concepts, and an interest is nothing but a
pleasure or the expectation of pleasure can certain kind of concept of objects - which
be linked to it. And a desire for the exist- is to say, of a class of objects. This follows
458 GU Y ER

from coupling the second Critique's defi- which can act as an incentive for the will
nition of interest with Kant's explanation by promising pleasure in the existence of
of aesthetic response. Alternatively, we any object which falls under it, and if a
might now revise the third Critique's defi- pleasure which is produced by the effect
nition of interest as a kind of pleasure, classi- of the actual representation of an object
fying as an interest any pleasure in an ob- on the imagination and understanding can-
ject dependent on the subsumption of that not be predicted by the use of any prior
object under a determinate concept. We conceptual characterization of it, then no
could then see the true form of the require- such concept can be used to formulate an
ment that pleasure in the beautiful not be interest in beautiful objects. But a number
pleasure in the real existence of an object, of claims which might seem to follow from
but in its mere representation. This require- this do not. First, it does not follow that
ment would not preclude any connection pleasure in a beautiful object will not, like
between aesthetic response and the actual any other pleasure, produce a tendency
existence of an object, but only demand towards, or desire for, its own continuation.
that the existence of the object effect a feel- At best, it follows that the object of such a
ing of pleasure without having to be seen desire cannot be represented as desirable
as instantiating any particular concept. Aes- through a concept, but only through either
thetic response would have to derive from an intuition of it, or some definite descrip-
the mere contemplation of an object, not tion, formulated with general terms but
from the recognition that an object of a understood to refer only to the particular
certain sort exists or from the judgment that object. Secondly, if the physical existence
it is an object with a certain network of of a given object is indeed a condition of
causal and practical relations, consequences enjoying its representation - if, for in-
of its empirical actuality. That is, what stance, no adequate reproduction of objects
pleasure in the beautiful must be separated in a particular medium is possible - then
from is not existence itself, but the kinds of the disinterestedness of aesthetic judgment
judgments we typically make about the ex- does not preclude a perfectly natural desire
istence of objects. Such judgments, as well for the continuation of that object's exist-
as any pleasures they generate, require the ence. It only entails that such a desire is a
application of determinate concepts to their desire for the existence of a particular ob-
objects. But we must note that on this view ject (e.g., Leonardo's Last Supper), and not
the separation of disinterested pleasure a desire for it as an object of a given type
from real existence implies neither that aes- (paintings, or paintings of meals, or paint-
thetic response is not directed to an actually ings with a particular formal organization)
existent object nor incapable of producing - though that object will, of course, belong
any concern for such, but only that, unlike to many types. Finally, while it might be
both ordinary cognitive and practical re- the case that the independence of aesthetic
sponses, it requires no judgment about the response from the subsumption of its objects
existence and connections of its object. under any determinate concepts does pre-
The disinterestedness of aesthetic judg- clude the development of determinate con-
ment thus does not entail a total separation cepts - whether they be "rose" or "Haydn
of aesthetic pleasure and desire, but only the quartets" - which, in virtue of past ex-
independence of pleasure in beautiful ob- perience, can truly promise pleasure in any
jects from desires that can be attached to object falling in the classes denoted by
determinate general concepts. The force of them, and thus found an interest in the
Kant's claim that aesthetic judgment pro- technical sense of the Critique of Practical
duces no interest in its object is, however, Reason, nothing in this thesis suggests that
quite limited when it is viewed as derived aesthetic response itself - under the simple
from this theory - which, for the lack of description "pleasure in the beautiful" -
any other support, it must be. If an interest cannot be something we desire, and some-
is a determinate conception of an object thing which motivates some of our activities
Disinterestedness and Desire 459

in the way that other objects of desire do. and the page number for the text in Volume V of
the above edition, and references to the latter are
Thus, twhile the impossibility of formulat-
given by the abbreviation "FI" succeeded by the
ing a certain kind of concept-connected in- page number for Volume XX of that edition.
terest on the basis of aesthetic judgments References to the Foundation of the Metaphysics
might be a consequence of Kant's explana- of Morals are given by "FMM," followed by the
tion of aesthetic response, it does not fol- page number in Volume IV of the Akademie edi-
low that aesthetic response itself cannot pro- tion, and those to the Critique of Practical Reason
duce a perfectly natural desire for the ex- by "CPR," followed by the page number for
Volume V; the latter are taken from the transla-
istence of its particular objects, nor that it tion by Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis, 1956).
cannot itself become the object of an equally Reference to the Anthropology from a Pragmatic
natural - though certainly less determinate Point of View is given by "APV" and the page
- desire. number for Volume VII of the Akademie edition;
I have used the translation by Mary J. Gregor
Without the definition of interest adopt- (The Hague, 1974).
ed from the Critique of Practical Reason, 2 I have considered some problems with Kant's
the Critique of Judgment can furnish no assertion of formalism in "Formalism and the
argument at all for the thesis that the judg- Theory of Expression in Kant's Aesthetics," Kant-
Studien 68, Heft 1 (1977), 46-70. A much broader
ment of beauty can produce no interest in discussion of my interpretation of Kant's theory
its object. With this definition, the third of taste is offered in my forthcoming book, Kant
Critique can supply such an argument. But and the Claims of Taste (Harvard University Press).
if the thesis is interpreted as deriving from aThis treatment may be found in my article
this argument, it no longer does violence "Interest, Nature, and Art: A Problem in Kant's
to our ordinary belief that the beauty of Aesthetics," in The Review of Metaphysics, Volume
XXXI, Number 4 (June, 1978), 580-603.
objects is itself a sufficient ground for 'See for instance the translation by J. C. Mere-
the interest we take in them and the efforts dith (Oxford, 1911), p. 42. The translation by J.
we devote to them. For it does not, as it H. Bernard (London, 1896), does not introduce
appears to, mean that we must look outside the adjective "real."
6 Hume used the example of a palace, maintain-
of the nature of aesthetic response to ex-
ing that "the order and convenience of a palace
plain much of what we ordinarily think of are no less essential to its beauty, than its mere
as an interest in beautiful objects. Kant's figure and appearance" (A Treatise of Human
theory does entail that the experience of Nature, Book II, Part I, Section viii) . But for the
the beauty of particular objects cannot lead fact that Kant is not supposed to have been fa-
to the formation of interests in the existence miliar with this work, we could take his example
in ? 2 to be a polemical reference to Hume. But
of determinate classes of objects. But if that Kant certainly would have been familiar with the
is all it entails, and if it is only for the ex- example of a "magnificent building" used by
planation of such interests that Kant's Henry Home, Lord Kames, in his Elements of
Criticism (Part I, Ch. 1).
theory of an intellectual interest in the R Donald Crawford has also argued that the
beautiful must be invoked, then Kant's
problems with Kant's argument in ? 2 prevent its
theory of disinterestedness is less counter- analysis of disinterestedness from functioning as
intuitive than has traditionally been sup- the real starting-point of Kant's theory of taste
posed. And Kant's further theory of this (Kant's Aesthetic Theory [Madison, 1974], pp. 41-
intellectual interest, with the attendant 50). But while he has argued against Kant's con-
problem of its preference for natural over clusion that an aesthetic judgment cannot ground
artistic beauty, can be safely excluded from an interest in its object (pp. 50-54) , he does not
the core of his theory of taste. argue, as I will, that this thesis is not really a con-
sequence of Kant's theory of aesthetic judgment
except in a very limited sense.
lAll references are to Kants Gesammelte Schrif- 7A similar point is suggested by John Fisher and
ten, edited by the Koniglichen Preussischen (now Jeffrey Maitland in "The Subjectivist Turn in
Deutschen) Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin, Aesthetics: A Critical Analysis of Kant's Theory of
1902). Translations from the Critique of Judgment Appreciation," The Review of Metaphysics, Volume
and the document known as its First Introduction XXVII, Number 4 (June, 1974), 741.
are my own; references to the former are given by 8See FI, 230. Kant there says that the "trans-
the Roman numeral for the section of the Intro- cendental explanation" [Erklarung] of pleasure
duction, or the Arabic numeral for the text section, must be perfectly general, "whether it accompany
460 G U Y ER

sensation, reflection, or the determination of the the latter pleasure "through the imagination"
will," and then explains pleasure as "the condition rather than pleasure in reflective judgment), it is
of the mind, in which a representation is in har- admissible evidence.
mony with it, either merely to preserve this [con- 10Lewis White Beck has argued that the sig-
dition] (for the condition of mutually assisting nificance of Kant's classification of this principle as
faculties of mind in a representation preserves it-
analytic is obscure (A Commentary to Kant's Cri-
self) or to bring forth its object" (FI, 230-231).
tique of Practical Reason [Chicago, 1960] p. 86).
James Haden translates Kant as offering a "trans-
That is certainly true, but does not affect my
cendental definition" of pleasure (in his translation
of Kant, The First Introduction to the Critique of present point, which is only that it is a clearly
Judgment [Indianapolis, 1965], p. 34), but since Kantian assumption that the interest of the faculty
Kant maintains that the effects of pleasure can be of desire extends from its object to that object's
understood but the feeling itself cannot be analyzed necessary conditions.
(FI, 232), it seems better to use the vaguer "ex- 11 At least, that is, where the nature of the means
planation" to render Erklarung. does not conflict with any other desires or ob-
9 The use of the Anthropology in the interpre-
jectives-a condition which should ordinarily be met
tation of Kant's aesthetics may seem suspect, since in the case of objects of aesthetic appreciation.
much of the material included in it antedates the This paper derives from an address delivered at
development of Kant's mature aesthetic theory in the Ohio University Kant Conference in March,
the years after 1787. But since the work was pub- 1977. I would like to thank Annette Baier, John M.
lished by Kant himself in 1798, and since it in- Cooper, Pamela Foa, and the editorial staff of
cludes Kant's mature distinction between sensory JAAC for comments helpful on the way to the
gratification and pleasure in the beautiful (calling present version.

You might also like