Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Opinion

Towards a bottom-up perspective on


animal and human cognition
Frans B.M. de Waal1 and Pier Francesco Ferrari2
1
Living Links, Yerkes National Primate Research Center, and Psychology Department, Emory University, 954 North Gatewood
Road, Atlanta, GA 30322, USA
2
Department of Evolutionary and Functional Biology and Department of Neuroscience, University of Parma, via Volturno 39,
43100 Parma, Italy

Over the last few decades, comparative cognitive degree to which these mechanisms are either widespread
research has focused on the pinnacles of mental evol- or special adaptations.
ution, asking all-or-nothing questions such as which
animals (if any) possess a theory of mind, culture, lin- From a top-down to a bottom-up approach
guistic abilities, future planning, and so on. Research Even if continuity among all life forms is widely accepted in
programs adopting this top-down perspective have relation to anatomy, genetics, development and neuro-
often pitted one taxon against another, resulting in science, this view remains controversial when it comes
sharp dividing lines. Insight into the underlying mech- to cognition. Proposals of discontinuity are innate in the
anisms has lagged behind. A dramatic change in focus top-down perspective that has steered comparative cogni-
now seems to be under way, however, with increased tion in the direction of the most complex expressions of any
appreciation that the basic building blocks of cognition given capacity. Do only humans have a theory of mind, or
might be shared across a wide range of species. We do apes, too? Can animals have culture? What is imitation
argue that this bottom-up perspective, which focuses and which species are capable of it? Do apes, in fact, ape?
on the constituent capacities underlying larger cognitive Does not reciprocal exchange require scorekeeping too
phenomena, is more in line with both neuroscience and demanding for any animal? Pitting humans against apes,
evolutionary biology. apes against monkeys, primates against corvids, dogs
against apes, and so on, it almost seems like a contest of
Introduction ‘who is the smartest of them all?’ Scala Naturae assump-
A few decades ago, scientists focused on language – a tions remain prevalent enough that cognitive similarities
typically human characteristic – to see how far apes could between distant taxa, such as birds and primates, are
go with it. When attempts to teach apes speech failed, sometimes viewed as antithetical to evolutionary theory
training moved to the gestural domain and performance [3].
exceeded expectations: symbolic communication seemed to The absence of certain cognitive abilities in certain
be within the grasp of our close relatives [1]. Definitions of taxonomic groups is critical to this approach, so negative
language were quickly changed, however, stressing syntax evidence has received unwarranted attention. Although
over reference [2]. both positive and negative evidence risk being false, a
The field of animal cognition rarely shies away from profound asymmetry exists: there are many more possible
advanced faculties, leading to regular conflict regarding reasons why an existing capacity might not be found than
the human–animal divide. But what if we were to replace why a non-existing capacity could be found. This is why
our obsession with complex cognition with an exploration negative evidence should be treated with great circumspec-
of basic processes? Instead of asking which species can do tion. Nevertheless, failures to demonstrate certain
X, the question would become how does X actually work? capacities, along with premature conclusions about their
What are the necessary ingredients of X and how did these absence, have appeared in major journals, such as the
evolve? We pursue this bottom-up perspective in this report that nonhuman primates do not care about the
article by reviewing recent research on future planning, welfare of others [4], a claim contradicted by subsequent
imitation and altruistic behavior to demonstrate how com- research (see the section on Prosocial behavior and empa-
plex capacities can often be broken down into components thy). Similarly, a failure to demonstrate that apes under-
that humans share not just with the apes, but also with a stand gravity has been taken to mean that only humans
host of other species. We argue that to document and possess such an understanding [5], even though it would
understand these components at the neural level should seem a rather adaptive capacity for arboreal primates,
be our highest priority. This approach, which has been which do in fact show signs of this [6]. Debates around
gaining ground in the last few years, will move the field of theory of mind and imitation have followed similar cycles of
comparative cognition towards an understanding of initial denial for nonhuman species based on negative
capacities in terms of underlying mechanisms and the evidence, with subsequent partial or complete acceptance
based on experimental paradigms with greater ecological
Corresponding author: de Waal, F.B.M. (dewaal@emory.edu). validity (see the section on Imitation).
1364-6613/$ – see front matter ß 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2010.03.003 Available online 1 April 2010 201
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol.14 No.5

The result is a literature of claims and counter-claims however, because our brain seems to be a linearly scaled-
regarding complex mental faculties with less of a focus on up primate brain [19]. Excessive attention to so-called
underlying mechanisms than on taxonomic dividing lines. higher cognitive functions and the corresponding neglect
Typical examples are the denial of imitation even in apes of subcortical processes in cognitive science have been
given that they fail to appreciate others as intentional criticized as ‘corticocentric myopia’ [20]. Some have gone
agents [7], claims of ‘humaniqueness’ (i.e. key differences so far as to label the fascination with uniquely human
between the cognition of humans and other animals) capacities as non-evolutionary, together with a warning
because animals lack the ability to combine old concepts against ‘hopeful monsters’, that is, the belief that a brief
into new ones [8], and the sweeping conclusion that ‘the evolutionary time interval could have produced a well-
functional discontinuity between human and nonhuman integrated set of novel capacities [21]. Every species, in-
minds pervades nearly every domain of cognition’ [9,p. cluding our own, comes with an enormous set of evolutio-
110]. narily ancient components of cognition that we need to
Others, however, have defended Darwin’s view of men- better understand before we can reasonably focus on what
tal continuity [10] or explained why cognitive similarity makes the cognition of each species special. Are cognitive
between distant species poses no problem for evolutionary specializations due to new capacities or rather to new
theory. Tool use, for example, might have evolved inde- combinations of old ones? Bottom-up approaches focus
pendently to serve extractive foraging in the great apes, on these building blocks and represent a new Zeitgeist
capuchin monkeys and New Caledonian crows. But even as reflected in the latest treatments of future planning
though a sound case for convergent evolution can be made [22], reciprocal altruism [23], theory of mind [24] and
[11], this does not necessarily imply independent neural comparative cognition in general [25]. Another good
mechanisms. The intriguing possibility exists of deep hom- example is the field of numerosity, which has moved from
ologies in the cognitive domain, much as shared genetic the all-or-nothing question ‘Can animals count?’ to a more
instructions underlie the eyes or limbs of animals as dis- diversified approach, noting how numerical skills are
tant as flies and rodents [12]. Re-evaluation of avian brain rooted in ‘nonlinguistic biological primitives’ [26].
evolution has indicated that even though a layer-like Cognitive capacities are never all-or-nothing phenom-
organization is absent from the pallium, this structure ena. Often they integrate a range of mechanisms and many
might nevertheless derive from the same reptilian telen- species can be expected to show some but not all those
cephalic structure as the mammalian neocortex [13]. If underlying theory of mind, self-awareness, culture,
both structures accomplish similar functions, many avian language, reciprocal altruism, planning, and so on. An
and mammalian cognitive capacities could share homolo- outcome-based science stresses differences, whereas a
gous mechanisms. focus on process makes one wonder how deep these differ-
The distinction between homology (i.e. shared ancestry) ences go and how outcomes are achieved. Theoretically, it
and analogy (i.e. independently evolved functional paral- is possible that different species achieve similar outcomes
lels) is less clear-cut in the cognitive domain than is often in different ways or use similar cognitive mechanisms to
assumed [5]. Developed by anatomists, this distinction is achieve different behavioral ends. Outcomes are important
easiest to apply to highly defined morphological and beha- from an evolutionary perspective in that they determine an
vioral traits with a traceable phylogeny, such as fixed organism’s success at dealing with its environment, but
action patterns and facial expressions [14]. The same from a cognitive perspective they are mere surface
distinction is much harder to apply to traits that escape phenomena. Unique outcomes do not always reflect unique
precise definition and measurement, such as cognitive processes. Even if humans produce cathedrals and sym-
capacities. Moreover, analogous traits often contain hom- phonies, the underlying processes include social learning,
ologous elements in the same way that the wings of birds tool use, musical appreciation, a sense of rhythm, and
and bats are products of convergent evolution yet contain large-scale synchronization and cooperation, all of which
homologous bones. When shaping cognitive capacities, we share with other animals.
evolution often seems to act on behavioral predispositions The dissection of basic components of cognition, now
and motivations while retaining core learning mechanisms more practicable with advanced technologies, aims to pro-
[15]. Only if we know their genetic and/or neural under- vide an understanding of how specific neural and beha-
pinnings can capacities be confidently classified as either vioral mechanisms contribute to the organization of a given
analogous or homologous. Recent research on face recog- cognitive process and whether the same mechanisms oper-
nition in humans and other primates, for example, strongly ate across species. Mirror neurons are a case in point (Box
suggests a shared neural background, and hence homology 1). Unfortunately, however, entire books and treatises on
[16,17]. Until more such evidence is available, the most animal intelligence barely mention neuroscience. With this
parsimonious Darwinian assumption is that if closely in mind, we briefly review three areas of cognition
related species – whether they be squid and octopus or research: memory and planning, imitation and prosocial
humans and apes – show similar solutions to similar behavior. Research in these areas is rapidly moving
problems, they probably involve similar cognitive mech- towards a bottom-up view in which mechanisms are cen-
anisms [18]. tral and species differences are less important.
The overwhelming tendency outside of biology to give
human cognition special treatment is commonly justified Remembering the past and planning for the future
by pointing to our outsized cerebral cortex. The latest Remembering specific personal experiences has been con-
neuroanatomical evidence lends little support to this view, sidered a sign of autonoetic consciousness that is uniquely

202
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol.14 No.5

Box 1. Mirror neurons and the bottom-up approach shared neural substrate for memory and action planning
[37]. Therefore, instead of viewing episodic memory and
The mental life of animals is considered the result of their unique
way of perceiving and integrating different types of sensory future orientation as advanced language-mediated pro-
information into a single framework to form an internal representa- cesses limited to humans, they should be considered as
tion. The merit of this cognitive approach has been in successfully part of the general memory and action organization found
comparing the sensory channels of different organisms and their to varying degrees in a wide range of species [22,38].
psychophysical properties and in clarifying how the perceptual
world is built and represented in an organism. However, this model
of how organisms perceive the world rests on the idea that Imitation
perceptual and motor functions are anatomically segregated in the Even though the population-specific traditions of wild
brain. It also emphasizes the perceptual system as the core system primates are commonly attributed to social learning,
for the analysis and representation of the external world. The primate imitation has become controversial ever since
discovery of neural mechanisms that combine action and percep-
tion, such as mirror neurons, has profoundly challenged this duality. the classical definition of imitation as ‘doing an act from
Mirror neurons were first found in the ventral premotor area F5 seeing it done’ [39] was replaced by a top-down definition
and subsequently in the inferior parietal lobe of macaques [27,28]. requiring a subject to understand the intentional structure
These neurons typically discharge both when a monkey performs a of another’s actions, such as the other’s goal and specific
motor act (e.g. grasping an object) and when it observes the same,
ways to achieve this goal [7,40]. Whereas apes and many
or a similar, act performed by an experimenter or another monkey.
The possibility of matching the visual description of a goal-directed other animals clearly exhibit imitation according to the old
act with its cortical motor representation could allow extraction of definition, the new definition has had the effect of exclud-
important information about another’s action, prompting the idea ing them (Box 2). Only humans have ‘true’ imitation, it was
that these neurons could be involved in action understanding. claimed.
Using brain imaging and transcranial magnetic stimulation tools,
However, the majority of studies failing to find ape
several human studies demonstrated the presence of a mirror
system involving the homolog premotor and parietal cortical areas imitation used human behavioral models. This is import-
[27], thus suggesting that this matching mechanism and its basic ant in light of the increasing view of imitation in neuro-
properties are a general part of primate brain evolution. Beyond science that places less emphasis on perceived
coding the goal of motor acts, recent neurophysiology shows that intentionality and more on the neural merging of percep-
mirror neurons also enable a monkey to discriminate between
similar actions with different goals. It is possible that these neurons
tion and action as a result of body mapping between
infer another’s intentions, or why an individual does something [29]. individuals. Given that body mapping relies on bodily
correspondence and is probably enhanced by social close-
ness and identification, models of a different species than
human [30] and includes the anticipation of future needs one’s own are unlikely to be optimal. Negative results can
and drive states [31]. Other animals, it was claimed, use be explained by this species barrier [41]. Once the extra
stored information merely to react to present stimuli or effort had been made to train conspecific models, the issue
anticipate the immediate future. of ape imitation was quickly settled to the point that major
Whereas autonoetic consciousness remains inaccessible skeptics have come around to this view. Exposed to models
in nonhuman animals, other aspects of the above claim of their own species, chimpanzees reliably and faithfully
have been challenged, starting with experiments on food- imitate tool use, foraging techniques and arbitrary action
caching birds. Western scrub jays seem to have precise sequences [42–44].
memories of past cashes, including the what, where and This leaves the question of whether ape imitation is
when characteristic of episodic memory [32]. Since then, based on an actual understanding of the model’s inten-
human episodic memory has been dissected with more tions. Even for human adults such understanding may not
sophisticated tools by neuroscientists. Increasing evidence be essential [45], so simpler processes are likely. Imitation
from neuroimaging and brain-damaged patients indicates probably stems from internal or external mimicry of
that remembering past events involves regions of the observed motor movements through shared neural repres-
hippocampus, parahippocampal gyrus and prefrontal cor- entations [27,46]. Externally visible mimicry in chimpan-
tex. Brain imaging shows that the same neural machinery zees is suggested by co-action, in which observers place
that serves the recollection of autobiographical events is their hand on the model’s hand or tool, thus gaining
recruited to make plans, perhaps by piecing together kinesthetic feedback of the other’s actions [44], or by
memories of past events to simulate the future. Thus, observers that move an empty hand in precise synchrony
episodic memory and planning rely on the same neural with a nut-cracking companion ‘consistent with a model of
structures [33]. imitation in which the imitator codes its observation of the
In this light, it is not surprising that the same birds said model immediately into a motoric representation’ [47].
to possess episodic-like memory also seem capable of future This would also explain why chimpanzees readily learn
planning, as reflected in storing food in anticipation of a solutions to problems from each other but not from
future hunger state, as opposed to being affected by their repeated demonstrations of the same solutions in the
current state [34]. The capacity to give future states absence of a real-life companion [48]. Primate imitation
priority over present preferences is also known for apes depends on inter-individual action coding and not on per-
[35] (but see Ref. [36]). Even rodents can show some of ceived modifications of the physical environment.
these capacities. A recent neurophysiological study found Neuroimaging and neurophysiological studies in
activity in a specific cell assembly of the rat hippocampus humans have shown that the cortical areas active during
during memory retrieval. The same assembly also predicts observation of another’s actions are homologous with those
future choices, suggesting that rats, like humans, use a containing mirror neurons in macaques [28,49]. These

203
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol.14 No.5

Box 2. Do monkeys ape? commonly presented as a quest for ‘true’ altruism, defined
as altruism without obvious advantages for the actor. From
The role of mirror neurons in imitation is sometimes questioned
because these neurons were discovered in monkeys, which lack this perspective, aid to offspring or kin hardly qualifies
imitation [52]. The latter statement is only true, however, if we (explained by kin selection) and any chance at reciproca-
narrowly define imitation in terms of the understanding of another’s tion by the beneficiary also disqualifies altruism as genu-
intentions or of copying complex novel sequences. By any other ine (explained by return benefits). But whereas these are
standard, monkeys do have imitative skills. In the wild, they show
socially learned cultural variation on a par with that of apes [53], and
critical distinctions in relation to the evolution of behavior,
in the laboratory they reliably copy a conspecific’s motor actions they hardly matter at the proximate level unless we
[54,55]. The tendency to do as others do is spontaneous, because assume that actors know about inclusive fitness and future
monkeys require no rewards for it [56]. There is also evidence of returns. Thus far, there is no evidence that they do. Since
neonatal imitation in monkeys [57] (Figure I) and an ability to one cannot want what one does not know about, altruistic
recognize when they are being imitated [58]. In sum, if action coding
is the essence of imitation, as argued here, monkeys most certainly motivations must stem from another source. Even animals
qualify as imitators. capable of learning the advantages of reciprocity can only
do so if they have a tendency to spontaneously help others
in the first place [59].
We must therefore assume an altruistic impulse inde-
pendent of incentives and long-term benefits. In one chim-
panzee study, the role of incentives was manipulated. The
apes spontaneously assisted humans and were also willing
to assist conspecifics, without altering their behavior de-
pendent on the availability of rewards [60]. Spontaneous
helping has also been experimentally demonstrated in
both marmosets [61] and capuchin monkeys [62,63]. In
both human and nonhuman primates altruistic behavior
correlates with socio-emotional connections between indi-
viduals, so the suggested motivational mechanism is
empathy [59] (Figure 1). Empathy leads to a stake in
another’s welfare, so that helping comes with an intrinsic
reward known in the human literature as the ‘warm glow’
effect. Humans report feeling good when they do good and
show activation of reward-related brain areas [64].
Empathy might be widespread in mammals. It is
thought to stem from an evolutionarily ancient percep-
tion–action mechanism, the most basic form of which is
state matching, also known as emotional contagion [65].
Figure I. Like human neonates, infant rhesus monkeys spontaneously mimic
the mouth movements of a human experimenter suggesting the early presence
of a neural mirroring system shared across species. Drawing by Frans de Waal
from Ref. [57].

neurons are usually tested in relation to existing behavior,


but can also mediate the acquisition of novel motor
sequences. Humans show activation of the same neural
areas of the mirror system during simple motor imitation,
as during imitation of novel behavior, thus suggesting that
copying of novel behavior recruits neural resources related
to the existing action repertoire [50].
Now that mirror neurons have also been found in birds,
it is assumed that the evolution of these neurons can be
traced back to the common ancestor of birds and mammals
[51]. Therefore, we should consider the theoretical possib-
ility that all imitation has a shared neural perception–
action foundation, from the vocal mimicry of birds to the
copying of foraging techniques by primates. This would
represent deep homology indeed.

Prosocial behavior and empathy


In the same way that the view of imitation went through a Figure 1. Chimpanzees frequently react to another’s need or distress with directed
altruism. Here, a mother, having heard her son’s screams, stretches out a hand to
phase in which some of its manifestations were considered
help him out of a tree. Recent experiments confirm that nonhuman primates care
more true than others, research on prosocial behavior is about the welfare of others, both kin and nonkin. Photograph by Frans de Waal.

204
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol.14 No.5

This mechanism has been demonstrated in mice [66] and is Box 3. Specific outstanding questions raised by the
being studied through yawn contagion in humans and bottom-up approach
other animals [67]. Like other forms of empathy, state
matching occurs most readily among bonded individuals  Homology: if distantly related species evolve similar cognitive
[66,68]. capacities to achieve similar ends (e.g. tool use in birds and
During observation of facial emotions, mirroring acti- primates) does this automatically mean that they use different
vation is present not only in human premotor areas, but neural mechanisms, or are their deep homologies in the neural
components of their respective capacities?
also in insular and cingulate cortices [69,70]. These areas  Linking imitation and empathy: even though imitation and
belong to neural circuits known for their involvement in empathy manifest themselves in quite different behavior, to what
visceromotor sensations related to unpleasant and painful degree do both rely on neural mechanisms of body mapping,
stimuli. When we observe a facial expression, motorically action coding and shared representation, and is this reflected in
similar expressions are unconsciously triggered, which are correlations at the individual or species level between both
capacities?
associated with corresponding emotions [71]. Thus, as with  Mirror system: what is actually mirrored in the mirror system of
imitation, basic empathy runs from body to body rather humans and other primates, actions, intentions or motor goals?
than from mind to mind [72]. How do mirror neurons work in parallel or in conjunction with
If empathy is indeed the main proximate mechanism of cognitive systems committed to inferential reasoning?
 Inner templates: how does sensory and motor information
so-called directed altruism (i.e. altruistic behavior in
converge during development to allow increasingly precise
response to another’s distress or need [59]), the cognitively matching between the two? This is important in relation to early
demanding assumption that acts of helping rest on cost– mirroring, such as neonatal imitation, in which matching occurs
benefit analyses needs to be replaced with a socio- without visual experience. Are animals born with an internal
emotional perspective. Altruistic behavior unexplained template of their bodies, both their own and others?
 Emotion recognition: a mirror-matching system concerning
by the first framework (e.g. humans sending money to
visceromotor reactions seems to be present within the human
distant victims of natural disasters) often does fit the limbic system. Might this constitute an ancient mechanism – as
second, a mechanism that might have evolved in social old as the mammals, if not the vertebrates – for the automatic
animals through individual selection rather than kin or recognition of another’s emotional state?
group selection [73].

Concluding remarks to the behavior of others to perspective-taking that


If there is one general trend in the field of comparative becomes increasingly complex with increasing brain size.
cognition, it is the rapid accumulation of evidence that The latter allows some species to gear their helping
more and more organisms show signs of any given capacity. behavior specifically to another’s situation and need.
In all areas discussed (i.e. episodic memory, planning, The most advanced forms of imitation and empathy are
imitation and prosocial behavior), initial claims that likely to encompass and build on more basic forms – and
humans, or at least hominoids, are special have had to hence remain connected to the core mechanism – so our
be revised when related capacities were discovered in terminology should strive for conceptual unity rather
other, sometimes taxonomically quite distant, species. than drive wedges between types.
De novo appearances of cognitive capacities are apparently In every given domain, functional refinements have
as unlikely as de novo anatomical features. evolved as adaptations to the ecology of a species, the study
Rather than focus on the pinnacles of cognition, the of which is critical for an evolutionary cognitive science.
field of comparative cognition seems to be moving The most logical route for comparative cognition, however,
towards a bottom-up perspective focused on the nuts is to try to understand the basic processes and common
and bolts of cognition, including underlying neural mech- denominators first before exploring species-typical special-
anisms (see Box 3). Most mechanisms are evolutionarily izations.
ancient, tying together phenomena such as bird song
learning and the cultural acquisition of tool use in Acknowledgments
primates and the prosocial behavior of both humans The authors are grateful to Sara Shettleworth and two anonymous
and other mammals. This does not mean that distinctions reviewers for constructive comments that helped to strengthen the
manuscript.
between taxonomic groups are irrelevant or that there is
no point to finer-grained classifications. But it does
References
suggest that, instead of dividing imitation into one ‘true’ 1 Gardner, R.A. and Gardner, B.T. (1969) Teaching sign language to a
form and other forms – which apparently do not deserve chimpanzee. Science 165, 664–672
the name – the most fruitful approach would be to return 2 Terrace, H.S. (1979) Nim, Knopf
to the classical definition and include all forms of imita- 3 Bolhuis, J.J. and Wynne, C.D.L. (2009) Can evolution explain how
minds work? Nature. 458, 832–833
tion in a single framework. Various forms of imitation can
4 Silk, J.B. et al. (2005) Chimpanzees are indifferent to the welfare of
then be distinguished according to the function they serve unrelated group members. Nature 437, 1357–1359
in the lives of animals, the stimuli that determine their 5 Povinelli, D.J. (2000) Folk Physics for Apes: The Chimpanzee’s Theory of
occurrence (i.e. body actions, perceived goals, changes How the World Works, Oxford University Press
produced in the environment) and the underlying cogni- 6 Hauser, M.D. et al. (2001) What guides a search for food that has
disappeared? Experiments on cotton-top tamarins. J. Comp. Psychol.
tive processes as part of the even larger category of social 115, 140–151
learning. The same applies to empathy, which ranges all 7 Tomasello, M. (1999) The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition,
the way from automatic emotional activation in response Harvard University Press

205
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol.14 No.5

8 Hauser, M.D. (2009) The possibility of impossible cultures. Nature 460, 39 Thorndike, E.L. (1898) Animal intelligence: an experimental study of
190–196 the associate processes in animals. Psychol. Rev. Monogr. Suppl. 2,
9 Penn, D.C. and Povinelli, D.J. (2007) On the lack of evidence 551–553
that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a 40 Whiten, A. and Ham, R. (1992) On the nature and evolution of
‘‘theory of mind’’. Philos Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 362, imitation in the animal kingdom: reappraisal of a century of
731–744 research. In Advances in the Study of Behavior (Vol. 21) (Slater,
10 de Waal, F.B.M. (2009) Darwin’s last laugh. Nature 460, 175 J.B. et al., eds), In pp. 239–283, Academic Press
11 Emery, N.J. and Clayton, N.S. (2004) The mentality of crows: 41 de Waal, F.B.M. (2001) The Ape and the Sushi Master, Basic Books
convergent evolution of intelligence in corvids and apes. Science 306, 42 Whiten, A. et al. (2005) Conformity to cultural norms of tool use in
1903–1907 chimpanzees. Nature 437, 737–740
12 Shubin, N. et al. (2009) Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary 43 Bonnie, K.E. et al. (2006) Spread of arbitrary conventions among
novelty. Nature 457, 818–823 chimpanzees: a controlled experiment. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol.
13 Jarvis, E.D. et al. (2005) Avian Brain Nomenclature Consortium. Avian Sci. 274, 367–372
brains and a new understanding of vertebrate brain evolution. Nat. 44 Horner, V. and de Waal, F.B.M. (2009) Controlled studies of
Rev. Neurosci. 6, 151–159 chimpanzee cultural transmission. Prog. Brain Res. 178, 3–15
14 Preuschoft, S. and van Hooff, J.A.R.A.M. (1995) Homologizing primate 45 Horowitz, A.C. (2003) Do humans ape? Or do apes human? Imitation
facial displays: a critical review of methods. Folia Primatol. 65, 121– and intention in humans (Homo sapiens) and other animals. J. Comp.
137 Psychol. 117, 325–336
15 Papini, M.R. (2002) Pattern and process in the evolution of learning. 46 Decety, J. and Chaminade, T. (2003) When the self represents the
Psychol. Rev. 109, 186–201 other: a new cognitive neuroscience view on psychological
16 Tsao, D.Y. et al. (2008) Comparing face patch systems in macaques and identification. Conscious Cogn. 12, 577–596
humans. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 105, 19514–19519 47 Marshall-Pescini, S. and Whiten, A. (2008) Social learning of
17 Parr, L.A. et al. (2009) Face processing in the chimpanzee brain. Curr. nut-cracking behavior in East African sanctuary-living
Biol. 19, 50–53 chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes schweinfurthii). J. Comp. Psychol.
18 de Waal, F.B.M. (1999) Anthropomorphism and anthropodenial: 122, 186–194
consistency in our thinking about humans and other animals. 48 Hopper, L. et al. (2007) Experimental studies of traditions and
Philos. Top. 27, 255–280 underlying transmission processes in chimpanzees. Anim. Behav.
19 Herculano-Houzel, S. (2009) The human brain in numbers: A linearly 73, 1021–1032
scaled-up primate brain. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 3, 1–11 49 Iacoboni, M. (2005) Neural mechanisms of imitation. Curr. Opin.
20 Parvizi, J. (2009) Corticocentric myopia: old bias in new cognitive Neurobiol. 15, 632–637
sciences. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 354–359 50 Iacoboni, M. (2009) Imitation, empathy, and mirror neurons. Annu.
21 Margoliash, D. and Nusbaum, H.C. (2009) Language: the perspective Rev. Psychol. 60, 653–670
from organismal biology. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 505–510 51 Prather, J.F. et al. (2008) Precise auditory–vocal mirroring in neurons
22 Raby, C.R. and Clayton, N.S. (2009) Prospective cognition in animals. for learned vocal communication. Nature 451, 305–310
Behav. Processes 80, 314–324 52 Visalberghi, E. and Fragaszy, D.M. (1990) Do monkeys ape? In
23 Brosnan, S.F. and de Waal, F.B.M. (2002) A proximate perspective on ‘‘Language’’ and Intelligence in Monkeys and Apes: Comparative
reciprocal altruism. Hum. Nat. 13, 129–152 Developmental Perspectives (Parker, S. and Gibson, K., eds), pp.
24 Call, J. and Tomasello, M. (2008) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of 247–273, Cambridge University Press
mind? 30 years later. Trends Cogn. Sci. 12, 187–192 53 Perry, S. et al. (2003) Social conventions in wild white-faced capuchin
25 Shettleworth, S.J. (2010) Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior, (2nd monkeys: evidence for traditions in a neotropical primate. Curr.
edn), Oxford University Press Anthropol. 44, 241–268
26 Nieder, A. and Dehaene, S. (2009) Representation of number in the 54 Voelkl, B. and Huber, L. (2007) Imitation as faithful copying of a novel
brain. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 32, 185–208 technique in marmoset monkeys. PLoS ONE 2 (7), e611
27 Rizzolatti, G. and Craighero, L. (2004) The mirror-neuron system. 55 Dindo, M. et al. (2010) Conditional copying fidelity in capuchin
Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 27, 169–192 monkeys (Cebus apella). J. Comp. Psychol. 124, 29–37
28 Ferrari, P.F. et al. (2009) From monkey mirror neurons to mirror- 56 Bonnie, K.E. and de Waal, F.B.M. (2007) Copying without rewards:
related behaviours: possible direct and indirect pathways. Philos. socially influenced foraging decisions among brown capuchin monkeys.
Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 364, 2311–2323 Anim. Cogn. 10, 283–292
29 Fogassi, L. et al. (2005) Parietal lobe: from action organization to 57 Ferrari, P.F. et al. (2006) Neonatal imitation in rhesus macaques. PLoS
intention understanding. Science 308, 662–667 Biol. 4, e302
30 Tulving, E. (2005) Episodic memory and autonoesis: uniquely human? 58 Paukner, A. et al. (2009) Capuchin monkeys display affiliation toward
In The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective humans who imitate them. Science 325, 880–883
Consciousness (Terrace, H.S. and Metcalfe, J., eds), pp. 3–56, Oxford 59 de Waal, F.B.M. (2008) Putting the altruism back into altruism: the
University Press evolution of empathy. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59, 279–300
31 Suddendorf, T. and Corballis, M. (1997) Mental time travel and the 60 Warneken, F. et al. (2007) Spontaneous altruism by chimpanzees and
evolution of the human mind. Genet. Soc. Gen. Psychol. Monogr. 123, young children. PLoS Biol. 5, e184
133–167 61 Burkart, J.M. et al. (2007) Other-regarding preferences in a non-
32 Clayton, N.S. et al. (2003) Can animals recall the past and plan for the human primate: common marmosets provision food altruistically.
future? Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 4, 685–691 Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 104, 19762–19766
33 Schacter, D.L. et al. (2007) Remembering the past to imagine the 62 de Waal, F.B.M. et al. (2008) Giving is self-rewarding for monkeys.
future: the prospective brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 8, 657–661 Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 105, 13685–13689
34 Correia, S.P.C. et al. (2007) Western scrub-jays anticipate future needs 63 Lakshminarayanan, V.R. and Santos, L.R. (2008) Capuchin monkeys
independently of their current motivational state. Curr. Biol. 17, 856– are sensitive to others’ welfare. Curr. Biol. 18, R999–R1000
861 64 Harbaugh, W.T. et al. (2007) Neural responses to taxation and
35 Osvath, M. and Osvath, H. (2008) Chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes) and voluntary giving reveal motives for charitable donations. Science
orangutan (Pongo abelii) forethought: self-control and pre-experience 316, 1622–1625
in the face of future tool use. Anim. Cogn. 11, 661–674 65 Preston, S.D. and de Waal, F.B.M. (2002) Empathy: its ultimate and
36 Suddendorf, T. et al. (2009) How great is great ape foresight? Anim. proximate bases. Behav. Brain Sci. 25, 1–72
Cogn. 12, 751–754 66 Langford, D.J. et al. (2006) Social modulation of pain as evidence for
37 Pastalkova, E. et al. (2008) Internally generated cell assembly empathy in mice. Science 312, 1967–1970
sequences in the rat hippocampus. Science 321, 1322–1327 67 Campbell, M.W. et al. (2009) Computer animations stimulate
38 Crystal, J.D. (2009) Elements of episodic-like memory in animal contagious yawning in chimpanzees. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci.
models. Behav. Processes 80, 269–277 276, 4255–4259

206
Opinion Trends in Cognitive Sciences Vol.14 No.5

68 Palagi, E. et al. (2009) Contagious yawning in gelada baboons as a 71 Dimberg, U. et al. (2000) Unconscious facial reactions to emotional
possible expression of empathy. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 106, facial expressions. Psychol. Sci. 11, 86–89
19262–19267 72 Niedenthal, P.M. (2007) Embodying emotion. Science 316, 1002–
69 Wicker, B. et al. (2003) Both of us disgusted in my insula: the common 1005
neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40, 655–664 73 Akçay, E. et al. (2009) A theory for the evolution of other-regard
70 Singer, T. et al. (2004) Empathy for pain involves the affective but not integrating proximate and ultimate perspectives. Proc. Natl. Acad.
sensory components of pain. Science 303, 1157–1162 Sci. U. S. A. 106, 19061–19066

207

You might also like