Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/235752826

The Importance of Qualitative Research for Causal Explanation in Education

Article  in  Qualitative Inquiry · October 2012


DOI: 10.1177/1077800412452856

CITATIONS READS

94 9,530

1 author:

Joseph Alex Maxwell


George Mason University
47 PUBLICATIONS   15,462 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Causal explanation in social research View project

Qualitative research design View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Joseph Alex Maxwell on 21 May 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Qualitative Inquiry
http://qix.sagepub.com/

The Importance of Qualitative Research for Causal Explanation in Education


Joseph A. Maxwell
Qualitative Inquiry 2012 18: 655
DOI: 10.1177/1077800412452856

The online version of this article can be found at:


http://qix.sagepub.com/content/18/8/655

Published by:

http://www.sagepublications.com

Additional services and information for Qualitative Inquiry can be found at:

Email Alerts: http://qix.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts

Subscriptions: http://qix.sagepub.com/subscriptions

Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav

Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav

Citations: http://qix.sagepub.com/content/18/8/655.refs.html

>> Version of Record - Sep 6, 2012

What is This?

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


452856
412452856MaxwellQualitative Inquiry
© The Author(s) 2012

Reprints and permission:


QIX18810.1177/1077800

sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav

Special Section on Causality


Qualitative Inquiry

The Importance of Qualitative Research


18(8) 655­–661
© The Author(s) 2012
Reprints and permission:

for Causal Explanation in Education sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav


DOI: 10.1177/1077800412452856
http://qix.sagepub.com

Joseph A. Maxwell1

Abstract
The concept of causation has long been controversial in qualitative research, and many qualitative researchers have rejected
causal explanation as incompatible with an interpretivist or constructivist approach. This rejection conflates causation with
the positivist theory of causation, and ignores an alternative understanding of causation, variously known as a “generative,”
“process,” or “realist” approach, which is influential in philosophy and is becoming widespread in the social sciences and
history. This alternative approach to causation is compatible with the practice and “theory-in-use” of many qualitative
researchers and enables qualitative researchers to credibly make and support causal claims. It also enables them to
defend their work against the dismissal of qualitative methods by proponents of “science-based” research, since the latter
assumes a positivist understanding of causation.  Adequate causal explanations in the social sciences depend on the in-depth
understanding of meanings, contexts, and processes that qualitative research can provide.

Keywords
causation, realism, process, ontology

The title of this article is “The Importance of Qualitative of articles—why many qualitative researchers believe that
Research for Causal Explanation in Education.” It is not causation is an inappropriate concept in qualitative research.
“The Importance of Causal Explanation for Qualitative Despite some notable exceptions (e.g., Coffey & Atkinson,
Research in Education.” Much qualitative research provides 1996, p. 243; Erickson, 1986, p. 82; Fielding & Fielding,
valuable and trustworthy accounts of educational settings 1986, p. 22; Huberman & Miles, 1985; Schwandt, 1997,
and activities, the contexts in which these are situated, and p. 14), this rejection of causation has been a widespread and
the meanings that they have for participants, that have noth- pervasive assumption within the qualitative community;
ing directly to do with causation. Although I’ll argue that particularly influential statements of this position are those
causal explanation is a legitimate and important goal for by Lincoln and Guba (1985, p. 141) and Guba and Lincoln
qualitative research (see Maxwell, 2004a, 2008, 2011a), my (1989, pp. 44, 86). The recently published two-volume Sage
main point is a quite different one—that educational research Encyclopedia of Qualitative Research (Given, 2008) had no
desperately needs qualitative approaches and methods if it is entries for cause or causation, and the only nondismissive
to make valid and useful claims about what works. Although mention of causation in the third edition of the Handbook of
I have focused my argument on educational research, where Qualitative Research (Denzin & Lincoln, 2005a) was in the
the dismissal of qualitative research in some quarters has chapter on qualitative evaluation and social policy (House,
been particularly virulent, this argument applies to the social 2005), where the issue of causation is almost impossible to
sciences generally, and in fact, to natural science as well. avoid. (There are no nondismissive mentions of causation
This argument draws on a point that I have made else- in the fourth edition of the Handbook; Denzin & Lincoln,
where (Maxwell, 2004a)—that so-called “scientific research” 2011). The author of one of the finalist dissertations for the
in education, which assumes that investigations of causation qualitative dissertation award given by the Qualitative
in educational settings must necessarily be quantitative, with Research Special Interest Group of the American Educational
randomized controlled trials (RCTs) as the best way to con- Research Association in 2011, Brianna Kennedy, confided
duct such investigations,1 is based on a narrow, incomplete,
1
and dated conception of causality. (I address this conception George Mason University, Fairfax,VA, USA
in more detail below.)
Corresponding Author:
But to build my case that qualitative research can make Joseph A. Maxwell, PhD, George Mason University, George Mason
an essential contribution to causal inquiry in education, I University 6D2, 4400 University Drive, Fairfax,VA 22030-4444, USA
need to address the question that motivated this collection Email: jmaxwell@gmu.edu

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


656 Qualitative Inquiry 18(8)

to me that she felt that “even uttering the word ‘causal’ in far too loosely to discredit anyone who is seen as insuffi-
qualitative methodology circles was akin to invoking evil ciently “progressive” in their approach to research, the term
spirits.” is in this case an accurate description of this approach. The
This is particularly puzzling given that most of us accept regularity theory of causation is a genuine living fossil that
the concept of causation in our everyday lives. We believe is consistent with basic logical positivist premises and has
that when our car doesn’t start, a mechanic can discover the survived in virtually unchanged form since the positivist
cause of this and fix the problem. Most of us also believe era. This concept of causation fits perfectly with quantita-
that greenhouse gases released by human activity are caus- tive research, which is ideally suited to identifying consis-
ing the earth to become warmer, regardless of how many tent associations between variables, and it is the basis for
people believe this theory. This acceptance of causation the claim that quantitative methods are the only way to val-
isn’t limited to the physical world; most of us also believe idly establish causal conclusions.
that changing people’s understanding of, and motivation to I think that there have been four main reasons that quali-
act on, global warming can cause a reduction in the amount tative researchers rejected the regularity view of causation
of greenhouse gases we produce. As the philosopher Hilary as valid for qualitative research:
Putnam has said,
1. They associated it with the positivist commitment
whether causation “really exists” or not, it certainly to “objective” knowledge of reality, implying that
exists in our “life world.”. . . The world of ordinary causes could be accurately identified in a theory-
language (the world in which we actually live) is full neutral way.
of causes and effects. It is only when we insist that 2. They saw it as mechanical and deterministic, as
the world of ordinary language . . . is defective . . . ruling out human agency, and as incompatible
and look for a “true” world . . . that we end up feeling with an interpretivist understanding of human
forced to choose between the picture of “a physical thought and action.
universe with a built-in structure” and “a physical 3. They saw it as denying the importance, not only of
universe with a structure imposed by the mind.” the meanings that things had for people, but of the
(1990, p. 89) importance of context and the need to take unique
circumstances into account in understanding why
So how did we get ourselves into a situation in which we some event or outcome occurred.
deny in our epistemology and methodology what we accept 4. Finally, they understood that it dismissed the idea
in our everyday lives? A major reason for—can I say “cause of process, of the possibility of understanding not
of”?—this rejection of causation by qualitative researchers just whether there was an association between
was the positivist account of causation, which was dominant variables, but of how one thing influenced another,
in philosophy for most of the 20th century and had a power- a goal that was central to Blumer’s view of sym-
ful influence on quantitative and experimental research. This bolic interactionism (1956).3
account, generally known as the “regularity” or “succession-
ist” theory of causation, was derived from David Hume’s However, in rejecting the regularity understanding of
analysis of causality (1739/1978), as further developed by causation, qualitative researchers threw the baby out with
J. S. Mill (1843/1988) and Carl Hempel (Hempel & the bathwater. For at about the same time that this rejection
Oppenheim, 1948). It held that we can’t directly perceive of causality was gaining force in qualitative research, an
causal relationships, only what Hume called the “constant alternative concept of causation was being developed, in
conjunction” of events. Hume denied that we can have any both philosophy (Bhaskar, 1978, 1989; Salmon, 1984, 1989,
knowledge of causality that goes beyond the observed regu- 1998) and in social science (Mohr, 1982). This theory,
larities in the association of events and repudiated any refer- which has variously been termed a “realist,” “generative,”
ence to unobservable mechanisms. In its current manifestation, or “process” approach, abandoned the Humean restriction
it holds that the demonstration of causation is simply a matter of our understanding of causation to observed regularities
of showing that there is a regular, law-like relationship and argued for the reality of causal processes. As subse-
between two variables, so that a change in the first (“indepen- quently developed in the social sciences and in history, this
dent”) variable results in a change in the second (“depen- alternative theory saw causal explanation as fundamentally a
dent”) variable (National Research Council, 2002). This matter of identifying the actual processes that resulted in a
account is the basis for some of the current, most respected specific outcome in a particular context (Little, 2010;
quantitative approaches to causal research (e.g., Mulaik, Pawson & Tilley, 1997; Sayer, 1992; for a more detailed dis-
2009, pp. 63-87; Murnane & Willett, 2010, pp. 26-38).2 cussion of the relevance of this approach for qualitative
Although logical positivism is no longer a viable phi- research, see Maxwell, 2011a). Little, addressing causation
losophy of science, and the term “positivist” is often used in history, argued that

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


Maxwell 657

it is very important for historians to arrive at deeper meanings and intentions of the members of these groups is
understandings of the metaphysics of social causa- seriously deficient and unlikely to be productive (Menzel,
tion. This means, first, understanding the complete 1978). The fundamental premise of symbolic interaction-
inadequacy of the traditional positivist interpretations ism “is that people act in accordance with their definitions
of causation: “causation is no more than regularity.” of situations, so that explanations are dependent on under-
This Humean view does not serve the natural sciences standing those definitions” (Hewitt, 1984, p. 269, cited by
well, and it certainly does not help us when it comes Goldenberg, 1992, p. 524)
to social causation. So it is necessary to explore a dif- Finally, an ontology that accepts the reality of causation is
ferent model of causation that fits better with what we quite compatible with a constructivist epistemology that
know about the actual workings of social processes. holds that our understanding of the world, including our
The model developed above is “causal realism.” understanding of causation and causal relationships, is neces-
(Little, 2010, p. 218) sarily our own creation, incomplete and fallible, rather than
an “objective” perception of reality (Bhaskar, 1989, p. 185;
This theory removes most of the barriers to the accep- Campbell, 1988, p. 447; Keller, 1992, pp. 73-74; Lakoff,
tance of causation by qualitative researchers (Maxwell, 1987, p. 265; for a detailed justification of this claim, see
2004a, 2004b, 2008, 2011a). First, it identifies process as a Maxwell, 2011a).5
necessary and central aspect of causation, a view that is From this perspective, I disagree with Donmoyer’s view
characteristic not only of our everyday understanding of (2012) that causality is a “convenient fiction.” The idea that
causation but is implicit in the work of many qualitative theories about the world are “convenient fictions” is another
researchers. It validates not only the idea that causal pro- vestigial holdover from logical positivism. Positivists argued
cesses can in some situations be directly observed (Maxwell, that theoretical terms and concepts were simply logical con-
2004a; Scriven, 2008), but also that they can be established structions based on, and defined by, observational data, “fic-
in single cases, without the need for comparison or quantita- tions” that were useful in making predictions but which had
tive measurement (Cartwright, 2000; Salmon, 1998, p. 15). no claim to any “reality” (Norris, 1983; Phillips, 1987, p. 40).
Causation is thus fundamentally local rather than general This view, generally termed “instrumentalism,” was (and
(Cartwright, 1999, 2000, 2007; Huberman & Miles, 1985); remains) influential in psychology and the social sciences
causal generalizations are necessarily secondary to particu- long after it was abandoned in philosophy (Salmon, 1984,
lar causal understanding. pp. 5-7).
Second, it makes context intrinsic to causal explanation. Seeing our understanding of causation as a construction
Causal processes always operate within a real context, and does not make it “fictional,” for at least two reasons. First, as
this context is inextricably involved in the outcome of that a construction, causation points to and captures (although not
process (Pawson & Tilley, 1997). The causally relevant “reflects”; see Keller, 1992, pp. 73-74) something about real-
contexts for understanding some phenomenon include not ity, an aspect of reality that can resist or fail to accommodate
only the immediate physical and social situation but also to our constructions of it (Blumer, 1969). Second, as a con-
broader social and cultural contexts, as argued by Anderson cept held by real human beings, this construction is itself real:
and Scott (2012). These contexts can’t be reduced to a set of It influences our actions (e.g., a realist concept of causation
“extraneous variables” without misrepresenting the nature played a major causal role in my writing this article).
of the causal process (Blumer, 1956, 1969). Accepting the legitimacy of causation in qualitative
Third, it extends causal efficacy to beliefs, values, inten- research does not put us on a slippery slope leading back to
tions, and meanings, not just to physical objects and events positivism or foundationalism. A realist process theory of
(Pawson, 2006, pp. 27-29; Sayer, 1992, pp. 110-112). The causation constitutes a rejection of the basic premises of the
view that beliefs and reasons have causal consequences is positivist understanding of causation as well as being
a position that has repeatedly been defended in philosophy incompatible with other aspects of positivism (Maxwell,
(Davidson, 1980, 1993, 1997; McGinn, 1991; Putnam, 2011a, pp. 8-9; Schwandt, 1997, pp. 133-134). The linking
1999; Robb & Heil, 2003) and is generally accepted in both of ontological realism and epistemological constructivism
our everyday explanation of people’s behavior and in psy- that I advocate here is also explicitly antifoundationalist in
chology as a science. However, the sharp separation of rejecting any fundamental beliefs or assumptions about
“meaning” and “cause” explanations by Dilthey (discussed reality other than that it exists. Reality is more complex than
by Donmoyer in his article in this issue), Weber, Winch, and any belief or theory can fully capture; multiple valid under-
others has been far more influential in qualitative research.4 standings of any phenomenon are possible (see Maxwell,
From the realist perspective presented here, meanings 2011b), and all beliefs and assumptions are tentative and
and beliefs are part of the causal processes that operate in subject to revision.
human individuals and communities, and any attempt to This view of causation is compatible with, and in fact
explain what happens in human groups that ignores the supports, the actual methods and interpretive concepts and

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


658 Qualitative Inquiry 18(8)

approaches used by many qualitative researchers—what these causes interact, and described ways in which these
Argyris and Schoen (1992) called the “theory-in-use” of causes might be alleviated.
these researchers. It is even explicit in the work of some A second example is a recent book by Stuart Buck,
qualitative researchers; for example, Weiss (1994) Acting White: The Ironic Legacy of Desegregation (2011),
argued, in which he argued that the perception that academically
successful Black students are “acting white” is a real phe-
In quantitative interview studies the demonstration of nomenon that causes serious problems in school for Black
causation rests heavily on the description of a visual- students, and is itself an unintended consequence of the way
izable sequence of events, each event flowing into the desegregation was implemented. It seems to me that if you
next. . . . Quantitative studies support an assertion of want to work against injustice and oppression, you need to
causation by showing a correlation between an earlier understand the causes of the particular forms of injustice
event and a subsequent event. An analysis of data and oppression you are dealing with, and how to counteract
collected in a large-scale sample survey might, for and overcome these causes.
example, show that there is a correlation between the In conclusion, I am making two claims. First, I am argu-
level of the wife’s education and the presence of a ing that qualitative researchers can draw and support causal
companionable marriage. In qualitative studies we conclusions—that this is not an inappropriate aspiration.
would look for a process through which the wife’s We are able to do this by focusing on the causal processes,
education or factors associated with her education mental as well as physical, that result in particular out-
express themselves in marital interaction. (p. 179) comes, rather than by simply demonstrating that a relation-
ship exists between particular variables. Not all qualitative
However, it is not compatible with the espoused theory researchers aspire to draw such conclusions, and that is
of some qualitative researchers—a radical constructivist or legitimate, but there are no good philosophical or method-
relativist ontology that denies the reality of causation. What ological prohibitions against our doing this.
I am arguing is there are good reasons to question this I am not just arguing that we can do this, but that we’re
espoused theory, and to try to better understand the theory- good at it. We have the methods that allow us to both develop
in-use that we employ in our work. and test causal explanations in education. However, we could
This view of causation is also essential to any approach be better at it. Drawing causal conclusions is challenging even
to causation that can be of real use to social and educa- in the best of conditions, and attempting to generalize such
tional researchers. This is most clearly illustrated by conclusions is even more difficult. If we want to credibly
mixed-method studies that combined qualitative and quan- make such claims to a wider audience, we need to be system-
titative approaches in ways that respected the value of both atic and rigorous in providing evidence that supports these
approaches and supported a dialog between the two. Good claims and that addresses potential validity threats to these
examples of this can be found in the collection of mixed- claims; I provide elsewhere a detailed discussion of methods
method studies edited by the ethnographer Tom Weisner, that qualitative researchers can use for this (Maxwell, 2004b,
with the title Discovering Successful Pathways in Children’s 2011a). However, in doing this, we also need to challenge
Development (Weisner, 2005). In these studies, the insights the positivist assumptions that typically inform “evidence-
gained by the qualitative researchers were essential to the based” approaches to research (Maxwell, 2009).
causal conclusions that emerged from the study, and in one Second, I am arguing that educational research, and social
study they not only refocused the quantitative data collection research generally, requires such qualitative approaches if it
on the outcomes that emerged from the qualitative work, but is to credibly identify the actual causes that influence a par-
“led us to develop an overall conceptual framework for ticular outcome, let alone to make claims about the broader
thinking about the mechanisms through which changes in efficacy of any intervention. Pawson (2006) argued,
outcomes due to moves out of high-poverty areas might
occur” (Kling, Liebman, & Katz, 2005, p. 244). The nature of causality in social programmes is such
I also believe that incorporating causal inference in qual- that any synthesis of evidence on whether they work will
itative research supports, rather than undermines, social jus- need to investigate how they work. This requires unearth-
tice agendas for our work. A particularly good example of ing information on mechanisms, contexts, and outcomes.
this is Dixiane Hallaj’s recent award-winning dissertation The central quest is to understand the conditions of
Caught by Culture and Conflict: Palestinian Refugee programme efficacy and this will involve the synthesis
Women’s Perceptions of Illiteracy and Education (2006), in investigating for whom, in what circumstances, and
which grew out of her work to establish family literacy cen- in what respects a family of programmes work. (p. 25)
ters within the refugee camps in the West Bank. Hallaj
explicitly identified cultural, environmental, and political The idea that randomized experiments or structural
causes of these women’s illiteracy and the ways in which equation models can provide valid general conclusions

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


Maxwell 659

about the effect of an intervention, in the absence of any phenomena. Thus, he describes both types of causation as
understanding of the actual causal processes that were operat- “establishing and accounting for ordered patterns of human
ing, the specific contexts in which these processes were situ- behavior” (p. 166; emphasis added). Although Howe acknowl-
ated, or the meaning that the intervention and contexts had for edges that for N-causation there is a realist/process alternative
participants, is an illusion. We need qualitative methods and to the regularity view, he makes no mention of this in his dis-
approaches in order to understand “what works” and why. cussion of intentional causation, and never addresses the pos-
sibility of causal explanations of singular events, as opposed to
Declaration of Conflicting Interests regularities.
The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with 5. Smith (2008; Smith & Deemer, 2000) argued that the con-
respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this straints of a constructivist epistemology make it impossible for a
article. realist ontology to have any practical value. (This is one manifes-
tation of what has been called the “ontological-epistemological
Funding collapse,” which sees ontology as simply a reflection of episte-
The author(s) received no financial support for the research, mology, for example, Denzin & Lincoln, 2005b, p. 203.) I have
authorship, and/or publication of this article. argued elsewhere (Maxwell, 2008, 2011a; Maxwell & Mittapalli,
2010) that this is simply false, and that a realist ontology has
Notes important implications for research that are not incompatible
1. For a particularly scathing critique of the idea that RCTs (ran- with a constructivist epistemology.
domized controlled trials) are the “gold standard” for causal
inference, see Scriven (2008). References
2. One statistician who was not committed to the regularity the- Anderson, G. L. & Scott, J. (2012). Toward an Intersectional
ory, and who sought to understand causal processes in particu- Understanding of Process Causality and Social Context. Qual-
lar cases, was David Freedman (2010). The philosopher Nancy itative Inquiry, 18, 674-685.
Cartwright, whose work (e.g., 2007) represents some of the best Argyris, C., & Schoen, D. (1992). Theory in practice: Increasing
thinking about using quantitative methods in causal research, professional effectiveness. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
has provided a detailed argument for what she called “causal Bhaskar, R. (1978). A realist theory of science (2nd ed.). Brighton,
pluralism,” the view that what causes are and what they do var- UK: Harvester.
ies from case to case. She stated that current approaches “are Bhaskar, R. (1989). Reclaiming reality: A critical introduction to
not alternative, incompatible views about causation; they are contemporary philosophy. London: Verso.
rather views that fit different kinds of causal systems” and that Blumer, H. (1956). Sociological analysis and the “variable.”
“there is no single interesting characterizing feature of causa- American Sociological Review, 22, 683-690. Reprinted in
tion; hence no off-the-shelf or one-size-fits-all method for H. Blumer, Symbolic interactionism: Perspective and method
finding out about it, no ‘gold standard’ for judging causal rela- (pp. 127-139). Berkeley: University of California Press.
tions” (2007, p. 2). Blumer, H. (1969). The methodological position of symbolic
3. The National Research Council Report Scientific Research in interactionism. In H. Blumer, Symbolic interactionism: Per-
Education (2002) acknowledged the value of understanding spective and method (pp. 1-60). Berkeley: University of Cali-
mechanisms, but made this subordinate to, and dependent on, fornia Press.
the quantitative demonstration of a causal relationship between Buck, S. (2011). Acting white: The ironic legacy of desegregation.
variables, and claimed that even the understanding of mecha- New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
nisms was necessarily a primarily quantitative activity (see Campbell, D. T. (1988). Methodology and epistemology for social
Maxwell, 2004a). science: Selected papers (S. Overman, Ed.). Chicago, IL: Uni-
4. For example, Howe (2011) has recently presented a different versity of Chicago Press.
analysis of causality in qualitative research from the one pro- Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundar-
posed here, accepting the validity of this concept, but arguing ies of science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
that causation of intentional phenomena (I-causation) is different Cartwright, N. (2000). An empiricist defence of singular causes.
in kind from that of natural phenomena (N-causation). Although In R. Teichmann (Ed.), Logic, cause, and action: Essays in
I endorse his recognition of causation in human interactions, and honour of Elizabeth Anscombe (pp. 47-58). Cambridge, UK:
his position that qualitative and quantitative methods can both be Cambridge University Press.
used for intentional and physical phenomena, I think that his Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them. Cam-
analysis in terms of two kinds of phenomena still leaves as mys- bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
terious the interaction between the two, an interaction that is Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford, UK:
intrinsic to our everyday understanding of causation. Oxford University Press
In addition, Howe still seems to implicitly rely on a regularity Davidson, D. (1993). Thinking causes. In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.),
understanding of causality, for both natural and intentional Mental causation (pp. 3-17). Oxford, UK: Clarendon.

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


660 Qualitative Inquiry 18(8)

Davidson, D. (1997). Indeterminism and antirealism. In C. B. Kulp Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What cat-
(Ed.), Realism/antirealism and epistemology (pp. 109-122). egories reveal about the mind. Chicago, IL: University of
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Chicago Press.
Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (2005a). Handbook of Lincoln, Y. S., & Guba, E. G. (1985). Naturalistic inquiry. Newbury
qualitative research (3rd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE. Park, CA: SAGE.
Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (2005b). Paradigmatic controver- Little, D. (2010). New contributions to the philosophy of history.
sies, contradictions, and emerging confluences. In N. K. Denzin New York, NY: Springer.
& Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research (3rd Maxwell, J. A. (2004a). Causal explanation, qualitative research,
ed., pp. 191-216). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE. and scientific inquiry in education. Educational Researcher,
Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (2011). Handbook of quali- 33(2), 3-11.
tative research (4th ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE. Maxwell, J. (2004b). Using qualitative methods for causal expla-
Donmoyer, R. (2012). Can Qualitative Researchers Answer Poli- nation. Field Methods, 16, 243-264.
cymakers’ What-Works Question? Qualitative Inquiry, 18(8), Maxwell, J. A. (2008). The value of a realist understanding of cau-
662-673. sality for qualitative research. In N. Denzin (Ed.), Qualitative
Erickson, F. (1986). Qualitative methods. In M. Wittrock (Ed.), research and the politics of evidence (pp. 163-181). Walnut
Handbook of research on teaching (pp. 119-161). New York, Creek, CA: Left Coast Press.
NY: Macmillan. Maxwell, J. A. (2009). Evidence: A critical realist perspective for
Fielding, N. G., & Fielding, J. L. (1986). Linking data. Thousand qualitative research. In N. K. Denzin & M. D. Giardina (Eds.),
Oaks, CA: SAGE. Qualitative inquiry and social justice (pp. 108-122). Walnut
Freedman, D. (2010). Statistical models and causal inference: A Creek, CA: Left Coast Press.
dialogue with the social sciences (D. Collier, J. S. Sekhon, & Maxwell, J. A. (2011a). A realist approach for qualitative research.
P. B. Stark, Ed.). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Given, L. (Ed.). (2008). The SAGE encyclopedia of qualitative Maxwell, J. A. (2011b). Paradigms or toolkits? Philosophical
research methods. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE. and methodological positions as heuristics for mixed meth-
Goldenberg, C. (1992). The limits of expectations: A case for case ods research. Mid-Western Educational Researcher, 24(2),
knowledge of teacher expectancy effects. American Educa- 27-30.
tional Research Journal, 29(3), 517-544. Maxwell, J. A., & Mittapalli, K. (2010). Realism as a stance for
Guba, E. G., & Lincoln, Y. S. (1989). Fourth generation evalua- mixed method research. In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie (Eds.),
tion. Newbury Park, CA: SAGE. Handbook of mixed methods in social and behavioral research
Hallaj, D. (2006). Caught by culture and conflict: Palestinian (2nd ed., pp. 145-167). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
refugee women’s perceptions of illiteracy and education. PhD McGinn, C. (1991). Conceptual causation: Some elementary
dissertation, George Mason University, Fairfax, VA. reflections. Mind, 100(4), 573-586. Reprinted in C. McGinn
Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of (1999), Knowledge and reality: Selected essays (pp. 152-167).
explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135-175. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Pres.
Hewitt, J. (1984). Self and society: A symbolic interactionist social Menzel, H. (1978). Meaning—who needs it? In M. Brenner,
psychology (3rd ed.). Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. P. Marsh, & M. Brenner (Eds.), The social contexts of method
House, E. (2005). Qualitative evaluation and changing social (pp. 140-171). New York, NY: St. Martin’s.
policy. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of Mill, J. S. (1988), A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive
qualitative research (3rd ed., pp. 1069-1088). Thousand Oaks, (8th ed.). New York, NY: Harper and Brothers. (Original work
CA: SAGE. published 1843)
Howe, K. R. (2011). Mixed methods, mixed causes? Qualitative Mohr, L. B. (1982). Explaining organizational behavior. San
Inquiry, 17, 166-171. Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Huberman, A. M., & Miles, M. B. (1985). Assessing local causal- Mulaik, S. (2009). Linear causal modeling with structural equa-
ity in qualitative research. In D. N. Berg & K. K. Smith (Eds.), tions. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall/CRC Press.
Exploring clinical methods for social research (pp. 351-382). Murnane, R. J., & Willett, J. B. (2010). Methods matter: Improving
Beverly Hills, CA: SAGE. causal inference in educational and social science research.
Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature (Edited, with an Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
analytical index, by L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2nd ed.) Oxford, UK: National Research Council. (2002). Scientific research in educa-
Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1739) tion. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Keller, E. F. (1992). Secrets of life, secrets of death: Essays on Norris, S. P. (1983). The inconsistencies at the foundation of con-
language, gender, and science. New York, NY: Routledge. struct validation theory. In E. R. House (Ed.), Philosophy of
Kling, J. R., Liebman, J. B., & Katz, L. F. (2005). “Bullets don’t got evaluation. New directions for program evaluation (Vol. 19,
no name”: Consequences of fear in the ghetto. In T. Weisner pp. 53-74). San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
(Ed.), Discovering successful pathways in children’s develop- Pawson, R. (2006). Evidence-based policy: A realist perspective.
ment (pp. 243-282). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. London: SAGE.

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


Maxwell 661

Pawson, R., & Tilley, N. (1997). Realistic evaluation. London: Smith, J. K. (2008). Relativism. In L. Given (Ed.), The SAGE
SAGE. encyclopedia of qualitative research methods (pp. 749-753).
Phillips, D. C. (1987). Validity in qualitative research: Why the Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
worry about warrant will not wane. Education and Urban Smith, J. K., & Deemer, D. K. (2000). The problem of criteria in
Society, 20, 9-24. the age of relativism. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.),
Putnam, H. (1990). Realism with a human face (Ed. J. Conant). Handbook of qualitative research (2nd ed., pp. 877-896).
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord: Mind, body, and world. Weisner, T. S. (Ed.). (2005). Discovering successful pathways
New York, NY: Columbia University Press. in children’s development: Mixed methods in the study of
Robb, D., & Heil, J. (2003). Mental causation. Stanford Encyclo- childhood and family life. Chicago, IL: University of Chi-
pedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/ cago Press.
entries/mental-causation/ Weiss, R. S. (1994). Learning from strangers: The art and
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal method of qualitative interviewing. New York, NY: Free
structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Press.
Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In Bio
P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation Joseph A. Maxwell is a professor in the College of Education
(pp. 3-219). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. and Human Development at George Mason University, where he
Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. New York, NY: teaches courses on qualitative and mixed-method research
Oxford University Press. design and methods. He is the author of Qualitative Research
Sayer, A. (1992). Method in social science: A realist approach Design: An Interactive Approach (2nd ed., 2005) and A Realist
(2nd ed.). London: Routledge. Approach for Qualitative Research (2011). His research and
Schwandt, T. A. (1997). Qualitative inquiry: A dictionary of terms. writing include work on research methodology and philosophy,
Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE. program evaluation, sociocultural theory, Native American
Scriven, M. (2008). A summative evaluation of RCT methodol- societies, and medical education; see http://cehd.gmu.edu/
ogy: An alternative approach to causal research. Journal of people/faculty/jmaxwell/. He has a PhD in anthropology from
Multidisciplinary Evaluation, 5(9), 11-24. the University of Chicago.

Downloaded from qix.sagepub.com by guest on September 8, 2012


View publication stats

You might also like