Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 57

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/299922290

The Neurology of Consciousness

Chapter · December 2016


DOI: 10.1016/B978-0-12-800948-2.00025-X

CITATIONS READS
19 11,666

4 authors:

Giulio Tononi Melanie Boly


University of Wisconsin–Madison University of Wisconsin–Madison
625 PUBLICATIONS 70,423 CITATIONS 308 PUBLICATIONS 28,194 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Olivia Gosseries Steven Laureys


University of Liège University of Liège
336 PUBLICATIONS 11,696 CITATIONS 952 PUBLICATIONS 58,387 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Ethical issues in Disorders of Consciousness View project

Hypnosis View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Melanie Boly on 17 November 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


C H A P T E R

c0025 25
The Neurology of Consciousness: An Overview
Giulio Tononi1, Melanie Boly2,3, Olivia Gosseries2,4 and Steven Laureys5
2
AU:1 Department of Psychiatry, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI, USA 3Department of Neurology, University of
Wisconsin, Madison, WI, USA 4Coma Science Group, Neurology Department and Cyclotron Research Center,
University of Liège, Liège, Belgium 5Cyclotron Research Center and Department of Neurology, University of Liège,
Liège, Belgium

O U T L I N E

Consciousness and Other Brain Functions 398 Cortex vs. Thalamus 419
Consciousness and Sensory Input/Motor Output 398 Primary Areas vs. Areas 420
Consciousness and Language 399 Ventral vs. Dorsal Stream 422
Consciousness and Introspection/Reflection 399 Posterior vs. Anterior (Prefrontal) Cortex 423
Consciousness and Attention 400 Lateral Fronto-Parietal Network vs.
Consciousness and Memory 401 (Medial) Default System 425
Consciousness and Space 403 Left vs. Right Hemisphere 427
Consciousness, Body, and Self 404 Reentrant vs. Feed-Forward Connections 428
Consciousness, Perception, Imagination, and Superficial vs. Deep Layers of Cortex 430
Absolute Agnosia 406
The Neurophysiology of Consciousness 430
Consciousness and Anosognosia 407
Synchronization and Oscillations 430
Global Alterations of Consciousness 408 P3b and other Evoked Potentials 432
Sleep 409 Cortical “Activation” 433
Anesthesia 411 Sustained vs. Phasic Activity 433
Coma and Related States 414
A Theoretical Perspective 435
Seizures 415
Consciousness as Integrated Information 435
The Neuroanatomy of Consciousness 417 Accounting for Neurobiological Observations 437
The Corticothalamic System vs. the Rest Some Implications 438
of the Brain 417
References 439
Cortex vs. Activating Systems 419

p0190 Many chapters of this book present a composite emerge, though dimly. But at least, this volume should
picture of the relationship between consciousness and have made clear that neurological investigations, often
the brain, as seen from several different angles by many forgotten by philosophers and neuroscientists alike
different authors. Can one discern, from such a fragmen- because what they offer is often rough, dirty, and idio-
ted perspective, the contours of the neural process syncratic, still provide the fundamental empirical evi-
underlying consciousness, the ghost in the machine? Not dence concerning the physical substrate of consciousness:
yet, a skeptical reader casting a cold eye on this book it is by examining how human consciousness is drasti-
might conclude; or perhaps something is beginning to cally changed by anatomical or functional changes in the

S. Laureys, G. Tononi & O. Gosseries (Eds) DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-800948-2.00025-X


The Neurology of Consciousness, Second edition. 397 © 2016 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
398 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

brain, and conversely by considering which changes in Consciousness and Sensory Input/Motor Output s0015
brain structure and dynamics do not seem to affect
consciousness much, that over the past 100 years or so We are usually conscious of what goes on around p0205 AU:2
we have been learning the lay of the land. us, and occasionally of what goes on within our body.
p0195 This final chapter attempts to provide the reader with So it is only natural to think that consciousness may be
an overview of the neurological and neurobiological lit- tightly linked to the ongoing interaction we maintain
erature, stating what seems to be reasonably established with the world and the body. However, there are
and what is instead still open or unknown. First, the many examples to the contrary. We are conscious of
chapter reviews the evidence suggesting that conscious- our thoughts, which do not seem to correspond to
ness can be dissociated from other brain functions, such anything out there; we can also imagine things that are
as responsiveness to sensory inputs, motor control, not out there. When we do so, sensory areas can be acti-
attention, language, memory, reflection, spatial frames vated from the inside (Kosslyn et al., 2001), though there
of reference, the body and perhaps even the self. The are some differences (Amedi et al., 2005). Also, stimulus-
chapter then summarizes what has been learned by independent consciousness is associated with its own
studying global changes in the level of consciousness, patterns of activation within cortex and thalamus
such as sleep, anesthesia, seizures, and post-comatose (Mason et al., 2007). During dreams, we are virtually
states. Next, it asks what can be said at this point about disconnected from the environment (Hobson et al.,
the neuroanatomy and the neurophysiology of con- 2000)—hardly anything of what happens around us
sciousness. The chapter ends by briefly considering how enters consciousness, and our muscles are paralyzed
a theoretical analysis of the fundamental properties of (except for eye muscles and diaphragm). Nevertheless,
consciousness can complement neurobiological studies. we are vividly conscious: all that seems to matter is
that the corticothalamic system continues to function
more or less like in wakefulness, as shown by unit
s0010 CONSCIOUSNESS AND OTHER BRAIN recording, electroencephalography (EEG), transcranial
FUNCTIONS magnetic stimulation (TMS), and functional neuroim-
aging studies performed during rapid eye movement
p0200 Many suggestions have been ventured in the hope of (REM) sleep, when dreams are most intense (Maquet
alleviating the puzzle of subjective experience. Perhaps et al., 1996; Braun et al., 1997; Massimini et al., 2010;
consciousness emerges somehow when an organism is Siclari et al., 2014b) (Chapter 7). Interestingly, certain
immersed in some complex sensorimotor loop that regions of the corticothalamic systems, such as dorso-
includes the environment. Another common idea is that lateral prefrontal cortex, are deactivated in REM
consciousness may arise when one part of the brain, sleep, which likely accounts for some peculiarities of
acting as the “subject” (typically the front), looks upon dreaming experiences, such as the reduction of vol-
another part as its object (typically the back), and untary control. Recently, it has been shown that these
evaluates or reflects upon its activity. It is often thought brain areas are reactivated during lucid dreaming,
that in the end consciousness may be reduced to atten- when one knows that one is dreaming and is able to
tion and its brain mechanisms, since we are usually control their dream (Dresler et al., 2012).
conscious of what we attend. Much could be said about Neurological evidence also indicates that neither p0210

each of these suggestions. Here, we consider some sensory inputs nor motor outputs are needed to generate
recent results (and some very old evidence) indicating consciousness. For instance, retinally blind people can
that consciousness—in the sense of having an experi- both imagine and dream visually if they become blind
ence—does not require sensorimotor loops involving after 6!7 years of age or so (Hollins, 1985; Buchel et al.,
the body and the world, does not require language, 1998) (Chapter 24). Patients with the locked-in syndrome
introspection, or reflection, can do without spatial can be almost completely paralyzed, and yet they are
frames of reference and perhaps even without a sense just as conscious as healthy subjects (Laureys et al., 2005;
of the body and the self, and does not reduce to atten- Lule et al., 2009) (Chapter 12) and can compose eloquent
tion or memory. Likewise, consciousness must not be accounts of their condition (Bauby, 1997). A transient AU:3
confounded with processes that directly precede or form of paralysis is one of the characteristic features of
follow experience itself, such as expectation, task plan- narcolepsy. Severe cataplectic attacks can last for min-
ning, self-monitoring, unconscious stimulus processing, utes and leave the patient collapsed on the floor, utterly
or giving a report (Revonsuo, 2000; Hohwy, 2009; Aru unable to move or to signal, but fully aware of their
et al., 2012b; de Graaf et al., 2012; Miller, 2014). Due to surroundings (Guilleminault, 1976; Siegel, 2000). Drug
space limitations, we will not discuss the relationship addicts known as frozen addicts who show symptoms of
between consciousness and time, between conscious- severe Parkinson’s disease due to 1-methyl-4-phenyl-
ness and emotion, or the notion of conscious access. 1,2,3,6-tetrahydropyridine (MPTP)-induced damage to

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


CONSCIOUSNESS AND OTHER BRAIN FUNCTIONS 399
the dopaminergic system are also fully conscious, yet leave little doubt that experience continues after the loss
AU:4 unable to move or speak (Langston and Palfreman, 1995, of the left hemisphere’s language functions.
2014). Thus, consciousness here and now seems to
depend on what certain parts of the brain are doing,
without requiring any obligatory interaction with the
Consciousness and Introspection/Reflection s0025

environment or the body. Consciousness is usually evaluated by verbal reports. p0220


Questions about consciousness (“Did you see anything
on the screen?”) are answered by “looking inside” retro-
s0020 Consciousness and Language spectively and reporting what one has just experienced.
p0215 There have been claims that consciousness only So it is perhaps natural to suggest that consciousness
emerges with language (Macphail, 1998), though it may arise through the ability to reflect on our own per-
seems preposterous to suggest that infants and animals ceptions: our brain would form a scene of what it sees,
are unconscious automata. Neurological evidence from but we would become conscious of it—experience it sub-
adult humans can help settle the issue by asking jectively—only when we, as a subject of experience,
whether consciousness is preserved in patients with watch that scene from the inside. This suggestion is often
aphasia. Nichelli (Chapter 23) reviews the evidence framed in a neurobiological context by assuming that
indicating that even deep aphasia does not seem to patterns of activity corresponding to “unconscious” or
interrupt the flow of experience, though it may alter or “subconscious” percepts form in posterior regions of the
abolish certain aspects of it, such as inner speech. He cerebral cortex involved in the categorization/associa-
points to the remarkable interview with Dr. Jill Bolte- tion of sensory stimuli. These percepts then become con-
Taylor, a neuroanatomist who was struck with a left scious when mainly anterior prefrontal and cingulate
hemisphere hemorrhage. Over the course of 3!4 h, she regions involved in self-representations interact with
lost her inner speech, became hemiparetic, and soon posterior cortex, perhaps by reading in signals through
realized that her utterances did not make sense, nor did forward connections and selectively amplifying them
those of others. In her retrospective recall of that time, through back-connections (more on this later).
she experienced the loss of function of a good part of There is of course no doubt that the brain cate- p0225
the left hemisphere, language included, and remained gorizes its own patterns of activity, in the sense that
fully conscious, though things felt differently from a neurons respond mainly to the activity of other neu-
“right hemisphere perspective.” Her account not only rons, so the brain is constantly “looking at itself.”
confirms that consciousness continues in the absence of However, this is not necessarily in terms of a “subject”
language—or at least left hemisphere specializations (the front) looking at an “object” represented in sen-
having to do with comprehension and production, but sory cortices (the back). Leaving aside the mystery of
that thought and self-reflection continue too. Another why reflecting on something should make it conscious,
extraordinary report is from a patient who underwent this scenario is made less plausible by a common
an anesthetic injection (Wada test) into the lower divi- observation: when we become absorbed in some
sion of the left middle anterior artery. The anesthetic intense perceptual task, for example watching an
presumably led to the inactivation of posterior tempo- engrossing movie, playing a fast-paced video game, or
ral, inferior parietal, and lateral temporo-occipital region rushing through the woods at high speed, we are viv-
of the left hemisphere, and caused as expected a deep idly conscious—we are immersed in the rapid flow of
Wernicke aphasia indistinguishable from that due to experience—without any need for reflection or intro-
strokes, except that it was temporary (a few minutes) spection. Often, we become so immersed in such flow
and fully reversible (Lazar et al., 2000). From the that we may lose the sense of self, the inner voice.
patient’s recollections of the experience, it is clear not Perhaps the habit of thinking about consciousness
only that he was conscious and thinking, but that he makes the experts forget that much of experience is
also had a much better understanding of the situation unreflective.
than appeared from the language tests being adminis- A neuroimaging study throws some interesting light p0230
tered. Moreover, he could usually recall what happened on these old observations (Goldberg et al., 2006).
and what he was trying to do, especially when pre- Subjects were scanned with functional magnetic reso-
sented with pictures rather than with spoken or written nance imaging (fMRI) in three conditions (Figure 25.1).
material. For instance, he recalled that he was desper- In the slow categorization task, subjects were asked to
ately trying to identify the picture of a tennis racket, of categorize pictures into animal/no-animal categories.
which he was fully aware, but all that came out was During the introspective task, subjects viewed the
“perkbull.” He wanted to add that he owned one, but images and then self-introspected about their emotional
thought he had said instead that he had just bought response (strong/neutral). Finally, the fast categoriza-
one—in reality, he had said nothing. These examples tion task was identical to the “slow” condition but at

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


400 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

f0010 FIGURE 25.1 Introspection versus sensorimotor activation. (A) Main activation for introspection (versus slow categorization) is in prefron-
tal areas and lateralized to the left hemisphere (yellow-orange) whereas main activation for rapid categorization (versus slow categorization)
is in the left motor and bilateral premotor regions (green). (B) Averaged time courses from the left superior frontal gyrus (SFG) during intro-
spection (red), rapid (dark blue), and slow (light blue) categorization conditions. Only introspection showed a positive response in this area.
ACC, anterior cingulate cortex; CS, central sulcus; IFG, inferior frontal gyrus; IPC, inferior parietal cortex; IPS, intraparietal sulcus; LOC, lat-
eral occipital complex; LS, lateral sulcus; pCgS, paracingulate sulcus; SFG, superior frontal gyrus; SFS, superior frontal sulcus; STS, superior
temporal sulcus. Source: Adapted from Goldberg et al. (2006).

triple the stimulation rate. Thus, “slow” and “introspec- upon it and report it to others. Indeed, it appears that
tion” conditions were identical in terms of sensory self-related activity is actually shut off during highly
stimuli and motor output but differed in the cognitive demanding sensory tasks (Goldberg et al., 2006).
task. On the other hand, “slow” and “rapid” conditions A recent fMRI study of binocular rivalry employing
were similar in the cognitive task but differed in optokinetic nystagmus and pupil size also showed that
the sensorimotor processing and attentional loads. frontal activity relates to introspection and report rather
Behavioral measurements confirmed that self- than to conscious perception (Frässle et al., 2014).
awareness was high during the introspection task, and
virtually abolished during rapid categorization. The
neuroimaging results were clear: during introspection Consciousness and Attention s0030

task there was an activation of prefrontal regions, Attention and consciousness often go hand-in- p0235
whereas sensory cortex was strongly activated during hand: when we pay attention to an object, our experi-
rapid categorization (Figure 25.1). Crucially, during ence of it becomes more vivid, and when we shift our
the rapid categorization task self-related cortex was attention, it fades from consciousness. Attention can
deactivated below the rest condition (Chapter 6). This be bottom-up, as when a salient stimulus—say a flash
deactivation of prefrontal regions was thus the neural or a sound turn our gaze or a colored letter in the
correlate of “losing oneself” in the categorization task. middle of a black text pops out at us, capturing atten-
To the extent that these prefrontal regions were indeed tion. Top-down attention instead is willingly deployed
involved in self-representation, these findings suggest toward a particular position in space, a particular
that their activation is not necessary for the emergence feature, or a particular object. It is often assumed that
of perceptual consciousness, but only to reflect attention is a necessary prerequisite for consciousness.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


CONSCIOUSNESS AND OTHER BRAIN FUNCTIONS 401
For example, if we do not attend to it, we may fail to necessarily result in conscious experience, and may even
see a large, stable stimulus at the very center of the be counterproductive.
visual display—the phenomenon known as inatten- The complementary dissociation—consciousness p0245
tional blindness (Mack and Rock, 1998). This view had without attention—is more controversial. When we
led many authors to think that consciousness and contemplate an empty blue sky, there is no need for
attention are indistinguishably intertwined, if not selective attention, and yet the experience is vivid.
identical (Chun and Wolfe, 2000; De Brigard and Conversely, when we attend intensely onto something,
Prinz, 2010; Cohen and Dennett, 2011; Marchetti, the world outside the focus of attention does not
2012). However, already Wundt and James argued disappear from consciousness: we still experience the
that attention was a mechanism for selecting within gist or context of the overall visual scene that faces us.
consciousness, and many studies since have reinforced Indeed, as observed by Tsuchiya and Koch, gist is
this view (Baars, 1997; Lamme, 2003; Koch and immune from inattentional blindness (Mack and Rock,
Tsuchiya, 2007, 2012). 1998)—when a photograph covering the entire back-
p0240 Tsuchiya and Koch make an especially strong case for ground is briefly and unexpectedly flashed onto the
a double dissociation between visual attention and visual screen, subjects can accurately report a summary of its
consciousness (Koch and Tsuchiya, 2007, 2012) content. In the 30 ms necessary to apprehend the gist of
(Chapter 5). For example, paying attention to a stimulus a scene, top-down attention cannot play much of a role.
decreases the duration of its afterimage, whereas seeing Similarly, a subject engaged in a task that requires focus-
the stimulus consciously increases the afterimage dura- ing attention on the center of the visual field, can still
tion, suggesting that attention and consciousness have perceive the difference between a background scene
contrasting effects (van Boxtel et al., 2010). The tip-of-the- containing an animal or a vehicle from one that
tongue phenomenon may be a familiar demonstration does not. Of course, while the gist of a scene may be
that attention may actually interfere with consciousness. experienced vividly, it is also coarse (Campana and
There are by now many reports, both in blindsight Tallon-Baudry, 2013). For example, outside the focus of
patients and healthy subjects, indicating that attention attention subjects cannot differentiate between a red-
can facilitate responses to unseen stimuli (Kentridge green bisected disk and a green-red one (Li et al., 2002).
et al., 1999, 2008; Zhang et al., 2012; Kentridge, 2013). For Or consider what happens when one is driving home on
instance, a recent study using continuous flash suppres- a familiar segment of the highway while attending to an
sion showed that a pop-out target can capture attention engaging radio program. While we are not attending the
even when the stimulus itself is invisible (Hsieh et al., familiar and monotonous road, does it mean that we do
2011). Another recent study reported that post-cued not experience at all, or is rather that we do not need
attention can retrospectively trigger the conscious percep- to form explicit memories (see below)? Finally, as indi-
tion of a stimulus that would otherwise have remained cated by neuroimaging studies mentioned above,
unconscious, and this effect lasts up to 400 ms after consciousness without attention and consciousness with
stimulus presentation (Sergent et al., 2013). Attention attention may have different neural correlates: Victor
without consciousness has now been demonstrated in Lamme has suggested that consciousness without atten-
more than 40 experiments manipulating bottom-up as tion could be generated by interactions among posterior
well as top-down spatial, temporal, feature-based, and regions of the cortex, whereas when top-down attention
object-based attention (Dehaene et al., 2006; van Boxtel boosts conscious experience prefrontal cortex enters the
et al., 2010; Cohen et al., 2012). Some neurophysiological game through reentrant interactions with posterior
and neuroimaging evidence also seems consistent with cortex (Lamme, 2006). We will return to this distinction
this view. For instance, an event-related potential compo- when considering the role of the front vs. the back of the
nent (N2pc) that appears to be a correlate of top-down brain in generating consciousness.
attention can be elicited by stimuli that remain invisible
(Woodman and Luck, 2003); also, attention to an invisible
stimulus can increase the activation of primary visual
cortex (Bahrami et al., 2007). Finally, a magnetoencepha-
Consciousness and Memory s0035

lography study showed that consciously seen stimuli Considerations similar to those just reviewed for p0250
induced increased mid-frequency gamma-band activity attention are likely to apply to working memory—the
over contralateral visual cortex whether attended or not, ability to keep things in mind for a few seconds. Indeed,
whereas spatial attention modulated high-frequency attention and working memory are closely related and
gamma-band activity in response to both consciously may be conceptualized as two different aspects of the
seen and unseen stimuli (Wyart and Tallon-Baudry, same process (Olivers, 2008): attention selects some
2008). In summary, attention can be deployed to stimuli aspects of an existing scene, whereas working memory
that remain unconscious, selective attention does not selects the same aspects in the absence of the stimulus.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


402 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

Moreover, the neural structures subserving working be present even when episodic memory is impaired (the
memory and top-down attention overlap to a large converse would seem to be out of the question). In
degree both anatomically and functionally (Mayer et al., syndromes of transient amnesia, patients are obviously
2007). Should one then expect a double dissociation conscious—they engage in conversations, carry out
also between working memory and consciousness? This complex tasks, but later show no memory of what they
question is complicated by the need to distinguish did (anterograde amnesia) (Bartsch and Deuschl, 2010)
between the targets of attention, working memory, and (Chapter 22). Butler and Zeman discuss a case described
imagery, typically located in posterior cortex, where by Hughlings-Jackson in which a doctor suffering from
activity is either enhanced in response to a stimulus, or epileptic transient amnesia visited a patient, correctly
else maintained or even generated in its absence; and diagnosed pneumonia, and wrote down prescriptions
control mechanisms, typically located in anterior cortex, and notes without remembering anything about the
which are responsible for directing attention, manipulat- episode. Perhaps the amnesia for a stretch of familiar
ing contents of working memory, and generate images highway is a normal example of the same dissociation:
(Postle, 2006). under normal circumstances, if our attention is engaged
p0255 Nevertheless, recent studies indicate that working elsewhere, and if there is no particular reason to engage
memory can be engaged without awareness (Hassin it on the scene we face when driving, we may simply not
et al., 2009; Soto and Silvanto, 2014). For instance, burden hippocampal circuits to lay down useless memo-
subjects can maintain in memory some visual cues ries. In transient amnesia, the hippocampus may not be
during a delay period filled with similar distractors and capable of laying down memories, either due to some
perform above chance level even though they are not kind of trauma (transient global amnesia) or because it
conscious of the cues, as shown by an awareness rating is preempted by seizure activity (transient epileptic
scale (Soto et al., 2011). Also, perceptual processing of amnesia). When damage to the hippocampal formation
unseen stimuli can be biased top-down by working is permanent, as with the bitemporal resection suffered
memory (Pan et al., 2014). Moreover, arithmetic by H.M. and similar patients, anterograde amnesia is
problems involving working memory can be solved permanent, and the patient is limited to the immediate
based on information that remains unconscious present and to the content of his working memory
(Ric and Muller, 2012; Sklar et al., 2012). Finally, (Squire, 2009; Corkin, 2013). Yet as described by Postle
monkeys who had their primary visual cortex removed (Chapter 21), when interacting with H.M. there was little
can make accurate saccades to a target presented in the doubt that he was conscious.
blind field even after the target has disappeared On the other hand, when amnesia is deep, con- p0265
from the screen (Takaura et al., 2011). Conversely, it is sciousness is altered in peculiar ways. Usually,
undisputable that one can be conscious of something patients with transient amnesia appear to be confused
without exercising working memory, as when we and uncertain about the past (retrograde amnesia).
follow the rapid flow of images in a movie. Indeed, H.M. and other patients recounted by Postle
when photographs or line drawings are flashed at a (Chapter 21) describe an unsettling feeling of entering
rapid rate, subjects are very poor at remembering the world as from deep sleep, when we may be briefly
a particular picture at a later time, yet they have no unsure about who we are and where we are, except
trouble seeing it—and detecting it—if they are cued that feeling in their case is permanent. Possibly, this
prior to the experiment (at 110!333 ms/picture, the deficit may also reduce the window of time over
experience is one of “grasping and losing large amounts which the conscious present flows. Moreover, several
of information within moments”) (Intraub, 1999). Also, studies have shown that patients with damage to the
several examples of inattentional blindness may hippocampal formation also show a deficit in imagina-
actually be cases of inattentional amnesia (Wolfe, 1999). tion, not just in memory, and their account of the
The latter may be the rule for low-level features, partly world, both remembered, experienced in the present,
because these features should be reset every time the and imagined, appears to be less rich, lacking in color,
image changes, and partly because it seems neither detail, and spatial coherence (Lee et al., 2005a; Barense
possible nor particularly useful to store a detailed snap- et al., 2007; Hassabis et al., 2007; Mullally et al., 2012).
shot of every fleeting activation pattern in low-level This view fits nicely with evidence for a role of the
visual areas. Finally, there are disorders, typically asso- hippocampal formation in responding to as well as
ciated with prefrontal lesions, in which working mem- storing relations among objects in a context-dependent
ory is severely compromised but consciousness is (episodic) manner (Hannula et al., 2006). Over time
clearly preserved (Muller and Knight, 2006). and over multiple episodes of retrieval the memory is
p0260 The relationship between consciousness and epi- transformed to one that is more schematic (semantic)
sodic memory (also known as autonoetic memory) is and independent of the hippocampus (Nadel and
complex, but there is little doubt that consciousness can Moscovitch, 1997; Winocur et al., 2007). Thus, while

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


CONSCIOUSNESS AND OTHER BRAIN FUNCTIONS 403
consciousness remains in the absence of episodic different frames of reference, showing responses to one
memory and of the hippocampal formation, it does stimulus modality (e.g., visual) that are influenced in a
seem to lose not just an external sketchpad for writing multiplicative manner by stimuli in other modalities
down memories, but actually a part of itself. (e.g., proprioceptive or vestibular)—an effect called gain
modulation (Cohen and Andersen, 2002).
How much of the information about external space p0280
that is constantly being updated within and across these
s0040 Consciousness and Space many maps leads to experience, and how much instead
p0270 We all have the strong impression that much of remains unconscious? Conscious experience of space is
experience is situated in an outside, external space. In so pervasive that it seems to provide a general frame-
turn, this external space is centered on an internal work for much of what we experience, at least in the
space, that of the body. And, whenever we think about visual and auditory domains. In fact, Kant thought that
our own experience, nothing is stronger than the feeling space was an essential substrate for all experience. For
that it is centered somewhere within the head, roughly the same reason, it is difficult to evaluate neuropsycho-
between the eyes. Can consciousness even exist without logical evidence to address the question whether
any representation of space, or of our own body, or consciousness could persist in the absence of spatial
without our “first-person” perspective, centered some- concepts and a spatial frame of reference. Patients with
where behind the eyes? These questions are hard to hemianopia due to occipito-parietal strokes are often
answer on the basis of neurological evidence because unaware of their deficit (Celesia et al., 1997; Baier et al.,
maps of space and of the body are widespread, and 2015), suggesting that one can lose awareness of
lesions that eliminate all such maps would have to be part of space. Patients with simultagnosia—a classic
so wide as to make any firm conclusion unwarranted. component of Balint’s syndrome (together with optic
Nevertheless, a few lessons can still be learned. ataxia and apraxia of gaze (Robertson, 2004), have an
p0275 Neurophysiological studies have demonstrated that extremely narrow “window of attention” (Dalrymple
the brain employs multiple maps of external space, some et al., 2013): at any given time they only experience one
unimodal, some multimodal, many in the cerebral particular object, the one that happens to grab their
cortex, especially but not exclusively in parietal lobes, fixation point, at the exclusion of everything else.
but some also in thalamus and colliculi. Parietal areas Moreover, while they can easily recognize and describe
receive converging visual, auditory, and touch inputs, as the object they are experiencing, they have no idea of
well as proprioceptive and vestibular signals about the where it might be in space: left, right, up and down are
position of the eyes, head, and limbs. These maps impossible for them to say, and especially spatial
implement different frames of reference, so there are relationships among objects are out of the question.
eye-centered, head-centered, and body-centered maps, They also have a problem binding colors with shapes,
maps for distant space and maps for peri-personal space as indicated by frequent illusory conjunctions, in which
(Robertson, 2004). Attention can rapidly shift between the color of another object is mistakenly attributed to
one frame of reference and the other, and there are the one they are experiencing. In the few cases studied
indications that more global frames of reference may be in detail, the site of the lesion was bilateral inferior pari-
a specialty of right hemisphere maps, whereas more etal cortex, centered around the angular gyrus (area 39).
local maps are a specialty of the left. It is also clear that, As usual with attention and consciousness, it is difficult
under normal conditions, many different maps are kept to decide whether the problem with simultagnosia is
in register for smooth functioning, and that posterior primarily one of narrow attention, which makes it
parietal cortex, especially on the right side, is important impossible for them to be aware of where things are in
in coordinating these various maps, perhaps through visual (or auditory) space. Yet simultagnosics still seem
what has been called a master map. Indeed, studies in to know that space exists and contains objects they can-
monkeys have identified neurons that respond only to not see (see Robertson, 2004, p. 159), they still experi-
the stimulus that is being selected as the current target ence space in reference to their own body, as well as
for attention—a kind of a winner-takes-all principle over within a single, spatially extended object. In this sense,
space, and do so in a stable manner, in line with the simultagnosia would be an extreme form of extinction,
need of a stable perceptual representation of a target for in which the object they are attending extinguishes any
action (Andersen et al., 2014). This fits with the finding other object in the visual field (see Robertson, 2004,
that parietal neurons are involved not only in multi- p. 159). The inability to locate the single perceived
modal spatial integration of sensory input, but also in object in extrapersonal space might then be due not to
the early stages of planning spatial movements. unawareness of space per se, but to a disconnection
Multimodal neurons in different parietal areas are also (unbinding) of ventral stream neurons specifying
well-suited to mediate smooth transformations between position-invariant concepts of the object from the dorsal

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


404 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

stream neurons specifying spatial locations, due to a left hemispheres is kept in a delicate push-pull balance
lesion of some of the maps that link the two streams. through mutual inhibitory interactions.
p0285 While simultagnosia is exceedingly rare, presum- A constellation of symptoms that usually accompa- p0290
ably because it involves bilateral, symmetric parietal nies hemispatial neglect is a reduction in arousal and
lesions, neglect is a common occurrence, especially vigilance, as well as an inability to maintain sustained
early on after acute brain lesions on the right side attention. These functions, together with the reorienting
(Chapter 18). A patient with hemispatial neglect acts of attention, are supported by the ventral attention net-
as if he is inattentive to one half of the world—most work, which is lateralized to the right hemisphere and
often the left half. He may not notice people and may receive preferential innervation from brainstem
objects on the left side, may read only the right side of and subcortical systems that promote arousal (Corbetta
a map, may eat only the right side of the food on his and Shulman, 2011; Corbetta, 2014; Gazzaniga et al.,
plate, or shave only one side of his face. Neglect can 2014). The ventral attention network includes ventral
occur in sensory modalities besides vision, including frontal cortex and insula, the temporoparietal junction
audition, touch, proprioception, and smell, and it can and the superior temporal gyrus.
affect various aspects of space, from one’s own body Over the past several years, an extensive set of p0295
(personal space) to nearby objects (peri-personal space) anatomical and functional studies has led to a compre-
to distant objects. For example, one patient may hensive model of hemispatial neglect (Corbetta and
neglect objects on the left side that are out of reach but Shulman, 2011; Corbetta, 2014; Gazzaniga et al., 2014).
not objects nearby, another one may neglect only Right cortical lesions causing neglect tend to occur in
objects that are within reach, and yet another may the ventral attention network and in the underlying
neglect his own left face. Or a patient may ignore his white matter, especially the superior longitudinal
left arm and leg, trying to climb out of bed without fasciculus, thus explaining the problems with arousal,
them even though he is not at all paralyzed. Finally, vigilance and sustained attention. However, these right
some patients may show predominantly motor neglect, ventral lesions also cause large-scale changes of func-
in that their eye or hand movements are biased toward tional connectivity within and between bilateral dorsal
the right. In the clinic, hemispatial neglect can be frontoparietal networks, in their interactions with
revealed by simple paper-and-pencil tests. For exam- default mode and control networks, and in their inter-
ple, asked to mark all lines on a page, the patient actions with the basal ganglia (Baldassarre et al., 2014).
marks only those on the right side. Asked to mark the Changes in functional connectivity and, presumably,
middle of a line, he errs toward the right side. Asked excitability may lead to a reduced activation of the
to draw a figure, he leaves out the left side of it. right dorsal attention network, impairing the normal
Nevertheless, a typical neglect patient is definitely not interhemispheric balance between the left and right
blind: if an isolated object is shown on the left, the side, thereby accounting for hemispatial neglect
patient can see it and pick it up. Indeed, neglect is (Corbetta et al., 2005). Moreover, the reduced activa-
most apparent in competitive situations, a phenome- tion of many spatial maps on the right side indirectly
non called “extinction.” The same stimulus on the left affects sensory regions, at least in the acute stage of
side that is reported if presented alone, is ignored if neglect (Corbetta et al., 2005). This conclusion is
presented simultaneously with a stimulus on the right supported by the partial, short-lasting recovery of
side. Importantly, patients may also show neglect for neglect that can be achieved by increasing arousal and
imagined or remembered left space: asked to imagine the degree of activation of the right hemisphere, for
the buildings lining the main piazza in Milan, a patient example by galvanic or caloric stimulation of the ear.
would only recall those on the right side of where he
imagined himself standing (Bisiach and Luzzatti,
1978). In short, a patient with neglect behaves as if his
attention were pathologically attracted to events and
Consciousness, Body, and Self s0045

things on the right side and pathologically insensitive Can consciousness exist in the absence of a sense of p0300
to events and things on the left side. The spatial bias of self or of a body? The self is a multilayered concept,
attention that causes neglect is thought to depend on and different people or disciplines tend to conceptual-
an imbalance between the left and right dorsal atten- ize it in very different ways. In a neurological context, it
tion networks. These frontoparietal networks, which is useful to keep a few distinctions in mind. First and
include the frontal eye field and the intraparietal foremost is the narrative, autobiographical self—the one
sulcus, contain multiple maps of space, including that characterizes in a fundamental sense who we are.
maps for directing attention, eye movements, and As important as this self may be for each of us, it seems
arm movements directed toward contralateral space. clear that an autobiographical self is not a prerequisite
Normally, activity in the two sets of maps in right and for experience—just think of how it may take some time

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


CONSCIOUSNESS AND OTHER BRAIN FUNCTIONS 405
to reconnect with it when awakening in the morning, respect to his body, typically hovering over it at some
though experience is already present. distance. Moreover, he may be able to contemplate his
p0305 Then there is the feeling of agency: experiencing that own body from this new perspective (autoscopy).
one is the source of one’s actions There is a growing Out-of-body experiences, which can be triggered by
neurological literature about the neural substrate of brain lesions, seizures, anesthesia and some drugs, and
agency, and about how agency may be altered in sometimes occur when falling asleep, are associated
pathological conditions (Ruby and Decety, 2001; Frith, with an altered functioning of the temporo-parietal
2002; Farrer et al., 2003; David et al., 2006). Again, junction, including the insula, especially on the right
however, it seems that experience of agency is not side. This brain region combines tactile, propriocep-
necessary for consciousness—one can be completely tive, and visual signals in a coordinated reference
passive and still experience the flow of images. frame, and receives abundant vestibular projections. It
p0310 At a more basic level then there is the feeling of owner- is activated when subjects imagine to change perspec-
ship—the knowledge that your body and its parts are tive and see the world from somewhere else (e.g.,
indeed yours. The body is heavily represented in the Vogeley et al., 2004). Compellingly, focal electrical
brain, and not only in the cerebral cortex. There are maps stimulation in the same area can produce full-fledged
of the body already in the brainstem, in the thalamus, out-of-body experiences (Blanke et al., 2005). Clinical
and in multiple cortical areas, especially primary and data and a further electrical stimulation study in
secondary somatosensory cortex, right posterior insular humans suggest that disembodiment and autoscopy
cortex, and portions of the parieto-temporal junction. (and change in perspective) can be dissociated: disem-
The representations deal with touch, proprioception, and bodiment would be due to perturbations of the junc-
vestibular signals, which very soon become integrated tion between right supramarginal and angular gyri,
into multimodal maps. The hypothalamus and brainstem leading to somatosensory-vestibular disintegration,
have access to many other inputs from the body and the whereas autoscopy/change in perspective would be
viscera, although much of what is recorded there does obtained by perturbing a slightly more posterior
not seem to make it to consciousness. region of the right angular gyrus involving visual
p0315 Like the experience of external space, the experience of pathways (De Ridder et al., 2007). An extrastriate body
our own body might appear as an integral aspect of all areas is also thought to be involved in perception of
experience. Usually, awareness of the body is discrete the body (Downing et al., 2001; Arzy et al., 2006b). It
and stays in the background, perhaps because it is always remains to be clarified whether disembodiment can
there and is relatively stable compared to the awareness indeed be construed as a true lack of experience of the
of external circumstances. But is a complete loss of body body, or rather as a dislocation of such experience. But
awareness impossible, perhaps even unconceivable? altogether, asomatognosia and out-of-body experiences
A few intriguing phenomena may speak to the issue. suggest that it may be possible to lose one’s bodily self
p0320 Recent experiments, exploiting for instance the so- without losing consciousness.
called rubber hand illusion, have shown that our sense What seems to be left if we take away the bodily self p0330
of ownership can be altered, and we may feel like we is the centeredness of any experience: even in the out-of
own a hand that is not ours (Tsakiris et al., 2007). The body experience, experience seems to be localized
sense that our body is ours appears to depend on neu- somewhere behind the eyes, even if such disembodied
ral circuits centered in right posterior insula. Then self is not associated with any physical simulacrum.
there is asomatognosia, a condition in which patients But it is centered somewhere. One could argue
may claim that the left arm and leg may be missing, or that what is centered in this case is just the visual expe-
that it may disappear. In such cases the site of lesions rience of space—since subjects report seeing their
is usually in right posterior parietal areas, though own body from such altered first-person perspective.
premotor cortex may also play a role (Arzy et al., Conceivably, however, one could have an out-of-body
2006a). Asomatognosia suggests that certain brain experience induced in a patient with Balint’s syndrome,
lesions may selectively eliminate awareness of the in which case there would be simultagnosia—the loss
body without compromising consciousness. However, of a spatial reference frame for experience, together
asomatognosia is usually for just a part of the body, so with a loss of a reference to the body. What kind of
firm conclusions are not possible. experience would this be, or would experience vanish?
p0325 A more global phenomenon is the out-of-body expe- Though such thought experiments are always danger-
rience (Lenggenhager et al., 2006) (Chapter 20). In its ous, a reasonable guess would be that experience would
full manifestation, a subject may feel that he is disem- still persists: like a Balint patient, one would experience
bodied, that is, he does not feel located within his own a single object, or say an intense smell, not located in
body. Instead, the subject feels that he—his experienc- space, and not associated to a body. Perhaps states
ing self—is located or centered somewhere else with achieved thorough transcendental meditation

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


406 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

techniques can approximate a loss of awareness of association with other areas that ensure a proper level
space, body, and self: experts reports a feeling of silence, of consciousness); another cortical area A provides
no bodily feelings, unboundedness (no space, and possi- “processed” sensory input to area C—say by comput-
bly no self), and no time. Even in such cases, though, the ing color constancy—so that the appropriate activity
experience would still be happening to one particular patterns are triggered in C when a surface of a certain
entity—it would be “centered,” if you wish, but not in reflectance is viewed; finally, a cortical area B can
the conventional spatial sense. This last sense of “self,” generate similar patterns (maybe less effectively) in C
which we may call the “intrinsic” or “subjective” self— in a top-down manner, implementing the ability to
would be one and the same as the experience, not imagine colors.
further dissociable. Given such a scenario, a lesion of area A would p0350
lead to what might be called pure achromatopsia: a
patient would not be able to discriminate among colors
and would not experience colors when presented with
s0050 Consciousness, Perception, Imagination, and
colored stimuli. However, the patient would still be
Absolute Agnosia able to imagine, remember, or dream of colors.
p0335 Neuropsychology provides perhaps the most com- Moreover, he would be perfectly aware that he is miss-
pelling evidence concerning which brain areas are ing color, that is, things would look strangely black
necessary for experiencing particular conscious modali- and white. Such patients have indeed been described
ties. In principle, compiling a list of the areas whose (Shuren et al., 1996; Bartolomeo et al., 1997). For exam-
lesion eliminates the experience of colors, shapes, ple, E.H. (Shuren et al., 1996) was impaired at color
visual motion, faces, places and so on, should yield the perception: he could not recognize colored characters
anatomical substrate of conscious vision. Completing in the Ishihara pseudoisochromatic plates, could not
the list for other modalities and submodalities would arrange patches in terms of their hue, and could
yield the anatomical substrate of consciousness in its not match objects with the proper colored swatch. On
entirety. However, such a list is hard to come by, and the other hand, he could imagine colored objects and
not just because brain lesions are rarely selective and say the appropriate color, and respond correctly if
symptoms change with time: a more fundamental asked, for example, which of a plum and an eggplant
reason is that, to ascertain that the neural substrate of had more red in it.
a conscious modality, say a sensory modality, has truly By contrast, a lesion of area B would lead to the p0355
been eliminated, one must be able to demonstrate a isolated loss of the ability to imagine colors, with no
complete loss of: (i) the corresponding sensory experi- deficit in color perception, and a preserved understand-
ences; (ii) the ability to imagine, remember, or dream ing of what color means. Again, such patients have
any such experience; (iii) the first-hand understanding been described (De Vreese, 1991, case II; Goldenberg,
of what is missing. 1992, case KQu; Luzzatti and Davidoff, 1994, see also
p0340 To see why, consider first a simple thought experi- Bartolomeo, 2002). An especially selective example is
ment concerning a hypothetical sixth sense—let’s say that of patient QP (Jakobson et al., 2008), who had an
echolocation. Obviously, we are not endowed with isolated deficit in color imagery and color memory sec-
neural hardware appropriate for generating echoloca- ondary to a concussive episode. QP had normal color
tion qualia. Not surprisingly, when we move around perception, would properly name colors, could even
our house, we do not experience any echolocation-like dream in color, but since the time of the injury she had
quale. But it is not just a matter of not having the trouble imagining colors or remembering most colors,
appropriate sensors or sensory pathways: we cannot both short and long-term (intriguingly, she had little
even imagine what such a quale would feel like, or problem with shades of blue).
dream that we are echolocating. Finally, we do not Continuing along these lines, a combined lesion of p0360
really understand first-hand what we are missing, both areas A and B (or of their connections) would
even though we may know a lot about how bats, for produce a patient who not only does not experience
example, make use of echolocation, and some of us the color of objects but, in addition, cannot imagine or
can talk about echolocation in great detail. Equipping remember color. However, he would be fully aware
us with a bat-like sonar (say with a visual or auditory that his world has turned black and white, and would
output) might help us to navigate in the dark, but it complain about missing color. Such achromatopsic
would not generate echolocation qualia. patients with no color imagery have also been
p0345 To make things a bit more concrete, consider a described. For example, the painter I., recounted by
conscious submodality we are familiar with, namely Oliver Sacks (1995), described his symptoms after a car
color. Assume that a cortical area C is the one actually accident thus: “My vision was such that everything
responsible for providing us with color qualia (in appeared to me as a black and white television screen

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


CONSCIOUSNESS AND OTHER BRAIN FUNCTIONS 407
. . . I can see a worm wiggling a block away. . . But—I about the physics of color, but it would seem that he
AM TOTALLY COLOUR-BLIND.” To him it made no knows about color second-hand, as a biologist may
difference if he was looking with his eyes open, or know about echolocation. Uneasily, he admits that he
attempting to imagine colors, or remembering scenes may be color blind “or something like that,” though
that he knew had color or whether he was dreaming— occasionally he claims to like colors (especially Fauve
he only saw “awful and disgusting” shades of grey. paintings). It may be that, though he does see differ-
Being a painter, he could discuss the 256 colors of the ences between differently colored objects, these may be
Pantone chart and the finer aspects of hues without in terms of brightness or other achromatic attributes,
being able to see them. Obviously, patient I. under- and that he may lack color qualia. In that case, he may
stood perfectly what colors meant, and was over- not really understand color first-hand the way normal
whelmed by its loss. In such cases, one could speculate subjects do, or the way pure achromatopsic patients
that area C, being deafferented from areas A and B, do: we might call his condition one of absolute agnosia
would have no opportunity to become activated, but it for color. Absolute agnosia would automatically imply
would still be functional (for example, direct stimula- loss of conscious perception for that modality, as well
tion with transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) as loss of imagery, memory, and dreaming. What
might produce colored phosphenes). The inactivity of MAH is missing, then, would truly be the neural
area C would then constantly signal to upstream areas substrate for the qualia pertaining to the color sub-
that the current visual input is achromatic, just as modality, due to the absence of the relevant circuits.
when watching black and white movies. Recently, another patient has been identified who,
p0365 However, feeling of an absence is not the same as during the initial phase after a stroke, had an absolute
an absence of feeling—having a functional but inactive agnosia for color: he could not discriminate colors and,
area C is very different from not having it at all. in addition, he had no idea of what he was missing
Indeed, with damage to area C, there should be a com- (von Arx et al., 2010) (Figure 25.2). Thus, at least in
plete loss of color consciousness, whether seen, imag- principle, identifying patients with absolute agnosia
ined, remembered or dreamt and, crucially, the patient for different modalities and submodalities of con-
would not understand first-hand what color really sciousness, as well as the underlying dysfunction (the
means (just as we do not understand echolocation equivalent of “area C”) would reveal the true neural
first-hand) and what he is missing. Nevertheless, he substrate of the corresponding qualia.
could certainly talk about color second-hand, just as
we can talk about echolocation. A patient possibly sim-
ilar to this ideal case has also been described (van
Zandvoort et al., 2007). Patient MAH seems to have a
Consciousness and Anosognosia s0055

pure form of color agnosia: he cannot name the color Given the above definition of absolute agnosia (lack p0370
of colored pencils (though he has no problem with of first-hand understanding) as essential to the lack of
color naming per se), and he cannot tell whether an consciousness in a given modality, it is natural to ask
object is shown with its proper color (as opposed to, whether examples of anosognosia (unawareness of def-
say, a purple banana). Moreover, he fails to group icit) in the neuropsychological literature (Vuilleumier,
colored tokens according to their color, and is clearly 2000, 2004; Prigatano, 2009) may represent a similar
not sure about what he is trying to do. When asked to lack of first-hand understanding, and thus of con-
color line drawings of common objects, he produced sciousness for that modality. Patients with anosognosia
an orange cherry with a purple stick, or a blue often seem to deny their loss without understanding
meadow with pink daffodils. On the other hand, MAH what they are talking about. For instance, patients with
can respond to color unconsciously, as demonstrated Anton’s syndrome can be completely blind due to cor-
by priming tasks and a Stroop task, and he performed tical lesions (to the point that they may not be able to
flawlessly and rapidly on the Ishihara test (he could tell whether the light is on or off), yet they insist that
easily see the characters as being different from the they do see, and make up excuses as to why they fail
background). He could also discriminate between dif- in the simplest visual tasks. It could be that such
ferent hues, although slowly and with little confidence patients, besides being blind, have indeed absolute
about what he was doing. But when asked about the agnosia for vision, having lost all sense of what seeing
color of a bright green bag, he hesitated, and then said (and not seeing) means: they may merely resort to
it was a bright color, perhaps yellow or orange. His vision-related words and memories without actually
condition was apparently congenital (and possibly being able to experience anything visual, not even in
hereditary, as his mother and one of his daughters their imagination or their dreams.
showed similar deficits), and he had no relevant neu- Examples of selective anosognosia are hard to come p0375
rological problem. MAH is highly educated and knows by, but there are examples of selective unawareness of

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


408 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

f0015 FIGURE 25.2 Cerebral achromatopsia with anosognosia. The patient could only see shades of grey but did not report impaired color per-
ception (the deficit lasted less than 2 months). (A) Axial T2-weighted MRI scan slices of the patient showing bilateral hyperintense lesions in
the occipito-temporal cortex 2 days after the stroke. (B) During an Ishihara task, the patient showed visual fixations that were unsystematically
distributed while the control subject clearly followed the path. (C) Fixation density plots for an object-color matching task where subjects were
instructed to search for any oddity in the image (here a blue carrot). The patient did not notice anything in particular. Source: Adapted from
von Arx et al. (2010).

deficits in other visual submodalities, such as anosogno- determine, in each patient, what exactly is amiss
sia for face perception (Young et al., 1990), and in other within a given modality of consciousness: does he lack
modalities, such as anosognosia for hemi-anesthesia, for the relevant aspects of conscious perception as well as
unilateral neglect, for language comprehension and imagination, memory, dreaming and, crucially, first-
production, and so on. A dramatic example of anosog- hand understanding of what he is missing? Does he
nosia is unawareness of motor deficit, whereby patients have a selective anosognosia because of an absolute
deny that their left arm or leg is paralyzed, and usually agnosia, or conversely because he can still concoct
ignore requests to move it (often in the absence of sen- conscious images in the absence of sensory input? And
sory loss and intellectual impairment). Recent studies can he still make covert (unconscious) use of relevant
have indicated that unawareness of (left) paralysis may information? All of these questions must be addressed
result from lesions of (right) premotor cortex, especially before cortical “nodes” for individual modalities and
areas 6 and 44, sensorimotor cortex, and right insula submodalities of consciousness can be identified with
(Berti et al., 2005). These lesions would compromise the some confidence.
comparison between signals representing the intended
actions and those monitoring the actual action
(Spinazzola et al., 2008). In this way, the area responsi- GLOBAL ALTERATIONS OF s0060
ble for motor awareness (“area C”) would receive the CONSCIOUSNESS
motor intention signals (presumably from supplemen-
tary motor area) but no mismatch signal, and would In neurology, a distinction is traditionally drawn p0385
thus not be able to tell that the movement was not between the level of consciousness and the content of
executed. Alternatively, the input layer to “area C” consciousness. When you fall asleep, for example, the
from the sensory stream may be dysfunctional, so the level of consciousness decreases to the point that you
patient cannot tell anymore whether activity patterns in become virtually unconscious—the degree to which
“area C” are triggered by extrinsic or intrinsic sources. you are conscious (of anything) becomes progressively
p0380 These examples not only highlight the importance less and less. The content of consciousness, instead,
of neuropsychological investigations—above and refers to the particular experience you are having at
beyond what can be established with neuroimaging any given time, for a similar level of consciousness.
alone—but they also indicate how difficult it is to This distinction is useful when considering alterations

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


GLOBAL ALTERATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 409
of consciousness. On one side there are localized brain Altogether, these studies point to a breakdown of
lesions that lead to the loss of specific dimensions of functional integration.
consciousness—defined above as absolute agnosia— EEG studies show that, overall, power in the delta p0400
without any major change in the level of conscious- range and slow wave density is lower when subjects
ness. On the other side there are global alterations in report, upon awakening, that they had been conscious
the level of consciousness, such as occur, besides (Chellappa et al., 2011). Moreover, a recent study using
certain stages of sleep, in anesthesia, coma, vegetative high-density EEG shows that, when subjects report
states, and generalized seizures. It is to these that we having been conscious during a NREM sleep episode,
now turn. the EEG is locally activated over a parieto-occipital
hotspot, even though other cortical areas exhibit
slow wave activity (Siclari et al., 2014b). This finding is
consistent with the observation that NREM slow
s0065 Sleep waves most often occur locally, in just a subset
p0390 The most commonplace, daily demonstration that of brain areas (Nir et al., 2011). In REM sleep, this
the level of consciousness can change dramatically is parieto-occipital hotspot of low delta is associated with
provided by sleep (see Chapter 7). In the laboratory, a perceptual experiences whereas a frontal hotspot of
subject is awakened during different stages of sleep high-frequency activity is associated with thought-like
and asked to report “anything that was going through experiences. Moreover, content-specific activations
your mind just before waking up.” What is most note- such as faces, places, movement and speech closely
worthy for the present purposes is that a number of resemble those observed during wakefulness (Siclari
awakenings from non-rapid eye movement (NREM) et al., 2014b). In another recent study, machine-
sleep, especially early in the night when EEG slow learning technique could decode the contents of visual
waves are prevalent, can yield no report whatsoever. imagery during the sleep-onset period from higher-
Thus, early slow wave sleep is the only phase of adult level visual areas (Horikawa et al., 2013).
life during which healthy human subjects may deny What are the mechanisms of loss of consciousness p0405
that they were experiencing anything at all. When during early NREM sleep? It is well established that,
present, reports from NREM sleep early in the night due to a decrease in acetylcholine and other modula-
are often short and thought-like. However, especially tors, cortical and thalamic neurons undergo slow
later in the night, reports from NREM sleep can be oscillations (1 Hz or less) between up- and down-
longer, more hallucinatory and, generally speaking, state (Steriade et al., 2001). During the up-state
more dream-like. On the other hand, awakenings dur- cortical cells remain depolarized at waking levels for
ing REM sleep almost always yield dreams—vivid around a second and fire at waking rates, often in the
conscious experiences, sometimes organized within a gamma range (Destexhe et al., 2007). However, the
complex narrative structure (Hobson et al., 2000; up-state of NREM sleep is not stable as in wakeful-
Hobson and Pace-Schott, 2002; Siclari et al., 2013). ness and REM sleep, but it is inherently bistable. The
p0395 What are the neural correlates of the fading of con- longer neurons remain depolarized, the more likely
sciousness during early slow wave sleep? Metabolic they become to precipitate into a hyperpolarized
rates do decrease in many cortical areas, especially down-state—a complete cessation of synaptic activity
frontal and parietal areas, and related thalamic nuclei, that can last for a tenth of a second or more—after
as is seen in other conditions characterized by reduced which they revert to another up-state. The transition
consciousness, such as coma, vegetative states, and from up- to down-state appears to be due to
anesthesia. By contrast, primary sensory cortices are depolarization-dependent potassium currents and to
not deactivated compared to resting wakefulness short-term synaptic depression, both of which
(Braun et al., 1997; Maquet et al., 1997; Nir et al., 2015). increase with the amount of prior activation (Steriade,
Functional connectivity studies using fMRI and EEG 2003). The slow oscillation is found in virtually every
reveal that, during NREM sleep, the hierarchical cortical neuron, and is synchronized across the corti-
organization of large-scale networks is changed into cal mantle by cortico-cortical connections, which is
smaller independent modules (Boly et al., 2012b; why the EEG records high-voltage, low-frequency
AU:5 Tagliazucchi et al., 2013a,b). A decrease in long-range waves.
functional connectivity has been observed in frontopar- An intriguing possibility is that changes in the level p0410
ietal default mode and dorsal attention networks of consciousness during sleep may be related to the
(Spoormaker et al., 2012; Tagliazucchi et al., 2013a,b). degree of bistability of corticothalamic networks, lead-
Decreased corticothalamic functional connectivity has ing to a breakdown of cortical integration—loosely
also been found in heteromodal regions such as medial defined as the ability of different cortical regions to talk
frontal gyrus and precuneus (Picchioni et al., 2014). to each other (Tononi, 2004a,b; Massimini et al., 2012) AU:6

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


410 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

(Chapter 7). Alternatively, deep sleep may impair con- full-fledged, high-amplitude slow wave (Massimini
sciousness by leading to bistable, stereotypic cortical et al., 2007) that closely resembled spontaneous ones
responses associated with a loss of information and that traveled through much of the cortex
(Tononi, 2004a,b; Massimini et al., 2007). Consider first (Massimini et al., 2004) (Figure 25.3). Such stereotypi-
the loss of integration. During wakefulness, TMS cal responses can be induced even when, for the
induces a sustained response made of rapidly changing preceding seconds, there are no slow waves in
patterns of EEG responses that persists until 300 ms thespontaneous EEG, indicating that perturbations
and involved the sequential activation of specific brain can reveal the potential bistability of a system irre-
areas. During early NREM sleep, however, the brain spective of its observed state. A recent study using
response to TMS changes markedly. When applied to intra-cerebral local field potential recordings coupled
any medial cortical regions, the activity evoked by TMS with single-pulse electrical stimulation of the cerebral
remains localized to the site of stimulation, without cortex shows that stimulation during wakefulness
activating connected brain regions, and lasts for less induces a chain of deterministic phase-locked activa-
than 150 ms (Massimini et al., 2005) (Figure 25.3). This tions in its cortical targets lasting up to 600 ms.
finding indicates that during early NREM sleep, when By contrast, in NREM sleep, the same stimulation
the level of consciousness is reduced, effective connec- triggers a slow wave associated with a cortical
tivity among cortical regions breaks down, implying a down-state (suppression of power .20 Hz), which
corresponding breakdown of cortical integration. interrupts the phase-locked chain. Thus, bistability
Computer simulations suggest that this breakdown of during NREM sleep leads to breakdown of the brain’s
effective connectivity may be due to the induction of a ability to integrate information (Pigorini et al., 2015).
local down-state (Esser et al., 2009). Altogether, these measurements suggest that the
p0415 Further experiments with TMS/EEG suggest that sleeping brain, despite being active and reactive,
early NREM sleep may be associated with a loss of becomes inherently bistable: it either breaks down in
information even when the brain can produce global causally independent modules or bursts into a global,
responses. When applied over centromedian parietal stereotypical response. By contrast, during REM sleep
regions and using higher intensity of stimulation late in the night, when dreams become long and vivid
(i.e., between 65 and 85% of maximal stimulator out- and the level of consciousness returns to levels close
put), each TMS pulse triggers a stereotypical response to those of wakefulness, the responses to TMS also
implying the induction of a global down-state: a recover and come to resemble more closely those

(A)
Wakefulness NREM sleep REM sleep
TMS (90 V/m) TMS (90 V/m) TMS (160 V/m) TMS (90 V/m)

(B) (C)
Wakefulness Anesthesia VS/UWS MCS
TMS (120 V/m) TMS (120 V/m) TMS (120 V/m) TMS (120 V/m)

f0020 FIGURE 25.3 TMS-EEG responses in sleep, anesthesia and post-comatose patients. (A) During wakefulness, transcranial magnetic stimula-
tion (TMS) triggers a widespread response with differentiated patterns of activation. During non rapid eye movement (NREM) sleep, the corti-
cothalamic system loses its ability to engage in complex activity patterns and either breaks down in casually independent modules (loss of
integration) or it bursts in an explosive response (loss of differentiation/information, with higher intensity of stimulation). During REM sleep,
TMS response shows a recovery of spatially and temporally differentiated patterns of activation. (B) As in NREM sleep, similar results have
been observed during general anesthesia using propofol, midazolam and xenon. (C) Patients in a vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness
syndrome (VS/UWS) show similar responses to NREM sleep and anesthesia while patients in a minimally conscious state (MCS) show pat-
terns of activity that resemble those in wakefulness and REM sleep. Source: Taken from Sarasso et al. (2014).

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


GLOBAL ALTERATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 411
observed during wakefulness: evoked patterns of to their minimum alveolar concentration (MAC): a
activity become more complex and spatially differen- MAC value of 1 is the dose that prevents movement
tiated, although some late components are still miss- in 50% of subjects in response to a painful surgical
ing (Massimini et al., 2010). stimulation. At low MAC values (0.1!0.2) anesthetics
p0420 The study of consciousness during sleep provides not produce amnesia, first explicit and then implicit.
only a window into the neural mechanisms that deter- Frequently there are distortions of time perception,
mine the quantity or global level of consciousness, but such as slowing down and fragmentation, and a feel-
also its quality. For example, local bistability in some ing of disconnection from the environment. Also, at
regions (Nir et al., 2011) may produce temporary, revers- low MAC values anesthetics produce increasing sleep-
ible alterations in the quality of consciousness similar to iness and make arousal progressively more difficult,
persistent, partially irreversible ones caused by lesions suggesting that to some extent they can mimic neuro-
resulting in neuropsychological impairments. Thus, physiological events underlying sleep. At around 0.3
localized bistability in Wernicke’s area may produce a MAC people experience a decrease in the level of
temporary dream aphasia, posterior parietal bistability consciousness, also described as a “shrinking” in the
may produce the dream equivalent of Balint’s syndrome, field of consciousness, as if they were kept on
widespread bistability in visual cortex may produce a the verge of falling asleep. MAC-awake, usually
dream equivalent of Anton’s syndrome, more restricted around 0.3!0.4 MAC, is the point at which response
bistability may produce absolute dream achromatopsia to verbal command is lost in 50% of patients, and is
or prosopagnosia, and so on. Parasomnias—dissociated considered the point at which consciousness is lost
states that mix aspects of both wakefulness and sleep— (LOC). The transition to unconsciousness (LOC)
suggest that such neuropsychological alterations of appears to be rather brusque, not unlike the collapse
consciousness can occasionally have a behavioral coun- of muscle tone that usually accompanies it, suggesting
terpart. For example, patients with somnambulism often that neural processes underlying consciousness
exhibit complex behaviors such as walking and talking, change in a non-linear manner. At concentrations
but they are hard to awaken and often deny that above LOC, movements are still possible, especially
they had been conscious of anything (Zadra et al., partially coordinated responses to painful stimuli,
2013; Perrault et al., 2014). Indeed, slow-wave activity suggesting that some degree of “unconscious” proces-
increases before the onset of sleepwalking (Perrault sing is still possible. Complete unresponsiveness is
et al., 2014). Episodes of confusional arousal during usually obtained just above MAC 1.0.
NREM sleep are another case in point (Terzaghi et al., At the cellular level, many anesthetics have mixed p0430
2009; Jaar et al., 2010). Neuroimaging during such states effects, but the overall result is a decrease in neuronal
demonstrate mixed signs of local sleep (in associative excitability by either increasing inhibition or decreasing
cortices) and wake (in motor and cingulate cortices) excitation. Most anesthetics act by enhancing gamma-
(Bassetti et al., 2000; Terzaghi et al., 2012). At the other amino-butyric-acid (GABA) inhibition or by hyperpo-
end of the spectrum, lucid dreaming, in which subjects larizing cells through an increase of potassium leak
become aware that they are dreaming and can partially currents. They can also interfere with glutamatergic
control and reflect upon their experiences, show that transmission and antagonize acetylcholine at nicotinic
reflective consciousness can also occur when asleep. receptors (Campagna et al., 2003; Franks, 2006, 2008).
Neuroimaging correlates of lucid dreaming indicate a But what are critical circuits mediating the LOC
reactivation of frontal but also parietal and temporo- induced by anesthetics (Alkire et al., 2008)?
occipital cortices (Dresler et al., 2012; Stumbrys et al., A considerable number of neuroimaging studies in p0435
2013; Voss et al., 2014; Filevich et al., 2015). humans have recently shed some light on this
issue (Alkire and Miller, 2005; Mashour, 2014) (see
Chapter 9). A common site of action of several anes-
thetics is posterior cingulate cortex and medial parietal
s0070 Anesthesia cortical areas, as well as lateral parietal areas. During
p0425 The most common among exogenous manipula- propofol- or sevoflurane-induced LOC, high-level
tions of the level of consciousness is general anesthe- cortical networks become functionally disconnected but
sia. Anesthetics come in two main classes: intravenous primary sensory networks seem relatively preserved
agents used for induction, such as propofol and (Boveroux et al., 2010; Martuzzi et al., 2010; Liu et al.,
ketamine, generally administered together with seda- 2012) (Figure 25.4). However, it is difficult to say if
tives such as midazolam and dexmedetomidine; and anesthetics produce unconsciousness when they affect
inhaled agents such as isoflurane, sevoflurane a particular set of areas, as opposed to by producing a
and desflurane, or the gases xenon and nitrous oxide. widespread deactivation of corticothalamic circuits.
The doses of inhaled anesthetics are usually referred The most consistent effects produced by most

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


412 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

f0025 FIGURE 25.4 The Perturbational Complexity Index (PCI). (A) To calculate PCI, a binary spatiotemporal matrix of significant cortical acti-
vation triggered by TMS is compressed (“zipped”) by Lempel-Ziv algorithmic complexity. (B) In healthy subjects, PCI measured during con-
sciousness ranged between 0.44 and 0.67, whereas the PCI measured during unconsciousness ranged between 0.12 and 0.31. (C) In severely
brain-injured patients, PCI progressively increases from vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness syndrome (VS/USWS) to a minimally con-
scious state (MCS) and to recovery of functional communication (EMCS). PCI attains levels of healthy awake subjects in locked-in patients
(LIS). CRS-R: Coma-Recovery Scale-Revised. Source: Adapted from Casali et al. (2013).

anesthetics at LOC is a reduction of thalamic metabo- tomography (PET) and fMRI signals mostly reflect
lism and blood flow, suggesting the possibility that the synaptic activity rather than cellular firing, and the thal-
thalamus may serve as a consciousness switch (Alkire amus receives a massive innervation from cortex.
et al., 2000). However, both positron emission Moreover, the relative reduction in thalamic activity

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


GLOBAL ALTERATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 413
occurs on a background of a marked decrease in global anesthetics suppress fronto-occipital gamma coher-
metabolism (30!60%) that involves many cortical ence, both under visual stimulation and at rest. The
regions. Thus, thalamic activity as recorded by neuro- effect is gradual and much stronger for long-range
imaging may represent an especially sensitive, localized than local coherence (Imas et al., 2006). The loss of
readout of the extent of widespread cortical deactiva- front-to-back interactions between anterior and poste-
tion, rather than the final common pathway of uncon- rior regions of the cortex may be especially critical: at
sciousness (Ori et al., 1986). In fact, spontaneous anesthetic concentrations leading to unresponsiveness
thalamic firing in animal models of anesthesia is mostly in rats, transfer entropy, which provides a directional
driven by corticothalamic feedback (Vahle-Hinz et al., measure of information flow, decreases in the front-
2007), and the metabolic effects of enflurane on the thal- to-back direction—from frontal to parietal and from
amus can be abolished by an ipsilateral cortical ablation frontal or parietal to occipital cortex—when feed-
(Nakakimura et al., 1988), suggesting that the switch in forward transfer entropy is still high (Imas et al.,
thalamic unit activity is driven primarily through a 2005). Several human studies have also identified a
reduction in afferent corticothalamic feedback more selective suppression of feedback connectivity in
than by a direct effect of anesthesia on thalamic fronto-parietal networks after the administration of
neurons. Recently, thalamic activity was recorded using various anesthetic agents (Lee et al., 2009, 2013; Ku
depth electrodes in a patient undergoing anesthesia for et al., 2011; Boly et al., 2012a). In line with these
the implant of a deep brain stimulator (Velly et al., observations, at hypnotic concentrations the anes-
2007). With either propofol or sevoflurane, when the thetic desflurane suppresses selectively the late
patient lost consciousness, the cortical EEG changed component of neuronal firing ( . 100 ms), presumably
dramatically. However, there was little change in the due to reentrant connections, but not the early
thalamic EEG until almost 10 min later. This result (B40 ms), feed-forward component, in rat visual
implies that the deactivation of cortex alone is sufficient cortex (Hudetz et al., 2009). Unit recording studies in
for loss of consciousness, and conversely that thalamic animals also show that feed-forward responses persist
activity alone is insufficient to maintain it (see below). during anesthesia (in fact, that is how they were tradi-
More recent fMRI and EEG studies confirmed that LOC tionally investigated), but contextual modulation of
induced by propofol is mostly tied to cortico-cortical firing, associated for instance with attention and pre-
and not to thalamo-cortical processes (Boly et al., 2012a; sumably mediated by back-connections, are abolished
Monti et al., 2013). However, anesthetic-induced LOC (Lamme et al., 1998a,b; Lamme and Roelfsema, 2000).
in rodents was associated with changes in the Anesthetic agents may be especially effective at
centromedial thalamus prior to changes in the cerebral disrupting integration because the corticothalamic
cortex (Baker et al., 2014), and in another study system seems to be organized like a small-world
propofol led to a simultaneous depression of cortical network—mostly local connectivity augmented by
and thalamic (ventroposterolateral nucleus) activity comparatively few long-range connections (Buzsaki
(Verdonck et al., 2014). et al., 2004). Thus, anesthetics need only disrupt a few
p0440 Whatever the ultimate target of anesthetics, loss of long-range connections to produce a set of discon-
consciousness may not necessarily require that neurons nected components (Rozenfeld and Ben-Avraham,
in these structures be inactivated. In fact, it may be 2007). Indeed, computer simulations demonstrate a
sufficient that subtler, dynamic aspects of neural activ- rapid state transition at a critical anesthetic dose
ity be affected. As with sleep, some evidence indicates (Steyn-Ross et al., 2001a,b). On the other hand, recent
that anesthetic agents may impair consciousness by human and rodents studies suggest that small-world
disrupting cortical integration (Schrouff et al., 2011; networks may be maintained during anesthetic-
Boly et al., 2012b). Alternatively, anesthetics may induced LOC (Liang et al., 2012; Schroter et al., 2012).
impair consciousness by leading to bistable, stereotypic An overall explanation of how various anesthetics,
cortical responses associated with a loss of information. despite different mechanisms of action, may lead to
p0445 Consider first large-scale integration. Anesthetics loss of consciousness, is that they invariably cause a
are known to slow down neural responses (Munglani breakdown of information integration, as shown
et al., 1993; Andrade et al., 1996; Plourde et al., 1998). using TMS-EEG for midazolam, propofol, sevoflurane
As this effect may not occur uniformly across the cor- and xenon (Ferrarelli et al., 2010; Casali et al., 2013).
tex, it is likely to disrupt synchronization among dis- As with sleep, it is likely that the breakdown of inte-
tant areas. Indeed, when consciousness fades there is gration may be especially sensitive to the occurrence
a drop in coherence in the gamma range (usually of bistability in cortical and thalamic cells.
20!80 Hz) between right and left frontal cortices as Consider now the information aspect. When the num- p0450
well as between frontal and occipital regions (John ber of differentiated activity patterns that can be
et al., 2001). Animal experiments also show that produced by the corticothalamic system shrinks, neural

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


414 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

activity becomes less informative, even though it may be Patients who survive a coma may recover while p0465
globally integrated (Tononi, 2004a,b, 2012). Several others enter the so-called vegetative state, now called
general anesthetics produce a characteristic burst- “unresponsive wakefulness syndrome” (Laureys et al.,
suppression pattern in which a near-flat EEG is 2010), in which eyes reopen, giving the appearance of
interrupted every few seconds by brief, quasi-periodic wakefulness, but unresponsiveness persists
bursts of global activation that are remarkably stereo- (Chapter 10). Soon, sleep/waking cycles follow, though
typic. It has now been shown that such stereotypic in many cases they remain highly irregular (Cruse
bursts can also be elicited by visual, auditory, and even et al., 2013). Respiration, other autonomic functions and
micromechanical stimuli (Hartikainen et al., 1995; brainstem functions are relatively preserved, and ste-
Makela et al., 1996; Hudetz and Imas, 2007; Kroeger and reotypic, reflex-like responses can occur, including
Amzica, 2007). Whether evoked or spontaneous, this yawning and grunting, but no purposeful behavior.
stereotypic burst-suppression pattern indicates that Patients may remain unresponsive for a long time, or
during deep anesthetic unconsciousness the corticotha- may emerge to a “minimally conscious state.” This is
lamic system can still be active—in fact hyperexcitable— distinguished from the unresponsive wakefulness
and can produce global, integrated responses. However, syndrome because of the occasional occurrence of some
the repertoire of responses has shrunk to a stereotypic behaviors that do not appear to be purely reflexive,
burst-suppression pattern, with a corresponding loss of suggesting that some degree of consciousness may be
information. present (Giacino et al., 2002). The minimally conscious
p0455 An intriguing phenomenon that occurs occasionally state has recently been subcategorized into minimally
during anesthesia is “intraoperative awareness” conscious plus (presence of language processing) and
(Mashour and Avidan, 2015). Intraoperative awareness minimally conscious minus (presence of purposeful
with explicit recall has been found in approximately behaviors that do not necessitate comprehension, such
1!2/1000 patients (Mashour et al., 2012). The isolated as visual pursuit) (Bruno et al., 2011, 2012).
forearm technique can be used to assess awareness Post-mortem analysis in unresponsive patients p0470
during anesthesia: a cuff prevents paralysis of the reveals that the brainstem and hypothalamus, and
hand, which allows the patient to move the arm in specifically the reticular activating system, are largely
response to a verbal command. Using this technique, spared, which explains why patients look awake.
the incidence of awareness during anesthesia, without Usually the unresponsive wakefulness syndrome is
explicit recall afterwards, seems to be much higher due to widespread lesions of grey matter in neocortex
than the incidence of awareness with recall (Sanders and thalamus, to widespread white matter damage
et al., 2012). However, the use of the isolated forearm and diffuse axonal injury, or to bilateral thalamic
technique in clinical practice is still controversial lesions, especially of the paramedian thalamic nuclei
(Russell, 2013; Sleigh, 2013; Mashour and Avidan, (Posner and Plum, 2007). Thalamic damage can be
2015), partly because it is difficult to be sure that secondary to diffuse cortical damage due to retro-
forearm responses always reflect full consciousness. grade degeneration (just like in metabolic studies of
anesthesia, changes in the thalamus are much more
concentrated and therefore easier to document that in
s0075 Coma and Related States cortex). However, isolated paramedian thalamic
p0460 While consciousness may nearly fade during certain damage can cause persistent unconsciousness. Indeed,
phases of sleep, and be kept at very low levels for a recovery from an unresponsive wakefulness syn-
prescribed period during general anesthesia, coma and drome was associated with the restoration of func-
the vegetative state, are characterized by a loss of con- tional connectivity between intralaminar thalamic
sciousness that is hard or impossible to reverse (Posner nuclei and prefrontal and anterior cingulate cortices AU:7
and Plum, 2007). Coma—an enduring sleep-like state of (Laureys et al., 2000a,b). A seminal study by Schiff
immobility with eyes closed from which the patient et al. shows the role of the thalamus even more
cannot be aroused—represents the paradigmatic form dramatically: bilateral deep brain electrical stimula-
of pathological loss of consciousness (Chapter 10). tion of the central thalamus restored a degree of
Typically, coma is caused by a suppression of corti- behavioral responsiveness in a patient who had
cothalamic function by drugs, toxins, or internal meta- remained in a minimally conscious state for 6 years
bolic derangements. Other causes of coma are head following brain trauma (Schiff et al., 2007). In an older
trauma, strokes, or hypoxia due to heart failure, which study, a state of akinetic mutism was associated with
again cause a widespread destruction of corticothala- hypersynchronous spike and wave activity in parame-
mic circuits. Smaller lesions of the reticular activating dian thalamus. After an induced Phenobarbital coma,
system can also cause unconsciousness, presumably by seizures activity resolved and the patients began to
deactivating the corticothalamic system indirectly. speak (Williams and Parsons-Smith, 1951).

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


GLOBAL ALTERATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 415
p0475 In patients with unresponsive wakefulness syn- for example by considering the functioning of feedback
drome, brain metabolism is globally reduced by connections (Boly et al., 2011), or by employing a
50!60%, most notably in regions such as the posterior combination of many different indices (Sitt et al., 2014,
AU:8 cingulate cortex and the precuneus (Laureys et al., see also Boly et al., 2008, 2011; Vanhaudenhuyse et al.,
2004; Schiff, 2006a,b). These are also the areas that 2010; Gosseries et al., 2011; Wu et al., 2011; Lehembre
reactivate most reliably if a patient regains conscious- et al., 2012; Fingelkurts et al., 2013; King et al., 2013;
ness. A case study reported an extraordinary recovery Forgacs et al., 2014; Sitt et al., 2014; Stender et al.,
of verbal communication and motor function in a 2014). TMS-EEG has also been applied in these
patient who had remained in a minimally conscious patients and showed clear-cut differences at the indi-
state for 19 years (Voss et al., 2006). Diffusion tensor vidual level (Rosanova et al., 2012; Casali et al., 2013;
MRI showed increased fractional anisotropy (assumed Gosseries et al., 2015). As seen in NREM sleep and
to reflect myelinated fiber density) in posteromedial general anesthesia, in unconscious subjects TMS
cortices, encompassing cuneus and precuneus. These typically triggers a stereotypical slow wave that
same areas showed increased glucose metabolism as remains local, which indicates a breakdown of effec-
studied by PET scanning, likely reflecting the neuronal tive connectivity. In minimally conscious patients,
regrowth paralleling the patient’s clinical recovery. brain activation patterns to TMS are widespread and
p0480 The differential diagnosis between unresponsive differentiated, as observed in healthy awake subjects
and minimally conscious patients is often challenging and locked-in patients (Figure 25.3). In order to quan-
and can lead to up to 40% of misdiagnoses if it is tify these TMS-EEG responses, the perturbational com-
based exclusively on clinical consensus without the plexity index (PCI) has recently been developed
adoption of standardized behavioral scales, such as the (Casali et al., 2013). This measure estimates brain com-
Coma-Recovery Scale Revised (Giacino et al., 2004; plexity, that is, information content and the integration
Schnakers et al., 2009; Stender et al., 2014). But even of brain activations, via algorithmic compressibility
the most accurate behavioral assessment cannot rule (“zipping”) (Figure 25.5A). PCI successfully differenti-
out some degree of awareness. Neuroimaging studies ates between conscious and unconscious states: it is
have now shown that, even in completely unrespon- invariably high in healthy awake subjects, in patients
sive patients, as long as significant portions of the in a minimally conscious state and in locked-in syn-
corticothalamic system are preserved, cognitive stimuli drome as well as in REM sleep, whereas PCI is always
can induce patterns of activation similar to those seen low in both patients in an unresponsive wakefulness
in healthy subjects (Laureys et al., 2004; Schiff, 2006a, syndrome and under general anesthesia as well as
b). Since stimuli that are not perceived consciously can during NREM sleep (Figure 25.5B and C).
still activate appropriate brain areas (see below
and Chapters 4 and 18), inferring the presence of
consciousness may be unwarranted. However, in a
seminal study, a clinically unresponsive patient was
Seizures s0080

put in the scanner and asked to imagine playing tennis The abnormal, hypersynchronous discharge of neu- p0485
or navigating through her room. Remarkably, the rons is a frequent cause of short-lasting impairments
patient showed fMRI activation patterns of the appro- of consciousness. Consciousness is lost or severely
priate cortical regions, exactly like healthy subjects. affected in so-called generalized seizures, such as
Obviously, these activations could not be due to absence and tonic-clonic seizures, and to a lesser extent
unconscious processing of stimuli (Owen et al., 2006). in complex partial seizures (Chapter 16). Absence
Of note, this patient had widespread frontal lesions, seizures, which are more frequent in children, are
while posterior cortex was largely preserved. Using momentary lapses of consciousness during which a
the same fMRI paradigm, one patient in minimally child stops what she was doing and stares straight
conscious state has been able to accurately answer ahead blankly. Absence seizures are accompanied by
yes!no biographical questions (Monti et al., 2010). spike-and-wave complexes at around 3 Hz in the EEG,
Since then, several studies have reported similar reflecting cycles of synchronous firing and silence of
results using other paradigms (e.g., other imagery large number of neurons. There is great variability in
tasks, attentional task, passive viewing of a movie) and the degree of unresponsiveness both across subjects
techniques (e.g., EEG, event-related potentials, electro- and, within the same subject, between seizures.
myography) (Schnakers et al., 2008; Bardin et al., 2011; Sometimes, simple behaviors such as repetitive tap-
Cruse et al., 2011; Naci and Owen, 2013; Habbal et al., ping or counting, can proceed unimpaired during the
2014). Recent PET, fMRI and EEG studies have had seizures, but more complex tasks come to a halt.
some success in distinguishing between minimally Generalized convulsive seizures usually comprise a p0490
conscious and unconscious patients at the group level, tonic phase of muscle stiffening, followed by a clonic

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


416 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

FIGURE 25.5 Loss of consciousness induced f0030


by electrical stimulation. In a patient with
intractable epilepsy, electrical stimulation of the
anterior-dorsal insula area elicited loss of con-
sciousness (red circle). The claustrum is
highlighted in yellow to show its proximity to the
stimulated target. So far, no similar response to
electrical stimulation of any other brain area has
ever been reported. Source: Taken from Koubeissi
et al. (2014).

phase with jerking of the arms and legs. After the con- seizures the abnormalities are confined to a medial
vulsion the person may be lethargic or in a state of temporal focus on one side. However, neuroimaging
confusion for minutes up to hours. During the tonic studies using single photon emission computed
phase of a convulsive seizure neural activity is greatly tomography (SPECT), PET, and fMRI, and depth EEG
increased, as indicated by high-frequency activity in recordings in humans and animals have revealed that
the EEG. The clonic phase is accompanied by synchro- generalized seizures do not affect all brain areas
nous spikes and waves in the EEG, corresponding to indiscriminately, whereas complex partial seizures
millions of neurons alternately firing in strong bursts alter brain activity less focally than initially thought
and turning silent. Loss of consciousness during the (Blumenfeld and Taylor, 2003; Blumenfeld et al.,
tonic phase of generalized seizures is noteworthy 2003, 2004; Blumenfeld, 2005). In fact, it now appears
because it occurs at times when neuronal activity is that all seizures causing an impairment of conscious-
extremely high and synchronous. ness are associated with changes in activity in three
p0495 Partial complex seizures often begin with strange sets of brain areas (Chapter 16), namely: (i) increased
abdominal sensations, fears, premonitions, or auto- activity in the upper brainstem and medial thalamus;
matic gestures. The person progressively loses contact (ii) decreased activity in the anterior and posterior
with the environment, exhibits a fixed stare and cingulate, medial frontal cortex, and precuneus; (iii)
is unable to respond adequately to questions or altered activity in the lateral and orbital frontal cortex
commands. Stereotyped, automatic movements are and in the lateral parietal cortex. In tonic-clonic
common. Complex partial seizures usually last from seizures, fronto-parietal association areas show
15 s to 3 min. Seizure activity is usually localized to increased activity, while the pattern is more complex
the medial temporal lobe. and variable in absence seizures, though parietal
p0500 The diagnosis of seizures is made through clinical areas are usually deactivated. Another recent study
observation and EEG recordings. Recent studies have showed a variable activation of different areas of the
attempted to better characterize the degree of loss of cortex during the generalized phase of secondary
consciousness during seizures using behavioral scales generalized tonico-clonic seizures, while postictally
(Lambert et al., 2012; Yang et al., 2012). These studies frontoparietal cortices were deactivated (Blumenfeld
have demonstrated a range of different alterations of et al., 2009). Complex partial seizures show decreased
consciousness during seizures, the largest impairment activity in frontal and parietal association cortex,
of conscious level being observed during generalized which is associated with the onset of slow waves
seizures (Yang et al., 2012) while partial seizures similar to those of sleep or anesthesia (rather than to
showed a more moderate impairment (closest to epileptiform discharges) (see also Englot et al., 2010).
minimally conscious state) and followed a bimodal Loss of consciousness during complex partial seizures
pattern (Cunningham et al., 2014). In absence and (parietal or temporal in origin) has also been linked to
tonic-clonic seizures the scalp EEG shows diffuse an increase in long range-cortical synchronization in
abnormalities, suggesting a generalized involvement fronto-temporo-parietal cortices (Arthuis et al., 2009;
of brain networks, whereas in partial complex Lambert et al., 2012).

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 417
p0505 At this stage, it is not clear which of these three sets The Corticothalamic System vs. the Rest of the s0090
of areas, alone or in combination, are crucial for the Brain
loss of consciousness. However, two things are clear:
first, the areas involved in the loss of consciousness As we just mentioned, the only conclusion that can p0520

associated with seizures correspond to those affected be drawn for sure about the neural substrate of
in sleep, anesthesia, and the unresponsive wakefulness consciousness is that it includes parts of the corticotha-
syndrome, pointing to a common substrate for the lamic system. The evidence comes from many different
most common forms of loss of consciousness; second, sources, and it constitutes the true bedrock of the
especially during the tonic phase of convulsive sei- neurology of consciousness. Unambiguous examples
zures, it would seem that consciousness is lost when of unresponsive wakefulness syndrome demonstrate
neurons are excessively and synchronously active, that the loss of consciousness is usually associated
rather than inactive. Perhaps, as with the bistable, with widespread lesions of the grey or white matter of
hypersynchronous transitions between down- and the cortex, and most of the time with a significant
up-states during sleep, and with the hypersynchronous thalamic involvement (Posner and Plum, 2007).
burst-suppression patterns during deep anesthesia, The evidence is just as persuasive that patients p0525

consciousness fades when the repertoire of available remain conscious after lesions of brain structures
neural states shrinks, and with it the information outside the corticothalamic system, first among them
capacity of the system (see below, and Tononi, 2004a, the spinal cord, which can be severed without affecting
b, 2008, 2012). consciousness in any direct manner. The cerebellum
offers another interesting case study. Even widespread
cerebellar lesions or complete ablations hardly affect
consciousness (Boyd, 2010; Lemon and Edgley, 2010;
s0085 THE NEUROANATOMY OF Yu et al., 2014), yet the cerebellum has even more neu-
CONSCIOUSNESS rons that the cerebral cortex (Herculano-Houzel, 2012),
is richly endowed with connections, neurotransmitters
p0510 Despite the wealth of evidence reviewed in this and neuromodulators, receives inputs from the sen-
book, it is still difficult to converge on a circumscribed sory periphery, controls motor outputs, contains maps
set of brain structures that are “minimally sufficient of the body and the outside space, is strongly con-
and jointly necessary” for consciousness (Crick and nected in both directions with thalamus and cortex,
Koch, 2003) (Chapter 1). It is also important to keep in and often shows selective activation during cognitive
mind that, at this stage, we have no idea whether the tasks and in relation to emotion (Glickstein, 2007;
elementary neural units that contribute to conscious- Schmahmann et al., 2007; Buckner, 2013). Altogether,
ness are local groups of neurons, such as cortical rather than playing a direct role in consciousness, the
minicolumns, or individual neurons, and perhaps only cerebellum appears to function to control the acquisi-
neurons located in certain layers or belonging to a tion of sensory inputs (Baumann et al., 2015) and as a
particular class. What is undisputed, and certainly not learning device for motor, perceptual and cognitive
new, is that broad lesions or inactivations of the corti- functions (Deluca et al., 2014). As we shall briefly
cothalamic system abolish consciousness, whereas discuss in a later section, the cerebellum can be
lesions of other parts of the brain do not. Beyond this, usefully contrasted to the corticothalamic complex
it is still difficult to be more precise with a sufficient to evince which aspects of neural organization are
degree of confidence. Recent developments, however, important for generating consciousness.
make it at least possible to ask some pertinent Concerning other brain structures the evidence is p0530

questions and suggest comparisons that may help to more complex. A case has been made for the claustrum
sharpen scientific inquiry. as a key structure for consciousness. The claustrum is a
p0515 Below, we briefly review, without any pretence at thin sheet of nerve cells located just underneath the
completeness: (i) the evidence that establishes the insular cortex and connected to most cortical regions
central role of the corticothalamic system and rules (Crick and Koch, 2006). To this day selective lesions AU:9
out other areas of the brain; (ii) the role of the have not been reported, but claustral lesions associated
thalamus vs. that of the cortex; (iii) that of primary with widespread striatal lesions do not necessarily
areas vs. higher-level visual areas; (iv) the ventral vs. cause unconsciousness (Straussberg et al., 2002). On the
the dorsal stream; (v) fronto-parietal networks vs. the other hand, in a recent single case report, electrical
default system; and finally (vi) posterior vs. anterior stimulation of the forebrain induced an abrupt loss of
(prefrontal) cortices; (vii) reentrant vs. feed-forward consciousness in which the patient stared blankly ahead
connections; and finally, (viii) superficial vs. deep and became unresponsive (Figure 25.6). After the
layers of cortex. stimulation was stopped, the patient became conscious

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


418 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

FIGURE 25.6 Functional connectivity in pri- f0035


Wakefulness Unconsciousness mary and in higher order cortices. (A) Normal
wakefulness and propofol-induced uncon-
(A) 15 15 sciousness resting-state networks connectivity
in the default network, (B) in the right executive
control network, (C) in the left executive control
network, (D) anticorrelations between default
3 3
network and lateral frontoparietal cortices. (E)
x = –9 mm z = 19 mm x = –9 mm z = 19 mm
Connectivity patterns in the visual resting-state
networks, and (F) in the auditory resting-state
15 15
(B) networks during wakefulness and during
unconsciousness. Large-scale network connec-
tivity such as in the default network and execu-
3 3 tive control networks is reduced during
x = 54 mm z = 2 mm x = 54 mm z = 2 mm unconsciousness. In contrast, visual and audi-
tory networks connectivity remains globally
stable across state. Source: Adapted from
10 10 Boveroux et al. (2010).
(C)

3 3
x = –55 mm z = 5 mm x = –55 mm z = 5 mm

5 5
(D)

3 3
x = –54 mm z = 2 mm x = –54 mm z = 2 mm

(E) 15 15

3 3
z = –2 mm x = 21 mm z = –2 mm x = 21 mm

(F)
15 15

3 3
z = 5 mm y = –35 mm z = 5 mm y = –35 mm

again but without recalling the intervening events progressing to aphonia, dysarthria and finally mutism,
(Koubeissi et al., 2014). and or with the execution of abnormal (athetoid) or
p0535 Selective, bilateral lesions of the basal ganglia automatic movements (Tremblay et al., 2015).
are rare (Jain et al., 2013), although there are cases of Consciousness, however, appears to be preserved—
selective bilateral necrosis of the striatum and related children affected before 3 years of age may not speak
structures, including the claustrum (Leuzzi et al., 1988, but respond to sensory stimuli and communicate
1992; Craver et al., 1996; Caparros-Lefebvre et al., 1997; with their parents (Straussberg et al., 2002); adults
Straussberg et al., 2002), as well as several instances of may develop cognitive problems, including a frontal
bilateral pallidotomy for the control of movement dis- syndrome, but are clearly conscious (Caparros-
orders (Scott et al., 1998; Ghika et al., 1999; York et al., Lefebvre et al., 1997). However, lesions involving por-
2007). Also, a case can be made for a virtual blockade tions of the basal ganglia as well as the anterior cingulate
of basal ganglia function in extreme Parkinson’s dis- can result in akinetic mutism (see below) or in the “slow
ease and perhaps in catatonic states (Northoff, 2002; syndrome” (Posner and Plum, 2007), and have been
Northoff et al., 2004). Such cases show some degree of implicated in the recovery of consciousness in brain-
cognitive impairment, but most problems have to do damaged patients (Schiff, 2010, “the meso-circuit
with movement initiation and control, dysphonia hypothesis”). In the latter case, patients are slow and

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 419
somnolent, but communications is possible. Circuits demonstrated that cell specific lesions of glutamatergic
involving the basal ganglia originate mostly from neurons in a parabrachial-precoeruleus complex cause
anterior cortex, the portion of the corticothalamic behavioral unresponsiveness and a monotonous
complex whose necessity for consciousness is more sub-1 Hz cortical EEG. These reticular activating
questionable, as discussed below. Thus, despite being neurons act indirectly by projecting to the basal fore-
an integral component of at least five parallel corti- brain, whose lesion also produces coma and slow EEG.
co!subcortico!cortical circuits, the basal ganglia may Indeed, brainstem stimulation that produces an
not contribute directly to consciousness. Rather, basal arousal reaction and the activation of the EEG
ganglia (and cerebellar circuits) are thought to play an (Moruzzi and Magoun, 1949) also becomes ineffective
important role in transforming hard, slow, error-prone when the local anesthetic lidocaine is injected into the
sequences of movements that are performed under basal forebrain, but not so much when it is injected
conscious control, into smooth, fast, and error-free into the thalamus (Dringenberg and Olmstead, 2003).
routines that are executed automatically (Debaere et al., Animal experiments indicate that as long as some p0550
2004; Floyer-Lea and Matthews, 2004). activating systems remain, for example both choliner-
p0540 Finally, we have seen above, on the section on gic and non-cholinergic cells in the basal forebrain
memory, that bilateral hippocampal lesions that abolish (Buzsaki et al., 1988; Dringenberg and Olmstead, 2003),
episodic, autobiographical memory do not abolish consciousness may be possible. However, as demon-
consciousness. However, what consciousness remains is strated by patients who awaken from coma and evolve
less rich—there is a deficit in imagination—and it may into an unresponsive wakefulness syndrome, a func-
be especially constricted in its temporal dimension—the tioning brainstem is insufficient for consciousness in
duration of the conscious present (see Chapter 21). the absence of a functioning corticothalamic system—
there is wakefulness (eyes open), but no experience.
Whether the corticothalamic system can resume its
function and sustain consciousness if the brainstem
s0095 Cortex vs. Activating Systems reticular activating system and its basal forebrain relay
p0545 Brainstem structures, as well as their hypothalamic are permanently damaged is unclear but, as suggested
and basal forebrain extensions, offer an instructive by the dramatic effects on consciousness of deep corti-
example concerning the difference between the neural cal stimulation in the median thalamus, the reticular
substrate of consciousness and factors that merely activating system appears to have the role of an
enable it. Every neurologist knows that if the brain- enabler or controller of the level of consciousness,
stem is damaged or compressed, coma is likely to an on-off “switch,” rather than of a generator of
ensue—even minor lesions affecting the “ascending consciousness. Another effective consciousness switch
reticular activating system” (Moruzzi and Magoun, may be located in the basal forebrain, as long as both
1949) can produce unconsciousness. The reticular cholinergic and noncholinergic cells are targeted
activating system in the upper brainstem reticular for- (Buzsaki et al., 1988).
mation ultimately acts by “activating” the EEG, that is,
by promoting low-voltage fast activity, presumably
by increasing excitability and facilitating effective
Cortex vs. Thalamus s0100
interactions within cortex. In the classic account, the
activating system acts on the cortex through two The thalamus is sometimes considered as a seventh p0555
branches: the thalamic branch, which innervates intra- layer of cortex, so contrasting its role with that of
laminar, relay, and reticular thalamic nuclei; and the the cortex proper may be a useless enterprise.
extra-thalamic branch, which reaches hypothalamic Nevertheless, it has been suggested that the thalamus,
nuclei and the basal forebrain, and also contains some and especially the intralaminar nuclei, may constitute a
projections to cortex. Subsequent work revealed neuro- “centrencephalic system” where consciousness resides
chemically specific components of the upper brainstem (Bogen, 1997). Very few patients in a unresponsive state
activating system, primarily noradrenergic neurons in or minimally conscious state have circumscribed brain
the locus coeruleus and various groups of cholinergic lesions. As we have seen however, those who do often
neurons, and identified additional hypothalamic have bilateral damage in a region including parame-
arousal systems including the histaminergic and orexi- dian thalamic nuclei (Posner and Plum, 2007).
nergic systems. However, selective lesions of brain- Moreover, the restoration of functional connectivity
stem noradrenergic and cholinergic cell groups did not between paramedian thalamus and cingulate cortices is
reproduce the deep coma seen after acute paramedian an early sign of recovery from the unresponsive wake-
midbrain lesions that transect ascending axons at fulness syndrome (Laureys et al., 2000a,b), and bilateral
the caudal midbrain level. Recent work in rats has deep brain electrical stimulation of the central thalamus

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


420 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

restored behavioral responsiveness in a patient who inducing and maintaining unconsciousness. Moreover,
had remained in a minimally conscious state for 6 years consistent with the role of the thalamus as a seventh
(Schiff et al., 2007). In animals, acute thalamic manipu- layer of cortex, efficient communication between
lations can have major effects. For example, an infusion cortical areas might requires a thalamic relay (Guillery
of GABA agonists (mimicking anesthetic action) into et al., 2001; Guillery and Sherman, 2002; Sherman and
central medial intralaminar nuclei causes animals to fall Guillery, 2002, but see Shipp, 2003; Jones, 2007), in that
“asleep” and the EEG to slow down (Miller and case thalamic lesions would lead to a functional dis-
Ferrendelli, 1990; Miller et al., 1993). Conversely, rats connection within cortex, despite an activated EEG.
kept under an anesthetic concentration of sevoflurane The anatomy is also consistent with such a role:
can be awakened by a minute injection of nicotine in calbindin-positive matrix cells, which are especially
the same area (Alkire et al., 2007). However, other concentrated within some of the intralaminar thalamic
experiments indicate that the thalamus may not be nec- nuclei (Jones, 1998, 2007), project diffusely to many
essary for consciousness. Thus, paramedian thalamic areas of the cortex, where they provide a more superfi-
lesions inducing coma usually include neighboring cial innervations (layers I, II, and upper III).
fiber tracts, including the newly discovered projection Also, matrix cells receive collaterals mostly from
from glutamatergic neurons in the parabrachial- cortical cells in layer V, which in turn have much
precoeruleus complex of the brainstem that activate the wider intracortical collaterals than layer VI cells, (and
cortex through a basal forebrain relay (Fuller et al., are especially sensitive to anesthetics). Cells within
2011). The same rodent study showed that extensive intralaminar thalamic nuclei are capable of firing in
thalamic lesions have little effect on EEG or behavioral the gamma range and can provide NMDA receptor
measures of wakefulness (Fuller et al., 2011). It was also activation, subthreshold depolarization and coherent
reported long ago that, following a complete ablation oscillatory bias to distant cortical areas (Llinas et al.,
of the thalamus, the cortex can still produce an 2002), thereby potentially facilitating long range inter-
activated EEG (Villablanca and Salinas-Zeballos, 1972; actions. Also, intralaminar nuclei are ideally poised to
Vanderwolf and Stewart, 1988). Moreover, as was work as an anatomical hub connecting many cortical
mentioned above, when a patient with depth electrodes regions (Scannell et al., 1999), and are a prominent
in the thalamus was anesthetized, the cortical EEG target of inputs from the reticular activating system of
changed dramatically the instant the patient lost the brainstem. For these reasons, matrix cells can be
consciousness, but the thalamic EEG remained conceptualized as a veritable thalamic activating
unchanged until almost 10 min later (Velly et al., 2007). system capable of facilitating effective interactions
A complementary result is provided by another study among many cortical areas and thereby of sustaining
in epileptic patient: during REM sleep—a state usually consciousness.
associated with dreaming—the cortical EEG was duly
activated, but the thalamic EEG in the medial pulvinar
nucleus showed slow wave activity (Magnin et al.,
2004). Also, unlike sedation, loss of consciousness per se
Primary Areas vs. Areas s0105

is accompanied by a decrease in cortico-cortical rather Since the suggestion by Crick and Koch that p0565
than by changes in thalamo-cortical connectivity (Boly primary visual cortex may not be part of the “neural
et al., 2012a; Monti et al., 2013). correlate of consciousness” (Crick and Koch, 1995),
p0560 On the other hand, the thalamus is important in a remarkable amount of refined neuroscience has
ensuring connectedness to the external environment attempted to settle the question whether this brain
AU:10
AU:11 (Steriade, 2001; Sanders et al., 2012) and in facilitating area is “in” or “out.” That is, does primary visual
cortico-cortical interactions (Theyel et al., 2010). Thus, cortex contribute directly to visual consciousness, or
when the thalamus is acutely deactivated, interfering only indirectly—a sort of larger, higher-up retina
with environmental connectedness, the cortex may (Silvanto, 2014)? Consider retinal neurons. Though
become more bistable and consciousness may be lost. they certainly rely information to all parts of the
Indeed, some studies show that thalamic activity can visual system, and their activity usually determines
change before or simultaneously with changes in corti- what we see when we open our eyes, they do not
cal activity during the transition to unconsciousness seem to contribute directly to conscious experience.
(Magnin et al., 2010; Baker et al., 2014; Verdonck et al., For example, their rapidly shifting firing patterns do
2014). Thus, it may be that thalamic deactivation may not correspond well with what we perceive, which is
promote loss of consciousness, acting as an acute “con- much more stable. Moreover, during blinks and eye
sciousness switch” (Alkire et al., 2000), probably movements retinal activity changes dramatically, but
through an indirect action on cortical excitability. visual perception does not. Also, the retina has a
However, only cortical deactivation is sufficient for blind spot at the exit of the optic nerve where

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 421
there are no photoreceptors, and it has low spatial quarter of the visual field), suggesting that V1 is
resolution and no color sensitivity at the periphery of insufficient for conscious vision. Conversely, in blind-
the visual field, but we are not aware of any of this. sight patients with intact extrastriate areas and dam-
More importantly, lesioning the retina does not pre- aged V1, phosphene-like percepts can be induced by
vent conscious visual experiences. As we have seen, stimulating parietal cortex with TMS (Figure 25.7)
a person who becomes retinally blind as an adult (Mazzi et al., 2014).
continues to have vivid visual images and dreams. Additional evidence against a direct contribution p0580
Conversely, stimulating the retina during sleep by of not only V1 but other primary sensory cortices
keeping the eyes open and presenting various visual comes from studies of sensory stimulation during
inputs does not yield any visual experience and does slow wave sleep (Chapter 9, general anesthesia, and
not affect visual dreams (Rechtschaffen and Foulkes, in patients with unresponsive wakefulness syndrome,
1965). Chapter 10). Using evoked responses or neuroimag-
p0570 What is the situation with primary visual cortex? ing techniques, these studies show the localized
Psychophysical experiments indicate that several activation of primary areas in the absence of any
stimuli known to affect the activity of V1 neurons have indication of consciousness (Figure 25.4) (Laureys
no perceptual counterpart (Andrade et al., 1996; He et al., 2000a,b, 2002; Coleman et al., 2009; Boveroux
and MacLeod, 2001; Jiang et al., 2007). Also, single et al., 2010). In contrast, when patients are (mini-
neuron recordings from the monkey, using paradigms mally) conscious, they typically recruit a widespread
such as binocular rivalry, find that activity in V1 tends set of associative sensory cortices (Boly et al., 2004,
to follow the physical stimulus, rather than the 2008). However, it should be remembered that areas
percept, unlike neurons higher up in the visual hierar- higher up in the cortical hierarchy, often considered
chy (Logothetis, 1998; Leopold and Logothetis, 1999; to be contributing to experience, can also be acti-
Blake and Logothetis, 2002). On the other hand, a vated, at least at the fMRI level, in the absence of
number of fMRI BOLD studies found that activity in conscious perception, as shown by studies of back-
human V1, and even in the lateral geniculate nucleus, ward masking (Dehaene et al., 2001), inattention
was correlated with perception (Chapter 4) during bin- (Marois et al., 2004; Sergent et al., 2005), and neglect
ocular rivalry (Polonsky et al., 2000; Lee et al., 2005b) (Vuilleumier et al., 2001). Perhaps in some of these
or working memory tasks (Harrison and Tong, 2009), instances the activation that reaches higher areas
this is not true for motion-induced blindness (Donner is merely insufficient, for instance in masking.
et al., 2008). Similarly, V1 fMRI signals associated with Alternatively, the fMRI signal may be strong, as in
unperceived line drawings were modulated by visual inattention and neglect, but it may lack some other
attention (Bahrami et al., 2007). Finally, it is possible to features that would only be evident with units
decode from V1 BOLD activity the orientation of a recordings, such as fast oscillations or synchroniza-
masked stimulus, even though subjects could not tion with other areas, or it may be that higher areas
guess its orientation (Haynes et al., 2005). must respond to inputs from lower areas for their
p0575 Lesions of V1 lead to the striking phenomenon of activation to contribute to consciousness. Finally,
“blindsight,” in which patients claim to have no less is known about the possible contribution to
conscious perception of stimuli, though they perform consciousness of other primary cortices such as motor
better than chance on forced-choice tasks where they cortex. However, some evidence exists to show, for
are asked to detect stimuli, locate them, decide on example, that masked visual stimuli can elicit motor
their orientation and direction of motion (Weiskrantz, cortex activation and increase its excitability as
1996) (see also Chapter 18). Compelling evidence probed with TMS (Theoret et al., 2004), and yet AU:12
supports the idea that blindsight is subserved by remain unperceived. Of course, demonstrating that
subcortical visual pathways that originate from the activation or changes in excitability in primary
superior colliculus and bypass primary visual cortex. cortices do not translate in reportable changes in
The subjective blindness of blindsight patients may experience does not prove that no activation pattern
perhaps be explained purely in terms of insufficient would be able to elicit experience—just think of the
feed-forward activation of higher visual areas, deny- fact that even high intensity TMS or direct electrical
ing any direct role to V1 per se in generating stimulation usually fail to affect consciousness, no
experience. Alternatively, their blindness could be matter what brain area is the target, with only a few
due to lack of feedback to V1, in which case V1 exceptions (Penfield, 1975; Salminen-Vaparanta et al.,
would be necessary for conscious vision. Current 2014).
evidence indicates that patients with damaged extra- Current evidence thus seems to support the p0585
striate visual areas and intact V1 can have quadranta- hypothesis that V1 does not contribute directly to
nopia (Horton and Hoyt, 1991) (blindness in a visual experience, and this may be generalized

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


422 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

FIGURE 25.7 TMS applied to parietal cor- f0040


tex induces phosphene in blindsights patients.
Stimulation of the parietal lobe of the lesioned
hemisphere elicited conscious visual percepts
in two hemianopic patients, even in absence
of any involvements of the occipital cortex,
specifically of V1 (A); Brain lesion reconstruc-
tion (B); Visual field defect (C); Location of
stimulation in the two patients (D);
Phosphene drawings for two TMS intensities
(50 and 95%) (E). Note that TMS on the dam-
aged occipital cortex did not produce any con-
scious visual percepts within the blind visual
field. Source: Adapted from Mazzi et al. (2014). AU:23

to other primary areas such as the auditory cortex


Ventral vs. Dorsal Stream s0110
(Meyer, 2011, but see Wiegand and Gutschalk, 2012).
However, it is hard to say whether this applies to all Based on previous work indicating a subdivision p0590
visual attributes, such as precise topography, detailed between a ventral and a dorsal visual stream diverging
contours, or luminosity, as has been argued by some from primary visual cortex, a case has been made for
(Zeki, 1993; Pollen, 2008; Oizumi et al., 2014). distinguishing between a ventral stream for perception

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 423
and a dorsal stream for action (Milner and Goodale, proximity. Indeed, given that visual objects can activate
1995; Goodale and Milner, 2005). The ventral stream ventral areas in neglect syndromes and inattentional
includes a number of areas in ventral temporal and blindness without giving rise to conscious experience,
lateral occipital cortex (the lateral occipital complex); one wonders which set of object-selective areas is more
the dorsal stream includes areas V3A, V5, V7 and important for experience. As mentioned above, phos-
intraparietal areas in the posterior parietal cortex. phenes induced by TMS to intraparietal cortex correlated
According to the initial account (Milner and Goodale, with an early EEG response in parietal cortex in both
1995), which was subsequently refined (Goodale and healthy subjects (70 ms) and in a patient with a complete
AU:13 Milner, 2005), activity in the ventral stream gives rise lesion of ipsilateral V1 (80 ms) (Bagattini et al., 2015).
to conscious experience, extracting invariant features Finally, projections from the dorsal stream to the
that subserve object identification, as well as the prefrontal, premotor and medial temporal cortices may
relationships among objects within the context of a support not just unconconscious visuospatial processes
visual scene. This system would allow us to construct but also conscious ones (e.g., working memory, visually
a lasting representation of the world, categorize objects guided action and navigation) (Kravitz et al., 2011).
and events, talk about them, form explicit memories,
and plan long-term actions (Milner, 2012). By contrast,
the dorsal stream deals with the moment-to-moment
information about the precise size, shape, location, and
Posterior vs. Anterior (Prefrontal) Cortex s0115

disposition of objects for the rapid visual control of Lesion studies support the notion that consciousness p0600
skilled actions, such as tracking, reaching, and grasp- does not require prefrontal cortex and, by inference,
ing the object. It has little memory and its activity the functions it performs. Early studies showed that
remains unconscious. There is in fact neurological large, bilateral prefrontal resections did not abolish
evidence for a double dissociation between the two consciousness. Brickner’s patient A. was the first
systems: some patients with ventral stream lesions human to undergo bilateral frontal lobectomy: “. . . one
have a “visual object agnosia” in which they lack the of the salient traits of A’s case was his ability to pass
conscious experience of the shape of objects, but can as an ordinary person under casual circumstances, as
unconsciously adapt the reaching and grasping to the when he toured the Neurological Institute in a party of
unperceived object just as well as healthy controls five, two of whom were distinguished neurologists,
(Goodale et al., 1991). Other patients with dorsal and none of them noticed anything unusual until their
stream lesions have an “optic ataxia” in which they attention was especially called to A. after the passage
perceive the objects but cannot execute the appropriate of more than an hour” (Brickner, 1952). In another
skilled movements (Pisella et al., 2000) (see also case, Hebb reported that removal of large portions of
Chapter 18). Some visual illusions can also be used to the frontal cortex had little effect on intelligence:
show a dissociation between the two systems. One Penfield had resected one third or more of each frontal
sees here another aspect of the dichotomy between the lobe of patient K.P. to eliminate epileptic foci, yet K.P.
slow, consciously controlled actions when first learn- showed “a striking post-operative improvement in
ing a new skill, and the rapid, effortless executed skill personality and intellectual capacity” (Hebb and AU:14
after it has been learned: in the first case, the brain Penfield, 1940). Psychosurgery led to the widespread
calls on a large and diverse amount of information, adoption of prefrontal lobotomy and leucotomy, in
specifying a wide context, whereas in the latter case it which prefrontal cortex was deafferented from its
employs only the minimum amount of information thalamic inputs, again with no major impairment of
that is required to execute the movement at hand. consciousness (Fulton, 1949; Mashour et al., 2005)
p0595 Recently, however, it was shown that areas in the (with the exception of anterior cingulotomy, which
dorsal stream respond not only to the location of objects could result in akinetic mutism, see below).
but also to their identity, and that hierarchically higher A number of psychiatric patients also underwent the
intraparietal areas in the dorsal stream do so in a view- bilateral resection of prefrontal cortical areas, either in
point- and size-invariant manner, just as ventral areas isolation or in combination, according to Brodmann’s
do (Konen and Kastner, 2008), and as required by atlas (“topectomy”) (Mettler, Columbia University.
perceptual constancies that are characteristic of Department of Neurology et al., 1949). Yet even
conscious experience. These selective, invariant patients receiving a bilateral resection of, say, areas 10,
responses to objects could be elicited irrespective of any 11, 45, 46, 47, or 8, 9, 10, or 44, 45, 46, 10, or area
requirement for action, and were not due to attentional 24 (ventral anterior cingulate), showed no gross behav-
confounds. As we have seen, areas in posterior parietal ioral change and certainly maintained consciousness.
cortex implement a detailed map of space, so both Some received both topectomy and lobotomy, again
spatial and object information are available in close with no gross effects on consciousness.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


424 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

p0605 Patients with widespread, bilateral damage to therapy, as well as acute akinesia in Parkinsonism,
prefrontal cortex remain rare, but two more recent are also difficult to interpret, and may or may not
clinical studies provide additional, intriguing evidence. resemble classic akinetic mutism from a functional
A young man who had fallen on an iron spike that point of view. Perhaps the most intriguing results have
completely penetrated through both of his frontal been obtained in such patients by using event-related
lobes, nevertheless went on to live a stable family potentials. Such studies have shown that, while several
life—marrying and raising two children—in an appro- aspects of the EEG responses may be altered, there can
priate professional and social setting. Although be a differential response to semantically meaningful
displaying many of the typical frontal lobe behavioral stimuli, for example in oddball paradigms (Kotchoubey
disturbances, he never complained of loss of sensory et al., 2003, 2005; Kotchoubey, 2005). Similar findings
perception nor did he show visual or other deficits have been obtained in a number of patients with unre-
(Mataro et al., 2001). Another case is that of a young sponsive wakefulness syndrome, usually when the
woman with massive bilateral prefrontal damage of background EEG contained frequencies above 4 Hz.
unclear etiology (Markowitsch and Kessler, 2000). Though these preserved responses are hard to interpret,
While manifesting grossly deficient scores in frontal they support the possibility that at least some degree of
lobe tests, she showed no abnormal perceptual abili- consciousness may be preserved after medial anterior
ties, and there was no issue whether she was conscious lesions and possibly also in other instances of clinical
(that is not to say that such patients do not suffer from unresponsiveness.
subtle visual deficits (Barcelo et al., 2000)). Contrast these examples of widespread anterior p0615
p0610 The evidence is more ambiguous with medial damage with patients with bilateral posterior damage
prefrontal lesions, especially those involving anterior resulting in a syndrome of hyperkinetic mutism (Fisher,
cingulate cortex and supplementary motor areas, often 1983; Inbody and Jankovic, 1986; Mori and Yamadori,
due to ruptured aneurysms of the anterior communi- 1989; Schiff and Plum, 2000): such patients are engaged
cating artery. The presentation of such patients has in a whirlwind of motor activity, coordinated but with-
been described as akinetic mutism (Cairns et al., 1941), out purpose. There is no indication that they have any
which is usually categorized as a variant of minimally awareness of self or environment (and of course they
conscious states (Schiff and Plum, 2000). Although the do not speak). An extreme case was described by
term akinetic mutism has been sometimes used to Schiff and colleagues (2002), Patient 1). The patient AU:15
denote different clinical conditions having different exhibited continuous, spontaneous, non-directed cho-
pathology (e.g., the so-called slow syndrome), the clas- reiform movements of head, body, and extremities
sic presentation is that of a patient who lies indeed when awake. He was mute and his movements had no
immobile and mute, but gives the impression of relationship to visual, auditory or tactile stimuli.
hypervigilance, following actions and objects with A PET study showed a profound hypometabolism of
conjugated eye movements. However, it is generally posterior forebrain regions, whereas anterior, cortico-
impossible to elicit any responses, establish contact striato-pallido-thalamo-cortical circuits showed com-
(though in some patients, occasionally, monosyllabic paratively high metabolism. Is there any experience
answers are reported), and there is no spontaneous left in such patients? Is a self despairing in complete
purposive activity. In a few cases, clinicians have the nothingness, experiencing thoughts of action with no
impression that such patients may understand what is object? Or is this condition associated with a complete
going on (which is why they are considered to be disappearance of the world and the self, and thus of
mute rather than having an unresponsive wakefulness consciousness? Intriguingly, a late posterior positivity
syndrome), implying that consciousness is present having a parietal peak is the event-related potential
(though possibly impaired), but not evidenced in component that is most reliably impaired in states of
behavior due to a complete lack of motivation or block seeming unconsciousness, and which distinguishes
of executive function (as opposed to paralysis, as in best between consciously detected vs. undetected sti-
the locked-in syndrome, Chapter 12). Others instead muli (Kotchoubey, 2005). Additionally, posterior cortex
consider such patients as essentially unconscious. has been correlated with consciousness in experiments
The interpretation is complicated by the fact that, in contrasting awareness with task relevance (Pitts et al.,
the rare instance in which such patients recover, there 2014), in studies matching expectations and perfor-
is usually amnesia for the akinetic episode, as in the mance during target presentation (Melloni et al., 2011),
original case of Cairns, though one patient who even- and in an no-task, within state paradigm during both
tually recovered reported that she remembered the REM and NREM sleep (Siclari et al., 2014b). Another
questions posed by the doctor but did not see a reason interesting finding is that, during the transition to
to respond (Laureys, personal communication). Cases sleep, slow waves tend to first affect the medial
in which the syndrome resolves through dopaminergic frontal cortex rather than the occipital, temporal, and

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 425
lateral posterior parietal areas (Siclari et al., 2014a). Lateral Fronto-Parietal Network vs. (Medial) s0120
This anterior-posterior slow-wave gradient at sleep Default System
onset may explain certain patterns of mental activity
such as the visual experiences typically observed An orthogonal way of slicing the cortical cake is p0630

during sleep onset along with the lack of voluntary to distinguish between the relative contribution to con-
control (i.e., the primary visual cortex and the lateral sciousness of lateral vs. mesial regions. In fact, there is
parieto-temporal areas are still relatively unaffected increasing evidence for the existence of two corticotha-
by slow waves, while the prefrontal cortex is already lamic networks usually characterized by antagonistic
“asleep”). activation patterns in fMRI studies (Raichle et al., 2001;
p0620 Altogether, at present it would seem that con- Fox and Raichle, 2007; Raichle and Snyder, 2007)
sciousness abides mostly in the back of the corticotha- (Chapter 6). One is a lateral “attention” network, the
lamic complex (though maybe not in the very back), other a predominantly mesial “default” system. The
rather than in the front, and that the front may not be lateral attention network is further subdivided into a
strictly required for experience to be present, but dorsal and a ventral attentional system (Corbetta et al.,
instead, it may be needed to report the experience 2000). The dorsal system is bilateral and composed of
itself (Frässle et al., 2014). Also, there is no doubt that the intraparietal sulcus and frontal eye field at the
the bulk of experience is sensory, and as such resides junction of the precentral and superior frontal sulcus.
in posterior cortex. As we have seen, neuroimaging It is involved in voluntary (top-down) orienting and
experiments do some justice to this view, showing shows activity increases after presentation of cues indi-
that prefrontal cortex is deactivated when self- cating where, when, or to what subjects should direct
reflection is abolished by task demand, but experience their attention. The ventral system is right-lateralized
is vividly present (Goldberg et al., 2006). Similarly, and composed of the right temporal-parietal junction
prefrontal cortex is relatively deactivated during REM and the right ventral frontal cortex. This system shows
sleep, when subjects dream vividly (Nir and Tononi, activity increases upon detection of salient targets and
2010). Moreover, multivariate pattern analysis of fMRI after abrupt changes in sensory stimuli. The dorsal
data can decode the identity of visual stimuli from and ventral lateral attentional systems also appear in
medial and lateral occipital regions but not from functional connectivity maps during spontaneous
regions of prefrontal cortex and intraparietal sulcus, activity, and their function can be coordinated by other
despite their task-related activation. Also, decoding prefrontal regions (Fox et al., 2006). Not surprisingly,
strength in visual regions correlates with the precision since attention and consciousness often go together,
of visual working memory for the stimuli, whereas many neuroimaging studies show an activation of this
decoding of frontal cortex and intraparietal sulcus lateral network, usually with the addition of anterior
activity is related to attentional context, kind of task, cingulate areas, in paradigms contrasting perceived vs.
and task difficulty (Postle, 2015). unperceived stimuli (Rees et al., 2002; Dehaene et al.,
p0625 However, that anterior cortex may not be necessary 2006) (Chapter 4). For instance, these regions are more
for consciousness does not entail that it does not active for unmasked vs. masked words and images;
AU:16 contribute directly to it in any aspect (Stuss and detected vs. undetected changes during change blind-
Alexander, 2001). After all, being self-conscious ness; reported vs. missed stimuli during the attentional
(reflecting upon what one perceives) is different from blink, seen vs. extinguished stimuli in neglect patients.
being conscious (perceiving it), yet both are experi- The “default” network (Raichle et al., 2001; Raichle p0635

ences. Perhaps feelings of thought, reflection, effort, and Snyder, 2007) includes primarily medial cortical
will, emotion and so on are generated by anterior areas such as the medial prefrontal cortex, the poste-
cortex, though no firm evidence exists. Also, premotor rior cingulate cortex, and the precuneus. However, it
and supplementary motor cortex may contribute to also includes a lateral parietal component posterior to
specific aspects of consciousness, such as the aware- the intraparietal sulcus. The default network was iden-
ness of movement (Sarrazin et al., 2008). Alternatively, tified because it typically shows decreased activity
prefrontal cortex may provide unconscious plans, when subjects perform cognitive tasks. In resting func-
strategies, skills and memories, as well as attention. If tional connectivity studies, regions of the default
this were the case, we would need to know what is network show strong positive correlations among
wrong with this large portion of the cortex. Is it wired themselves, presumably due to the high density of
in radically different way from posterior cortex? Is it anatomical connections (Fox and Raichle, 2007).
broken up into segregated loops encompassing the Posteromedial cortex appears to be a particularly
basal ganglia? At the very least, the study of the contri- important area of the brain, since it happens to have
bution of anterior cortical areas to consciousness is higher levels of baseline energy consumption (the
one of the ripest areas for future investigations. precuneus) than the rest of the cortex. Nevertheless,

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


426 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

the functional role of posteromedial cortex is only default network (Dehaene et al., 2001; Boly et al., 2007). In
partially understood, as selective, bilateral lesions of another study, however, awareness of auditory stimuli
these areas are hardly ever reported. Therefore, triggered the opposite pattern (Sadaghiani et al., 2009).
evidence comes mostly from neuroimaging studies Despite the temptation to assign consciousness to either
and transient, incomplete disruption through TMS. the lateral or medial component given their task-on vs.
Regions within posteromedial cortex, especially the task-off activation pattern, and their anticorrelated func-
precuneus, are activated during visuo-spatial imagery, tional connectivity, there are reasons to wonder whether
retrieval of episodic memories, spontaneous thought, these two subdivisions may actually be jointly involved
and during tasks that refer to the self and require a in generating experience. For example, the anticorrelated
first-person perspective (Cavanna and Trimble, 2006). functional connectivity emerges only after regressing out
While these studies suggest a role in conscious a large, correlated component (Fox et al., 2005). It has also
processes focusing on internal signals rather than on recently been demonstrated that over the fast time scale
external ones, other studies point to a more direct of consciousness, medial and lateral networks are actually
relevance to consciousness per se. Activity in postero- often co-activated in various combinations (Allen et al.,
medial areas is altered during generalized seizures, 2014; Barttfeld et al., 2015), making it unlikely that
and a strong deactivation is observed in hypnosis, consciousness is supported exclusively by one or the
sleep, general anesthesia with both propofol and inha- other. Moreover, there is evidence that both medial and
lation agents, and in the unresponsive wakefulness lateral areas may be part of a larger, anatomically defined
syndrome. As we have seen, recovery of function in “structural core.” Recently, the application of graph-
posteromedial cortex and reestablishment of functional theoretical methods to diffusion spectrum imaging of
connectivity with thalamus and frontal cortex are fiber tracts in humans has revealed the existence of a
among the early signs of recovery of consciousness. structural core of heavily interconnected cortical regions
However, it should be noted that posteromedial cortex (Hagmann et al., 2008; Bullmore and Sporns, 2009;
appear to be deactivated to a similar extent in both Sporns, 2013). This core is centered on a prominent
NREM and REM sleep (Maquet et al., 1996, 1997; medial “backbone” that includes the posterior cingulate
Braun et al., 1997). Given that REM sleep is usually cortex, the precuneus, the cuneus, as well as the paracen-
associated with vivid dreams, it is questionable tral lobule, and the isthmus of the cingulate (retrosplenial)
whether the activation of posteromedial cortex is nec- cortex. The structural core thus overlaps in part with the
essary for consciousness per se or rather for certain “default network,” although the medial prefrontal cortex
aspects of self-consciousness and related cognitive is conspicuously absent. There is, however, an important
activities (reviewed in Nir and Tononi, 2010). For lateral component of this structural core, which includes
instance, at intermediate doses certain anesthetics such the bank of the superior temporal sulcus, the temporo-
as xenon produce a selective deactivation of posterior parieto-occipital junction, and the inferior and superior
mesial cortex, yet subjects report depersonalization parietal cortex. Thus, the structural core also includes the
and out of body experiences, rather than unconscious- posterior portion of the lateral attentional system.
ness. Moreover, a patient with bilateral hypometabo- The structural core extends symmetrically to both hemi-
lism in the precuneus and superior temporal lobe, as spheres, and all its constituent areas have strong bilateral
well as in right posterior cingulate gyrus, was connections to associative (non-primary) nuclei of the
demented and psychotic, with delusions and halluci- thalamus, as well as to diffusely projecting thalamic cells.
nations, but evidently conscious (Le Ber et al., 2007, Neuroimaging studies also point to a joint involve- p0645
but see Damasio, 1999) for the view that posteromedial ment of both lateral and medial regions: in unrespon-
lesions may compromise consciousness). sive patients, minimally conscious patients, seizures
p0640 Switching between the “default” network and the associated with alterations of consciousness, general
“attention” network seem to occur spontaneously every anesthesia, and sleeping subjects, there is a remarkably
20 s on average. Activation of the “attention” network has similar set of regions that are deactivated compared to
been correlated with subjects’ reports of being “strongly control conditions: these include both the lateral
externally aware” (i.e., perception of environmental fronto-parietal network and medial regions such as
sensory stimuli) whereas activation of the “default” medial prefrontal cortex and precuneus. Another inter-
system has been correlated with reports of being esting case is that of patients emerging from a mini-
“strongly internally aware” (i.e., stimuli-independent mally conscious state (due to diffuse axonal injury)
thoughts such as inner speech or autobiographical memo- after the administration of the GABA agonist zolpidem
ries) (Vanhaudenhuyse et al., 2011). Other studies also (Clauss et al., 2001; Clauss and Nel, 2006; Brefel-
showed that awareness of somatosensory and visual Courbon et al., 2007; Whyte and Myers, 2009; Chatelle
stimuli typically correlates with an increase in activity in et al., 2014). In these patients, blood flow as measured
lateral fronto-parietal cortices and a deactivation of the by SPECT and PET increased by almost 40% bilaterally

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 427
in medial frontal cortex as well as in lateral areas such marriages. Also, its cognitive style seems to be very
as middle frontal and supramarginal gyri. So perhaps different. As we have seen, it is much more literal in its
both the medial and lateral contingents are important. recognition of images and events, and thereby often
Given the evidence just reviewed that posterior cortex more accurate, in contrast with a left hemisphere that is
is more important than anterior cortex, and the exam- constantly formulating hypotheses and trying to make
ples of posterior damage resulting in hyperkinetic sense of what happens. Also, in some tests the right
mutism, it may be that a posterior complex of associative hemisphere’s cognitive style is strangely “un-human.”
areas comprising the lateral temporo-parieto-occipital For example, in a guessing game in which a stimulus is
junction and perhaps a posteromesial backbone cur- red say 75% of the time, and green 25% of the time, and
rently represents the safest bet as to the brain regions the occurrence of stimuli is entirely at random, humans
that are most likely to be necessary for the bulk of respond by trying to match the probability of red and
conscious experience. As mentioned above, a similar green, thereby making many mistakes. By contrast,
posterior hotspot was found to distinguish between animals such as rats and goldfish respond red all the
retrospective reports of conscious experience and non time, and in this way maximize their success rate. In
conscious experience upon awakening from both such a game, the left hemisphere behaves just like a
NREM and REM sleep—two physiological states that human, probably because it is a characteristic human
are otherwise extremely different and do not require feature to try and find a pattern even in random events.
responsiveness to stimuli or task preparation and The right hemisphere, by contrast, behaves just like a
performance (Siclari et al., 2014b). rat or a goldfish would. Michael Gazzaniga has also
shown that the right hemisphere fails in certain simple
reasoning and classification tasks that are solved both
by 12-month-old children as well as by monkeys. The
s0125 Left vs. Right Hemisphere right hemisphere may however play a role in updating
p0650 One should also consider the most traditional inappropriate beliefs or hypotheses. Indeed, during
of dichotomies: the one between the left and the right verbal moral judgments, the split-brain patients’ left
brain. As discussed by Marinsek, Gazzaniga, and hemispheres failed to update its initial judgment when
Miller (Chapter 17), the evidence from split brain new evidence was provided (Miller et al., 2010). In the
patients, and even more so the results of right hemi- domain of inferential reasoning, another recent study
spherectomy operations, show beyond any doubt that showed that the right hemisphere tries to resolve
the isolated left hemisphere, whether alone or discon- inconsistency while the left hemisphere tries to reduce
nected from the right hemisphere, can support a uncertainty (Marinsek et al., 2014).
conscious self that is similar to that supported by of The extraordinary patient P.S., studied by Joseph p0665
an intact, fully equipped brain. Importantly, after a Ledoux and Michael Gazzaniga, who had a remark-
hemispherectomy or split-brain operation, the patient able ability to comprehend words with the right
(speaking through the left hemisphere) is anosognosic hemisphere, and went on to develop a limited ability
and feels in no way changed, although for example to speak through it, leaves little doubt that the right
the left half of the visual field is no longer available hemisphere can at times even have an individual
(Gazzaniga, 2014). sense of self. The rare cases of left hemispherectomy
p0655 People familiar with split-brain patients have little in right-handed adolescents also indicate that the
doubt that the isolated right hemisphere can support a right hemisphere can sustain a consciousness and a
second consciousness (Chapter 17). Long-term obser- self, although when the right hemisphere is left alone
vations make it clear that the disconnected right hemi- after the operation it is certain to undergo a variety of
sphere not only has its own private sensory and motor plastic changes that may partly modify its original
channels with which it can communicate with the functioning. It seems inconceivable, however, that
environment, but it has its specific perceptual skills, consciousness would return in a left hemispherecto-
can have a word lexicon, has its own memories and mized patient only when and to the extent that
may even have its own characteristic preferences language is recovering—it is much more plausible
and dislikes. After spending some time testing split- that consciousness and self are already there, and it is
brain patients, examiners spontaneously refer to the just language skills that are being added, just as in a
two hemispheres as if they were distinct people. recovering aphasic patient (see above).
p0660 Naturally enough, being limited in language and Despite the remarkable evidence that the discon- p0670
reasoning skills, under usual circumstances the right nected right hemisphere has its own conscious experi-
hemisphere is literally dominated by the left hemi- ence and perhaps at times even its own self (Damasio
sphere—it is usually passive, and does not complain and Meyer, 2009), it is worth considering the alternative
or cause trouble, just as in some highly asymmetric possibility that the isolated right hemisphere may

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


428 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

actually be just an unconscious “zombie.” Could it be purpose, and giving rise to a conscious percept might
that its responses are not dissimilar from those just fit the bill. However, back-connections, and associ-
provided by a patient with blindsight? Or by the ated reentrant volleys, are just as numerous between
“unconscious action system” of Miller and Goodale? V1 and visual thalamus, which is usually denied any
Several considerations cast doubt on this possibility. direct contribution to awareness. Also, there does not
Unlike blindsight patients, the isolated right hemi- seem to be any lack of back-connections within the
sphere does not respond just in forced-choice tests, but dorsal stream. It should be emphasized that the
can exhibit spontaneous choices. It is capable not just of strength and termination pattern of back-connections
adjusting behavior for action, but can master perceptual seems more suited to a modulatory/synchronizing
tasks that are impossible for patients with temporal role than to driving their target neurons. For example,
lesions that lack explicit object recognition. It can do the focal inactivation of area 18 can slightly increase or
much more than just “automatic routines,” and can decrease discharge rates of units in area 17, but does
initiate purposeful behaviors if properly asked. It is far not change their feature selectivity for location
more lucid than a sleepwalker or a patient with a partial and orientation (Martinez-Conde et al., 1999). Also, the
complex seizure. Finally, the isolated right hemisphere numerosity of backward connections is a natural
can even express individual preference and goals, and consequence of the hierarchical organization of feed-
recognize a picture of itself (although less easily than forward ones. For instance, cells in the lateral genicu-
the left hemisphere). Thus, the kind of consciousness late nucleus (LGN) are not oriented, while cells in area
associated with the isolated right hemisphere could be 17 are. To be unbiased, feedback to any one LGN cell
comparable, and in some cases more sophisticated, should come from area 17 cells of all orientations,
with that of other primates lacking language. which requires many connections; on the other hand,
since at any given time only area 17 cells correspond-
ing to a given orientation would be active, feedback
effects would not be strong. If they were, properties of
s0130 Reentrant vs. Feed-Forward Connections area 17 cells, such as orientation selectivity, would be
p0675 Another possibility that has been investigated for transferred upon LGN cells, which they are not (to a
explaining the presence of awareness is the occurrence first approximation). Backward signals certainly play
of a “reentrant” wave of activity (also described as a role in sensory function: for instance, they can medi-
recurrent, recursive, or reverberant) from higher to ate some extra-classical receptive field effects, provide
lower level cortical areas. This view is based on several a natural substrate for both attentional modulation
considerations. An important one, though rarely and imagery, and can perhaps dynamically route feed-
confessed, is that a mere sequence of feed-forward pro- forward signaling processing according to prior expec-
cessing steps seems far too “straightforward” and tations. But are backward connections really critical for
mechanical to offer a substrate for subjective experience. consciousness?
Reentrant processes, by “closing the loop” between The most intriguing data in support of a role for reen- p0685
past- and present activity, or between predicted and trant connections in conscious perception have come
actual versions of the input, would seem to provide a from neurophysiological experiments. Experiments
more fertile substrate for giving rise to reverberations requiring ultra-rapid categorizations, such as deciding
(Lorente de Nó, 1938), generating emergent properties whether a natural image contains an animal or not
through cell assemblies (Hebb, 1949), implementing (Thorpe et al., 1996; Bacon-Mace et al., 2005; Kirchner
hypothesis testing through resonances (Grossberg, and Thorpe, 2006) can also be used to partially dissociate
1999), linking present with past (Edelman and feed-forward from reentrant signaling. In such experi-
Mountcastle, 1978; Edelman, 1989), and subject with ments, a sweep of activity travels from the retina
object (Damasio, 1999). through several stages of feed-forward connections
p0680 A more concrete reason why reentrant activity is along the hierarchy of ventral visual areas, until it elicits
an attractive candidate for the neural substrate of con- an appropriate categorization response. This process
sciousness is that it travels through back-connections, takes as little as 150 ms, which leaves only about 10 ms
of which the cerebral cortex is extraordinarily rich of processing per stage. Thus, only a few spikes can be
(Felleman and Van Essen, 1991). In primates, feed- fired before the next stage produces its output, yet they
forward connections originate mainly in supragranular are sufficient to specify selective responses for orienta-
layers and terminate in layer 4. Feedback connections tion, motion, depth, color, shape, and even animals,
instead originate in both superficial and deep layers, faces, or places, conveying most of the relevant informa-
and usually terminate outside of layer 4. The sheer tion about the stimulus (Hung et al., 2005). While this
abundance of back-connections in sensory regions fast feed-forward sweep within the ventral system is
suggests that they ought to serve some important sufficient for the near-automatic categorization of stimuli

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROANATOMY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 429
and a behavioral response, it seems insufficient to gener- phosphene (small and stationary). Their interpretation
ate a conscious percept (VanRullen and Koch, 2003). For was that activity in V5 that, on its own, is insufficient to
example, if another image (the mask) is flashed soon induce a moving percept, can produce such a percept if
after the target image, subjects are still able to categorize the level of induced activity in V1 is high enough.
the target, though they may deny having seen it In another study (Boyer et al., 2005), subjects where p0700
consciously. shown either an oriented bar or a colored patch—
p0690 A set of elegant experiments in animals and stimuli that are processed in visual cortex. If, around
humans, supported by computational models, have 100 ms later, a TMS pulse was applied to V1, the
provided evidence that visual stimuli become stimulus became perceptually invisible, although on
conscious only when the feed-forward sweep is joined forced-choice subjects could still discriminate orienta-
by a reentrant sweep (Lamme and Roelfsema, 2000, tion or color. This result indicates that, without any
see also Self et al., 2012). In awake monkeys trained to overt participation of V1, stimuli can reach extrastriate
signal whether or not they saw a salient figure on a areas without eliciting a conscious percept, just as in
background, the early, feed-forward response of V1 blindsight patients. It also suggests that, since the
neurons was the same, no matter whether or not the forward sweep reaches V1 after just 30 or 40 ms, the
monkey saw the figure (Super et al., 2001). However, a TMS pulse may abolish the awareness of the stimulus
later response component was suppressed when the not so much by blocking feed-forward transmission,
monkey did not see the figure. Light anesthesia also but by interfering with the backward volley (see also
eliminated this later component without affecting the Ro et al., 2003). On the other hand, it cannot be ruled
initial response. Late components are thought to reflect out that the TMS pulse may act instead by triggering a
reentrant volleys from higher areas (Rossi et al., 2001). cortical!thalamo!cortical volley that interferes with
The late response component crucial for the visibility the offset discharge triggered by the stimulus, as may
of stimuli under backward masking might also be due indeed be the case in backward masking.
to a reentrant volley (Lamme and Roelfsema, 2000), Yet another study, this time using fMRI, examined p0705
which is mediated primarily by NMDA receptors (Self the neural correlates of brightness (perceptual light-
et al., 2012). However, others have suggested that the ness) using backward masking. The psychometric
timing of maximal masking depends on the timing of visibility function was not correlated with the stimu-
target offset, suggesting that the component that is lated portion of V1, but with downstream visual
obliterated is a feed-forward offset discharge, not a regions, including fusiform cortex, parietal!functional
reentrant one (Macknik, 2006). Moreover, the late com- areas, and with the sectors of V1 responding to
ponent can be dissociated from a behavioral response the unstimulated surround (Haynes et al., 2005).
simply by raising the decision criterion (Super et al., Remarkably, visibility was also correlated with the
2001), and it can occur in the absence of report during amount of coupling (effective connectivity) between
change- and inattentional blindness (Scholte et al., fusiform cortex and the portion of V1 that responded
2006). Perhaps in such cases subjective experience is to the surround. Once again, this result could be
present but, due to an insufficient involvement of explained by the activation of reentrant connections,
frontal areas, it cannot be reported (Block, 2005; though fMRI cannot distinguish between forward and
Tsuchiya and Koch, 2005; Lamme, 2006). backward influences.
p0695 Another main source of evidence for a role of reentrant While the above studies provide evidence for a role p0710
volleys in consciousness comes from early experiments of backconnections to V1 in visual experience, a recent
using TMS. In an early experiment, Pascual-Leone TMS experiment in a blindsight patient with intact
and Walsh applied TMS to V5 to elicit large, moving extrastriate areas and damaged V1 has shown that the
phosphenes (Pascual-Leone and Walsh, 2001). They then patient could experience phosphenes after stimulation
applied another, subthreshold TMS pulse to a corre- of parietal cortex (Figure 25.7) (Mazzi et al., 2014). This
sponding location in V1. When TMS to V1 was delivered finding suggests that backconnections to V1 are not
after TMS to V5 (15 to 145 ms), subjects often did not necessary for visual consciousness, though it does not
see the V5 phosphene, and when they saw one, it was rule out the involvement of backconnections to other
not moving. Their interpretation was that disruption of brain areas.
activity in V1 at the time of arrival of a reentrant volley Finally, recent human directional connectivity studies p0715
from V5 interferes with the experience of attributes show that top-down connectivity is stronger when
encoded by V5. In a subsequent study (Silvanto et al., somatosensory stimuli are perceived than when they are
2005), it was shown that, when a subthreshold pulse not (Auksztulewicz et al., 2012, see also Sachidhanandam
was applied over V5, followed 10!40 ms later by a et al., 2013 in rodents). Neuroimaging studies using
suprathreshold pulse over V1, subjects reported a V5- directed transfer entropy and dynamic causal modeling
like phosphene (large and moving), rather than a V1 in anesthetized human subjects (Ku et al., 2011; Boly

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


430 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

et al., 2012a) and in brain-damaged patients (Boly et al., 1967; Pins and Ffytche, 2003). The late negative shift
2011) also support the hypothesis that preserved feed- in slow cortical potentials disappears with propofol
back connectivity is necessary for consciousness (Tononi anesthesia, whereas the early positive component is
and Edelman, 1998; Lamme and Roelfsema, 2000; preserved (Fitzgerald et al., 2001). In somatosensory
Dehaene and Naccache, 2001; Lamme, 2006; Dehaene cortex of awake monkeys conscious detection is corre-
and Changeux, 2011; Oizumi et al., 2014). lated with magnitude and latency of the N1 potential,
presumably generated by excitatory input onto supra-
granular layers through backconnections from higher
cortical areas (Cauller and Kulics, 1991). Notably, the
s0135 Superficial vs. Deep Layers of Cortex N1 is abolished during general anesthesia (Arezzo
p0720 An important open question is whether distinct et al., 1981) and slow wave sleep (Cauller and Kulics,
cortical cell types have a privileged association with 1988). Finally, a late membrane potential depolariza-
consciousness. During slow wave sleep in cats, tion occurs in supragranular neurons in somatosen-
autoradiography shows a reduction in the activity of sory cortex of head-fixed mice on trials in which the
infragranular layers of visual cortex (Livingstone and mouse detects vibrissal stimulation (Sachidhanandam
Hubel, 1981). Large, thick-tufted pyramidal neurons et al., 2013). In the near future, laminar recordings
of layer 5B are ideally suited to integrate local and coupled with selective optogenetic stimulation should
long-distance inputs (Larkum, 2013), and their distal help clarify the involvement of specific cell types in
apical tufts are the recipients of massive feedback consciousness.
from higher-level cortical regions. On the other hand,
these cells project primarily to subcortical structures
and their limited connectivity within cortex may
THE NEUROPHYSIOLOGY OF s0140
be more appropriate for implementing cortico-
CONSCIOUSNESS
subcortico-cortical loops that mediate unconscious
behaviors (Harris and Shepherd, 2015). By contrast,
The studies discussed above indicate that, even p0725
thin-tufted pyramidal cells in L5A, as well as
within the cerebral cortex, changes in neural activity
some cells in L6, have exclusively cortico-cortical
do not necessarily correlate with changes in conscious
connections and are more heavily interconnected.
experience. Also, we saw earlier that most of the cortex
Supragranular pyramidal cells in L2/3 are even more
is active during early NREM sleep and anesthesia, not
densely interconnected and more specific in their dis-
to mention during generalized seizures, but subjects
charge properties (Douglas and Martin, 2004;
have little conscious content to report. Thus, it is natu-
Binzegger et al., 2009; Sakata and Harris, 2009; Harris
ral to suggest that some additional dynamic feature of
and Shepherd, 2015). Accordingly, both feed-forward
neural activity must be present to generate conscious
and feedback projections originating in superficial
content. Here we consider the role of: (i) synchronous
layers exhibit greater topographic precision than those
or oscillatory activity; (ii) the P3b wave and other
from infragranular layers (Markov et al., 2014). The
evoked potentials; (iii) cortical “activation”; and (iv)
apical dendrites of supragranular pyramidal cells and
sustained vs. phasic activity.
that of different types of inhibitory interneurons in
superficial layers (Zhang et al., 2014)—are also the
preferential target of backconnections and of diffusely
projecting thalamic matrix cells (Shipp, 2007). An
Synchronization and Oscillations s0145

intriguing finding is that supragranular layers, while An idea that has prompted much experimental and p0730
interconnected, can become uncoupled through atten- theoretical work is that consciousness may require the
tional modulation (Maier et al., 2010; Buffalo et al., synchronization, at a fine temporal scale, of large
2011) and during sleep (Funk et al., 2014). Neuronal populations of neurons distributed over many cortical
avalanches are spatiotemporal patterns of spontane- areas, in particular via rhythmic discharges in the
ous activity that reflect a critical state of network gamma range (30!70 Hz and beyond) (Crick and
excitability favorable to information integration, and Koch, 1990; Fries et al., 2007; Brunet et al., 2014)
they occur only in supragranular layers (Shew and (Chapter 3). The emphasis on synchrony ties well with
Plenz, 2013). Furthermore, neural activity in supragra- the common assumption that consciousness requires
nular layers often correlates with conscious sensation the “binding” together of a multitude of attributes
across species. Between stimulus onset and response, within a single experience, as when we see a rich
a negative slow potential of likely supragranular visual scene containing multiple objects and attributes
origin (He and Raichle, 2009) occurs only when a that is nevertheless perceived as a unified whole
near-threshold stimulus is perceived (Libet et al., (Singer, 1999). According to this view, the neural

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROPHYSIOLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 431
substrate of such an experience would include two that synchrony in one or another frequency band is not
aspects: first, the underlying activation pattern (groups necessarily a marker of consciousness. For example,
of neurons that have increased their firing rates) would while some EEG and MEG studies in humans also
be widely distributed across different areas of the cere- suggest that long-distance gamma synchrony may corre-
bral cortex, each specialized in signaling a different late with visual consciousness (Rodriguez et al., 1999;
object or attribute within the scene; second, the firing Melloni et al., 2007; Wyart and Tallon-Baudry, 2009),
of these activated neurons would be synchronized on often they did not fully distinguish the effects of
a fast time scale to signal their binding into a single conscious visibility from those of selective attention.
percept. In this respect, synchrony seems ideally suited Moreover, one may see a stimulus with or without
to signal relatedness: for example, in the presence of a accompanying gamma activity, depending on the con-
red square, some neurons would respond to the pres- text. Thus, a recent study using intracranial recordings
ence of a square, while other would respond to the in humans showed gamma activation in visual cortex
presence of the color red. If they synchronize at a fast when a degraded stimulus is made visible by increasing
time scale, they would indicate to other groups of sensory evidence. However, when visibility was
neurons that there is a red square, “binding” the two increased to the same extent by showing the pictures
features together (Tononi et al., 1992). By contrast, sig- beforehand, there was no “gamma ignition” (Aru et al.,
naling relatedness by increased firing rates alone 2012a). Also, gamma synchrony is high and may even be
would be more cumbersome and probably slower enhanced during early NREM sleep, anesthesia
(Singer, 1999). Also, fine temporal scale synchrony has (Figure 25.8) (Imas et al., 2005; Murphy et al., 2011), or
the welcome property of disambiguating among multi- seizures (Pockett and Holmes, 2009), and can be
ple objects—if a green cross was present simulta- observed with emotional stimuli that remain uncon-
neously with the red square, cross and green neurons scious (Luo et al., 2009), suggesting that there may be
would also be active, but false conjunctions would be gamma synchrony without consciousness. Furthermore,
avoided by precise phase locking (Tononi et al., 1992). there may be consciousness without synchrony. In
Moreover, computational models predict that, for human visual cortex narrowband gamma oscillations is
the same level of firing, synchronous input is more induced reliably only by certain luminance gratings, and
effective on target neurons than asynchronous input not by many natural images that were easily seen
(Abeles, 1991; Tononi et al., 1992), and indeed and recognized (Hermes et al., 2014), suggesting that
synchrony makes a difference to the outputs to the rest gamma band oscillations are not necessary for seeing
of the brain (Brecht et al., 1999; Schoffelen et al., 2005). (Ray and Maunsell, 2011).
Finally, large-scale models predict that synchrony in Finally, there are some difficult conceptual problems p0740
the gamma range occurs due to the reciprocal connec- in characterizing synchrony as an essential ingredient
tivity and loops within the corticothalamic system that unifies perceptual states and thereby makes them
(Lumer et al., 1997a,b), and indeed phase alignment conscious. While many experiences do indeed involve
between distant groups of neurons in the gamma several different elements and attributes that are
range anticipates by a few milliseconds an increase in “bound” together into a unified percept, there
gamma-band power (Womelsdorf et al., 2007). In this are many other experiences, equally conscious, that do
respect, oscillatory activity, even when subthreshold, not seem to require much binding at all: for instance,
could further facilitate synchronous interactions by an experience of pure darkness or of pure blue, or a
biasing neurons to discharge within the same time loud sound that briefly occupies consciousness and
frame (Engel et al., 2001). has no obvious internal structure—would merely seem
p0735 Experimental evidence concerning the role of to require the strong activation of the relevant neurons,
synchrony/synchronous oscillations in perceptual with no need for signaling relatedness to other ele-
operations was initially obtained in primary visual areas ments, and thus no need for synchrony. Also, the idea
of anesthetized animals (Chapter 3). For example, in that the neural correlate of a given conscious experi-
primary visual cortex, neurons have been found that ence are given by active neurons bound by synchrony
respond to a coherent object by synchronizing their discounts the importance of inactive ones: information
firing in the gamma range. Stimulus-specific, gamma specifying that particular unified experience must be
range synchronization is greatly facilitated when the conveyed both by which neurons are active and which
EEG is activated by stimulating the mesencephalic retic- are not, yet for inactive neurons there does not seem to
ular formation (Munk et al., 1996; Herculano-Houzel be anything to bind. On the other hand, if most
et al., 1999), by attention (Roelfsema et al., 1997), and neurons in the cortex were to become active hypersyn-
increases for a dominant stimulus under binocular chronously, as is the case in generalized seizures, they
rivalry even though firing rates may not change (Fries should result in maximal “binding,” but consciousness
et al., 1997, 2001). However, it has since become clear vanishes rather than become more vivid.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


432 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

f0045 FIGURE 25.8 Gamma synchrony without consciousness. Power spectrum changes across vigilance states in frontal (anterior cingulate)
and parietal (posterior cingulate) regions showing increased gamma power during propofol-induced loss of consciousness (LOC) compared
with wakefulness. Semi-logarithmic plots of power spectra for each region are displayed in waking (W, black), mild sedation (Ms, blue), and
LOC (red). The blue bars in the middle panel show frequency band-specific changes in power during the transition from waking to sedation
and then to LOC. Source: Taken from Boly et al. (2012a).

s0150 P3b and other Evoked Potentials amplification or “ignition” of cortical activity through
p0745 In addition to gamma synchrony, another influential a distributed network involving frontoparietal areas
idea has been that the P300 wave, or more specifically (Dehaene and Changeux, 2011). However, there is
the P3b component, may constitute a reliable indicator increasing evidence that the P3b signals instead the
of consciousness (Dehaene and Changeux, 2011). The occurrence of post-perceptual processes, including
P300—a late positive event-related potential (ERP) memory updating, decision-making and motor prepa-
appearing after 300 ms or more, discovered 50 years ration. For example, when subjects already have a
ago (Sutton et al., 1965), is often observed when a working memory representation of the target stimulus,
subject reports that he is aware of a sensory stimulus. there is no P3b when they see the stimulus (Melloni
Many studies have employed masking, attentional et al., 2011). Moreover, stimuli that are task-irrelevant
blink, and manipulations of stimulus strength and do not trigger a P3b (Pitts et al., 2012), yet subjects are
shown that the P3b component of the ERP correlates clearly conscious of them (Pitts et al., 2014). Also, the
with reports of stimulus visibility (Dehaene and P3b component cannot be used to distinguish the state
Naccache, 2001; Sergent et al., 2005; Del Cul et al., of consciousness from that of unconsciousness. For
2007). Accordingly, the P3b has been proposed as a example, one cannot rely on the P3b triggered by
“signature” of consciousness. Specifically, the occur- global violations of auditory regularities to discrimi-
rence of the P3b wave would reflect a non-linear nate between unresponsive and minimally conscious

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


THE NEUROPHYSIOLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 433
patients (Sitt et al., 2014). Moreover, the P3b is absent different factors, such as a decrease in the firing rate of
in the majority of brain-damaged patients who are subcortical activating systems (Moruzzi and Magoun,
clearly conscious (Kotchoubey et al., 2005; Fischer 1949; McCormick et al., 1993), excessive thalamic inhibi-
et al., 2010; Holler et al., 2011) and virtually useless for tion due to the globus pallidus (Schiff, 2009), or a critical
the identificartion of patients who are minimally level of cortical deafferentation (Timofeev et al., 2000).
conscious (Faugeras et al., 2011). By contrast, up to Repeated high-amplitude (.75 µV) slow waves in p0760
40% of patients who are comatose, as well as pharma- the EEG remains the simplest and most effective way
cologically sedated and hypothermic can be shown to to assess the loss of consciousness (Boly et al., 2009),
have a P3b-like component (Tzovara et al., 2015). superior to most alternatives (Murphy et al., 2011;
p0750 While it is now clear that the P3b cannot serve as an Kertai et al., 2012). Prominent slow waves during deep
indicator of consciousness, recent work supports the NREM early in the night herald the time when
notion that an earlier ERP, the visual awareness subjects, if awakened, are most likely to deny that they
negativity (VAN), may constitute a promising correlate were experiencing anything at all (Stickgold et al.,
of the visibility of stimuli, though an attentional 2001). Similarly, upon induction of general anesthesia
component is hard to rule out. The VAN starts as early with propofol, a sudden increase of slow wave power
as 100 ms from the onset of a visual stimulus, peaks at coincides with behavioral loss of consciousness
around 200!250 ms, and is localized to posterior (Purdon et al., 2013). Indeed, the visual detection of
cortex (occipital, temporal and posterior parietal lobes) slow waves and their relative contribution to total EEG
(Railo et al., 2011). Correlates of visibility of phos- power outperforms by far most other proposed mar-
phenes elicited by TMS can be obtained earlier kers of consciousness, including gamma power and
(B70 ms) in parietal cortex after parietal stimulation the P3b, when the goal is to discriminate between
and in temporal cortex after occipital TMS (Pitts et al., conscious and unconscious brain-injured patients at
2014; Bagattini et al., 2015). the group level (Forgacs et al., 2014; Sitt et al., 2014).
Overall, the progression from a predominance of delta,
through theta, to alpha-range frequencies corresponds
s0155 Cortical “Activation” to the progression from coma or the unresponsive
p0755 Since the early days of the EEG, and the early work wakefulness syndrome, through the minimally
of Moruzzi and Magoun (1949), neurologists and neu- conscious state, to behavioral consciousness (Schiff
roscientists have routinely relied on the occurrence of et al., 2014). However, slow waves are not as reliable
EEG low-voltage fast-activity, also known as “activated” when discriminating between unresponsive and mini-
EEG, to assess the likely presence of consciousness. mally conscious patients based on single-subject EEG
When REM sleep was discovered (Aserinsky and (Forgacs et al., 2014; Sitt et al., 2014). Also, some
Kleitman, 1953), it became apparent that, despite behav- unconscious patients who are in a severe post-anoxic
ioral immobility and unresponsiveness, the occurrence coma show steady, widespread alpha rhythm rather
of an activated EEG was a reliable marker for the than slow waves (Westmoreland et al., 1975).
occurrence of dreams. By contrast, EEG high-voltage, Conversely, in some cases consciousness is present but
low-frequency activity, typically in the delta range, often there are large slow waves, as with atropine adminis-
correlates with the loss of consciousness. Over the last tration (Wikler, 1952; Bradley, 1968) or with some rare
decades, intracellular recordings from cortical and forms of status epilepticus (Gokyigit and Caliskan,
thalamic neurons have revealed the mechanisms that 1995). Importantly, however, in such cases high-
underlie the transition from the low-voltage fast-activity voltage, slow-activity may involve only some cortical
typical of wakefulness, to the high-voltage, slow-activity areas and not others, in a way that cannot be resolved
of deep NREM sleep and general anesthesia (Steriade, by conventional EEG. Indeed, as already mentioned,
2000). Hyperpolarization of thalamocortical neurons subjects awakened from NREM sleep report visual
makes them switch from a tonic into a bursting mode, dreams if the EEG is locally activated over a parieto-
leading to a synchronization of the EEG in the spindle occipital hotspot, even though other cortical areas
(12!14 Hz) and theta (5!8 Hz) range. When cortical display low-frequency activity. Conversely, if the same
neurons are further disfacilitated and start alternating hot spot shows delta activity, subjects do not report
synchronously between depolarized up-states and any dream (Siclari et al., 2014b).
hyperpolarized down-states every second or so, larger
slow waves in the delta range (,4 Hz) appear in the
EEG (Steriade et al., 2001). This schematic sequence of
Sustained vs. Phasic Activity s0160
events accompanies the loss of consciousness in physio-
logical, pharmacological, and pathological conditions A plausible idea is that neural activity may contribute p0765
(Brown et al., 2010). Slow waves can be initiated by to consciousness only if it is sustained for a minimum

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


434 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

period of time, perhaps around a few hundred millise- hubs along the medial surface of the cortex may
conds. At the phenomenological level, there is no doubt facilitate the interaction of distant cortical regions;
that the “now” of experience unfolds at a time scale com- more diffuse projections from thalamic matrix cells
prised between tens and several hundred milliseconds may provide a shared background of excitability that
(Bachmann, 2000), and in some aspects may even stretch also facilitates long-range interactions; and the reticu-
to 1 or 2 s (Poppel and Artin, 1988). Other experiments lar thalamic nucleus may provide strong inhibitory
have made use of the attentional blink phenomenon: coupling among distributed cortical areas. The rapid
when an observer detects a target in a rapid stream of formation of attractors may be enhanced by short-term
visual stimuli, there is a brief period of time during strengthening of activated synapses, while their disso-
which the detection of subsequent targets is impaired. lution after a period of stability may be facilitated by
Remarkably, targets that directly follow the first target the short-term depression of synapses and/or destabi-
are less impaired than those that follow after lizing signals from neuromodulatory systems (Sporns
200!400 ms (Raymond et al., 1992). By manipulating et al., 1991; Tononi et al., 1992). The time constants of
attention, identical visual stimuli can be made conscious neuronal integration, of various intrinsic currents, of
or unconscious. In such studies, event-related potentials AMPA and GABA receptors, and especially of NMDA
reflecting early sensory processing (the P1 and N1 receptors, ranging from tens to hundreds of millise-
components) were identical for seen and unseen stimuli, conds, also seem well suited to boosting, sustaining,
but quickly diverged around 270 ms, suggesting that sti- and terminating interactions in a way that is both
muli only become visible when a sustained pattern of effective and flexible. It is also important that neurons
activation/deactivation is elicited in a distributed net- are extremely reactive to perturbations, being poised at
work of cortical association areas (Vogel et al., 1998; the edge of firing, in line with work on avalanches,
Sergent et al., 2005). By the same token, there must be criticality, and neural “noise” (Chen et al., 2010;
ways for such sustained patterns of activation to dissolve Sporns, 2010; Deco et al., 2011). On theoretical
quickly and leave room for new patterns, for example grounds, it is expected that the time scale of attractor
when new stimuli occur (metastability). formation and dissolution would correspond to the
p0770 It has been recognized for a long time that the macro time scale at which integrated information
massive interconnectivity within and among cortical reaches a maximum (Tononi, 2012; Hoel et al., 2013).
areas (and with thalamus) provides an ideal substrate In that case, consciousness would flow at the longer
for cooperative dynamics among distributed neurons, time scale of metastable transient attractors, while the
which Hebb called cell assemblies, others called coali- micro-level interactions among neurons at the time
tions (Crick and Koch, 2003). Simply put, neurons in scale of a few milliseconds would not contribute to
the corticothalamic system seem coupled in such a phenomenology, despite constitute the underlying
way as to ensure the rapid emergence of firing pat- microstructure.
terns that are distributed over wide regions of the On the other hand, other data would seem to suggest p0775
cortex, where some neurons are strongly activated, that it may actually be the phasic, onset- or offset
and many more are deactivated. These patterns of discharge of neurons that correlates with experience.
activity can be thought of as transient attractors The most stringent data come again from studies of
(Friston, 1997, 2000; Rabinovich et al., 2006; Deco et al., visual masking (for a review see Macknik, 2006). To
2009): they remain stable (hence attractors) over a time be effective, masking stimuli must either precede
scale of tens/hundreds of milliseconds, but then (forward masking) or follow (backward masking) target
dissolve rapidly (hence transient), to make room for stimuli at appropriate time intervals, and usually need
another transient attractor. Indeed, some EEG and to be spatially contiguous. Macknik and collaborators
MEG studies suggest that cortical activity patterns showed, using a combination of psychophysics, unit
show brief periods of stability linked by even shorter recordings in animals, and neuroimaging in humans,
periods of instability (Lehmann, 2010; Musso et al., that for simple, unattended target stimuli, masking
2010; Van de Ville et al., 2010). An example of this stimuli suppress visibility if their “spatiotemporal
attractor dynamics from an early model of large-scale edges” overlap with the spatiotemporal edges of the
cortical networks is shown in (Tononi, 2012) targets, that is, if they begin or end when target stimuli
(Figure 25.7). The rapid formation of transient attrac- begin or end, in space and time. They confirmed that
tors is facilitated by the connectional architecture of such spatiotemporal edges correspond to transient
the corticothalamic system, which includes strong local bursts of spikes in primary visual cortex. If these bursts
links as well as a network of long-range connections are inhibited, for example if the offset discharge elicited
among nearby and distant areas, often reciprocal, by the target stimulus is obliterated by the onset of the
supporting reentrant loops that favor integration mask, the target becomes invisible. Most likely, these
(Stratton and Wiles, 2010; Sporns, 2011). Connectional spatiotemporal edges of increased firing are both

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


A THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVE 435
generated (target stimuli) and suppressed (masking structures or processes that are associated with
stimuli) by mechanisms of lateral inhibition, which are consciousness from those that are not. But even if we
ubiquitous in sensory systems (Macknik, 2006). come closer to this goal, we still need to understand
p0780 Additional evidence for the importance of phasic, why certain structures and processes have a privileged
transient activation of neurons in determining the visi- relationship with subjective experience. For example,
bility of stimuli comes from studies of microsaccades— why is it that neurons in corticothalamic circuits are
the small, involuntary movements that our eyes make essential for conscious experience, whereas cerebellar
continually (Martinez-Conde et al., 2004). If microsac- neurons, despite their huge numbers, are not? And
cades are counteracted by image stabilization on the what is wrong with many cortical circuits that may
retina, stationary objects fade and become completely make them unsuitable to yield subjective experience?
invisible. In a recent study (Martinez-Conde et al., Or why is it that consciousness wanes during slow
2006), subjects were asked to fixate a central dot (which wave sleep early in the night, despite levels of neural
tends to reduce microsaccades) while attending to a firing in the corticothalamic system that are compara-
surrounding circle. Soon, the circle fades and merges ble to those in quiet wakefulness? Other questions
into the background (the Troxler illusion). It was are even more difficult to address in the absence of
found that before a fading period, the probability, rate, a theory. For example, is consciousness present in
and magnitude of microsaccades decreased. Before animals that have a nervous system considerably
transitions toward visibility, the probability, rate, and different from ours? And what about computerized
magnitude of microsaccades increased, compatible robots or other artifacts that behave intelligently but
with the hypothesis that microsaccades are indeed are organized in a radically different way from human
necessary for visibility. Importantly, in macaque brains?
monkeys, when an optimally oriented line was centered
over the receptive field of cells in V1, the cell’s activity
increased after microsaccades, and tended to emit
bursts (Martinez-Conde et al., 2002), suggesting again
Consciousness as Integrated Information s0170

that phasic activity may be crucial for visibility. It would seem that, to address these questions, we p0795
p0785 One should remember, however, that the impor- need a theoretical approach that tries to establish, at
tance of phasic discharges for stimulus awareness has the fundamental level, what consciousness is, how it
only been demonstrated for early visual cortex but, as can be measured, and what requisites a physical sys-
we saw above, the neural substrate of consciousness is tem must satisfy in order to generate it. Integrated infor-
more likely to lie elsewhere. Psychophysically, mask- mation theory of consciousness (IIT) represents such an
ing is similarly effective when masking stimuli are approach (Figure 25.9) (Tononi, 2004a,b, 2008, 2012;
presented monoptically (through the same eye as the Oizumi et al., 2014).
target) and dichoptically (through the other eye). The According to the theory, an essential property of con- p0800
analysis of fMRI data in humans show that a correlate sciousness is that it exists intrinsically—an experience
of monoptic visual masking can be found in all retinoto- exists for the experiencing subject, rather than for
pic visual areas, whereas dichoptic masking is only an external observer. Another essential property of
seen in retinotopic areas downstream of V2 within the consciousness is that it is extraordinarily informative.
occipital lobe (Tse et al., 2005), suggesting an anatomical This is because, whenever you experience a particular
lower bound for the neural substrate of consciousness. conscious scene, it rules out a huge number of alterna-
Thus, it could be that phasic onset- and offset dis- tive experiences. For example, you lie in bed with eyes
charges are important not in and of themselves, but open and experience pure darkness and silence. This is
because they are particularly effective in activating one of the simplest experiences you might have, one
downstream areas that directly support consciousness. that may not be thought as conveying much informa-
In these downstream areas, perhaps, consciousness may tion. One should realize, however, that the informative-
actually require sustained firing. Indeed, the duration ness of what you just experienced lies not in how
of the activation of face-selective neurons in IT is complicated it is to describe, but in what makes it what
strongly correlated with the visibility of masked faces it is and thereby different from myriads of other experi-
(Rolls et al., 1999). ences that you could have had but actually did not
have: you could have experienced any one frame from
any of innumerable movies, or the smoke and flames of
s0165
A THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVE your room burning, or any other possible scene, but you
did not—instead, you experienced darkness and silence.
p0790 Progress in neuroscience will hopefully lead to a This means that when you experienced darkness and
better understanding of what distinguishes neural silence, whether you think or not of what was ruled out

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


436 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

f0050 FIGURE 25.9 Integrated information theory. An experience is a maximally irreducible conceptual structure composed of concepts speci-
fied over itself by a complex constituted of elements in a state—a “form” in cause-effect space. In this example, the system constituted of logic
gates A,B,C,D,E, and contains a complex ABC. This complex specifies a conceptual structure (a maximally irreducible cause-effect structure
made of concepts). The conceptual structure is presented as the set of concepts specified by a mechanism of the system in its present state
over all past and future states of the system (right). It is presented as a 2-D projection in which the cause-effect repertoire of each concept is a
“star” in cause-effect where each axis is a possible past (in blue) and future (in green) state of the complex, and the position along the axis is
the probability of that state (middle). The position of each star in cause-effect space specifies how the corresponding concept changes the
“form” of the quale and thus how it contributes to experience as a phenomenal distinction (quale—q). The size of the star measures how irre-
ducible the concept is and thus how much it contributes to experience. The overall “form” of the conceptual structure or quale sensu lato (Q)
(constellation of stars) is identical to the quality of the experience, how the experience feels. The intrinsic irreducibility of the entire conceptual
structure measures how much consciousness there is—the quantity of experience. Different shapes of qualia correspond to different experi-
ences. Source: Taken from Tononi (2015).

(and you typically do not), you actually gained access to Based on these and other considerations, the theory p0805
a large amount of information. This point is so simple claims that the neural substrate of consciousness is a set
that its importance has been overlooked. It is just as of elements, called “complex,” that specifies an “intrin-
essential to realize that the information associated with sic, maximally irreducible cause-effect structure of a
the occurrence of a conscious state is integrated informa- specific form,” called “conceptual structure” (Tononi,
tion. When you have a particular experience, that expe- 2012, 2015; Oizumi et al., 2014). That is, substrate of
rience is an integrated whole—it cannot be subdivided consciousness must be a set of elements whose present
into components that are experienced independently. state (say, some neurons firing, some not) makes the
For example, the conscious experience of the particular most difference to itself, rather than to an external
phrase you are reading now cannot be experienced observer (intrinsic cause-effect power). The form of the
as subdivided into, say, the conscious experience of conceptual structure in cause-effect space—the possible
how the words look independently of the conscious past states (causes) and future states (effects) of the
experience of how they sound in your mind. Similarly, complex as specified by its subsets in their present
you cannot experience visual shapes independently of state—specifies the quality or content of an experience
their color, or perceive the left half of the visual field of (informativeness)—what the experience is like. The
view independently of the right half. irreducibility of the conceptual structure (integration),

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


A THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVE 437
measured by integrated information (Φ) specifies the allows these parts to interact profusely. And indeed, as
quantity or level of consciousness. The set of elements we have seen, the corticothalamic system is precisely
constituting the complex (the neural substrate of the part of the brain that cannot be severely impaired
consciousness), their spatial grain (neurons or groups) without loss of consciousness.
and the relevant temporal intervals are the ones at Conversely, Φ is low for systems that are made up p0820
which Φ reaches a maximum (ΦMax). of small, quasi-independent modules. This may be
p0810 Some properties of complexes are worth pointing why the cerebellum, despite its large number of neu-
out. A given physical system, such as a brain, is likely rons, does not contribute much to consciousness: its
to contain more than one complex, many small ones synaptic organization is such that individual patches
with low Φ values, and perhaps a few larger ones. of cerebellar cortex tend to be activated independently
Some of the “minor” complexes may mediate behaviors of one another, with little interaction between distant
that are usually considered to be unconscious (e.g., patches (Cohen and Yarom, 1998; Bower, 2002).
Mudrik and Koch, 2013), although behavior mediated Computer simulations also show that units along p0825
by purely feedforward circuits would be strictly uncon- multiple, segregated incoming or outgoing pathways
scious. On the other hand, it is likely that the neural are not incorporated within the repertoire of the main
substrate of our everyday consciousness is a “major” complex. This may be why neural activity in afferent
complex of very high Φ. As discussed earlier, it is still pathways (perhaps as far as V1), though crucial for
unclear where in the brain this major complex may be triggering this or that conscious experience, does not
located, although areas of posterior cortex, extending contribute directly to conscious experience; nor does
around the temporo-parieto-occipital junction, are most activity in efferent pathways (perhaps starting with
likely involved. It is also unclear whether the borders of primary motor cortex), though it is crucial for report-
this major complex may change much during wakeful- ing each different experience.
ness. Whatever the final answer, according to IIT the The addition of many parallel cycles also generally p0830
major complex must correspond to a maximum of does not change the composition of the main complex,
intrinsic cause-effect power. Moreover, neural elements although Φ values can be altered. Instead, cortical and
that are part of the major complex must contribute to its subcortical cycles or loops implement specialized
conscious experience, while elements that are not part subroutines that are capable of influencing the states
of it do not, even though they may be connected to it of the main corticothalamic complex without joining it.
and exchange signals with it through ports-in Such informationally insulated cortico-subcortical
and ports-out (Tononi, 2015). Also, this major should loops could constitute the neural substrates for many
support consciousness whether or not we are function- unconscious processes that can affect and be affected
ally connected to the environment or dreaming. Finally, by conscious experience (Baars, 1988; Tononi, 2004a,b),
the major complex may shrink (say with absolute such as those that enable object recognition, language
achromatopsia), move (say when having experiences of parsing, or translating our vague intentions into the
pure thought during certain stages of sleep), split right words. At this stage, however, it is hard to say
anatomically (as in split brain patients) and perhaps precisely which cortical circuits may be information-
functionally (perhaps in certain dual-task conditions ally insulated. Are primary sensory cortices organized
and in some psychiatric disorders). like massive afferent pathways to a main complex
“higher up” in the cortical hierarchy? Is much of pre-
frontal cortex, and the parallel loops originating there
s0175 Accounting for Neurobiological Observations and going through basal ganglia and thalamic nuclei,
p0815 Measuring Φ and finding complexes is not easy for organized like a massive efferent pathway? Do certain
realistic systems, but it can be done for simple cortical areas, such as those belonging to the dorsal
networks that bear some structural resemblance to visual stream, remain partly segregated from the main
different parts of the brain (Tononi, 2004a,b, 2005). For complex? Do interactions within a corticothalamic
example, by using computer simulations, it is possible minicolumn qualify as intrinsic mini-loops that
to show that high Φ requires networks that conjoin support the main complex without being part of it?
functional specialization (due to its specialized connec- Unfortunately, answering these questions and properly
tivity, each element has a unique functional role within testing the predictions of the theory requires a much
the network) with functional integration (there are better understanding of cortical neuroanatomy than is
many pathways for interactions among the elements.). presently available.
In very rough terms, this kind of architecture is charac- Other simulations show that the effects of cortical dis- p0835
teristic of the mammalian corticothalamic system: connections are readily captured in terms of integrated
different parts of the cerebral cortex are specialized for information (Tononi, 2004a,b): a “callosal” cut produces,
different functions, yet a vast network of connections out of large complex corresponding to the connected

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


438 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

thalamocortical system, two separate complexes, in line structure and appropriate physiological parameters: it
with many studies of split-brain patients (Gazzaniga, also needs time (Bachmann, 2000). The theory predicts
1995). However, because there is great redundancy that the time requirement for the generation of
between the two hemispheres, their Φ value is not conscious experience in the brain emerge directly from
greatly reduced compared to when they formed a single the time requirements for the build-up of an integrated
complex. Functional disconnections may also lead to a repertoire among the elements of the corticothalamic
restriction of the neural substrate of consciousness, as is major complex (Tononi, 2004a,b; Balduzzi and Tononi,
seen in neurological neglect phenomena, in psychiatric 2008). To give an obvious example, if one has to perturb
conversion and dissociative disorders, and possibly dur- half of the elements of the main complex for less than a
ing dreaming and hypnosis. It is also likely that certain millisecond, no perturbations would produce any effect
attentional phenomena may correspond to changes in on the other half within this time window, and the
the composition of the main complex underlying con- repertoire measured by Φ would be equal to zero. After
sciousness. Phenomena such as the attentional blink, say 100 ms, however, there is enough time for differen-
where a fixed sensory input may at times make it to con- tial effects to be manifested, and Φ should grow.
sciousness and at times not, may also be due to changes
in functional connectivity: access to the main corticotha-
lamic complex may be enabled or not based on dynam-
ics intrinsic to the complex (Dehaene et al., 2003).
Some Implications s0180

Phenomena such as binocular rivalry may also be Naturally, IIT converges with other neurobiological p0850
related, at least in part, to dynamic changes in the com- frameworks (e.g., Edelman, 1989; Crick and Koch, 2003;
position of the main corticothalamic complex caused by Dehaene et al., 2006) and cognitive theories (Baars, 1988)
transient changes in functional connectivity (Lumer, on certain key facts: that our own consciousness is gen-
1998). Computer simulations confirm that functional dis- erated by distributed corticothalamic networks, that
connection can reduce the size of a complex and reduce reentrant interactions among multiple cortical regions
its capacity to integrate information (Tononi, 2004a,b). are important, that the mechanisms of consciousness
While it is not easy to determine, at present, whether a and attention overlap but are not the same, and
particular group of neurons is excluded from the main that there are many “unconscious” neural systems.
complex because of hard-wired anatomical constraints, Importantly, however, the examples discussed above
or is transiently disconnected due to functional changes, show that IIT can begin to account, in a coherent man-
the set of elements underlying consciousness is not ner, for several puzzling facts about consciousness and
static, but form a “dynamic complex” or “dynamic core” the brain. This goes beyond proposing a provisional list
(Tononi and Edelman, 1998). of candidate brain areas for the neural substrate of con-
p0840 From the perspective of integrated information, a sciousness, and of seemingly important neural ingredi-
reduction of consciousness during early sleep would be ents, such as synchronization, sustained or phasic firing,
consistent with the ensuing bistability of cortical reentrant activity, or widespread “broadcasting,” with-
circuits. As we have seen, studies using TMS in con- out a principled explanation of why they would be
junction with high-density EEG show that early NREM important or whether they would be always necessary.
sleep is associated either with a breakdown of the effec- Starting from first principles—consciousness is a
tive connectivity among cortical areas, and thereby maximum of irreducible intrinsic cause-effect power,
with a loss of integration, or with a stereotypical global IIT can actually explain why: because no purely feed-
response suggestive of a loss of repertoire and thus of forward system has intrinsic cause-effect power.
information (Massimini et al., 2007). As we have also Synchronization may signify that elements of the PSC
seen, similar changes are seen in animal studies of are interacting efficiently, but it is neither necessary nor
anesthesia (Imas et al., 2005; Hudetz and Imas, 2007; sufficient for consciousness, as there can be strong
Kroeger and Amzica, 2007). Computer simulations also synchronization with little consciousness and conscious-
indicate that the capacity to integrate information is ness with little synchronization.
also reduced if neural activity is extremely high and IIT also avoids the pitfalls associated with assigning p0855
near-synchronous, due to a dramatic decrease in the conscious qualities to individual brain elements. For
available degrees of freedom (Balduzzi and Tononi, example, it is sometimes assumed loosely that the
2008). This reduction in degrees of freedom could be firing of specific corticothalamic elements (e.g., those
the reason why consciousness is reduced or eliminated for red) conveys some specific information (e.g., that
in absence seizure and other conditions characterized there is something red), and that such information
by hypersynchronous neural activity. becomes conscious either as such, or perhaps if it is
p0845 Finally, we have seen that consciousness not only disseminated widely. However, a given corticothala-
requires a neural substrate with appropriate anatomical mic element has no information about whether what

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 439
made it fire was a particular color rather than a shape, References
a visual stimulus rather than a sound, a sensory stimu-
Abeles, M., 1991. Corticonics: Neural Circuits of the Cerebral Cortex.
lus rather than a thought. All it knows is whether Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York.
it fired or not, just as each receiving element only Alkire, M.T., Miller, J., 2005. General anesthesia and the neural
knows whether it received an input or not. Thus, the correlates of consciousness. Prog. Brain Res. 150, 229!244.
information specifying “red” cannot possibly be in Alkire, M.T., Haier, R.J., Fallon, J.H., 2000. Toward a unified theory
of narcosis: brain imaging evidence for a thalamocortical switch
the message conveyed by the firing of any neural
as the neurophysiologic basis of anesthetic-induced unconscious-
element, whether it is located in a high-order cortical ness. Conscious. Cogn. 9 (3), 370!386.
area, or whether it is broadcasting widely. According Alkire, M.T., McReynolds, J.R., Hahn, E.L., Trivedi, A.N., 2007.
to the theory, that information resides instead in form Thalamic microinjection of nicotine reverses sevoflurane-induced
of the conceptual structure specified by the major com- loss of righting reflex in the rat. Anesthesiology. 107 (2), 264!272.
Alkire, M.T., Hudetz, A.G., Tononi, G., 2008. Consciousness and
plex in the brain—the complex, and not its elements, is
anesthesia. Science. 322 (5903), 876!880.
the locus of consciousness. Indeed, within a complex, Allen, E.A., Damaraju, E., Plis, S.M., Erhardt, E.B., Eichele, T.,
both active and inactive neurons count, just as the Calhoun, V.D., 2014. Tracking whole-brain connectivity dynamics
sound of an orchestra is specified both by the instru- in the resting state. Cereb. Cortex. 24 (3), 663!676.
ments that are playing and by those that are silent. Amedi, A., Malach, R., Pascual-Leone, A., 2005. Negative BOLD
differentiates visual imagery and perception. Neuron. 48 (5),
p0860 IIT also predicts that consciousness depends exclu-
859!872.
sively on the ability of a system to integrate informa- Andersen, R.A., Andersen, K.N., Hwang, E.J., Hauschild, M., 2014.
tion, whether or not it has a strong sense of self, Optic ataxia: from Balint’s syndrome to the parietal reach region.
language, emotion, or is immersed in an environ- Neuron. 81 (5), 967!983.
ment, contrary to some common intuitions, but Andrade, J., Sapsford, D.J., Jeevaratnum, D., Pickworth, A.J., Jones, J.
G., 1996. The coherent frequency in the electroencephalogram as
consistent, as reviewed in this overview, with the
an objective measure of cognitive function during propofol seda-
overall neurological evidence. Of course, the theory tion. Anesth. Analg. 83 (6), 1279!1284.
recognizes that these same factors are important Arezzo, J.C., Vaughan Jr., H.G., Legatt, A.D., 1981. Topography and
historically because they favor the development of intracranial sources of somatosensory evoked potentials in the
neural circuits forming a main complex of high Φ. monkey. II. Cortical components. Electroencephalogr. Clin.
Neurophysiol. 51 (1), 1!18.
For example, integrated information grows as that
Arthuis, M., Valton, L., Regis, J., Chauvel, P., Wendling, F.,
system incorporates statistical regularities from its Naccache, L., et al., 2009. Impaired consciousness during tempo-
environment and learns (Tononi et al., 1996). In this ral lobe seizures is related to increased long-distance cortical-sub-
sense, the emergence of consciousness in biological cortical synchronization. Brain. 132 (Pt 8), 2091!2101.
systems is predicated on a long evolutionary history, Aru, J., Axmacher, N., Do Lam, A.T., Fell, J., Elger, C.E., Singer, W.,
et al., 2012a. Local category-specific gamma band responses in
on individual development, and on experience-
the visual cortex do not reflect conscious perception. J. Neurosci.
dependent change in neural connectivity. 32 (43), 14909!14914.
p0865 Finally, IIT says that the presence and extent of Aru, J., Bachmann, T., Singer, W., Melloni, L., 2012b. Distilling the
consciousness can be determined, in principle, also in neural correlates of consciousness. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 36
cases in which we have no verbal report, such as (2), 737!746.
Arzy, S., Overney, L.S., Landis, T., Blanke, O., 2006a. Neural mechan-
infants or animals, or in neurological conditions such
isms of embodiment: asomatognosia due to premotor cortex
as minimally conscious states, akinetic mutism, damage. Arch. Neurol. 63 (7), 1022!1025.
psychomotor seizures, and sleepwalking. In practice, Arzy, S., Thut, G., Mohr, C., Michel, C.M., Blanke, O., 2006b. Neural
of course, measuring Φ accurately in such systems will basis of embodiment: distinct contributions of temporoparietal
not be easy, but approximations and informed guesses junction and extrastriate body area. J. Neurosci. 26 (31),
8074!8081.
are certainly conceivable. The theory also implies that
Aserinsky, E., Kleitman, N., 1953. Regularly occurring periods of eye
consciousness is not an all-or-none property, but is motility, and concomitant phenomena, during sleep. Science. 118
graded: specifically, it increases in proportion to a (3062), 273!274.
system’s repertoire of available states. In fact, any Auksztulewicz, R., Spitzer, B., Blankenburg, F., 2012. Recurrent neu-
physical system with some capacity for integrated ral processing and somatosensory awareness. J. Neurosci. 32 (3),
799!805.
information would have some degree of experience,
Baars, B.J., 1988. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge
irrespective of the constituents of which it is made, University Press, New York.
and independent of its ability to report. Baars, B.J., 1997. Some essential differences between consciousness
p0870 Whether these and other predictions turn out to be and attention, perception, and working memory. Conscious.
compatible with future clinical and experimental evi- Cogn. 6 (2!3), 363!371.
Bachmann, T., 2000. Microgenetic Approach to the Conscious Mind.
dence, a coherent theoretical framework should at
John Benjamins Pub. Co, Amsterdam; PA.
least help to systematize a number of neuropsycho- Bacon-Mace, N., Mace, M.J., Fabre-Thorpe, M., Thorpe, S.J., 2005. The
logical and neurobiological results that might other- time course of visual processing: backward masking and natural
wise seem disparate. scene categorisation. Vision Res. 45 (11), 1459!1469.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


440 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

Bagattini, C., Mazzi, C., Savazzi, S., 2015. Waves of awareness for Blumenfeld, H., Taylor, J., 2003. Why do seizures cause loss of con-
occipital and parietal phosphenes perception. Neuropsychologia. sciousness? Neuroscientist. 9 (5), 301!310.
70C, 114!125. Blumenfeld, H., Westerveld, M., Ostroff, R.B., Vanderhill, S.D.,
Bahrami, B., Lavie, N., Rees, G., 2007. Attentional load modulates Freeman, J., Necochea, A., et al., 2003. Selective frontal, parietal,
responses of human primary visual cortex to invisible stimuli. and temporal networks in generalized seizures. Neuroimage. 19
Curr. Biol. 17 (6), 509!513. (4), 1556!1566.
Baier, B., Geber, C., Muller-Forell, W., Muller, N., Dieterich, M., Blumenfeld, H., McNally, K.A., Vanderhill, S.D., Paige, A.L., Chung,
Karnath, H.O., 2015. Anosognosia for obvious visual field defects R., Davis, K., et al., 2004. Positive and negative network
in stroke patients. Brain Struct. Funct. 220 (3), 1855!1860. correlations in temporal lobe epilepsy. Cereb. Cortex. 14 (8),
Baker, R., Gent, T.C., Yang, Q., Parker, S., Vyssotski, A.L., Wisden, 892!902.
W., et al., 2014. Altered activity in the central medial thalamus Blumenfeld, H., Varghese, G.I., Purcaro, M.J., Motelow, J.E., Enev,
precedes changes in the neocortex during transitions into both M., McNally, K.A., et al., 2009. Cortical and subcortical networks
sleep and propofol anesthesia. J. Neurosci. 34 (40), 13326!13335. in human secondarily generalized tonic-clonic seizures. Brain. 132
Baldassarre, A., Ramsey, L., Hacker, C.L., Callejas, A., Astafiev, S.V., (Pt 4), 999!1012.
Metcalf, N.V., et al., 2014. Large-scale changes in network interac- Bogen, J.E., 1997. Some neurophysiologic aspects of consciousness.
tions as a physiological signature of spatial neglect. Brain. 137 Semin. Neurol. 17 (2), 95!103.
(Pt 12), 3267!3283. Boly, M., Faymonville, M.E., Peigneux, P., Lambermont, B., Damas, P.,
Balduzzi, D., Tononi, G., 2008. Integrated information in discrete Del Fiore, G., et al., 2004. Auditory processing in severely brain
dynamical systems: motivation and theoretical framework. PLoS injured patients: differences between the minimally conscious state
Comput. Biol. 4 (6), e1000091. and the persistent vegetative state. Arch. Neurol. 61 (2), 233!238.
Barcelo, F., Suwazono, S., Knight, R.T., 2000. Prefrontal modulation Boly, M., Balteau, E., Schnakers, C., Degueldre, C., Moonen, G.,
of visual processing in humans. Nat. Neurosci. 3 (4), 399!403. Luxen, A., et al., 2007. Baseline brain activity fluctuations predict
Bardin, J.C., Fins, J.J., Katz, D.I., Hersh, J., Heier, L.A., Tabelow, K., somatosensory perception in humans. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA.
et al., 2011. Dissociations between behavioural and functional 104 (29), 12187!12192.
magnetic resonance imaging-based evaluations of cognitive func- Boly, M., Faymonville, M.E., Schnakers, C., Peigneux, P.,
tion after brain injury. Brain. 134 (Pt 3), 769!782. Lambermont, B., Phillips, C., et al., 2008. Perception of pain in the
Barense, M.D., Gaffan, D., Graham, K.S., 2007. The human medial minimally conscious state with PET activation: an observational
temporal lobe processes online representations of complex study. Lancet Neurol. 7 (11), 1013!1020.
objects. Neuropsychologia. 45 (13), 2963!2974. Boly, M., Massimini, M., Tononi, G., 2009. Theoretical approaches to
Bartolomeo, P., 2002. The relationship between visual perception and the diagnosis of altered states of consciousness. Prog. Brain Res.
visual mental imagery: a reappraisal of the neuropsychological 177, 383!398.
evidence. Cortex. 38 (3), 357!378. Boly, M., Garrido, M.I., Gosseries, O., Bruno, M.-A., Boveroux, P.,
Bartolomeo, P., Bachoud-Levi, A.C., Denes, G., 1997. Preserved imag- Schnakers, C., et al., 2011. Preserved feedforward but impaired
ery for colours in a patient with cerebral achromatopsia. Cortex. top-down processes in the vegetative state. Science. 332 (6031),
33 (2), 369!378. 858!862.
Bartsch, T., Deuschl, G., 2010. Transient global amnesia: functional Boly, M., Moran, R., Murphy, M., Boveroux, P., Bruno, M.A.,
anatomy and clinical implications. Lancet Neurol. 9 (2), 205!214. Noirhomme, Q., et al., 2012a. Connectivity changes underlying
Barttfeld, P., Uhrig, L., Sitt, J.D., Sigman, M., Jarraya, B., Dehaene, S., spectral EEG changes during propofol-induced loss of conscious-
2015. Signature of consciousness in the dynamics of resting-state ness. J. Neurosci. 32 (20), 7082!7090.
brain activity. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 112 (3), 887!892. Boly, M., Perlbarg, V., Marrelec, G., Schabus, M., Laureys, S., Doyon, J.,
Bassetti, C., Vella, S., Donati, F., Wielepp, P., Weder, B., 2000. SPECT et al., 2012b. Hierarchical clustering of brain activity during human
during sleepwalking. Lancet. 356 (9228), 484!485. nonrapid eye movement sleep. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 109 (15),
Bauby, J.-D., 1997. The Diving-Bell and the Butterfly: A Memoir of 5856!5861.
Life in Death. Alfred A. Knopf, New York. Boveroux, P., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Bruno, M.A., Noirhomme, Q.,
Baumann, O., Borra, R.J., Bower, J.M., Cullen, K.E., Habas, C., Ivry, Lauwick, S., Luxen, A., et al., 2010. Breakdown of within- and
R.B., et al., 2015. Consensus paper: the role of the cerebellum in between-network resting state functional magnetic resonance
perceptual processes. Cerebellum. 14 (2), 197!220. imaging connectivity during propofol-induced loss of conscious-
Berti, A., Bottini, G., Gandola, M., Pia, L., Smania, N., Stracciari, A., ness. Anesthesiology. 113 (5), 1038!1053.
et al., 2005. Shared cortical anatomy for motor awareness and Bower, J.M., 2002. The organization of cerebellar cortical circuitry
motor control. Science. 309 (5733), 488!491. revisited: implications for function. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 978,
Binzegger, T., Douglas, R.J., Martin, K.A., 2009. Topology and 135!155.
dynamics of the canonical circuit of cat V1. Neural Netw. 22 (8), Boyd, C.A., 2010. Cerebellar agenesis revisited. Brain. 133 (Pt 3),
1071!1078. 941!944.
Bisiach, E., Luzzatti, C., 1978. Unilateral neglect of representational Boyer, J.L., Harrison, S., Ro, T., 2005. Unconscious processing of ori-
space. Cortex. 14 (1), 129!133. entation and color without primary visual cortex. Proc. Natl.
Blake, R., Logothetis, N.K., 2002. Visual competition. Nat. Rev. Acad. Sci. USA. 102 (46), 16875!16879.
Neurosci. 3 (1), 13!21. Bradley, P.B., 1968. The effect of atropine and related drugs on the
Blanke, O., Mohr, C., Michel, C.M., Pascual-Leone, A., Brugger, P., EEG and behaviour. Prog. Brain Res. 28, 3!13.
Seeck, M., et al., 2005. Linking out-of-body experience and self Braun, A.R., Balkin, T.J., Wesenten, N.J., Carson, R.E., Varga, M.,
processing to mental own-body imagery at the temporoparietal Baldwin, P., et al., 1997. Regional cerebral blood flow throughout
junction. J. Neurosci. 25 (3), 550!557. the sleep-wake cycle. An H2(15)O PET study. Brain. 120 (Pt 7),
Block, N., 2005. Two neural correlates of consciousness. Trends 1173!1197 (1!2).
Cogn. Sci. 9 (2), 46!52. Brecht, M., Singer, W., Engel, A.K., 1999. Patterns of synchronization
Blumenfeld, H., 2005. Consciousness and epilepsy: Why are patients in the superior colliculus of anesthetized cats. J. Neurosci. 19 (9),
with absence seizures absent? Prog. Brain Res. 150, 271!286. 3567!3579.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 441
Brefel-Courbon, C., Payoux, P., Ory, F., Sommet, A., Slaoui, T., Cavanna, A.E., Trimble, M.R., 2006. The precuneus: a review of its
Raboyeau, G., et al., 2007. Clinical and imaging evidence of functional anatomy and behavioural correlates. Brain. 129 (Pt 3),
zolpidem effect in hypoxic encephalopathy. Ann. Neurol. 62 (1), 564!583.
102!105. Celesia, G.G., Brigell, M.G., Vaphiades, M.S., 1997. Hemianopic ano-
Brickner, R., 1952. Brain of patient A. after bilateral frontal lobec- sognosia. Neurology. 49 (1), 88!97.
tomy; status of frontal-lobe problem. AMA Arch. Neurol. Chatelle, C., Thibaut, A., Gosseries, O., Thonnard, M., Bernard, C.,
Psychiatry. 68 (3), 293!313. Hustinx, R., et al., 2014. Zolpidem effect on recovery of conscious-
Brown, E.N., Lydic, R., Schiff, N.D., 2010. General anesthesia, sleep, ness: a FDG-PET study. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8, 917.
and coma. N. Engl. J. Med. 363 (27), 2638!2650. Chellappa, S.L., Frey, S., Knoblauch, V., Cajochen, C., 2011. Cortical
Brunet, N., Vinck, M., Bosman, C.A., Singer, W., Fries, P., 2014. activation patterns herald successful dream recall after NREM
Gamma or no gamma, that is the question. Trends Cogn. Sci. 18 and REM sleep. Biol. Psychol. 87 (2), 251!256.
(10), 507!509. Chen, W., Hobbs, J.P., Tang, A., Beggs, J.M., 2010. A few strong con-
Bruno, M.A., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Thibaut, A., Moonen, G., nections: optimizing information retention in neuronal ava-
Laureys, S., 2011. From unresponsive wakefulness to minimally lanches. BMC Neurosci. 11, 3.
conscious PLUS and functional locked-in syndromes: recent Chun, M.M., Wolfe, J.M., 2000. Visual attention. In: Goldstein, E.B.
advances in our understanding of disorders of consciousness. (Ed.), Blackwell’s Handbook of Perception. Blackwell, Oxford,
J. Neurol. 258 (7), 1373!1384. pp. 272!310.
Bruno, M.A., Majerus, S., Boly, M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Schnakers, Clauss, R., Nel, W., 2006. Drug induced arousal from the permanent
C., Gosseries, O., et al., 2012. Functional neuroanatomy underly- vegetative state. NeuroRehabilitation. 21 (1), 23!28.
ing the clinical subcategorization of minimally conscious state Clauss, R.P., van der Merwe, C.E., Nel, H.W., 2001. Arousal from a
patients. J. Neurol. 259 (6), 1087!1098. semi-comatose state on zolpidem. S. Afr. Med. J. 91 (10), 788!789.
Buchel, C., Price, C., Frackowiak, R.S., Friston, K., 1998. Different Cohen, D., Yarom, Y., 1998. Patches of synchronized activity in the
activation patterns in the visual cortex of late and congenitally cerebellar cortex evoked by mossy-fiber stimulation: questioning
blind subjects. Brain. 121 (Pt 3), 409!419. the role of parallel fibers. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 95 (25),
Buckner, R.L., 2013. The cerebellum and cognitive function: 25 years of 15032!15036.
insight from anatomy and neuroimaging. Neuron. 80 (3), 807!815. Cohen, M.A., Dennett, D.C., 2011. Consciousness cannot be separated
Buffalo, E.A., Fries, P., Landman, R., Buschman, T.J., Desimone, R., from function. Trends Cogn. Sci. 15 (8), 358!364.
2011. Laminar differences in gamma and alpha coherence in the Cohen, M.A., Cavanagh, P., Chun, M.M., Nakayama, K., 2012. The
ventral stream. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 108 (27), 11262!11267. attentional requirements of consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 16
Bullmore, E., Sporns, O., 2009. Complex brain networks: graph (8), 411!417.
theoretical analysis of structural and functional systems. Nat. Cohen, Y.E., Andersen, R.A., 2002. A common reference frame for
Rev. Neurosci. 10 (3), 186!198. movement plans in the posterior parietal cortex. Nat. Rev.
Buzsaki, G., Bickford, R.G., Ponomareff, G., Thal, L.J., Mandel, R., Neurosci. 3 (7), 553!562.
Gage, F.H., 1988. Nucleus basalis and thalamic control of neocor- Coleman, M.R., Davis, M.H., Rodd, J.M., Robson, T., Ali, A., Owen,
tical activity in the freely moving rat. J. Neurosci. 8 (11), A.M., et al., 2009. Towards the routine use of brain imaging to
4007!4026. aid the clinical diagnosis of disorders of consciousness. Brain. 132
Buzsaki, G., Geisler, C., Henze, D.A., Wang, X.J., 2004. Interneuron (9), 2541!2552.
diversity series: circuit complexity and axon wiring economy of Corbetta, M., 2014. Hemispatial neglect: clinic, pathogenesis, and
cortical interneurons. Trends Neurosci. 27 (4), 186!193. treatment. Semin. Neurol. 34 (5), 514!523.
Cairns, H., Oldfield, R.C., Pennybacker, J.B., Whitteridge, D., 1941. Corbetta, M., Shulman, G.L., 2011. Spatial neglect and attention net-
Akinetic mutism with an epidermoid cyst of the 3rd ventricle. works. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 34, 569!599.
Brain. 64 (4), 273!290. Corbetta, M., Kincade, J.M., Ollinger, J.M., McAvoy, M.P., Shulman,
Campagna, J.A., Miller, K.W., Forman, S.A., 2003. Mechanisms of G.L., 2000. Voluntary orienting is dissociated from target
actions of inhaled anesthetics. N. Engl. J. Med. 348 (21), detection in human posterior parietal cortex. Nat. Neurosci. 3 (3),
2110!2124. 292!297.
Campana, F., Tallon-Baudry, C., 2013. Anchoring visual subjective Corbetta, M., Kincade, M.J., Lewis, C., Snyder, A.Z., Sapir, A., 2005.
experience in a neural model: the coarse vividness hypothesis. Neural basis and recovery of spatial attention deficits in spatial
Neuropsychologia. 51 (6), 1050!1060. neglect. Nat. Neurosci. 8 (11), 1603!1610.
Caparros-Lefebvre, D., Destee, A., Petit, H., 1997. Late onset familial Corkin, S., 2013. Permanent present tense. The Unforgettable Life of
dystonia: could mitochondrial deficits induce a diffuse lesioning the Amnesic Patient, H.M. Books. Basic Books, New York.
process of the whole basal ganglia system? J. Neurol. Neurosurg. Craver, R.D., Duncan, M.C., Nelson, J.S., 1996. Familial dystonia and
Psychiatry. 63 (2), 196!203. choreoathetosis in three generations associated with bilateral
Casali, A.G., Gosseries, O., Rosanova, M., Boly, M., Sarasso, S., striatal necrosis. J. Child. Neurol. 11 (3), 185!188.
Casali, K.R., et al., 2013. A theoretically based index of conscious- Crick, F., Koch, C., 1990. Some reflections on visual awareness. Cold
ness independent of sensory processing and behavior. Sci. Transl. Spring Harb. Symp. Quant. Biol. 55, 953!962.
Med. 5 (198), 198ra105. Crick, F., Koch, C., 1995. Are we aware of neural activity in primary
Cauller, L.J., Kulics, A.T., 1988. A comparison of awake and sleeping visual cortex? Nature. 375 (6527), 121!123.
cortical states by analysis of the somatosensory-evoked response Crick, F., Koch, C., 2003. A framework for consciousness. Nat.
of postcentral area 1 in rhesus monkey. Exp. Brain Res. 72 (3), Neurosci. 6 (2), 119!126.
584!592. Cruse, D., Chennu, S., Chatelle, C., Bekinschtein, T.A., Fernandez-
Cauller, L.J., Kulics, A.T., 1991. The neural basis of the behaviorally Espejo, D., Pickard, J.D., et al., 2011. Bedside detection of aware-
relevant N1 component of the somatosensory-evoked potential in ness in the vegetative state: a cohort study. Lancet. 378 (9809),
SI cortex of awake monkeys: evidence that backward cortical pro- 2088!2094.
jections signal conscious touch sensation. Exp. Brain Res. 84 (3), Cruse, D., Thibaut, A., Demertzi, A., Nantes, J.C., Bruno, M.A.,
607!619. Gosseries, O., et al., 2013. Actigraphy assessments of circadian

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


442 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

sleep-wake cycles in the vegetative and minimally conscious Douglas, R.J., Martin, K.A., 2004. Neuronal circuits of the neocortex.
states. BMC Med. 11, 18. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 27, 419!451.
Cunningham, C., Chen, W.C., Shorten, A., McClurkin, M., Downing, P.E., Jiang, Y., Shuman, M., Kanwisher, N., 2001. A cortical
Choezom, T., Schmidt, C.P., et al., 2014. Impaired consciousness area selective for visual processing of the human body. Science.
in partial seizures is bimodally distributed. Neurology. 82 (19), 293 (5539), 2470!2473.
1736!1744. Dresler, M., Wehrle, R., Spoormaker, V.I., Koch, S.P., Holsboer, F.,
Dalrymple, K.A., Barton, J.J., Kingstone, A., 2013. A world unglued: Steiger, A., et al., 2012. Neural correlates of dream lucidity
simultanagnosia as a spatial restriction of attention. Front. Hum. obtained from contrasting lucid versus non-lucid REM sleep: a
Neurosci. 7, 145. combined EEG/fMRI case study. Sleep. 35 (7), 1017!1020.
Damasio, A., Meyer, K., 2009. Consciousness: an overview of the phe- Dringenberg, H.C., Olmstead, M.C., 2003. Integrated contributions of
nomenon and of its possible neural basis. In: Laureys, S., Tononi, G. basal forebrain and thalamus to neocortical activation elicited by
(Eds.), The Neurology of Consciousness: Cogntive Neuroscience pedunculopontine tegmental stimulation in urethane-
and Neuropathology. Academic Press, Oxford, pp. 3!14. anesthetized rats. Neuroscience. 119 (3), 839!853.
Damasio, A.R., 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion Edelman, G.M., 1989. The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory
in the Making of Consciousness. Harcourt Brace, New York. of Consciousness. BasicBooks, Inc, New York.
David, N., Bewernick, B.H., Cohen, M.X., Newen, A., Lux, S., Fink, Edelman, G.M., Mountcastle, V.B., 1978. The Mindful Brain: Cortical
G.R., et al., 2006. Neural representations of self versus other: Organization and the Group-Selective Theory of Higher Brain
visual-spatial perspective taking and agency in a virtual ball- Function. MIT Press, Cambridge.
tossing game. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 18 (6), 898!910. Engel, A.K., Fries, P., Singer, W., 2001. Dynamic predictions: oscilla-
De Brigard, F., Prinz, J., 2010. Attention and consciousness. Wiley tions and synchrony in top-down processing. Nat. Rev. Neurosci.
Interdiscip. Rev. Cogn. Sci. 1, 51!59. 2 (10), 704!716.
de Graaf, T.A., Hsieh, P.-J., Sack, A.T., 2012. The ‘correlates’ in neural Englot, D.J., Yang, L., Hamid, H., Danielson, N., Bai, X., Marfeo, A.,
correlates of consciousness. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 36 (1), 191!197. et al., 2010. Impaired consciousness in temporal lobe seizures:
De Ridder, D., Van Laere, K., Dupont, P., Menovsky, T., Van de role of cortical slow activity. Brain. 133 (Pt 12), 3764!3777.
Heyning, P., 2007. Visualizing out-of-body experience in the Esser, S.K., Hill, S., Tononi, G., 2009. Breakdown of effective connec-
brain. N. Engl. J. Med. 357 (18), 1829!1833. tivity during slow wave sleep: investigating the mechanism
De Vreese, L.P., 1991. Two systems for colour-naming defects: verbal underlying a cortical gate using large-scale modeling.
disconnection vs colour imagery disorder. Neuropsychologia. 29 J. Neurophysiol. 102 (4), 2096!2111.
(1), 1!18. Farrer, C., Franck, N., Georgieff, N., Frith, C.D., Decety, J., Jeannerod,
Debaere, F., Wenderoth, N., Sunaert, S., Van Hecke, P., Swinnen, S.P., M., 2003. Modulating the experience of agency: a positron emis-
2004. Changes in brain activation during the acquisition of a sion tomography study. Neuroimage. 18 (2), 324!333.
new bimanual coodination task. Neuropsychologia. 42 (7), 855!867. Faugeras, F., Rohaut, B., Weiss, N., Bekinschtein, T.A., Galanaud, D.,
Deco, G., Rolls, E.T., Romo, R., 2009. Stochastic dynamics as a princi- Puybasset, L., et al., 2011. Probing consciousness with event-
ple of brain function. Prog. Neurobiol. 88 (1), 1!16. related potentials in the vegetative state. Neurology. 77 (3),
Deco, G., Jirsa, V.K., McIntosh, A.R., 2011. Emerging concepts for the 264!268.
dynamical organization of resting-state activity in the brain. Nat. Felleman, D.J., Van Essen, D.C., 1991. Distributed hierarchical proces-
Rev. Neurosci. 12 (1), 43!56. sing in the primate cerebral cortex. Cereb. Cortex. 1 (1), 1!47.
Dehaene, S., Changeux, J.-P., 2011. Experimental and theoretical Ferrarelli, F., Massimini, M., Sarasso, S., Casali, A., Riedner, B.A.,
approaches to conscious processing. Neuron. 70 (2), 200!227. Angelini, G., et al., 2010. Breakdown in cortical effective connec-
Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., 2001. Towards a cognitive neuroscience of tivity during midazolam-induced loss of consciousness. Proc.
consciousness: basic evidence and a workspace framework. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107 (6), 2681!2686.
Cognition. 79 (1!2), 1!37. Filevich, E., Dresler, M., Brick, T.R., Kuhn, S., 2015. Metacognitive
Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., Cohen, L., Bihan, D.L., Mangin, J.F., Poline, J. mechanisms underlying lucid dreaming. J. Neurosci. 35 (3),
B., et al., 2001. Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and uncon- 1082!1088.
scious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci. 4 (7), 752!758. Fingelkurts, A.A., Fingelkurts, A.A., Bagnato, S., Boccagni, C.,
Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., Changeux, J.P., 2003. A neuronal network Galardi, G., 2013. Dissociation of vegetative and minimally con-
model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data scious patients based on brain operational architectonics: factor of
during conscious perception. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 100 (14), etiology. Clin. EEG Neurosci. 44 (3), 209!220.
8520!8525. Fischer, C., Luaute, J., Morlet, D., 2010. Event-related potentials
Dehaene, S., Changeux, J.P., Naccache, L., Sackur, J., Sergent, C., (MMN and novelty P3) in permanent vegetative or minimally
2006. Conscious, preconscious, and subliminal processing: a conscious states. Clin. Neurophysiol. 121 (7), 1032!1042.
testable taxonomy. Trends Cogn. Sci. 10 (5), 204!211. Fisher, C.M., 1983. Honored guest presentation: abulia minor vs. agi-
Del Cul, A., Baillet, S., Dehaene, S., 2007. Brain dynamics underlying tated behavior. Clin. Neurosurg. 31, 9!31.
the nonlinear threshold for access to consciousness. PLoS Biol. 5 Fitzgerald, R.D., Lamm, C., Oczenski, W., Stimpfl, T., Vycudilik, W.,
(10), e260. Bauer, H., 2001. Direct current auditory evoked potentials during
Deluca, C., Golzar, A., Santandrea, E., Lo Gerfo, E., Estocinova, J., wakefulness, anesthesia, and emergence from anesthesia. Anesth.
Moretto, G., et al., 2014. The cerebellum and visual perceptual Analg. 92 (1), 154!160.
learning: evidence from a motion extrapolation task. Cortex. 58, Floyer-Lea, A., Matthews, P.M., 2004. Changing brain networks for
52!71. visuomotor control with increased movement automaticity.
Destexhe, A., Hughes, S.W., Rudolph, M., Crunelli, V., 2007. Are cor- J. Neurophysiol. 92 (4), 2405!2412.
ticothalamic ‘up’ states fragments of wakefulness? Trends Forgacs, P.B., Conte, M.M., Fridman, E.A., Voss, H.U., Victor, J.D.,
Neurosci. 30 (7), 334!342. Schiff, N.D., 2014. Preservation of electroencephalographic orga-
Donner, T.H., Sagi, D., Bonneh, Y.S., Heeger, D.J., 2008. Opposite nization in patients with impaired consciousness and imaging-
neural signatures of motion-induced blindness in human dorsal based evidence of command-following. Ann. Neurol. 76 (6),
and ventral visual cortex. J. Neurosci. 28 (41), 10298!10310. 869!879.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 443
Fox, M.D., Raichle, M.E., 2007. Spontaneous fluctuations in brain Gokyigit, A., Caliskan, A., 1995. Diffuse spike-wave status of 9-year
activity observed with functional magnetic resonance imaging. duration without behavioral change or intellectual decline.
Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 8 (9), 700!711. Epilepsia. 36 (2), 210!213.
Fox, M.D., Snyder, A.Z., Vincent, J.L., Corbetta, M., Van Essen, D.C., Goldberg, I.I., Harel, M., Malach, R., 2006. When the brain loses its
Raichle, M.E., 2005. The human brain is intrinsically organized self: prefrontal inactivation during sensorimotor processing.
into dynamic, anticorrelated functional networks. Proc. Natl. Neuron. 50 (2), 329!339.
Acad. Sci. USA. 102 (27), 9673!9678. Goldenberg, G., 1992. Loss of visual imagery and loss of visual
Fox, M.D., Corbetta, M., Snyder, A.Z., Vincent, J.L., Raichle, M.E., knowledge--a case study. Neuropsychologia. 30 (12), 1081!1099.
2006. Spontaneous neuronal activity distinguishes human dorsal Goodale, M., Milner, A., 2005. Sight Unseen: An Exploration of
and ventral attention systems. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103 Conscious and Unconscious Vision. Oxford University Press,
(26), 10046!10051. Oxford.
Franks, N.P., 2006. Molecular targets underlying general anaesthesia. Goodale, M.A., Milner, A.D., Jakobson, L.S., Carey, D.P., 1991. A
Br. J. Pharmacol. 147 (Suppl. 1), S72!S81. neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping
Franks, N.P., 2008. General anaesthesia: from molecular targets to them. Nature. 349 (6305), 154!156.
neuronal pathways of sleep and arousal. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 9 Gosseries, O., Schnakers, C., Ledoux, D., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Bruno,
(5), 370!386. M.A., Demertzi, A., et al., 2011. Automated EEG entropy measure-
Frässle, S., Sommer, J., Jansen, A., Naber, M., Einhäuser, W., 2014. ments in coma, vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness syn-
Binocular rivalry: frontal activity relates to introspection and drome and minimally conscious state. Funct. Neurol. 26 (1), 25!30.
action but not to perception. J. Neurosci. 34, 1738!1747. Gosseries, O., Sarasso, S., Casarotto, S., Boly, M., Schnakers, C.,
Fries, P., Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., Konig, P., Singer, W., 1997. Napolitani, M., et al., 2015. On the cerebral origin of EEG
Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual cortex corre- responses to TMS: insights from severe cortical lesions. Brain
lates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. Stimul. 8 (1), 142!149.
U.S.A. 94 (23), 12699!12704. Grossberg, S., 1999. The link between brain learning, attention, and
Fries, P., Neuenschwander, S., Engel, A.K., Goebel, R., Singer, W., consciousness. Conscious. Cogn. 8 (1), 1!44.
2001. Rapid feature selective neuronal synchronization through Guilleminault, C., 1976. Cataplexy. In: Guilleminault, C., Dennet, W.,
correlated latency shifting. Nat. Neurosci. 4 (2), 194!200. Passouant, P. (Eds.), Narcolepsy. Spectrum, New York,
Fries, P., Nikolic, D., Singer, W., 2007. The gamma cycle. Trends pp. 125!143.
Neurosci. 30 (7), 309!316. Guillery, R.W., Sherman, S.M., 2002. Thalamic relay functions and
Friston, K.J., 1997. Transients, metastability, and neuronal dynamics. their role in corticocortical communication: generalizations from
Neuroimage. 5 (2), 164!171. the visual system. Neuron. 33 (2), 163!175.
Friston, K.J., 2000. The labile brain. I. Neuronal transients and nonlin- Guillery, R.W., Feig, S.L., Van Lieshout, D.P., 2001. Connections of
ear coupling. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 355 (1394), higher order visual relays in the thalamus: a study of corticotha-
215!236. lamic pathways in cats. J. Comp. Neurol. 438 (1), 66!85.
Frith, C., 2002. Attention to action and awareness of other minds. Habbal, D., Gosseries, O., Noirhomme, Q., Renaux, J., Lesenfants, D.,
Conscious. Cogn. 11 (4), 481!487. Bekinschtein, T.A., et al., 2014. Volitional electromyographic
Fuller, P.M., Sherman, D., Pedersen, N.P., Saper, C.B., Lu, J., 2011. responses in disorders of consciousness. Brain Inj. 28 (9),
Reassessment of the structural basis of the ascending arousal sys- 1171!1179.
tem. J. Comp. Neurol. 519 (5), 933!956. Hagmann, P., Cammoun, L., Gigandet, X., Meuli, R., Honey, C.J.,
Fulton, J.F., 1949. Functional Localization in Relation to Frontal Wedeen, V.J., et al., 2008. Mapping the structural core of human
Lobotomy. Oxford University Press, New York. cerebral cortex. PLoS Biol. 6 (7), e159.
Funk, C., Honjoh, S., Rodriguez, A., Cirelli, C., Tononi, G., 2014. Hannula, D.E., Tranel, D., Cohen, N.J., 2006. The long and the short
Slow wave activity persists in superficial cortical layers during of it: relational memory impairments in amnesia, even at short
REM sleep. Sleep. 37 (Abstract Supplement), 0079. lags. J. Neurosci. 26 (32), 8352!8359.
Gazzaniga, M.S., 1995. Principles of human brain organization Harris, K.D., Shepherd, G.M., 2015. The neocortical circuit: themes
derived from split-brain studies. Neuron. 14 (2), 217!228. and variations. Nat. Neurosci. 18 (2), 170!181.
Gazzaniga, M.S., 2014. The split-brain: rooting consciousness in biol- Harrison, S.A., Tong, F., 2009. Decoding reveals the contents of visual
ogy. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 111 (51), 18093!18094. working memory in early visual areas. Nature. 458 (7238),
Gazzaniga, M.S., Ivry, R.B., Mangun, G.R., 2014. The neuropsychol- 632!635.
ogy of attention. In: Javsicas, A., Snavely, S. (Eds.), Cognitive Hartikainen, K., Rorarius, M., Makela, K., Perakyla, J., Varila, E.,
Neuroscience: The Biology of the Mind, fourth ed. W. W. Norton Jantti, V., 1995. Visually evoked bursts during isoflurane anaes-
& Company, New York, pp. 275!279. thesia. Br. J. Anaesth. 74 (6), 681!685.
Ghika, J., Ghika-Schmid, F., Fankhauser, H., Assal, G., Hassabis, D., Kumaran, D., Vann, S.D., Maguire, E.A., 2007. Patients
Vingerhoets, F., Albanese, A., et al., 1999. Bilateral contempora- with hippocampal amnesia cannot imagine new experiences.
neous posteroventral pallidotomy for the treatment of Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (5), 1726!1731.
Parkinson’s disease: neuropsychological and neurological side Hassin, R.R., Bargh, J.A., Engell, A.D., McCulloch, K.C., 2009.
effects. Report of four cases and review of the literature. Implicit working memory. Conscious. Cogn. 18 (3), 665!678.
J. Neurosurg. 91 (2), 313!321. Haynes, J.D., Driver, J., Rees, G., 2005. Visibility reflects dynamic
Giacino, J.T., Ashwal, S., Childs, N., Cranford, R., Jennett, B., Katz, changes of effective connectivity between V1 and fusiform cortex.
D.I., et al., 2002. The minimally conscious state: definition and Neuron. 46 (5), 811!821.
diagnostic criteria. Neurology. 58 (3), 349!353. He, B.J., Raichle, M.E., 2009. The fMRI signal, slow cortical potential
Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., Whyte, J., 2004. The JFK coma recovery and consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13 (7), 302!309.
scale-revised: measurement characteristics and diagnostic utility. He, S., MacLeod, D.I., 2001. Orientation-selective adaptation and tilt
Arch. Phys. Med. Rehabil. 85 (12), 2020!2029. after-effect from invisible patterns. Nature. 411 (6836), 473!476.
Glickstein, M., 2007. What does the cerebellum really do? Curr. Biol. Hebb, D.O., 1949. The Organization of Behavior; A
17 (19), R824!R827. Neuropsychological Theory. Wiley, New York.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


444 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

Hebb, D.O., Penfield, W., 1940. Human behavior after extensive bilat- haemorrhage in a conscious adult: a rare case report. Brain Inj. 27
eral removal from the frontal lobes. Arch. Neurol. Psychiatry. 42, (4), 500!503.
421!438. Jakobson, L.S., Pearson, P.M., Robertson, B., 2008. Hue-specific
Herculano-Houzel, S., 2012. The remarkable, yet not extraordinary, colour memory impairment in an individual with intact colour
human brain as a scaled-up primate brain and its associated cost. perception and colour naming. Neuropsychologia. 46 (1),
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 109 (Suppl. 1), 10661!10668. 22!36.
Herculano-Houzel, S., Munk, M.H., Neuenschwander, S., Singer, W., Jiang, Y., Zhou, K., He, S., 2007. Human visual cortex responds to
1999. Precisely synchronized oscillatory firing patterns require invisible chromatic flicker. Nat. Neurosci. 10 (5), 657!662.
electroencephalographic activation. J. Neurosci. 19 (10), John, E.R., Prichep, L.S., Kox, W., Valdes-Sosa, P., Bosch-Bayard, J.,
3992!4010. Aubert, E., et al., 2001. Invariant reversible QEEG effects of anes-
Hermes, D., Miller, K.J., Wandell, B.A., Winawer, J., 2014. Stimulus thetics. Conscious. Cogn. 10 (2), 165!183.
AU:17 dependence of gamma oscillations in human visual cortex. Cereb. Jones, E.G., 1998. A new view of specific and nonspecific thalamocor-
Cortex.. tical connections. Adv. Neurol. 77, 49!71.
Hobson, J.A., Pace-Schott, E.F., 2002. The cognitive neuroscience of Jones, E.G., 2007. The Thalamus. Cambridge University Press,
sleep: neuronal systems, consciousness and learning. Nat. Rev. Cambridge and New York.
Neurosci. 3 (9), 679!693. Kentridge, R.W., 2013. Visual attention: bringing the unseen past into
Hobson, J.A., Pace-Schott, E.F., Stickgold, R., 2000. Dreaming and the view. Curr. Biol. 23 (2), R69!R71.
brain: toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states. Behav. Kentridge, R.W., Heywood, C.A., Weiskrantz, L., 1999. Attention
Brain Sci. 23 (6), 793!842. without awareness in blindsight. Proc. Biol. Sci. 266 (1430),
Hoel, E.P., Albantakis, L., Tononi, G., 2013. Quantifying causal emer- 1805!1811.
gence shows that macro can beat micro. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. Kentridge, R.W., Nijboer, T.C., Heywood, C.A., 2008. Attended but
USA. 110 (49), 19790!19795. unseen: visual attention is not sufficient for visual awareness.
Hohwy, J., 2009. The neural correlates of consciousness: new experi- Neuropsychologia. 46 (3), 864!869.
mental approaches needed? Conscious. Cogn. 18 (2), 428!438. Kertai, M.D., Whitlock, E.L., Avidan, M.S., 2012. Brain monitoring
Holler, Y., Bergmann, J., Kronbichler, M., Crone, J.S., Schmid, E.V., with electroencephalography and the electroencephalogram-
Golaszewski, S., et al., 2011. Preserved oscillatory response but derived bispectral index during cardiac surgery. Anesth. Analg.
lack of mismatch negativity in patients with disorders of con- 114 (3), 533!546.
sciousness. Clin. Neurophysiol. 122 (9), 1744!1754. King, J.R., Sitt, J.D., Faugeras, F., Rohaut, B., El Karoui, I., Cohen, L.,
Hollins, M., 1985. Styles of mental imagery in blind adults. et al., 2013. Information sharing in the brain indexes conscious-
Neuropsychologia. 23 (4), 561!566. ness in noncommunicative patients. Curr. Biol. 23 (19),
Horikawa, T., Tamaki, M., Miyawaki, Y., Kamitani, Y., 2013. Neural 1914!1919.
decoding of visual imagery during sleep. Science. 340 (6132), Kirchner, H., Thorpe, S.J., 2006. Ultra-rapid object detection with
639!642. saccadic eye movements: visual processing speed revisited.
Horton, J.C., Hoyt, W.F., 1991. Quadrantic visual field defects. A hall- Vision Res. 46 (11), 1762!1776.
mark of lesions in extrastriate (V2/V3) cortex. Brain. 114 (Pt 4), Koch, C., Tsuchiya, N., 2007. Attention and consciousness: two
1703!1718. distinct brain processes. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11 (1), 16!22.
Hsieh, P.J., Colas, J.T., Kanwisher, N., 2011. Pop-out without aware- Koch, C., Tsuchiya, N., 2012. Attention and consciousness: related
ness: unseen feature singletons capture attention only when top- yet different. Trends Cogn. Sci. 16 (2), 103!105.
down attention is available. Psychol. Sci. 22 (9), 1220!1226. Konen, C.S., Kastner, S., 2008. Two hierarchically organized neural
Hudetz, A.G., Imas, O.A., 2007. Burst activation of the cerebral cortex systems for object information in human visual cortex. Nat.
by flash stimuli during isoflurane anesthesia in rats. Neurosci. 11 (2), 224!231.
Anesthesiology. 107 (6), 983!991. Kosslyn, S.M., Ganis, G., Thompson, W.L., 2001. Neural foundations
Hudetz, A.G., Vizuete, J.A., Imas, O.A., 2009. Desflurane selectively of imagery. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2 (9), 635!642.
suppresses long-latency cortical neuronal response to flash in the Kotchoubey, B., 2005. Event-related potential measures of conscious-
rat. Anesthesiology. 111 (2), 231!239. ness: two equations with three unknowns. Prog. Brain Res. 150,
Hung, C.P., Kreiman, G., Poggio, T., DiCarlo, J.J., 2005. Fast readout 427!444.
of object identity from macaque inferior temporal cortex. Science. Kotchoubey, B., Schneck, M., Lang, S., Birbaumer, N., 2003. Event-
310 (5749), 863!866. related brain potentials in a patient with akinetic mutism.
Imas, O.A., Ropella, K.M., Ward, B.D., Wood, J.D., Hudetz, A.G., Neurophysiol. Clin. 33 (1), 23!30.
2005. Volatile anesthetics enhance flash-induced gamma oscilla- Kotchoubey, B., Lang, S., Mezger, G., Schmalohr, D., Schneck, M.,
tions in rat visual cortex. Anesthesiology. 102 (5), 937!947. Semmler, A., et al., 2005. Information processing in severe disor-
Imas, O.A., Ropella, K.M., Wood, J.D., Hudetz, A.G., 2006. Isoflurane ders of consciousness: vegetative state and minimally conscious
disrupts anterio-posterior phase synchronization of flash-induced state. Clin. Neurophysiol. 116 (10), 2441!2453.
field potentials in the rat. Neurosci. Lett. 402 (3), 216!221. Koubeissi, M.Z., Bartolomei, F., Beltagy, A., Picard, F., 2014.
Inbody, S., Jankovic, J., 1986. Hyperkinetic mutism: bilateral ballism Electrical stimulation of a small brain area reversibly disrupts
and basal ganglia calcification. Neurology. 36 (6), 825!827. consciousness. Epilepsy Behav. 37C, 32!35.
Intraub, H., 1999. Understanding and remembering briefly glimpsed Kravitz, D.J., Saleem, K.S., Baker, C.I., Mishkin, M., 2011. A new neu-
pictures: implications for visual scanning and memory. ral framework for visuospatial processing. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 12
In: Coltheart, V. (Ed.), Fleeting Memories: Cognition of Brief (4), 217!230.
Visual Stimuli. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 47!70. Kroeger, D., Amzica, F., 2007. Hypersensitivity of the anesthesia-
Jaar, O., Pilon, M., Carrier, J., Montplaisir, J., Zadra, A., 2010. induced comatose brain. J. Neurosci. 27 (39), 10597!10607.
Analysis of slow-wave activity and slow-wave oscillations prior Ku, S.W., Lee, U., Noh, G.J., Jun, I.G., Mashour, G.A., 2011.
to somnambulism. Sleep. 33 (11), 1511!1516. Preferential inhibition of frontal-to-parietal feedback connectivity
Jain, S.K., Sundar, I.V., Sharma, V., Prasanna, K.L., Kulwal, G., is a neurophysiologic correlate of general anesthesia in surgical
Tiwari, R.N., 2013. Bilateral large traumatic basal ganglia patients. PLoS One. 6 (10), e25155.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 445
Lambert, I., Arthuis, M., McGonigal, A., Wendling, F., Bartolomei, F., Lehembre, R., Marie-Aurelie, B., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Chatelle, C.,
2012. Alteration of global workspace during loss of consciousness: Cologan, V., Leclercq, Y., et al., 2012. Resting-state EEG study of
a study of parietal seizures. Epilepsia. 53 (12), 2104!2110. comatose patients: a connectivity and frequency analysis to find
Lamme, V.A., 2003. Why visual attention and awareness are differ- differences between vegetative and minimally conscious states.
ent. Trends Cogn. Sci. 7 (1), 12!18. Funct. Neurol. 27 (1), 41!47.
Lamme, V.A., 2006. Towards a true neural stance on consciousness. Lehmann, D., 2010. Multimodal analysis of resting state cortical
Trends Cogn. Sci. 10 (11), 494!501. activity: what does fMRI add to our knowledge of microstates in
Lamme, V.A., Roelfsema, P.R., 2000. The distinct modes of vision resting state EEG activity? Commentary to the papers by Britz
offered by feedforward and recurrent processing. Trends et al. and Musso et al. in the current issue of NeuroImage.
Neurosci. 23 (11), 571!579. Neuroimage. 52 (4), 1173!1174.
Lamme, V.A., Super, H., Spekreijse, H., 1998a. Feedforward, horizon- Lemon, R.N., Edgley, S.A., 2010. Life without a cerebellum. Brain.
tal, and feedback processing in the visual cortex. Curr. Opin. 133, 652!654.
Neurobiol. 8 (4), 529!535. Lenggenhager, B., Smith, S.T., Blanke, O., 2006. Functional and
Lamme, V.A., Zipser, K., Spekreijse, H., 1998b. Figure-ground activ- neural mechanisms of embodiment: importance of the vestibular
ity in primary visual cortex is suppressed by anesthesia. Proc. system and the temporal parietal junction. Rev. Neurosci. 17 (6),
Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 95 (6), 3263!3268. 643!657.
Langston, J., Palfreman, J., 1995. The Case of the Frozen Addicts. Leopold, D.A., Logothetis, N.K., 1999. Multistable phenomena:
Vintage Books, New York. changing views in perception. Trends Cogn. Sci. 3 (7), 254!264.
Langston, J.W., Palfreman, J., 2014. The Case of the Frozen Addicts: Leuzzi, V., Favata, I., Seri, S., 1988. Bilateral striatal lesions. Dev.
How the Solution of a Medical Mystery Revolutionized the Med. Child Neurol. 30 (2), 252!257.
Understanding of Parkinson’s Disease. IOS Press, Amsterdam. Leuzzi, V., Bertini, E., De Negri, A.M., Gallucci, M., Garavaglia, B.,
Larkum, M., 2013. A cellular mechanism for cortical associations: an 1992. Bilateral striatal necrosis, dystonia and optic atrophy in two
organizing principle for the cerebral cortex. Trends Neurosci. 36 siblings. J. Neurol. Neurosurg. Psychiatry. 55 (1), 16!19.
(3), 141!151. Li, F.F., VanRullen, R., Koch, C., Perona, P., 2002. Rapid natural
Laureys, S., Faymonville, M.E., Degueldre, C., Fiore, G.D., Damas, P., scene categorization in the near absence of attention. Proc. Natl.
Lambermont, B., et al., 2000a. Auditory processing in the vegeta- Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 99 (14), 9596!9601.
tive state. Brain. 123 (Pt 8), 1589!1601. Liang, Z., King, J., Zhang, N., 2012. Intrinsic organization of the anes-
Laureys, S., Faymonville, M.E., Luxen, A., Lamy, M., Franck, G., Maquet, thetized brain. J. Neurosci. 32 (30), 10183!10191.
P., 2000b. Restoration of thalamocortical connectivity after recovery Libet, B., Alberts, W.W., Wright Jr., E.W., Feinstein, B., 1967.
from persistent vegetative state. Lancet. 355 (9217), 1790!1791. Responses of human somatosensory cortex to stimuli below
Laureys, S., Faymonville, M.E., Peigneux, P., Damas, P., threshold for conscious sensation. Science. 158 (3808), 1597!1600.
Lambermont, B., Del Fiore, G., et al., 2002. Cortical processing of Liu, X., Lauer, K.K., Ward, B.D., Rao, S.M., Li, S.J., Hudetz, A.G.,
noxious somatosensory stimuli in the persistent vegetative state. 2012. Propofol disrupts functional interactions between sensory
Neuroimage. 17 (2), 732!741. and high-order processing of auditory verbal memory. Hum.
Laureys, S., Owen, A.M., Schiff, N.D., 2004. Brain function in coma, Brain Mapp. 33 (10), 2487!2498.
vegetative state, and related disorders. Lancet Neurol. 3 (9), Livingstone, M.S., Hubel, D.H., 1981. Effects of sleep and arousal on
537!546. the processing of visual information in the cat. Nature. 291 (5816),
Laureys, S., Pellas, F., Van Eeckhout, P., Ghorbel, S., Schnakers, C., 554!561.
Perrin, F., et al., 2005. The locked-in syndrome: what is it like to Llinas, R.R., Leznik, E., Urbano, F.J., 2002. Temporal binding via cor-
be conscious but paralyzed and voiceless? Prog. Brain Res. 150, tical coincidence detection of specific and nonspecific thalamocor-
495!511. tical inputs: a voltage-dependent dye-imaging study in mouse
Laureys, S., Celesia, G.G., Cohadon, F., Lavrijsen, J., Leon-Carrion, J., brain slices. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 99 (1), 449!454.
Sannita, W.G., , et al.,European Task Force on Disorders of Logothetis, N.K., 1998. Single units and conscious vision. Philos.
Consciousness 2010. Unresponsive wakefulness syndrome: a new Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 353 (1377), 1801!1818.
name for the vegetative state or apallic syndrome. BMC Med. 8, 68. Lorente de Nó, R., 1938. The cerebral cortex: architecture, intracorti-
Lazar, R.M., Marshall, R.S., Prell, G.D., Pile-Spellman, J., 2000. The cal connections and motor projections. In: Fulton, J. (Ed.),
experience of Wernicke’s aphasia. Neurology. 55 (8), 1222!1224. Physiology of the Nervous System. Oxford University Press,
Le Ber, I., Marie, R.M., Chabot, B., Lalevee, C., Defer, G.L., 2007. London, pp. 291!339.
Neuropsychological and 18FDG-PET studies in a family with Lule, D., Zickler, C., Hacker, S., Bruno, M.A., Demertzi, A., Pellas, F.,
idiopathic basal ganglia calcifications. J. Neurol. Sci. 258 (1!2), et al., 2009. Life can be worth living in locked-in syndrome. Prog.
115!122. Brain Res. 177, 339!351.
Lee, A.C., Bussey, T.J., Murray, E.A., Saksida, L.M., Epstein, R.A., Lumer, E.D., 1998. A neural model of binocular integration and
Kapur, N., et al., 2005a. Perceptual deficits in amnesia: challeng- rivalry based on the coordination of action-potential timing in
ing the medial temporal lobe ‘mnemonic’ view. primary visual cortex. Cereb. Cortex. 8 (6), 553!561.
Neuropsychologia. 43 (1), 1!11. Lumer, E.D., Edelman, G.M., Tononi, G., 1997a. Neural dynamics in
Lee, S.H., Blake, R., Heeger, D.J., 2005b. Traveling waves of activity a model of the thalamocortical system. 1. Layers, loops and the
in primary visual cortex during binocular rivalry. Nat. Neurosci. emergence of fast synchronous rhythms. Cereb. Cortex. 7 (3),
8 (1), 22!23. 207!227.
Lee, U., Kim, S., Noh, G.J., Choi, B.M., Hwang, E., Mashour, G.A., Lumer, E.D., Edelman, G.M., Tononi, G., 1997b. Neural dynamics in
2009. The directionality and functional organization of frontopar- a model of the thalamocortical system. 2. The role of neural syn-
ietal connectivity during consciousness and anesthesia in chrony tested through perturbations of spike timing. Cereb.
humans. Conscious. Cogn. 18 (4), 1069!1078. Cortex. 7 (3), 228!236.
Lee, U., Ku, S., Noh, G., Baek, S., Choi, B., Mashour, G.A., 2013. Luo, Q., Mitchell, D., Cheng, X., Mondillo, K., McCaffrey, D.,
Disruption of frontal-parietal communication by ketamine, propo- Holroyd, T., et al., 2009. Visual awareness, emotion, and gamma
fol, and sevoflurane. Anesthesiology. 118 (6), 1264!1275. band synchronization. Cereb. Cortex. 19 (8), 1896!1904.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


446 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

Luzzatti, C., Davidoff, J., 1994. Impaired retrieval of object-colour Mashour, G.A., Walker, E.E., Martuza, R.L., 2005. Psychosurgery:
knowledge with preserved colour naming. Neuropsychologia. 32 past, present, and future. Brain Res. Brain Res. Rev. 48 (3),
(8), 933!950. 409!419.
Mack, A., Rock, I., 1998. Inattentional Blindness. MIT Press, Mashour, G.A., Shanks, A., Tremper, K.K., Kheterpal, S., Turner,
Cambridge, MA. C.R., Ramachandran, S.K., et al., 2012. Prevention of intraopera-
Macknik, S.L., 2006. Visual masking approaches to visual awareness. tive awareness with explicit recall in an unselected surgical
Prog. Brain Res. 155, 177!215. population: a randomized comparative effectiveness trial.
Macphail, E.M., 1998. The Evolution of Consciousness. Oxford Anesthesiology. 117 (4), 717!725.
University Press, Oxford and New York. Mason, M.F., Norton, M.I., Van Horn, J.D., Wegner, D.M., Grafton, S.
Magnin, M., Bastuji, H., Garcia-Larrea, L., Mauguiere, F., 2004. T., Macrae, C.N., 2007. Wandering minds: the default network
Human thalamic medial pulvinar nucleus is not activated during and stimulus-independent thought. Science. 315 (5810), 393!395.
paradoxical sleep. Cereb. Cortex. 14 (8), 858!862. Massimini, M., Huber, R., Ferrarelli, F., Hill, S., Tononi, G., 2004. The
Magnin, M., Rey, M., Bastuji, H., Guillemant, P., Mauguiere, F., sleep slow oscillation as a traveling wave. J. Neurosci. 24 (31),
Garcia-Larrea, L., 2010. Thalamic deactivation at sleep onset pre- 6862!6870.
cedes that of the cerebral cortex in humans. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. Massimini, M., Ferrarelli, F., Huber, R., Esser, S.K., Singh, H.,
U.S.A. 107 (8), 3829!3833. Tononi, G., 2005. Breakdown of cortical effective connectivity
Maier, A., Adams, G.K., Aura, C., Leopold, D.A., 2010. Distinct during sleep. Science. 309 (5744), 2228!2232.
superficial and deep laminar domains of activity in the visual cor- Massimini, M., Ferrarelli, F., Esser, S.K., Riedner, B.A., Huber, R.,
tex during rest and stimulation. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 4, 31. Murphy, M., et al., 2007. Triggering sleep slow waves by transcra-
Makela, K., Hartikainen, K., Rorarius, M., Jantti, V., 1996. nial magnetic stimulation. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104 (20),
Suppression of F-VEP during isoflurane-induced EEG suppres- 8496!8501.
sion. Electroencephalogr. Clin. Neurophysiol. 100 (3), 269!272. Massimini, M., Ferrarelli, F., Murphy, M., Huber, R., Riedner, B.,
Maquet, P., Péters, J., Aerts, J., Delfiore, G., Degueldre, C., Luxen, A., Casarotto, S., et al., 2010. Cortical reactivity and effective connec-
et al., 1996. Functional neuroanatomy of human rapid-eye- tivity during REM sleep in humans. Cogn. Neurosci. 1 (3),
movement sleep and dreaming. Nature. 383 (6596), 163!166. 176!183.
Maquet, P., Degueldre, C., Delfiore, G., Aerts, J., Péters, J.M., Luxen, Massimini, M., Ferrarelli, F., Sarasso, S., Tononi, G., 2012. Cortical
A., et al., 1997. Functional neuroanatomy of human slow wave mechanisms of loss of consciousness: insight from TMS/EEG
sleep. J. Neurosci. 17 (8), 2807!2812. studies. Arch. Ital. Biol. 150 (2!3), 44!55.
Marchetti, G., 2012. Against the view that consciousness and atten- Mataro, M., Jurado, M.A., Garcia-Sanchez, C., Barraquer, L., Costa-
tion are fully dissociable. Front. Psychol. 3, 36. Jussa, F.R., Junque, C., 2001. Long-term effects of bilateral frontal
Marinsek, N., Turner, B.O., Gazzaniga, M., Miller, M.B., 2014. brain lesion: 60 years after injury with an iron bar. Arch. Neurol.
Divergent hemispheric reasoning strategies: reducing uncertainty 58 (7), 1139!1142.
versus resolving inconsistency. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8, 839. Mayer, J.S., Bittner, R.A., Nikolic, D., Bledowski, C., Goebel, R.,
Markov, N.T., Vezoli, J., Chameau, P., Falchier, A., Quilodran, R., Linden, D.E., 2007. Common neural substrates for visual working
Huissoud, C., et al., 2014. Anatomy of hierarchy: feedforward memory and attention. Neuroimage. 36 (2), 441!453.
and feedback pathways in macaque visual cortex. J. Comp. Mazzi, C., Mancini, F., Savazzi, S., 2014. Can IPS reach visual aware-
Neurol. 522 (1), 225!259. ness without V1? Evidence from TMS in healthy subjects and
Markowitsch, H.J., Kessler, J., 2000. Massive impairment in executive hemianopic patients. Neuropsychologia. 64C, 134!144.
functions with partial preservation of other cognitive functions: McCormick, D.A., Wang, Z., Huguenard, J., 1993. Neurotransmitter
the case of a young patient with severe degeneration of the control of neocortical neuronal activity and excitability. Cereb.
prefrontal cortex. Exp. Brain Res. 133 (1), 94!102. Cortex. 3 (5), 387!398.
Marois, R., Yi, D.J., Chun, M.M., 2004. The neural fate of consciously Melloni, L., Molina, C., Pena, M., Torres, D., Singer, W., Rodriguez,
perceived and missed events in the attentional blink. Neuron. 41 E., 2007. Synchronization of neural activity across cortical areas
(3), 465!472. correlates with conscious perception. J. Neurosci. 27 (11),
Martinez-Conde, S., Cudeiro, J., Grieve, K.L., Rodriguez, R., 2858!2865.
Rivadulla, C., Acuna, C., 1999. Effects of feedback projections Melloni, L., Schwiedrzik, C.M., Muller, N., Rodriguez, E., Singer, W.,
from area 18 layers 2/3 to area 17 layers 2/3 in the cat visual 2011. Expectations change the signatures and timing of
cortex. J. Neurophysiol. 82 (5), 2667!2675. electrophysiological correlates of perceptual awareness.
Martinez-Conde, S., Macknik, S.L., Hubel, D.H., 2002. The function J. Neurosci. 31 (4), 1386!1396.
of bursts of spikes during visual fixation in the awake primate Mettler, F.A., Columbia University. Department of Neurology and
lateral geniculate nucleus and primary visual cortex. Proc. Natl. Greystone Park Psychiatric Hospital, 1949. Selective Partial
Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 99 (21), 13920!13925. Ablation of the Frontal Cortex, a Correlative Study of its Effects
Martinez-Conde, S., Macknik, S.L., Hubel, D.H., 2004. The role of on Human Psychotic Subjects. Hoebar, New York.
fixational eye movements in visual perception. Nat. Rev. Meyer, K., 2011. Primary sensory cortices, top-down projections and
Neurosci. 5 (3), 229!240. conscious experience. Prog. Neurobiol. 94 (4), 408!417.
Martinez-Conde, S., Macknik, S.L., Troncoso, X.G., Dyar, T.A., 2006. Miller, J.W., Ferrendelli, J.A., 1990. Characterization of GABAergic
Microsaccades counteract visual fading during fixation. Neuron. seizure regulation in the midline thalamus. Neuropharmacology.
49 (2), 297!305. 29 (7), 649!655.
Martuzzi, R., Ramani, R., Qiu, M., Rajeevan, N., Constable, R.T., Miller, J.W., Gray, B.C., Turner, G.M., Bardgett, M.E., 1993. An
2010. Functional connectivity and alterations in baseline brain ascending seizure-controlling pathway in the medial brainstem
state in humans. Neuroimage. 49 (1), 823!834. and thalamus. Exp. Neurol. 121 (1), 106!112.
Mashour, G.A., 2014. Top-down mechanisms of anesthetic-induced Miller, M.B., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Young, L., King, D., Paggi, A.,
unconsciousness. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 8, 115. Fabri, M., et al., 2010. Abnormal moral reasoning in complete and
Mashour, G.A., Avidan, M.S., 2015. Intraoperative awareness: contro- partial callosotomy patients. Neuropsychologia. 48 (7),
versies and non-controversies. Br. J. Anaesth. pii, aev034. 2215!2220.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 447
Miller, S.M., 2014. Closing in on the constitution of consciousness. Northoff, G., Kotter, R., Baumgart, F., Danos, P., Boeker, H.,
Front. Psychol. 5, 1293. Kaulisch, T., et al., 2004. Orbitofrontal cortical dysfunction in
Milner, A.D., 2012. Is visual processing in the dorsal stream accessi- akinetic catatonia: a functional magnetic resonance imaging study
ble to consciousness? Proc. Biol. Sci. 279 (1737), 2289!2298. during negative emotional stimulation. Schizophr. Bull. 30 (2),
Milner, A.D., Goodale, M.A., 1995. The Visual Brain in Action. 405!427.
Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York. Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., Tononi, G., 2014. From the phenomenol-
Monti, M.M., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Coleman, M.R., Boly, M., ogy to the mechanisms of consciousness: integrated information
Pickard, J.D., Tshibanda, L., et al., 2010. Willful modulation of theory 3.0. PLoS Comput. Biol. 10 (5), e1003588.
brain activity in disorders of consciousness. N. Engl. J. Med. 362 Olivers, C.N., 2008. Interactions between visual working memory
(7), 579!589. and visual attention. Front. Biosci. 13, 1182!1191.
Monti, M.M., Lutkenhoff, E.S., Rubinov, M., Boveroux, P., Ori, C., Dam, M., Pizzolato, G., Battistin, L., Giron, G., 1986. Effects
Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Gosseries, O., et al., 2013. Dynamic change of isoflurane anesthesia on local cerebral glucose utilization in the
of global and local information processing in propofol-induced rat. Anesthesiology. 65 (2), 152!156.
loss and recovery of consciousness. PLoS Comput. Biol. 9 (10), Owen, A.M., Coleman, M.R., Boly, M., Davis, M.H., Laureys, S.,
e1003271. Pickard, J.D., 2006. Detecting awareness in the vegetative state.
Mori, E., Yamadori, A., 1989. Rejection behaviour: a human homo- Science. 313 (5792), 1402.
logue of the abnormal behaviour of Denny-Brown and Chambers’ Pan, Y., Lin, B., Zhao, Y., Soto, D., 2014. Working memory biasing of
monkey with bilateral parietal ablation. J. Neurol. Neurosurg. visual perception without awareness. Atten. Percept. Psychophys.
Psychiatry. 52 (11), 1260!1266. 76 (7), 2051!2062.
Moruzzi, G., Magoun, H.W., 1949. Brain stem reticular formation Pascual-Leone, A., Walsh, V., 2001. Fast backprojections from the
and activation of the EEG. Electroencephalogr. Clin. motion to the primary visual area necessary for visual awareness.
Neurophysiol. 1 (4), 455!473. Science. 292 (5516), 510!512.
Mudrik, L., Koch, C., 2013. Differential processing of invisible con- Penfield, W., 1975. The Mystery of the Mind: A Critical Study of
gruent and incongruent scenes: a case for unconscious integra- Consciousness and the Human Brain. Princeton University Press,
tion. J. Vis. 13 (13), 24. Princeton.
Mullally, S.L., Intraub, H., Maguire, E.A., 2012. Attenuated boundary Perrault, R., Carrier, J., Desautels, A., Montplaisir, J., Zadra, A., 2014.
extension produces a paradoxical memory advantage in amnesic Electroencephalographic slow waves prior to sleepwalking epi-
patients. Curr. Biol. 22 (4), 261!268. sodes. Sleep Med. 15 (12), 1468!1472.
Muller, N.G., Knight, R.T., 2006. The functional neuroanatomy of Picchioni, D., Pixa, M.L., Fukunaga, M., Carr, W.S., Horovitz, S.G.,
working memory: contributions of human brain lesion studies. Braun, A.R., et al., 2014. Decreased connectivity between the thal-
Neuroscience. 139 (1), 51!58. amus and the neocortex during human nonrapid eye movement
Munglani, R., Andrade, J., Sapsford, D.J., Baddeley, A., Jones, J.G., 1993. sleep. Sleep. 37 (2), 387!397.
A measure of consciousness and memory during isoflurane admin- Pigorini, A., Sarasso, S., Proserpio, P., Szymanski, C., Arnulfo, G.,
istration: the coherent frequency. Br. J. Anaesth. 71 (5), 633!641. Casarotto, S., et al., 2015. Bistability breaks-off deterministic
Munk, M.H., Roelfsema, P.R., Konig, P., Engel, A.K., Singer, W., responses to intracortical stimulation during non-REM sleep.
1996. Role of reticular activation in the modulation of intracortical Neuroimage. 112, 105!113.
synchronization. Science. 272 (5259), 271!274. Pins, D., Ffytche, D., 2003. The neural correlates of conscious vision.
Murphy, M., Bruno, M.A., Riedner, B.A., Boveroux, P., Noirhomme, Cereb. Cortex. 13 (5), 461!474.
Q., Landsness, E.C., et al., 2011. Propofol anesthesia and sleep: a Pisella, L., Grea, H., Tilikete, C., Vighetto, A., Desmurget, M., Rode,
high-density EEG study. Sleep. 34 (3), 283!291A. G., et al., 2000. An ‘automatic pilot’ for the hand in human poste-
Musso, F., Brinkmeyer, J., Mobascher, A., Warbrick, T., Winterer, G., rior parietal cortex: toward reinterpreting optic ataxia. Nat.
2010. Spontaneous brain activity and EEG microstates. A novel Neurosci. 3 (7), 729!736.
EEG/fMRI analysis approach to explore resting-state networks. Pitts, M.A., Martı́nez, A., Hillyard, S.A., 2012. Visual processing of
Neuroimage. 52 (4), 1149!1161. contour patterns under conditions of inattentional blindness. J.
Naci, L., Owen, A.M., 2013. Making every word count for nonre- Cogn. Neurosci. 24 (2), 287!303.
sponsive patients. JAMA Neurol. 70 (10), 1235!1241. Pitts, M.A., Metzler, S., Hillyard, S., 2014. Isolating neural correlates
Nadel, L., Moscovitch, M., 1997. Memory consolidation, retrograde of conscious perception from neural correlates of reporting one’s
amnesia and the hippocampal complex. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 7 perception. Front. Psychol. 5, 1078.
(2), 217!227. Plourde, G., Villemure, C., Fiset, P., Bonhomme, V., Backman, S.B.,
Nakakimura, K., Sakabe, T., Funatsu, N., Maekawa, T., Takeshita, H., 1998. Effect of isoflurane on the auditory steady-state response
1988. Metabolic activation of intercortical and corticothalamic and on consciousness in human volunteers. Anesthesiology. 89
pathways during enflurane anesthesia in rats. Anesthesiology. 68 (4), 844!851.
(5), 777!782. Pockett, S., Holmes, M.D., 2009. Intracranial EEG power spectra and
Nir, Y., Tononi, G., 2010. Dreaming and the brain: from phenomenol- phase synchrony during consciousness and unconsciousness.
ogy to neurophysiology. Trends Cogn. Sci. 14 (2), 88!100. Conscious. Cogn. 18 (4), 1049!1055.
Nir, Y., Staba, R.J., Andrillon, T., Vyazovskiy, V.V., Cirelli, C., Fried, Pollen, D.A., 2008. Fundamental requirements for primary visual
I., et al., 2011. Regional slow waves and spindles in human sleep. perception. Cereb. Cortex. 18 (9), 1991!1998.
Neuron. 70 (1), 153!169. Polonsky, A., Blake, R., Braun, J., Heeger, D.J., 2000. Neuronal
Nir, Y., Vyazovskiy, V.V., Cirelli, C., Banks, M.I., Tononi, G., 2015. activity in human primary visual cortex correlates with
Auditory responses and stimulus-specific adaptation in rat audi- perception during binocular rivalry. Nat. Neurosci. 3 (11),
tory cortex are preserved across NREM and REM sleep. Cereb. 1153!1159.
Cortex. 25 (5), 1362!1378. Poppel, E., Artin, T., 1988. Mindworks: Time and Conscious
Northoff, G., 2002. What catatonia can tell us about ‘top-down modu- Experience. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Inc., Boston.
lation’: a neuropsychiatric hypothesis. Behav. Brain Sci. 25 (5), Posner, J.B., Plum, F., 2007. Plum and Posner’s Diagnosis of Stupor
555!577. and Coma. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


448 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

Postle, B.R., 2006. Working memory as an emergent property of the Russell, I.F., 2013. Fourteen fallacies about the isolated forearm tech-
mind and brain. Neuroscience. 139 (1), 23!38. nique, and its place in modern anaesthesia. Anaesthesia. 68 (7),
Postle, B.R., 2015. The cognitive neuroscience of visual short-term 677!681.
memory. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci. 1, 40!46. Sachidhanandam, S., Sreenivasan, V., Kyriakatos, A., Kremer, Y.,
Prigatano, G.P., 2009. Anosognosia: clinical and ethical considera- Petersen, C.C., 2013. Membrane potential correlates of sensory per-
tions. Curr. Opin. Neurol. 22 (6), 606!611. ception in mouse barrel cortex. Nat. Neurosci. 16 (11), 1671!1677.
Purdon, P.L., Pierce, E.T., Mukamel, E.A., Prerau, M.J., Walsh, J.L., Sacks, O.W., 1995. An Anthropologist on Mars: Seven Paradoxical
Wong, K.F., et al., 2013. Electroencephalogram signatures of loss Tales. Knopf, New York.
and recovery of consciousness from propofol. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sadaghiani, S., Hesselmann, G., Kleinschmidt, A., 2009. Distributed
Sci. USA. 110 (12), E1142!E1151. and antagonistic contributions of ongoing activity fluctuations to
Rabinovich, M., Varona, P., Selverston, A.I., Abarbanel, H.D., 2006. auditory stimulus detection. J. Neurosci. 29 (42), 13410!13417.
Dynamical principles in neuroscience. Rev. Mod. Phys. 78, Sakata, S., Harris, K.D., 2009. Laminar structure of spontaneous and
1213!1265. sensory-evoked population activity in auditory cortex. Neuron.
Raichle, M.E., Snyder, A.Z., 2007. A default mode of brain function: a 64 (3), 404!418.
brief history of an evolving idea. Neuroimage. 37 (4), 1083!1090. Salminen-Vaparanta, N., Vanni, S., Noreika, V., Valiulis, V., Moro, L.,
Raichle, M.E., MacLeod, A.M., Snyder, A.Z., Powers, W.J., Gusnard, Revonsuo, A., 2014. Subjective characteristics of TMS-induced
D.A., Shulman, G.L., 2001. A default mode of brain function. phosphenes originating in human V1 and V2. Cereb. Cortex. 24
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 98 (2), 676!682. (10), 2751!2760.
Railo, H., Koivisto, M., Revonsuo, A., 2011. Tracking the processes Sanders, R.D., Tononi, G., Laureys, S., Sleigh, J.W., 2012.
behind conscious perception: a review of event-related potential cor- Unresponsiveness not equal unconsciousness. Anesthesiology.
relates of visual consciousness. Conscious. Cogn. 20 (3), 972!983. 116 (4), 946!959.
Ray, S., Maunsell, J.H., 2011. Network rhythms influence the relation- Sarasso, S., Rosanova, M., Casali, A.G., Casarotto, S., Fecchio, M.,
ship between spike-triggered local field potential and functional Boly, M., et al., 2014. Quantifying cortical EEG responses to TMS
connectivity. J. Neurosci. 31 (35), 12674!12682. in (un)consciousness. Clin. EEG Neurosci. 45 (1), 40!49.
Raymond, J.E., Shapiro, K.L., Arnell, K.M., 1992. Temporary suppres- Sarrazin, J.C., Cleeremans, A., Haggard, P., 2008. How do we know
sion of visual processing in an RSVP task: an attentional blink?” what we are doing? Time, intention and awareness of action.
J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 18 (3), 849!860. Conscious. Cogn. 17 (3), 602!615.
Rechtschaffen, A., Foulkes, D., 1965. Effect of visual stimuli on dream Scannell, J.W., Burns, G.A., Hilgetag, C.C., O’Neil, M.A., Young, M.
content. Percept. Mot. Skills. 20 (Suppl.), 1149!1160. P., 1999. The connectional organization of the cortico-thalamic
Rees, G., Kreiman, G., Koch, C., 2002. Neural correlates of conscious- system of the cat. Cereb. Cortex. 9 (3), 277!299.
ness in humans. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 3 (4), 261!270. Schiff, N.D., 2006a. Measurements and models of cerebral function in
Revonsuo, A., 2000. The reinterpretation of dreams: an evolutionary the severely injured brain. J. Neurotrauma. 23 (10), 1436!1449.
hypothesis of the function of dreaming. Behav. Brain Sci. 23, Schiff, N.D., 2006b. Multimodal neuroimaging approaches to disor-
877!901. ders of consciousness. J. Head Trauma Rehabil. 21 (5), 388!397.
Ric, F., Muller, D., 2012. Unconscious addition: when we uncon- Schiff, N.D., 2009. Central thalamic deep-brain stimulation in the
sciously initiate and follow arithmetic rules. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. severely injured brain: rationale and proposed mechanisms of
141 (2), 222!226. action. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1157, 101!116.
Ro, T., Breitmeyer, B., Burton, P., Singhal, N.S., Lane, D., 2003. Schiff, N.D., 2010. Recovery of consciousness after brain injury: a
Feedback contributions to visual awareness in human occipital mesocircuit hypothesis. Trends Neurosci. 33 (1), 1!9.
cortex. Curr. Biol. 13 (12), 1038!1041. Schiff, N.D., Plum, F., 2000. The role of arousal and ‘gating’ systems
Robertson, L.C., 2004. Space, Objects, Minds, and Brains. Psychology in the neurology of impaired consciousness. J. Clin.
Press, New York. Neurophysiol. 17 (5), 438!452.
Rodriguez, E., George, N., Lachaux, J.P., Martinerie, J., Renault, Schiff, N.D., Ribary, U., Moreno, D.R., Beattie, B., Kronberg, E.,
B., Varela, F.J., 1999. Perception’s shadow: long-distance Blasberg, R., et al., 2002. Residual cerebral activity and behaviour-
synchronization of human brain activity. Nature. 397 (6718), al fragments can remain in the persistently vegetative brain.
430!433. Brain. 125 (Pt 6), 1210!1234.
Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., Konig, P., Singer, W., 1997. Visuomotor Schiff, N.D., Giacino, J.T., Kalmar, K., Victor, J.D., Baker, K., Gerber,
integration is associated with zero time-lag synchronization M., et al., 2007. Behavioural improvements with thalamic stimula-
among cortical areas. Nature. 385 (6612), 157!161. tion after severe traumatic brain injury. Nature. 448 (7153),
Rolls, E.T., Tovee, M.J., Panzeri, S., 1999. The neurophysiology of 600!603.
backward visual masking: information analysis. J. Cogn. Schiff, N.D., Nauvel, T., Victor, J.D., 2014. Large-scale brain dynamics
Neurosci. 11 (3), 300!311. in disorders of consciousness. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 25, 7!14.
Rosanova, M., Gosseries, O., Casarotto, S., Boly, M., Casali, A.G., Schmahmann, J.D., Weilburg, J.B., Sherman, J.C., 2007. The neuropsy-
Bruno, M.A., et al., 2012. Recovery of cortical effective connectiv- chiatry of the cerebellum - insights from the clinic. Cerebellum. 6
ity and recovery of consciousness in vegetative patients. Brain. (3), 254!267.
135 (Pt 4), 1308!1320. Schnakers, C., Perrin, F., Schabus, M., Majerus, S., Ledoux, D.,
Rossi, A.F., Desimone, R., Ungerleider, L.G., 2001. Contextual modu- Damas, P., et al., 2008. Voluntary brain processing in disorders of
lation in primary visual cortex of macaques. J. Neurosci. 21 (5), consciousness. Neurology. 71 (20), 1614!1620.
1698!1709. Schnakers, C., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Giacino, J., Ventura, M., Boly,
Rozenfeld, H.D., Ben-Avraham, D., 2007. Percolation in hierarchical M., Majerus, S., et al., 2009. Diagnostic accuracy of the vegetative
scale-free nets. Phys. Rev. E Stat. Nonlin. Soft Matter Phys. 75 (6 and minimally conscious state: clinical consensus versus stan-
Pt 1), 061102. dardized neurobehavioral assessment. BMC Neurol. 9, 35.
Ruby, P., Decety, J., 2001. Effect of subjective perspective taking dur- Schoffelen, J.M., Oostenveld, R., Fries, P., 2005. Neuronal coherence
ing simulation of action: a PET investigation of agency. Nat. as a mechanism of effective corticospinal interaction. Science. 308
Neurosci. 4 (5), 546!550. (5718), 111!113.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 449
Scholte, H.S., Witteveen, S.C., Spekreijse, H., Lamme, V.A., 2006. The Soto, D., Silvanto, J., 2014. Reappraising the relationship between
influence of inattention on the neural correlates of scene segmen- working memory and conscious awareness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 18
tation. Brain Res. 1076 (1), 106!115. (10), 520!525.
Schroter, M.S., Spoormaker, V.I., Schorer, A., Wohlschlager, A., Soto, D., Mäntylä, T., Silvanto, J., 2011. Working memory without
Czisch, M., Kochs, E.F., et al., 2012. Spatiotemporal reconfigura- consciousness. Curr. Biol. 21 (22), R912!R913.
tion of large-scale brain functional networks during propofol- Spinazzola, L., Pia, L., Folegatti, A., Marchetti, C., Berti, A., 2008.
induced loss of consciousness. J. Neurosci. 32 (37), 12832!12840. Modular structure of awareness for sensorimotor disorders: evi-
Schrouff, J., Perlbarg, V., Boly, M., Marrelec, G., Boveroux, P., dence from anosognosia for hemiplegia and anosognosia for
Vanhaudenhuyse, A., et al., 2011. Brain functional integration hemianaesthesia. Neuropsychologia. 46 (3), 915!926.
decreases during propofol-induced loss of consciousness. Spoormaker, V.I., Gleiser, P.M., Czisch, M., 2012. Frontoparietal
Neuroimage. 57 (1), 198!205. connectivity and hierarchical structure of the brain’s functional
Scott, R., Gregory, R., Hines, N., Carroll, C., Hyman, N., network during sleep. Front. Neurol. 3, 80.
Papanasstasiou, V., et al., 1998. Neuropsychological, neurological Sporns, O., 2010. Networks of the Brain. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
and functional outcome following pallidotomy for Parkinson’s Sporns, O., 2011. The human connectome: a complex network. Ann.
disease. A consecutive series of eight simultaneous bilateral and N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1224, 109!125.
twelve unilateral procedures. Brain. 121 (Pt 4), 659!675. Sporns, O., 2013. Structure and function of complex brain networks.
Self, M.W., Kooijmans, R.N., Super, H., Lamme, V.A., Roelfsema, P. Dialogues Clin. Neurosci. 15 (3), 247!262.
R., 2012. Different glutamate receptors convey feedforward and Sporns, O., Tononi, G., Edelman, G.M., 1991. Modeling perceptual
recurrent processing in macaque V1. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. grouping and figure-ground segregation by means of active reen-
109 (27), 11031!11036. trant connections. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 88 (1), 129!133.
Sergent, C., Baillet, S., Dehaene, S., 2005. Timing of the brain events Squire, L.R., 2009. The legacy of patient H.M. for neuroscience.
underlying access to consciousness during the attentional blink. Neuron. 61 (1), 6!9.
Nat. Neurosci. 8 (10), 1391!1400. Stender, J., Gosseries, O., Bruno, M., Charland-Verville, V.,
Sergent, C., Wyart, V., Babo-Rebelo, M., Cohen, L., Naccache, L., Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Demertzi, A., et al., 2014. Diagnostic precision
Tallon-Baudry, C., 2013. Cueing attention after the stimulus is of PET imaging and functional MRI in disorders of consciousness: a
gone can retrospectively trigger conscious perception. Curr. Biol. clinical validation study. Lancet. 384 (9942), 514!522.
23 (2), 150!155. Steriade, M., 2000. Corticothalamic resonance, states of vigilance and
Sherman, S.M., Guillery, R.W., 2002. The role of the thalamus in the mentation. Neuroscience. 101 (2), 243!276.
flow of information to the cortex. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Steriade, M., 2003. The corticothalamic system in sleep. Front. Biosci.
Biol. Sci. 357 (1428), 1695!1708. 8, D878!D899.
Shew, W.L., Plenz, D., 2013. The functional benefits of criticality in Steriade, M., Timofeev, I., Grenier, F., 2001. Natural waking and
the cortex. Neuroscientist. 19 (1), 88!100. sleep states: a view from inside neocortical neurons.
Shipp, S., 2003. The functional logic of cortico-pulvinar connections. J. Neurophysiol. 85 (5), 1969!1985.
Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 358 (1438), 1605!1624. Steyn-Ross, D.A., Steyn-Ross, M.L., Wilcocks, L.C., Sleigh, J.W.,
Shipp, S., 2007. Structure and function of the cerebral cortex. Curr. 2001a. Toward a theory of the general-anesthetic-induced phase
Biol. 17 (12), R443!R449. transition of the cerebral cortex. II. Numerical simulations, spec-
Shuren, J.E., Brott, T.G., Schefft, B.K., Houston, W., 1996. Preserved color tral entropy, and correlation times. Phys. Rev. E Stat. Nonlin. Soft
imagery in an achromatopsic. Neuropsychologia. 34 (6), 485!489. Matter Phys. 64 (1 Pt 1), 011918.
Siclari, F., Larocque, J.J., Postle, B.R., Tononi, G., 2013. Assessing Steyn-Ross, M.L., Steyn-Ross, D.A., Sleigh, J.W., Wilcocks, L.C.,
sleep consciousness within subjects using a serial awakening par- 2001b. Toward a theory of the general-anesthetic-induced phase
adigm. Front. Psychol. 4, 542. transition of the cerebral cortex. I. A thermodynamics analogy.
Siclari, F., Bernardi, G., Riedner, B., LaRocque, J., Benca, M.R., Phys. Rev. E Stat. Nonlin. Soft Matter Phys. 64 (1 Pt 1), 011917.
Tononi, G., 2014a. Two distinct synchronization processes in the Stickgold, R., Malia, A., Fosse, R., Propper, R., Hobson, J.A., 2001.
transition to sleep: a high-density electroencephalographic study. Brain-mind states : I. Longitudinal field study of sleep/wake
Sleep. 37 (10), 1621!1637. factors influencing mentation report length. Sleep. 24, 171!179.
Siclari, F., Larocque, J., Bernardi, G., Postle, B., Tononi, G., 2014b. Stratton, P., Wiles, J., 2010. Self-sustained non-periodic activity in
The neural correlates of consciousness in sleep: a no-task, within- networks of spiking neurons: the contribution of local and
AU:18 state paradigm. bioRxiv. Available from: http://dx.doi.org/ long-range connections and dynamic synapses. Neuroimage. 52
10.1101/012443. (3), 1070!1079.
Siegel, J., 2000. Narcolepsy. Sci. Am. 282, 76!81. Straussberg, R., Shorer, Z., Weitz, R., Basel, L., Kornreich, L., Corie,
Silvanto, J., 2014. Is primary visual cortex necessary for visual aware- C.I., et al., 2002. Familial infantile bilateral striatal necrosis: clini-
ness?”. Trends Neurosci. 37 (11), 618!619. cal features and response to biotin treatment. Neurology. 59 (7),
Silvanto, J., Cowey, A., Lavie, N., Walsh, V., 2005. Striate cortex (V1) 983!989.
activity gates awareness of motion. Nat. Neurosci. 8 (2), 143!144. Stumbrys, T., Erlacher, D., Schredl, M., 2013. Testing the involvement
Singer, W., 1999. Neuronal synchrony: a versatile code for the defini- of the prefrontal cortex in lucid dreaming: a tDCS study.
tion of relations? Neuron. 24 (1), 49!65, 111!125. Conscious. Cogn. 22 (4), 1214!1222.
Sitt, J.D., King, J.R., El Karoui, I., Rohaut, B., Faugeras, F., Gramfort, Stuss, D.T., Alexander, M.P., 2001. Consciousness, self-awareness AU:19
A., et al., 2014. Large scale screening of neural signatures of con- and the frontal lobes. In: Malloy, P., Salloway, S., Duffy, J. (Eds.),
sciousness in patients in a vegetative or minimally conscious The Frontal Lobes and Neuropsychiatric Illness. American
state. Brain. 137 (Pt 8), 2258!2270. Psychiatric Press, Washington, DC, pp. 101!112.
Sklar, A.Y., Levy, N., Goldstein, A., Mandel, R., Maril, A., Hassin, R. Super, H., Spekreijse, H., Lamme, V.A., 2001. Two distinct modes of
R., 2012. Reading and doing arithmetic nonconsciously. Proc. sensory processing observed in monkey primary visual cortex
Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 109 (48), 19614!19619. (V1). Nat. Neurosci. 4 (3), 304!310.
Sleigh, J., 2013. The place of the isolated forearm technique in mod- Sutton, S., Braren, M., Zubin, J., John, E.R., 1965. Evoked-potential
ern anaesthesia: yet to be defined. Anaesthesia. 68 (7), 681!683. correlates of stimulus uncertainty. Science. 150 (3700), 1187!1188.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


450 25. THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: AN OVERVIEW

Tagliazucchi, E., von Wegner, F., Morzelewski, A., Brodbeck, V., Vahle-Hinz, C., Detsch, O., Siemers, M., Kochs, E., 2007.
Borisov, S., Jahnke, K., et al., 2013a. Large-scale brain functional Contributions of GABAergic and glutamatergic mechanisms to
modularity is reflected in slow electroencephalographic rhythms isoflurane-induced suppression of thalamic somatosensory infor-
across the human non-rapid eye movement sleep cycle. mation transfer. Exp. Brain Res. 176 (1), 159!172.
Neuroimage. 70, 327!339. van Boxtel, J.J., Tsuchiya, N., Koch, C., 2010. Consciousness and
Tagliazucchi, E., von Wegner, F., Morzelewski, A., Brodbeck, V., attention: on sufficiency and necessity. Front. Psychol. 1, 217.
Jahnke, K., Laufs, H., 2013b. Breakdown of long-range temporal Vanderwolf, C.H., Stewart, D.J., 1988. Thalamic control of neocortical
dependence in default mode and attention networks during deep activation: a critical re-evaluation. Brain Res. Bull. 20 (4), 529!538.
sleep. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 110 (38), 15419!15424. Van de Ville, D., Britz, J., Michel, C.M., 2010. EEG microstate
Takaura, K., Yoshida, M., Isa, T., 2011. Neural substrate of spatial sequences in healthy humans at rest reveal scale-free dynamics.
memory in the superior colliculus after damage to the primary Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107 (42), 18179!18184.
visual cortex. J. Neurosci. 31 (11), 4233!4241. Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Noirhomme, Q., Tshibanda, L.J., Bruno, M.A.,
Terzaghi, M., Sartori, I., Tassi, L., Didato, G., Rustioni, V., LoRusso, Boveroux, P., Schnakers, C., et al., 2010. Default network connec-
G., et al., 2009. Evidence of dissociated arousal states during tivity reflects the level of consciousness in non-communicative
NREM parasomnia from an intracerebral neurophysiological brain-damaged patients. Brain. 133 (Pt 1), 161!171.
study. Sleep. 32 (3), 409!412. Vanhaudenhuyse, A., Demertzi, A., Schabus, M., Noirhomme, Q.,
Terzaghi, M., Sartori, I., Tassi, L., Rustioni, V., Proserpio, P., Lorusso, Bredart, S., Boly, M., et al., 2011. Two distinct neuronal networks
G., et al., 2012. Dissociated local arousal states underlying essen- mediate the awareness of environment and of self. J. Cogn.
tial clinical features of non-rapid eye movement arousal parasom- Neurosci. 23 (3), 570!578.
nia: an intracerebral stereo-electroencephalographic study. VanRullen, R., Koch, C., 2003. Visual selective behavior can be trig-
J. Sleep Res. 21 (5), 502!506. gered by a feed-forward process. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 15 (2),
Theyel, B.B., Llano, D.A., Sherman, S.M., 2010. The corticothalamo- 209!217.
cortical circuit drives higher-order cortex in the mouse. Nat. van Zandvoort, M.J., Nijboer, T.C., de Haan, E., 2007. Developmental
Neurosci. 13 (1), 84!88. colour agnosia. Cortex. 43 (6), 750!757.
Thorpe, S., Fize, D., Marlot, C., 1996. Speed of processing in the Velly, L.J., Rey, M.F., Bruder, N.J., Gouvitsos, F.A., Witjas, T., Regis,
human visual system. Nature. 381 (6582), 520!522. J.M., et al., 2007. Differential dynamic of action on cortical and
Timofeev, I., Grenier, F., Bazhenov, M., Sejnowski, T.J., Steriade, M., subcortical structures of anesthetic agents during induction of
2000. Origin of slow cortical oscillations in deafferented cortical anesthesia. Anesthesiology. 107 (2), 202!212.
slabs. Cereb. Cortex. 10 (12), 1185!1199. Verdonck, O., Reed, S.J., Hall, J., Gotman, J., Plourde, G., 2014.
Tononi, G., 2004a. Consciousness and the brain: theoretical aspects. The sensory thalamus and cerebral motor cortex are affected
In: Adelman, G., Smith, B. (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Neuroscience. concurrently during induction of anesthesia with propofol: a
AU:20 Elsevier. case series with intracranial electroencephalogram recordings.
Tononi, G., 2004b. An information integration theory of conscious- Can. J. Anaesth. 61 (3), 254!262.
ness. BMC Neurosci. 5 (1), 42. Villablanca, J., Salinas-Zeballos, M.E., 1972. Sleep-wakefulness, EEG
Tononi, G., 2005. Consciousness, information integration, and the and behavioral studies of chronic cats without the thalamus: the
brain. Prog. Brain Res. 150, 109!126. ‘athalamic’ cat. Arch. Ital. Biol. 110 (3), 383!411.
Tononi, G., 2008. Consciousness as integrated information: a provi- Vogel, E.K., Luck, S.J., Shapiro, K.L., 1998. Electrophysiological evi-
sional manifesto. Biol. Bull. 215, 216!242. dence for a postperceptual locus of suppression during the atten-
Tononi, G., 2012. The integrated information theory of consciousness: tional blink. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 24 (6),
an updated account. Arch. Ital. Biol. 150, 290!326. 1656!1674.
Tononi, G., 2015. Integrated information theory. Scholarpedia. 10 (1), Vogeley, K., May, M., Ritzl, A., Falkai, P., Zilles, K., Fink, G.R., 2004.
4164. Neural correlates of first-person perspective as one constituent of
Tononi, G., Edelman, G.M., 1998. Consciousness and complexity. human self-consciousness. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 16 (5), 817!827.
Science. 282 (5395), 1846!1851. von Arx, S.W., Muri, R.M., Heinemann, D., Hess, C.W., Nyffeler, T.,
Tononi, G., Sporns, O., Edelman, G.M., 1992. Reentry and the prob- 2010. Anosognosia for cerebral achromatopsia!a longitudinal
lem of integrating multiple cortical areas: simulation of dynamic case study. Neuropsychologia. 48 (4), 970!977.
integration in the visual system. Cereb. Cortex. 2 (4), 310!335. Voss, H.U., Uluc, A.M., Dyke, J.P., Watts, R., Kobylarz, E.J.,
Tononi, G., Sporns, O., Edelman, G.M., 1996. A complexity measure McCandliss, B.D., et al., 2006. Possible axonal regrowth in late
for selective matching of signals by the brain. Proc. Natl. Acad. recovery from the minimally conscious state. J. Clin. Invest. 116
Sci. USA. 93 (8), 3422!3427. (7), 2005!2011.
Tremblay, L., Worbe, Y., Thobois, S., Sgambato-Faure, V., Feger, J., Voss, U., Holzmann, R., Hobson, A., Paulus, W., Koppehele-Gossel,
2015. Selective dysfunction of basal ganglia subterritories: from J., Klimke, A., et al., 2014. Induction of self awareness in dreams
AU:21 movement to behavioral disorders. Mov. Disord.. through frontal low current stimulation of gamma activity. Nat.
Tsakiris, M., Hesse, M.D., Boy, C., Haggard, P., Fink, G.R., 2007. Neurosci. 17 (6), 810!812.
Neural signatures of body ownership: a sensory network for Vuilleumier, P., 2000. Anosognosia. In: Bogousslavsky, J.,
bodily self-consciousness. Cereb. Cortex. 17 (10), 2235!2244. Cummings, J.L. (Eds.), Disorders of Behavior and Mood in Focal
Tse, P.U., Martinez-Conde, S., Schlegel, A.A., Macknik, S.L., 2005. Brain Lesions. Cambridge University Press, New York,
Visibility, visual awareness, and visual masking of simple unat- pp. 465!519.
tended targets are confined to areas in the occipital cortex beyond Vuilleumier, P., 2004. Anosognosia: the neurology of beliefs and
human V1/V2. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 102 (47), 17178!17183. uncertainties. Cortex. 40 (1), 9!17.
Tsuchiya, N., Koch, C., 2005. Continuous flash suppression reduces Vuilleumier, P., Sagiv, N., Hazeltine, E., Poldrack, R.A., Swick, D.,
negative afterimages. Nat. Neurosci. 8 (8), 1096!1101. Rafal, R.D., et al., 2001. Neural fate of seen and unseen faces in
Tzovara, A., Simonin, A., Oddo, M., Rossetti, A.O., De Lucia, M., visuospatial neglect: a combined event-related functional MRI
AU:22 2015. Neural detection of complex sound sequences in the and event-related potential study. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 98
absence of consciousness. Brain.. (6), 3495!3500.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


REFERENCES 451
Weiskrantz, L., 1996. Blindsight revisited. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 6 with EEG nonlinear analysis. Clin. Neurophysiol. 122 (10),
(2), 215!220. 1956!1966.
Westmoreland, B.F., Klass, D.W., Sharbrough, F.W., Reagan, T.J., Wyart, V., Tallon-Baudry, C., 2008. Neural dissociation between
1975. Alpha-coma. Electroencephalographic, clinical, pathologic, visual awareness and spatial attention. J. Neurosci. 28 (10),
and etiologic correlations. Arch. Neurol. 32 (11), 713!718. 2667!2679.
Whyte, J., Myers, R., 2009. Incidence of clinically significant Wyart, V., Tallon-Baudry, C., 2009. How ongoing fluctuations in
responses to zolpidem among patients with disorders of human visual cortex predict perceptual awareness: baseline shift
consciousness: a preliminary placebo controlled trial. Am. J. Phys. versus decision bias. J. Neurosci. 29 (27), 8715!8725.
Med. Rehabil. 88 (5), 410!418. Yang, L., Shklyar, I., Lee, H.W., Ezeani, C.C., Anaya, J., Balakirsky,
Wiegand, K., Gutschalk, A., 2012. Correlates of perceptual awareness S., et al., 2012. Impaired consciousness in epilepsy investigated by
in human primary auditory cortex revealed by an informational a prospective responsiveness in epilepsy scale (RES). Epilepsia.
masking experiment. Neuroimage. 61 (1), 62!69. 53 (3), 437!447.
Wikler, A., 1952. Pharmacologic dissociation of behavior and EEG York, M.K., Lai, E.C., Jankovic, J., Macias, A., Atassi, F., Levin, H.S.,
‘sleep patterns’ in dogs; morphine, n-allylnormorphine, and et al., 2007. Short and long-term motor and cognitive outcome of
atropine. Proc. Soc. Exp. Biol. Med. 79 (2), 261!265. staged bilateral pallidotomy: a retrospective analysis. Acta
Williams, D., Parsons-Smith, G., 1951. Thalamic activity in stupor. Neurochir. (Wien). 149 (9), 857!866.
Brain. 74 (4), 377!398. Young, A.W., de Haan, E.H., Newcombe, F., 1990. Unawareness of
Winocur, G., Moscovitch, M., Sekeres, M., 2007. Memory consolida- impaired face recognition. Brain Cogn. 14 (1), 1!18.
tion or transformation: context manipulation and hippocampal Yu, F., Jiang, Q.J., Sun, X.Y., Zhang, R.W., 2014. A new case of com-
representations of memory. Nat. Neurosci. 10 (5), 555!557. plete primary cerebellar agenesis: clinical and imaging findings in
Wolfe, J.M., 1999. Inattentional amnesia. In: Coltheart, V. (Ed.), a living patient. Brain. pii, awu239.
Fleeting Memories. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 71!94. Zadra, A., Desautels, A., Petit, D., Montplaisir, J., 2013.
Womelsdorf, T., Schoffelen, J.M., Oostenveld, R., Singer, W., Somnambulism: clinical aspects and pathophysiological hypothe-
Desimone, R., Engel, A.K., et al., 2007. Modulation of neuronal ses. Lancet Neurol. 12 (3), 285!294.
interactions through neuronal synchronization. Science. 316 Zeki, S., 1993. A Vision of the Brain. Blackwell Scientific Publications,
(5831), 1609!1612. Oxford and Boston.
Woodman, G.F., Luck, S.J., 2003. Dissociations among attention, Zhang, P., Jiang, Y., He, S., 2012. Voluntary attention modulates
perception, and awareness during object-substitution masking. processing of eye-specific visual information. Psychol. Sci. 23 (3),
Psychol. Sci. 14 (6), 605!611. 254!260.
Wu, D.Y., Cai, G., Zorowitz, R.D., Yuan, Y., Wang, J., Song, W.Q., Zhang, S., Xu, M., Kamigaki, T., Do, J.P.H., Chang, W.-C., Jenvay, S.,
2011. Measuring interconnection of the residual cortical functional et al., 2014. Long-range and local circuits for top-down modula-
islands in persistent vegetative state and minimal conscious state tion of visual cortex processing. Science. 345 (6197), 660!665.

THE NEUROLOGY OF CONSCIOUSNESS


View publication stats

You might also like