FosterHollemanClark MarxandSlavery

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 23

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/342614490

Marx and Slavery

Article in Monthly review (New York, N.Y.: 1949) · July 2020


DOI: 10.14452/MR-072-03-2020-07_9

CITATIONS READS

4 3,712

3 authors, including:

Hannah Holleman Brett Clark


Amherst College University of Utah
26 PUBLICATIONS 429 CITATIONS 176 PUBLICATIONS 4,214 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Energy, Technology, and Environmental Management View project

Reading Marx's Capital View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Brett Clark on 13 July 2020.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


monthlyreviewarchives.org
DOI: 10.14452/MR-072-03-2020-07_9

Marx and Slavery


JOHN BELLAMY FOSTER, HANNAH HOLLEMAN,
and BRETT CLARK

The rise to prominence of analyses of racial capitalism, building in par-


ticular on Cedric Robinson’s Black Marxism, along with the work of earlier
figures such as W. E. B. Du Bois and Oliver Cromwell Cox, represents
a breakthrough in Marxian theory.1 This has necessarily been accompa-
nied by a critique of previous Marxian analyses, which all too often ig-
nored or minimized the relation of slavery to capitalism.2 In recent years,
however, these criticisms of orthodox Marxist treatments of slavery have
been extended, much more problematically, to the work of Karl Marx
himself, who is sometimes said to have systematically circumvented and
downplayed the question of the significance of slave labor for capitalist
development, seeing the issue of slavery as largely confined to the mer-
cantilist era of “so-called primitive accumulation” and the height of the
transatlantic slave trade. Slavery continued to exist, it is suggested, but
Marx excised it from his analysis of capital itself.3
Thus, historian Stephanie Smallwood, author of Saltwater Slavery, has
written that “we have long since dismissed Marx’s misunderstanding
of slavery” as a historical “error,” which led him “to hold New World
slavery apart from capitalism.”4 Likewise, Walter Johnson, historian of
U.S. slavery and author of River of Dark Dreams, contends in his influen-
tial article “The Pedestal and the Veil: Rethinking the Capitalism/Slavery
Question” that Marx “simply evaded” the whole “question of slavery”
in his critique of capital, adhering to the “foundational exclusion of the
fact of slavery from the framing of political economy” that characterized
the work of classical-liberal economics.5
Yet, Marx is not easily set aside in any serious attempt to develop an
analysis of racial capitalism. Thus, after arguing that Marx had largely
excluded the question of slavery in Capital, Johnson indicates that we still
“have an enormous amount to learn from what Marx had to tell us about
the work of capitalists as we try to diagram the historical interconnec-
tions and daily practices of the global economy of the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries.”6 But this admission on his part raises the question

John Bellamy Foster is editor of Monthly Review and a professor of sociology at the
University of Oregon. Hannah Holleman is a director of the Monthly Review Foun-
dation and an associate professor of sociology at Amherst College. Brett Clark is
associate editor of Monthly Review and a professor of sociology at the University of Utah.

96
M arx and S lavery 97

of what a much more comprehensive look at Marx’s work as a whole,


informed by his entire historical-materialist frame of analysis and the
underlying structure of his critique of political economy, would reveal.
Such a method entails going beyond singling out a few select passages in
the first volume of Capital and placing them in a much wider and deeper
context. Indeed, we argue in what follows that Marx still has a great deal
to offer in the analysis of slavery, and especially of “slavery’s capitalism.”7
It is worth noting that Marx’s treatment of slavery or slave labor systems is
wide-ranging and profound, encompassing, in varying detail, such elements
as ancient Greek and Roman slavery; the question of the slave mode of pro-
duction; debt slavery; the enslavement of Native Americans; child slavery;
domestic slavery; slavery in England under Edward VI; slavery in the Dutch
East Indies; the transatlantic slave trade; the rise of slavery as a “second type
of colonialism”; torture under slavery; slavery as the basis of the Industri-
al Revolution; slave rebellions; the Haitian Revolution; the “Slave Power”
in the U.S. South; the Dred Scott decision; the Kansas-Missouri border war
of 1854–56; John Brown; Harriet Beecher Stowe; abolitionism; the revolu-
tionary struggle of freed Black soldiers in the Civil War; and the complex
historical relations between slave labor and wage labor. Marx’s analysis of
slaveowner capitalism in the antebellum South examined the capitalization
of the anticipated surplus value generated by slave labor as the basis of a
distinctive system of accumulation, including its role in the development of
capitalist management. He explored the ecological destruction and expan-
sionism built into the very nature of the “peculiar institution.”8
In his political organization within the British labor movement, Marx
played a key role, as witnessed by Henry Adams, in mobilizing workers
to prevent the country from entering into the U.S. Civil War on the side
of the Confederacy.9 As the leading figure in the International Working
Men’s Association, he corresponded with presidents Abraham Lincoln
and Andrew Johnson. In his role as the correspondent for the New York
Daily Tribune and later Die Presse in Vienna, he supported the revolutionary
abolitionist movement in the United States and the North in its war with
the Slave South, writing more than forty published newspaper articles
on slavery and the U.S. Civil War in 1861 and 1862 (along with numer-
ous others that were not published and are not extant). No other major
thinker of his time wrote so variously on slavery when his whole body
of work is taken into account, and perhaps none, except Frederick Dou-
glass, commented so profoundly on U.S. slavery. As Roger Ransom and
Richard Sutch observed in the opening sentence of their classic article
“Capitalists Without Capital,” “Karl Marx recognized the capitalist nature
of American slavery long before American historians.”10
98 M O NTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

Marx’s research into slavery was extensive, going beyond general polit-
ical economy and including explorations in capitalism, colonialism, and
slavery via such works as: Henry Brougham, An Inquiry into the Colonial Policy
of the European Powers (1803); Thomas Stamford Raffles, History of Java (1817);
François-Charles-Louis Comte, Traité de législation (1837); William Howitt,
Colonization and Christianity (1838); Thomas Fowell Buxton, The African Slave
Trade and Its Remedy (1840); Herman Merivale, Letters on Colonization and
Colonies (1841); J. F. W. Johnston, Notes on North America (1851); Henry Carey,
The Slave Trade, Domestic and Foreign (1853); Frederick Law Olmsted, A Jour-
ney in the Seaboard Slave States; With Remarks on the Economy (1856); and J. E.
Cairnes, The Slave Power (1862).11
Although Marx never wrote a treatise on slavery, the issue of slave
labor was woven into his analysis of social formations, both ancient and
modern, and was inextricably intertwined with his treatment of wage
labor. Marx’s studies of slavery under capitalism came to a head in the
late 1850s and early ’60s when he was simultaneously considering slav-
ery, often on a daily basis, engaging with the issue politically (including
helping organize meetings of the British working class in support of the
North in the U.S. Civil War), and writing the manuscripts (The Econom-
ic Manuscript of 1861–1863 and the Economic Manuscript of 1864–1865) that
would be the basis of Capital. Marx began the actual drafting of volume
one of Capital in January–February 1866, after the slave power in the
United States had already been defeated, a victory over slavery that is
celebrated in the preface to that work.12
The result was the formation in Marx’s work of a unique understand-
ing of slaveowner capitalism as a variant of capitalism and colonial-
ism. In fact, he understood slaveowner capitalism as the product of
a second colonialism, rooted in the plantation economy. This second
colonialism, he recognized, had immense implications for capitalist
development. In relation to the antebellum South, Marx wrote, “where
the capitalist conception prevails, as on American plantations,” slavery
takes the form of the production of “surplus value…conceived as prof-
it” on the backs of the slaves.13
Marx of course was aware that these fundamental issues did not au-
tomatically come to an end when the slave power in the United States
was finally defeated. As Du Bois declared in Black Reconstruction: “In 1865,
September, another address [this time to the American people as a whole]
over the signature of Marx declared boldly: ‘Injustice against a fraction
of your people having been followed by such dire consequences, put an
end to it. Declare your fellow citizens from this day forth free and equal,
without any reserve. If you refuse them citizens’ rights while you exact
M arx and S lavery 99

from them citizens’ duties, you will sooner or later face a new struggle
which will once more drench your country in blood.’”14

Th e Pe d e s t a l a n d t he Vei l
Perhaps the most incisive criticism of Marx on slavery in the last couple
of decades is Johnson’s “The Pedestal and the Veil,” in which it is pointed
out that in most accounts “slavery serves as an un-theorized historical
backdrop to the history of capitalism, an un-thought (even when present)
past to the inevitable emergence of the present.”15 According to Johnson,
Marx was particularly to blame in steering the critique of slavery in the
wrong direction in this respect. In his treatment of slavery in his chapter
on “The Genesis of the Industrial Capitalist” in volume one of Capital,
Marx pronounced, “In fact the veiled slavery of the wage-labourers in
Europe needed the unqualified slavery of the New World as its pedestal.”
Most readers of the pedestal and veil passage, as Johnson indicates, would
undoubtedly have seen it as a statement on the historical importance
of slavery for the development of capitalism. Turning this on its head,
however, Johnson insists that the real meaning of Marx’s metaphor was
structural and spatial: that naked, unqualified slavery in his analysis was
significant only insofar as it pointed to the “veiled slavery” of wage labor,
which then attained supreme importance.16
The notion that Marx might have created a dialectical metaphor de-
signed to highlight the historical significance of direct slavery as a cru-
cial element in capitalist development, while also pointing, after the
U.S. Civil War had concluded, to the continuing indirect slavery of wage
labor, is simply not considered in Johnson’s account. Yet, Marx’s actual
focus on slavery in and of itself is abundantly clear when the passage is
read in context. Thus, Marx footnoted the pedestal and veil statement
with a citation to Brougham’s An Inquiry into the Colonial Policy of the Eu-
ropean Powers, indicating that “in 1790 there were in the English West
Indies ten slaves to one free man, in the French fourteen to one, and
in the Dutch twenty three to one.”17 On the same page, Marx indicated
that the direct dependence of the British Industrial Revolution on New
World slavery could be seen in the growth in the number of slave ships:
“In 1730 Liverpool employed 15 ships in the slave trade; in 1751, 53; in
1760, 74; in 1770, 96; and in 1792, 132.” In the dozen pages preceding this
in the same chapter, he referred to “the extirpation, enslavement and
entombment in mines of the indigenous population” of the Americas,
“the conversion of Africa into a preserve for the commercial hunting of
blackskins,” slavery in the Dutch East Indies and in the West Indies, and
the commercialization of slavery in the United States.18
100 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

Given the depth with which he approached the issue of the slave trade
here as well as elsewhere in his analysis, Marx could hardly be said to be
referring to slavery, as Johnson contends, simply for “rhetorical effect”
in a critique of wage labor.19 A statement that literally and figuratively
emphasized how the capitalism of wage labor rested on the capitalism of
slave labor is turned, in Johnson’s interpretation, on its veiled head. It is as
if the pedestal itself was meant to stand, in Marx’s eyes, for a mere pedestal
and not for material relations. Johnson’s “The Pedestal and the Veil” has sub-
sequently been cited by other scholars in the analysis of racial capitalism
as evidence that Marx downgraded the reality of New World slavery.20
Given the importance of these issues, it is worthwhile to consider the
classical origins of the pedestal and veil metaphor. Marx, who was a leading
scholar in ancient Greek and Roman thought, knew the work of Plutarch
backward and forward, including Plutarch’s Moralia, which he referred
to in his dissertation. He was therefore well acquainted with Plutarch’s
description of the statue of Isis, goddess of nature, that the ancient Greek
philosopher saw in Sais, Egypt, with the famous, enigmatic inscription
on its pedestal: “I am all that has been, and is, and shall be, and my robe
[often translated as veil] no mortal has yet uncovered.”21 In the Enlighten-
ment, it became customary to depict a statue of a veiled Isis on a pedestal,
with the rendering of the veil constituting a symbol of enlightenment
itself and the discovery of material nature. G. W. F. Hegel commenced his
Philosophy of Nature by referring to the inscription on the pedestal of the
veiled Isis, arguing against the notion of the inscrutable noumena that the
veil could be torn aside to uncover the sensuous reality and true meaning
of nature necessary for the development of the absolute idea.22
In referring to the pedestal and veil metaphor, Marx was therefore trans-
forming a metaphor known to all educated persons in his time, using it
to reassert the materialist critique and emphasize that all “civilization” (or
class society), including its latest form under capitalism, had been built on
slavery. Wage labor under capitalism, or “veiled slavery,” symbolized by the
African goddess Isis, came into being materially and was dependent for its
material foundations on the naked slavery formed by the transatlantic slave
trade. None of this downplayed the horrors of slavery or its historical im-
portance in the development of capitalism. More than simply a “rhetorical
effect” or an attempt to discount the significance of slavery proper, by rel-
egating it to a pedestal, Marx was emphasizing that slavery constituted the
material form upon which the industrial proletariat itself had emerged, and
that the legacy of slavery would persist through a long era of reconstruction
and class struggle. It was thus foundational to the critique of capital, which
was about the whip as well as wages, the plantation as well as the factory.23
M arx and S lavery 101

Marx’s analysis of slavery evolved in definite stages from the 1840s to


the 1860s, moving from a consideration in the 1840s of capitalism’s de-
pendency on slavery, to a notion of slaveowner capitalism in the 1850s,
and to a mature political economy of slavery in the 1860s in the years of
the U.S. Civil War. Nevertheless, his emphasis on what he conceived of as
the second colonialism associated with the plantation economy, which
he stressed was an integral part of the historical development of capital-
ism, is continuous throughout his analysis. As he wrote as early as 1847
in The Poverty of Philosophy: “Direct slavery is just as much the pivot of
bourgeois industry as machinery, credits, etc. Without slavery you have
no cotton; without cotton you have no modern industry. It is slavery that
gave the colonies their value; it is the colonies that created world trade,
and it is world trade that is the pre-condition of large-scale industry. Thus,
slavery is an economic category of the greatest importance.”24
Central to Marx’s treatment of modern slavery was the recognition of
the absolutely horrific nature of slaveowner capitalism, which made it
worse than all other forms of slavery known in history. The “lash” and
the “barter of human flesh” were especially integral parts of New World
capitalist exploitation.25 Marx explained that the history of civilization
took its most “frightful” forms where slavery was combined with com-
mercialism (for example, in the ancient mines for precious metals de-
scribed by Diodorus Siculus).26 This was particularly the case where slave
labor was embedded within “a situation of capitalist production; thus, for
example, the southern states of the American Union.”27
A crucial concern was the high mortality rates of slave labor under the
capitalist plantation system. Slavery by its very nature, for Marx, took
the form of continual violence and the perpetual fear of torture and
premature death. Slaves were both capital assets and labor. The rules
of profit maximization in the slave economy, when there was an ac-
tive slave trade capable of very rapid replacement of human chattel, led
to the frequent application of a seven years rule, viewed by the planters
as the average life of their slaves, on which their computations of val-
ue were based. Slaves were so overworked in Jamaica and other British
colonies that their lives were generally consumed in seven years. For
the slave-owning capitalist, it was of relatively little significance if the
turnover of slaves through premature exhaustion of their working lives
and existence took place as long as they were easily replaceable. Fur-
thermore, under slave production, it was possible to work slaves more
intensively, superexploiting them, than in the case of wage labor.28
As Marx exclaimed, “If the overwork extends over a long period the
worker will perhaps only preserve himself and therefore his labour ca-
102 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

pacity for 7 years instead of the 20 or 30 years for which he might other-
wise have preserved it.” In the case of slave labor, such conditions were
prevalent, as opposed to even the most extreme forms of free wage labor.
“The slaves in the southern states of North America had to perform to
separate the cotton wool from its seed, after they had worked in the fields
for 12 hours, [which] reduced their average life expectancy to 7 years.”29
He quoted an article condemning the Virginia and Carolina planters from
the Daily Telegraph in 1860, in which it was asked: “What can be thought of
a town which holds a public meeting to petition that the period of labour
for men [slaves] shall be diminished to 18 hours a day?”30
In a similar condemnation of the disregard for human lives, Marx re-
marked that the shipment of so-called Chinese “coolies” to the Chincha
islands off the coast of Peru to dig guano in the 1850s was a condition
even “worse than slavery.” While their contracts generally specified eight
years of labor, 100 percent of the guano diggers failed to live to the end
of their contracts. As the Times of London reported in 1882, “The horrors
to which the Chinese coolies were formerly exposed were worse than the
worst excesses of American slavery. In 1860 it was believed that not one
of…the four thousand Chinese coolies who had been shipped to those
islands since the trade began, in 1844, had survived, all those who had not
died of exhaustion had put themselves voluntarily to death.”31
Such conditions of overwork, and grossly reduced life expectancy, pre-
vailed in the West Indies prior to the elimination of the slave trade, and
later in the slave plantations of the U.S. South when incorporated in a
major way into the world capitalist economy with the development of
the cotton industry and the Industrial Revolution in Britain.32 As Marx
put it, referring to both the U.S. South and the West Indies,
Considerations of economy…once trading in slaves is practiced, become rea-
sons for racking to the uttermost the toil of the slave; for, when his place can
at once be supplied from foreign preserves, the duration of his life becomes
a matter of less moment than its productiveness while it lasts. It is according-
ly a maxim of slave management, in slave importing countries [such as the
antebellum United States—legally before 1808, illegally after], that the most
effective economy is that which takes out of the human chattel in the short-
est space of time the utmost amount of exertion it is capable of putting forth.
It is in tropical culture, where annual profits often equal the whole capital of
plantations, that negro life is most recklessly sacrificed. It is the agriculture of
the West Indies, which has been for centuries prolific of fabulous wealth, that
has engulfed millions of the African race. It is Cuba, at this day, whose reve-
nues are reckoned by millions, and whose planters are princes, that we see in
the servile class, the coarsest fare, the most exhausting and unremitting toil,
and even the absolute destruction of a portion of its numbers every year.33
M arx and S lavery 103

In this sense, slavery under capitalism was far more brutal, in Marx’s
view, than anything ever seen before in human history. As “the export
of cotton became of vital interest to those states [the Southern United
States], the over-working of the Negro, and sometimes the consumption
of his life in seven years of labour, became a factor in a calculated and
calculating system. It was no longer a question of obtaining from him a
certain quantity of useful products [as in earlier more patriarchal forms
of slavery], but rather of the production of surplus-value itself.”34
Marx studied Carey’s The Slave Trade, Domestic and Foreign, which, after
providing detailed statistics on the importation of slaves in the various
British West Indian colonies, and their birth and death rates, had declared
that “we…find ourselves forced to the conclusion that slavery was here
attended with a destruction of life almost without a parallel in the history
of any civilized nation.”35 As Marx noted, the mortality rate of slaves in
the West Indies was so high that the slave population actually declined in
many areas despite the massive importation of slaves, of which as many
as “two-thirds of the number annually imported perished.”36
Not only was such “absolute destruction” of the slaves, as Marx put it,
a consequence of slavery, in the West Indies and in parts of Latin Ameri-
ca, but it was accompanied by the most inhuman tortures on top of the
“whip of the slave driver.” Thus, he referred to the use of the “spanso
bocko—one of the most cruel forms of punishment…used by the colo-
nists in Surinam,” as depicted in John Gabriel Stedman’s Narrative of a
Five Years’ Expedition Against the Revolted Negroes of Surinam and recounted
by Comte in his Traité de législation.37 In Marx’s words, a slave was “trussed
up in the spanso bocko torture of Surinam, unable to move hand or foot,
or any other of his limbs, and has to put up with everything done to
him.” Here he cited Comte on the defiance of slaves under such torture,
pointing to how they “scoff at their torturers” and “jeer at the latter’s
impotence even to force them to humble themselves, and they suppress
every ‘groan’ and every sigh, as long as the physical pain permits them
to do so.”38 In various parts of his work, Marx alluded to the slave revolts
and revolutions in Suriname, Haiti, and the United States, and the exis-
tence of runaways who banded together, determined to resist the “bar-
baric horrors of slavery.”39 Marx also took note of the post-slavery revolts
and colonial brutality in Jamaica.40 Commenting on Howitt’s discussion
of the barbarities of settler colonialism and Comte’s accounts of torture
under West Indian slavery, Marx observed in Capital: “This stuff ought
to be studied in detail, to see what the bourgeois makes of himself and
of the world when he can model the world according to his own image
without interreference” as under colonialism and slavery.41
104 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

It was the rapid “consumption” of the slave—as it was referred to by


political economists at the time—that, in Marx’s view, made the perpet-
uation of the world slave trade necessary for as long as possible, if the
capitalist slave system was to persist. Through his reading of Buxton’s The
African Slave and Its Remedy and Cairnes’s The Slave Power, Marx was well
aware that the transatlantic slave trade continued illegally even with the
British abolition of the slave trade in 1807 and the U.S. banning of the
trade in 1808. He quoted Stephen Douglas as saying in 1859, “During the
last year more Negroes have been imported from Africa than ever be-
fore in any single year, even at the time the slave trade was still legal.”42
Moreover, in the United States, Marx stressed, another solution had also
come into being: the active breeding of slaves in the border states such as
Virginia and Kentucky, providing the slave labor for the remainder of the
South. As a result, well into the 1860s, the absolute expropriation of human
beings through slavery remained the pedestal of the system, the basis on
which arose the veiled exploitation of wage labor.

The Po lit ic a l E c o no my o f Sl a veo wner Capitalism


It was not until the late 1850s in the Grundrisse and the 1860s in his Eco-
nomic Manuscript of 1861–1863 and Capital that Marx, as a result of his stud-
ies of political economy, was able to develop a full critique of the exploita-
tion of slave labor under modern capitalism. It was in this period that he
solidified his view of slaveowner capitalism as a particular form of capi-
talism, resulting from a “second type” of colonialism. For Marx, and for
classical political economists in general, colonialism proper (in Spanish
colono/a means settler), insofar as it pertained to labor, was usually asso-
ciated with the violent occupation of land by free laborers and peasant
proprietors engaged primarily in local and subsistence production.43 But
a second colonialism, not to be confused with colonialism proper, also
emerged, equally bathed in blood, in the form of the slave-plantation
economy. As he put it in Theories of Surplus Value:
In the second type of colonies—plantations—where commercial specula-
tions figure from the start and production is intended for the world mar-
ket, the capitalist mode of production exists, although only in a formal
sense, since the slavery of Negroes precludes free wage-labour, which is
the basis of capitalist production [as a whole]. But the business in which
slaves are used is conducted by capitalists. The method of production which
they introduce has not arisen out of slavery but is grafted on it. In this case,
the same person is capitalist and landowner.44

New World plantation slavery, Marx specified, was capitalist in form and
carried out by capitalists connected to the world economy, but it was not
M arx and S lavery 105

the primary form of capitalism, which was necessarily based on the expro-
priation of wage labor, on which the entire value structure of capitalism
was erected. “Slavery,” he wrote in the Grundrisse, “is possible at individual
points within the bourgeois system of production…only because it does
not exist at other points; and appears as an anomaly opposite the bour-
geois system itself.… The fact that we now not only call the plantation
owners in America capitalists, but they are capitalists, is based on their
existence as anomalies within a world market based on free labour.”45
Marx’s position in this respect was similar to that provided by Orlando
Patterson, who explained: “Capitalism, which is exclusively a product
of the modern world, has two major variants: the ‘free variant’ char-
acterized by the sale of the worker’s labour on the labour market; and
the slave variant found in the Americas up to the closing decades of the
19th century, in the…Dutch East Indies between the late 17th and mid-
19th centuries, and in the Indian Ocean slave colonies of the 18th and
19th centuries.” Capitalism based on wage labor, Patterson stated, was
“admittedly the most advanced” of these two forms.46 Indeed, in Marx’s
view, the slave variant of capitalism existed only insofar as it was an in-
tegral part of a larger world capitalist system, rooted in wage labor. Yet,
as Patterson indicated, in line with Marx, “the capitalist is often (though
not always) able to extract a higher level of surplus value from the slave
by forcing him to produce more than he would were he free, and by re-
ducing his costs of reproduction.”47
To understand the nature of Marx’s critique here, it is necessary to rec-
ognize that the law of value of capitalism underlying classical political
economy was dependent on a conception of equal exchange and formally
free labor and could not have slavery as its basis. Aristotle’s brilliant anal-
ysis of the commensurate value underlying the commodity in his Nicoma-
chean Ethics fell short, Marx argued, because, living in a society “founded
on the labour of slaves,” he was unable to grasp the basis of commodi-
ty-value in labor, which depended on a conception of “equal human la-
bour and therefore…labour of equal quality.”48 It is only with capitalism
that the concept of abstract labor based on a notion of the equality of
labor comes to the fore. This is not a minor matter because all bourgeois
political economy, along with the entire logic of capitalist valorization,
required wage labor as its basis.49
For this reason, although slaveowner capitalism clearly existed and had
definite historical importance, in Marx’s view, it could not constitute the
laws of motion of capital as a whole, but rather could only fully develop
and prosper on capitalist terms in a context in which wage labor was
the predominant form. The expropriation of human beings associated
106 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

with slavery was thus connected to capitalist wage labor in the form of
a “struggle of enemy brothers.”50 In the case of slaveowner capitalism,
there was no pretense of equal exchange. Rather, it rested on sheer pow-
er, or, as Sven Beckert calls it, “war capitalism.”51
In Marx’s day, slaveowner capitalism represented a conflict at the bar-
baric heart of the capitalist system itself. In January 1860, Marx wrote to
Frederick Engels: “In my opinion, the most momentous thing happening
in the world today is the slave movement—on the one hand, in America,
started by the death of [John] Brown, and in Russia, on the other [with re-
gard to serfs].… I have just seen in the [New York] Tribune that there’s been
another slave revolt in Missouri, which was put down, needless to say. But
the signal has now been given.”52 Marx therefore engaged in an intensive
study of the political economy of the slave question in the context of
writing articles for the New York Tribune and later Die Presse, as well as in
his economic notebooks, that were to be the basis of Capital. Here Marx
relied on a wide number of works, but the single most important treatise
on which he drew for his analysis of the system of accumulation in the
U.S. slave South was J. E. Cairnes’s The Slave Power, delivered as a series of
lectures in 1861 and published as a book in 1862.
Key to Marx’s whole understanding of slave-based accumulation in the
U.S. South was his notion that, under slaveowner capitalism in its most
developed form on “American plantations,” the “entire surplus-value”
produced by the slaves “is conceived as profit.… [As] the price that is paid
for the slave is no more than the anticipated and capitalized surplus-val-
ue or profit that is to be extracted from him” over his working life.53 Un-
like the “free wage worker” who has “no value” (as opposed to the value
of the worker’s labor power), the “slave…has exchange value, a value” and
represents a future stream of value, “a piece of capital.”54 The economics
of this meant that the working of slave labor was regulated, as in machin-
ery, in terms of capital consumption, its “wear and tear,” its availability,
and the cost of replacements. Nevertheless, the slave, whose initial price
was based on a working life of twenty years, was often “overworked,”
that is, consumed as a working instrument in seven years, as opposed to
twenty, in order to maximize the slave’s production of surplus value in
the shortest time. It was also common in this system, Marx emphasized,
for slave owners to borrow money upon their slaves as capital assets,
hence securities on which to obtain, and to rent them to other capital-
ists.55 “What Marx…understood,” as Ransom and Sutch pointed out,
was that the slave holding existed to make a profit for the owner. The
entire labor product of the slave and family, above whatever provision for
M arx and S lavery 107

food and other necessities the owner cared to make was expropriated. That
residual was the owner’s profit and the expectation of a continued flow
of such returns made slave property an earning asset. The price paid for a
slave reflected the consensus of the buyer and seller concerning the poten-
tial value of the continuous stream of profits that could be extracted from
the slave and, in the case of a female, from her descendants as well.56
Marx’s analysis thus led him to differ from other political economists
and critics of slavery in his time, such as Adam Smith, who argued that
slave labor was uneconomic and unable to compete with wage labor.57 In
contrast, Marx pointed to the vast surplus labor expropriated from slaves,
and the fact that the slaves themselves were a form of capital asset, form-
ing the basis of fictitious or speculative capital.58 Therefore, there seemed
to be little doubt, in his estimation, that the plantation economy of the
antebellum South was, as far as economic concerns alone were consid-
ered, enormously profitable, including the market for the breeding of
slaves. As Engels indicated in Anti-Dühring, the reason that only force
could remove slavery from the slave breeding and slave consuming states
of the South was that production on this basis paid, and thus it would not
simply die of its own accord on economic grounds.59
In order to be profitable on a capitalist basis, slave production required
a form of production suitable for slave labor.60 Marx explained that the es-
sential element of slave labor was that it was based on force and required
continuous external compulsion, requiring the whip of the overseer. Slav-
ery was characterized first of all for Marx by what he called “a relation of
domination.” As Patterson has commented in this respect, “Marx not only
shows clearly that he understands that slavery, on an institutional level,
is first and foremost a ‘relation of domination,’ but identifies the element
of direct force which distinguishes it.”61 Because it was directly forced
labor, Marx indicated, slaves were engaged in a constant, if not active,
resistance. Their laboring conditions lacked their consent; more so un-
der capitalist production where they were forced to work intensively and
for inordinate hours, threatening their own corporeal existence. “Forced
labour,” Marx wrote, “can never create general industriousness.”62 The resis-
tance of slaves evident in all of their actions, extending at times to slave
revolts, and the fear this engendered in their masters, were the primary
reasons that it was prohibited to educate slaves, particularly in the South,
which meant that they remained almost entirely unskilled labor.
These conditions combined to limit the forms in which slaves could
profitably be employed, in comparison to wage labor. Wage labor, Marx
argued, was distinguished from slave labor in its flexibility and versatili-
ty. Slave labor, in contrast, because continuous force was required, could
only be effectively employed in certain forms of production.63 The key
108 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

limit here, as Marx argued, following Cairnes, had to do with the costs of
superintendence. “The greater this [class] opposition” and the greater the
degree to which labor has to be forced, Marx wrote, “the greater the role
that this work of supervision plays. It reaches its high point in the slave
system” under capitalism. Indeed, “the overseer with his whip was nec-
essary to production…on the basis of slavery.”64 Slave labor was uneco-
nomical if dispersed in any way, due to the level of slave resistance, since
it would be removed from direct coercion and the whip of the overseer.
Nevertheless, slave labor was especially suitable to centralized large-scale
production in gangs on monocultural plantations where the costs of the
labor of superintendence could be kept down, and where only forced la-
bor could be employed on that scale and with that physical intensity.
Marx thus considered the supervision of plantation labor under sla-
veowner capitalism as the representation of a more developed form of
capitalist management, anticipating practices that would arise within
large-scale industry. Consequently, he marked the passages in his copy
of Cairnes’s Slave Power addressing this issue and frequently referred to
them. As Cairnes wrote, “the economic advantages of slavery are easily
stated: they are all comprised in the fact that the employer of slaves has
absolute power over his workmen, and enjoys the disposal of the whole
fruits of their labour. Slave labour, therefore, admits of the most com-
plete organization, that is to say, it may be combined on an extensive
scale, and directed by a controlling mind to a single end, and its cost can
never rise above that which is necessary to maintain the slave in health
and strength.” In agriculture, the slave system organized on the basis
of capitalist plantation agriculture was economically superior to peasant
proprietorship geared primarily to subsistence production: “Peasant pro-
prietorship…does not admit of combination and classification of labour
in the same degree as that of slavery,” though superior in respect to in-
dividual industry.65 In many ways, as both Cairnes and Marx recognized,
plantation slavery, therefore, was highly competitive with other forms
of production under capitalism, insofar as it took the form of large-scale,
combined production on plantations, including the extreme intensity
that could be imposed on slave labor in these circumstances.
If there was little doubt for Marx that slave-based accumulation in plan-
tation capitalism was effective economically, it clearly remained a labor-in-
tensive form of industry and was less conducive to industrialization, be-
cause capital was invested in slaves rather than physical capital, while slave
production was not conducive to factory work. It also had the effect, as in
all slave societies, of casting aspersions on manual labor. The slave econ-
omy in the United States around 1860 consisted, as Cairnes and Marx in-
M arx and S lavery 109

dicated, of three hundred thousand slave owners, four million slaves, and
another five million free white laborers, mostly engaged in subsistence
production. Industrial growth in the South was much less than the North,
as could be seen in the rise of railroad capital primarily in the latter.66
More important in undermining Southern slavery, however, was the
rapid ecological degradation that its monocultural plantation agriculture
represented. In the work of such thinkers as Merivale, Cairnes, Olmsted,
Carey, Johnston, and Marx himself, a major critique of the political econ-
omy of slavery in the South was an ecological one: the slave plantation
system rapidly exhausted the soil, as a consequence of the metabolic rift
in the soil nutrient cycle, requiring new lands to maintain production
and profits.67 This led to a violent westward and (southward) movement
driven principally by the slave power’s need to expand slaveowner cap-
italism, encompassing the Trail of Tears, the three Seminole Wars, the
seizure of Texas, and the Mexican-American War.68
The foremost thinker in presenting this ecological analysis was the ag-
ricultural chemist Johnston, a member of the Royal Society. Johnston in
his Notes on North America, which Marx studied in depth, emphasized that
Virginia had exhausted its soil through slave plantation agriculture and
had become dependent on breeding slaves for the slave consuming states
of the South. The general trend in the South (as distinct from the North)
was from richer soils that had been exhausted to poorer soils to the West,
creating an almost desperate need for new soils and an attempt to obtain
new lands for slavery as far west as California.69 Cairnes pointed to the
destructive nature of monocrop agriculture practiced on the slave planta-
tions, with, therefore, no “rotation of crops”:
The soil is tasked again and again to yield the same product, and the inev-
itable result follows. After a short series of years its fertility is completely
exhausted, the planter abandons the ground which he has rendered worth-
less, and passes on to seek new soils for that fertility under which alone
the agencies at his disposal can be profitably employed.… Even in Texas,
before it had yet been ten years under the dominion of this devastating
[slave] system, Mr. Olmsted tells us that the spectacle so familiar and so
melancholy in all the older Slave States was already not unfrequently seen
by the traveler—“an abandoned plantation of ‘worn out’ fields with its
little village of dwellings, now a home only for wolves and vultures.”
Slave cultivation, therefore, precluding the conditions of rotation of
crops or skilful [soil] management, tends inevitably to exhaust the land of
a country, and consequently requires for its permanent success not merely
a fertile soil but a practically unlimited extent of it.70

For Marx himself, who had been developing his theory of metabolic rift
at this time together with his critique of slavery, there was absolutely no
110 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

question of the material flaw that generated the crisis for the slavocracy
in the United States, leading to the Civil War. As he wrote in “The North
American Civil War” in October 1861,
The cultivation of the Southern export articles, cotton, tobacco, sugar,
etc., carried on by slaves, is only remunerative as long as it is conducted
with large gangs of slaves, on a mass scale and on wide expanses of a nat-
urally fertile soil, which requires only simple labor. Intensive cultivation,
which depends less on the fertility of the soil than the investment of
capital, intelligence and energy of labor, is contrary to the nature of slav-
ery. Hence the rapid transformation of states like Maryland and Virginia,
which formerly employed slaves on the production of export articles,
into states which raised slaves in order to export these slaves into the
deep South. Even in South Carolina, where the slaves form four-sevenths
of the population, the cultivation of cotton has been almost completely
stationary for years due to the exhaustion of the soil. Indeed, by force of
circumstances South Carolina has already been transformed in part into
a slave-raising state, since it already sells slaves to the sum of four million
dollars yearly to the states of the extreme South and Southwest. As soon
as this point is reached, the acquisition of new territories becomes neces-
sary, so that one section of the slaveholders may occupy new, fertile lands
and that a new market for slave-raising, therefore for the sale of slaves,
may be created for the remaining section.71

The reality was that “a strict confinement of slavery within its old ter-
rain…was bound according to economic law to lead to its gradual ex-
tinction,” whether by exhaustion of land, diminishing power in the U.S.
government, instability among its own “poor white” population, and not
least of all revolts by the slaves.72 As Johnson insightfully wrote in Rivers of
Dark Dreams, “The hegemony of this single plant over the landscape of the
Cotton Kingdom produced both a radical simplification of nature and a
radical simplification of human being.… Cotton mono-cropping stripped
the land of vegetation [and] leached out its fertility.”73 The ecological cri-
sis of slave cotton plantation production explained, Marx suggested, the
desperate aggression displayed by the South in the Kansas-Missouri bor-
der war (also known as the Bloody Kansas conflict) and in the attempts
to send bands of Texans into New Mexico to seize that territory for the
South.74 For Eugene Genovese in The Political Economy of Slavery, it was not
so much the economic failure of the slave system that was its undoing
but rather its “exhaustion of the soil,” leading to what Marx, following
William Henry Seward, had called an “irrepressible conflict.”75

Marx , t h e U. S . C i vi l Wa r, a nd Bl a c k Rec onstruction


As Robin Blackburn has observed in An Unfinished Revolution: Karl Marx
and Abraham Lincoln, Marx, at the time of the U.S. Civil War, “was focused
M arx and S lavery 111

on destroying true chattel slavery, which he knew to be a critical com-


ponent of the reigning capitalist order.” He viewed the conflict between
the North and South at the time of the U.S. Civil War as a contest be-
tween “two species of capitalism—one allowing slavery the other not.”76
Marx played a key role in organizing the English working-class move-
ment against the British government’s moves to intervene on the side of
the Confederacy in the U.S. Civil War. His participation in the antislavery
struggle was thus fully integrated with his overall critique of political
economy. The extensive economic manuscripts that were to form the ba-
sis of Capital were written during the years of the U.S. Civil War. Marx
commenced the drafting of the manuscript for volume one of Capital just
as the slavocracy was defeated.77
Marx’s numerous analyses of U.S. slavery and the U.S. Civil War were
unique in seeing it as a revolutionary struggle that could only be won by
revolutionary means, including the freeing of the slaves and the initia-
tion of a “people’s war” against the slave power. According to Tom Jean-
not in “Marx, Capitalism, and Race,”
Anticipating the “irrepressible conflict” (with William Seward), the trail
Marx blazes leads from “the Kansas war” (1854–1856) to the raid on Harp-
er’s Ferry (October 1859), to [the] Black revolt in Bolivar, Missouri (Decem-
ber 1859).… Against the standing temptation to trivialize or ignore the
self-activity of Black slaves themselves, or else cast them as passive by-
standers to the process of their own emancipation, Marx foresaw, in an
obscure, little-noticed event in Missouri before the war began, the key to
the future course of world events. Once the war was underway, he wrote
to Engels, “A single Negro regiment would have a remarkable effect on
Southern nerves” (August 1862).… In the same letter to Engels just quoted
[August 7, 1862], Marx returns to a related point that governs his thinking
about the progress and outcome of the Civil War as a whole: “The long
and short of the story seems to me to be that a war of this kind must be
conducted on revolutionary lines.”78

Marx did not simply write about the war on slavery, but he also en-
gaged directly in the political struggle. Although the U.S. Civil War coin-
cided with the intense period in which he drafted the Economic Manuscript
of 1861–1863 and Economic Manuscript of 1864–1865, prior to drafting Capital,
volume one, Marx, as Du Bois emphasized in “Karl Marx and the Negro,”
played a role in the organization of the “monster mass meetings” late in
1862 and 1863 aimed at preventing Britain’s intervention on behalf of the
slave South. On March 26, 1863, the biggest and most influential meeting
of British workers was held in support of Union forces in the U.S. Civil
War. The meeting packed James Hall in London with as many as three
thousand workers attending. Henry Adams, who attended the meeting in
112 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

place of his father Charles Francis Adams, the U.S. ambassador, credited
both Marx and Edward Beesly, a leading positivist, professor of history,
and later sympathizer of the International Working Men’s Association, for
organizing the meeting. The principal speaker was John Bright, a Quaker,
free trader, and mill owner, who was a fervent opponent of slavery and
had considerable admiration for Marx’s articles in the New York Tribune,
and for whom Marx had some respect as an orator and a thinker. This
and other massive working-class protests were credited by Marx, Charles
Francis Adams, and many others with having put a stop to the British gov-
ernment’s plans to go to war.79
The political organization of the British workers in the antislavery
struggle led to the development of the International Working Men’s
Association under Marx’s leadership. In his “Inaugural Address” to the
First International in September 1864, Marx heralded the international
solidarity of the working class in England with the slave laborers in the
U.S. South and with the North in the Civil War. He indicated that despite
the Cotton Crisis emanating from the war, the workers had allied them-
selves, against their own direct interests, with the antislavery struggle
and thus had “saved the west of Europe from plunging headlong into an
infamous crusade for the perpetuation and propagation of slavery on the
other side of the Atlantic.”80 In November 1864, Marx drafted the First
International’s famous letter to Abraham Lincoln, congratulating him
for his reelection and for the “matchless struggle for the rescue of an
enchained race and the reconstruction of a social world,” putting a final
end to the Confederacy’s cynical attempt to maintain “slavery to be ‘a be-
neficent institution,’ indeed the only solution of the great problem of ‘the
relation of labor to capital.’” Lincoln was to reply favorably via Charles
Francis Adams in a letter that created a stir in the British press.81
In May 1865, following Lincoln’s assassination and Andrew Johnson’s
rise to the presidency, Marx drafted a letter from the International to John-
son, referring to the defeat of “the demon of the ‘peculiar institution,’”
“the arduous task of political reconstruction,” and the “emancipation of
labor.”82 This was followed in October 1865 with a letter from the First
International over the signature of Marx and others addressed to the peo-
ple of the United States, which in Du Bois’s view represented Marx’s deep
concern over Reconstruction, and issued a grave warning: “Declare your
fellow citizens [former slaves] from this day forth free and equal with-
out reserve” or “a new struggle…will once more drench your country in
blood.”83 Marx, however, soon realized the reactionary dangers that John-
son posed to Reconstruction. As Du Bois explains, Marx “stood with the
Abolitionist democracy led by [Charles] Sumner and [Thaddeus] Stevens.”
M arx and S lavery 113

Marx, following the radical Republican Benjamin Franklin Wade, declared


that “the abolition of slavery” required “a radical change in the relation of
capital and property in land” in the former slave states. Nevertheless, “the
reaction,” he wrote to Engels in 1865, “has already begun in America.”84
Faced with these reactionary tendencies, Marx continually looked for
objective forces that would bring together Black and white workers. In
a deservedly famous statement in Capital in 1867, Marx evoked the need
for a broad labor alliance transcending race, now possible with the eman-
cipation of the slaves: “Labour in a white skin can’t emancipate itself
where it is branded in a black skin.… A new life immediately arose with
the death of slavery.” He still hoped for “a radical transformation in the
existing relations of capital and landed property” in the South during
Reconstruction.85 A decade later, troubled by the end of Reconstruction,
along with the power of railway capital, Marx nevertheless wrote to En-
gels in 1877 of the possibility of a broad Black/white, peasant farmer/in-
dustrial worker alliance: “The policy of the new president [Rutherford
B. Hayes] will turn the negroes, just as the big expropriations of land
(EXACTLY OF FERTILE LAND) for the benefit of the RAILWAY, MINING,
etc. companies will turn the peasants of the west—whose grumbling is
already plainly audible—into militant allies of the [industrial] workers. So
there’s a pretty fair storm brewing over there.”86
Marx, however, did not manage to address further the new develop-
ments with respect to racial capitalism in the United States associated
with Jim Crow. Thus, Du Bois wrote:
It was a great loss to American Negroes that the great mind of Marx and
his extraordinary insight into industrial conditions could not have been
brought to bear at first hand upon the history of the American Negro be-
tween 1876 and the World War. Whatever he said and did concerning the
uplift of the working class must, therefore, be modified so far as Negroes
are concerned by the fact that he had not studied at first hand their pecu-
liar race problem here in America. Nevertheless, he did know the plight of
the working class in England, France and Germany, and American Negroes
must understand what his panacea was for those folk if they would see
their way clearly in the future.87

The “panacea” was of course socialism, which Du Bois, along with


Marx, believed was a necessary part of the answer to the oppressions
of race and class.

Th e Ve ile d Fac e
Both Marx and Du Bois were fascinated with Isis, and the imagery of
the pedestal and the veil. Marx clearly saw the veiled Isis as an African
114 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

goddess, with the historical reality of the slave trade and the endless
struggle for human freedom revealed in a lifting of her veil. For Du Bois,
in “The Damnation of Women” in Darkwater, “Isis, the mother, is still
titular goddess, in thought if not in name, of the dark continent,” whose
veiled face is high above her pedestal.88 In his poem “Children of the
Moon,” accompanying the chapter on “The Damnation of Women,” the
veiled African Isis stood for “the blood-built way,” the struggle for Black
freedom through the horrors of slavery:
Up! Up! The blood-built way;
(Shadow grow vaster!
Terror come faster!)
Up! Up! to the blazing blackness
Of one veiled face.…

I rose upon the Mountain of the Moon


I felt the blazing glory of the Sun;
I heard the Song of Children crying, “Free!”
I saw the Face of Freedom—
And I died.89

The secret of Isis, for Du Bois, like Marx, was the struggle for freedom be-
yond slavery, beyond “the damnation of women,” beyond wage labor, beyond
racial capitalism—a struggle so great that it required permanent revolution.
N ot e s
1. Cedric J. Robinson, Black Marx- capitalism,” can still be found in some 6. Johnson, “The Pedestal and the Veil,”
ism (London: Zed, 1983); W. E. B. Du analyses. For example, Nick Nesbitt, 307.
Bois, Black Reconstruction in America, “The Slave Machine,” Six Archipelagos, 7. Sven Beckert and Seth Rothman,
1860–1880 (New York: Atheneum, July 9, 2019, 11–12. Yet, as John Clegg eds., Slavery’s Capitalism (Philadelphia:
1992); Oliver Cromwell Cox, Capitalism notes, “prior to Genovese most Marxist University of Pennsylvania Press, 2016).
as a System (New York: Monthly Review and Marxist-influenced writers followed 8. On “the second type of colonialism,”
Press, 1964). Marx in viewing slave plantations as see Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value,
2. The association of Marxism with the capitalist.” John Clegg, “A Theory of part 2 (Moscow: Progress Publishers,
view that slavery and capitalism in the Capitalist Slavery,” Journal of Historical 1971), 302–30. On Harriet Beecher
New World represented “two [economic] Sociology 33, no. 1 (2020): 76. Stowe, the “Slave Power,” the Dred Scott
systems” and the view that this was the decision, the Kansas War, John Brown,
orthodox Marxian position was almost 3. Karl Marx, Capital, vol. 1 (London: the “peculiar institution,” abolitionism,
entirely due to the influential Marxian Penguin, 1976), 871. and the revolutionary struggles of freed
historian of the slave South Eugene 4. Stephanie Smallwood, “What Slav- Black workers, see Karl Marx and Fried-
Genovese. See Eugene Genovese, The ery Tells Us About Marx,” Boston Review, rich Engels, The Civil War in the United
Political Economy of Slavery (New York: February 21, 2018; Stephanie Small- States, ed. Andrew Zimmerman (New
Vintage, 1965), 17; Eugene D. Genovese wood, Saltwater Slavery (Cambridge, York: International Publisher, 2016),
and Elizabeth Fox Genovese, “The Slave MA: Harvard University Press, 2008). 17, 19, 28, 30–31, 33, 43, 120, 124–27,
Economies in Political Perspective,” 153–54, 165. On torture under slavery
Journal of American History 66, no. 1 5. Walter Johnson, “The Pedestal and and the Haitian revolution, see Karl
(June 1979): 22. This same emphasis the Veil,” Journal of the Early Republic Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected
on two economic systems or modes of 24 (2004): 299–308; Walter Johnson, Works, vol. 5 (New York: International
production in the nineteenth-century River of Dark Dreams (Cambridge, MA: Publishers, 1975), 302, 308, 388, 599.
United States, “plantation slavery and Harvard University Press, 2013). On English slavery under Edward VI and
M arx and S lavery 115

enslavement of Native Americans, see See also W. E. B. Du Bois, “Karl Marx and ed with the plantation economy in the
Capital, vol. 1, 897, 915. the Negro,” in Marx and Fredrick Engels, South, and that slaveowner capitalism
9. Philip Foner, British Labor and the The Civil War in the United States, 218 and “the Southern states in the union”
American Civil War (New York: Holmes (reprinted from Crisis 40, no 3 [March were integrated with the “world market”
and Meier, 1981), 56–58. 1933]: 55–56). through the cotton trade. Marx, Capital,
15. Johnson, “The Pedestal and the vol. 3, 809. See also Edward Gibbon
10. Roger Ransom and Richard Sutch,
“Capitalists without Capital: The Burden Veil,” 300, 302–5. Wakefield, England and America, vol. 2
of Slavery and the Impact of Emanci- (London: Richard Bentley, 1833), 26–27.
16. Johnson, “The Pedestal and the
pation,” Agricultural History 62, no. 3 Veil,” 306. See the similar argument in As Cox wrote, the early nineteenth-cen-
(1988): 133. Dale Tomich, Through the Prism of Slav- tury “American economy rested upon
ery (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, its foreign commerce, of which slavery
11. Henry Brougham, An Inquiry into became a pivot.” Cox, Capitalism as a
the Colonial Policy of the European Pow- 2004), 23–24.
System, 124.
ers (Edinburgh: E. Balfour, Manners and 17. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 925.
Miller, and Archibald Constable, 1803); 24. Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philoso-
18. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 915–24. phy (New York: International Publishers,
Thomas Stamford Raffles, History of Java
19. Johnson, “The Pedestal and the 1963), 111. Of course, slavery was more
(London: John Murray, 1817); Thomas
Powell Buxton, The African Slave Trade Veil.” than simply an economic category for
and Its Remedy (London: John Murray, 20. See Smallwood, “What Slavery Marx—it was also a social category. Still,
1840); Herman Merivale, Lectures on Tells Us About Marx”; J. Lorand Matory, even in the context of the transatlantic
Colonization and Colonies (London: The Fetish Revisited (Durham, NC: Duke slave trade, Marx did not make the mis-
Muston Co., 1841); Henry C. Carey, The University Press, 2018), 61; Sara-Ma- take of confusing slavery as a system of
Slave Trade, Domestic and Foreign (Phil- ria Sorentino, “The Abstract Slave: forced labor with essentialist racial char-
adelphia: A. Hart, 1853); J. E. Cairnes, Anti-Blackness and Marx’s Method,” acteristics that were often used ideolog-
The Slave Power (New York: Follett International Labor and Working Class ically to justify it. He would have been
Foster and Co., 1862); François-Charles- History 96 (2019): 17. Johnson sought in full agreement with Eric Williams’s
Louis Comte, Traité de législation, ou to back up his argument that the ped- statement that “a racial twist has…been
exposition des lois générales suivant estal and veil metaphor was all about given to what is basically an economic
lesquelles les peuples prospèrent, the evasion of the reality of capitalism phenomenon. Slavery was not born of
dépérissent ou restent stationnaire, and slavery by pointing out that Marx racism: racism was the consequence of
3rd ed. (1827; repr. Brussels: Hauman, had used the metaphor of linen as a use slavery. Unfree labor in the New World
Cattoir et Comp, 1837). There are also in- value, comparing it to the use value of was brown, white, black, and yellow,
dications that Marx may have had some a coat. He claimed that this was another Catholic, Protestant, and pagan.” Criti-
familiarity with John Gabriel Stedman’s example of Marx’s evasion of slavery, cizing the view of bourgeois economists
eighteenth-century bestseller Narrative since cotton was thereby displaced from who say a “Negro slave…[is] a man of
of a Five Years’ Expedition Against the the argument. Yet, men’s frock coats the black race,” Marx replied: “A Negro is
Revolted Negroes of Surinam (1796, were often made of linen at the time, a Negro. Only under certain conditions
engraved by William Blake) to which and Marx’s purpose here was to com- does he become a slave.” Eric Williams,
Comte referred. See also David Mercer pare the use value of the final coat to Capitalism and Slavery (New York: Cap-
Hart, Class, Slavery, and the Industrial- the use value of the cloth out of which ricorn, 1966), 7; Karl Marx, “Wage-La-
ist Theory of History in French Liberal it was made. He may have been think- bour and Capital” in Wage Labour and
Thought, 1814–1830: The Contribution ing of his own linen coat when he wrote Capital/Value, Price and Profit (New York:
of Charles Comte and Charles Dunoyer the passage. Marx can hardly be said to International Publishers, 1976), 28.
(PhD dissertation, King’s College, Cam- have ignored cotton in the first volume 25. “The Lace Trade in Nottingham,”
bridge, June 1993). of Capital since it appears throughout Daily Telegraph, January 17, 1860, quot-
12. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 93; Hal Draper, that work. Johnson, “The Pedestal and ed in Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
The Marx-Engels Chronicle (New York: the Veil,” 301–2; Marx, Capital, vol. 1, vol. 30, 217.
Schocken, 1985), 130–31, 295; Karl 132–33.
26. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 345.
Marx, Marx’s Economic Manuscript of 21. Plutarch, “Isis and Osiris,” Moralia.
1864–1865 (Boston: Brill, 2015). In 27. Karl Marx and Fredrick Engels, Col-
22. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, The lected Works, vol. 30 (New York: Interna-
March 1865, as he was beginning to Philosophy of Nature (Oxford: Oxford
draft volume one of Capital, Marx wrote tional Publishers, 1975), 197.
University Press, 2004), 10; Guenter B.
to Engels: “It seems all up with Confed- Risse, “The Veil of Isis Allegory: Histor- 28. Robin Blackburn, The Making of
eracy.” Marx and Engels, The Civil War in ical Visions of the Natural World,” Re- New World Slavery (London: Verso,
the United States, 158. search Gate, August 1, 2017. 1997), 339–40.
13. Marx, Capital, vol. 3 (London: Pen- 23. Compare to Johnson who writes 29. Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
guin, 1981), 940. that slavery is “a history of wages as well vol. 30, 183–85; Marx, Capital, vol. 1,
14. W. E. B. Du Bois, Black Reconstruc- as whips, of factories as well as plan- 344–45; Casey Cep, “The Long War
tion in America, 1860–1880 (New York: tations.” Walter Johnson, “To Remake Against Slavery,” New Yorker, January
Atheneum, 1992), 354. Note this was the World,” Boston Review, February 27, 2020.
Du Bois’s own translation, which differs 20, 2018. Marx clearly believed that 30. Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
slightly from the standard translation. industry in the U.S. North was integrat- vol. 30, 215.
116 M ONTHLY RE V IE W / J uly – A u g ust 2020

31. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, of abstract labor/value insists that such capitalism—incremental increases in
On Colonialism (New York: Internation- notions were inconceivable in a society surplus value,” or surplus product, is
al Publishers, 1972), 115; editorial in that relies predominantly on slave labor, here contradicted by Marx’s analysis
Times of London, March 10, 1882, 9. as in Athens at the time of Aristotle. This in Capital, vol. 3, which points to the
See also Y. J. Murrow, “The Coolie Trade notion applies quite apart from the surplus value produced by slave labor.
in China and Peru,” Anti-Slavery Reporter specific use on occasion by both Marx What was different in the case of slave
16, no. 12 (December 1869): 273–79. and Engels, particularly in their earlier labor, as Marx also stated, was that “the
32. Carey, The Slave Trade, Domestic writings, of the notion of a slave mode price that is paid here for the slave is…
and Foreign, 8–15. of production. As Eric Hobsbawm has capitalized surplus-value or profit that is
pointed out, the concept of the slave to be extracted from him.” See Nesbitt,
33. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 377.
mode of production was utilized as a “The Slave Machine,” 13; Marx, Capital,
34. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 345. broad guide and never fully developed vol. 3, 945.
35. Carey, The Slave Trade, Domestic by Marx. He frequently referred to the 54. Marx, Grundrisse, 288–89; Karl
and Foreign, 12. ancient communal mode/form of pro- Marx, Capital, vol. 2 (London: Penguin,
36. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Se- duction (which, however, did not pre- 1978), 555; Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 377;
lected Correspondence (Moscow: Prog- clude slavery, primarily through war). Capital, vol. 3, 762.
ress Publishers, 1975), 78–79. See Eric J. Hobsbawm, introduction to 55. Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
Karl Marx, Pre-Capitalist Economic For- vol. 30, 184–85; Marx and Engels, Col-
37. Comte, Traité de législation, 392;
mations (New York: International Pub- lected Works, vol. 33, 10–11.
Stedman, Narrative of a Five Years’ Expe-
lishers, 1964). 18–22. For classic works
dition Against the Revolted Negroes of
building directly on Marx’s notions of 56. Ransom and Sutch, “Capitalists
Surinam, 320. without Capital,” 133–34.
ancient slavery, see G. M. E. de Ste Croix,
38. Marx and Engels, Collected Works, The Class Struggle in the Ancient Greek 57. Adam Smith, The Wealth of Na-
vol. 5, 308, 599; Comte, Traité de légis- World (London: Duckworth, 1981) and tions (New York: Modern Library, 1937),
lation, 392; Stedman, Narrative of a Five Perry Anderson, Passages from Antiquity 80–81.
Years’ Expedition Against the Revolted to Feudalism (London: Verso, 1975). 58. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 377; Marx,
Negroes of Surinam, 320–21. Space does not permit us to carry out Theories of Surplus Value, part 3, 243;
39. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 345; Marx and here an extensive exploration of Marx’s Marx, Capital, vol. 2, 555; Marx and En-
Engels, Collected Works, vol. 5, 308–09; rich analysis of ancient slavery or of the gels, Collected Works, vol. 34, 98.
Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy, 111. comparative analysis of slavery in differ- 59. Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
40. Karl Marx, On the First International ent productive relations. Nevertheless, it vol. 25, 149.
(New York: McGraw Hill, 1973), 99. is important to recognize that for Marx
slavery was defined very broadly, as 60. Karl Marx, A Contribution to a Cri-
41. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 916. tique of Political Economy (Moscow:
in the case of Patterson, as a system of
42. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in class relations based on force and the Progress Publishers, 1970), 203.
the United States, 30, 44; Buxton, The direct expropriation of the body of an- 61. Patterson, “On Slavery and Slave
African Slave Trade and Its Remedy, 202; other. It occurred at many times and in Formations,” 32–33; Marx, Grundrisse,
Cairnes, The Slave Power, 124. many contexts in history. Chattel slavery 326.
43. On Marx and settler colonialism, also occurred in ancient times but was 62. Marx, Grundrisse, 326; Marx and
see Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 934–35; John developed most fully under capitalism. Engels, Collected Works, vol. 34, 98;
Bellamy Foster, Brett Clark, and Hannah Ancient slavery and modern slavery John Bellamy Foster and Brett Clark, The
Holleman, “Marx and the Indigenous,” thus had commonalities, but are to be Robbery of Nature (New York: Monthly
Monthly Review 71, no. 9 (February regarded as historically distinct. It is in Review Press, 2020), 23–32.
2020): 1–19. On colonial labor and this sense that Patterson argues for the 63. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 1014, 1016,
classical political economy, see Donald kind of “bold, world-wide comparativ- 1033–34.
Winch, Classical Political Economy and ism” in the study of slavery that Marx
64. Marx, Capital, vol. 3, 507–8; Marx
Colonies (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni- advocated. Patterson, “On Slavery and
and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 30,
versity Press, 1965), 93–100. Slave Formations,” 67.
262–63; Cairnes, The Slave Power, 40.
44. Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Val- 49. Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
65. Cairnes, The Slave Power, 39, 41–
ue, part 2 (Moscow: Progress Publishers, vol. 33, 336.
42; Marx, Capital, vol. 3, 507–8; Marx
1968), 302–3. 50. Marx, Capital, vol. 3, 362. and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 30,
45. Karl Marx, Grundrisse (London: 51. Sven Beckert, The Empire of Cotton 262–63; Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 452.
Penguin, 1973), 464, 513. (New York: Vintage, 2014), xv–xvi. 66. Cairnes, The Slave Power, 63–67;
46. Orlando Patterson, “On Slavery and 52. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in Marx and Engels, The Civil War in the
Slave Formations,” New Left Review, se- the United States, 17. United States, 44.
ries 1, no. 117 (1979): 53.
53. Karl Marx, Capital, vol. 3 (London: 67. Merivale, Lectures on Colonization
47. Patterson, “On Slavery and Slave Penguin, 1981), 940, 945. The con- and Colonies, James F. W. Johnston,
Formations,” 55. tention of Nesbitt that Marx himself Notes on North America, vol. 2 (London:
48. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 151–52. viewed slaves in the U.S. South as mere William Blackwood, 1851), 319, 351–
Marx’s comment here on the concept “constant capital” unable “to produce 53; Carey, The Slave Trade, Domestic and
of equality, exchange, and the concept the essential and defining element of Foreign, 100–108; Olmsted, Journey
M arx and S lavery 117

in the Seaboard Slave States, 42–44, Marxist view of why the conflict over 1912), 224–25; Ephraim Douglass
56–57, 237–38; Cairnes, The Slave Pow- slavery was irrepressible, as opposed Adams, Great Britain and the American
er, 45, 75, 94; Williams, Capitalism and to repressible. Still, in the revised view, Civil War, vol. 2 (New York: Longmans,
Slavery, 7; John Bellamy Foster, Marx’s which he supported, it was ecological Green and Co., 1925), 291–92; John
Ecology (New York: Monthly Review, destruction rather than economic failure Nichols, The “S” Word (London: Verso,
2000). as such that was the main reason for the 2011), 61–99; Kevin B. Anderson, Marx
68. Cairnes, The Slave Power, 111–13. South’s expansionist drive. As Eugene at the Margins (Chicago: University of
Baptist has argued, in The Half Has Nev- Chicago Press, 2016), 106–114. See
69. Marx and Engels, Collected Works,
er Been Told, since slaveowner capital- also John Bright, Speeches on the Amer-
vol. 43, 384; Marx, Capital, vol. 3, 808;
ism was so successful, it could not have ican Question (Boston: Little Brown and
Johnston, Notes on North America, vol.
been ended except by war. Therefore the Co., 1865), 170–93. Although Marx was
2, 351–53; Olmsted, Journey in the
South made a “tremendous mistake,” it strongly opposed to many aspects of
Seaboard Slave States, 57; Foster, Marx’s
can be argued—like Marx and so many Bright’s views, he saw him as a cut above
Ecology, 152.
others did at that time—that behind its the usual bourgeois thinkers and exam-
70. Cairnes, The Slave Power, 45–46; material success was a flaw, an expan- ined his work closely, taking extracts in
see also Carey, The Slave Trade, Domestic sionist drive requiring ever more land to his notebooks. Karl Marx and Friedrich
and Foreign, 95–105. stave off future crisis, land that the North Engels, Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe
71. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in would not allow—not one more square (MEGA), IV/18 (Berlin: Walter de Gruy-
the United States, 45–46. See also Marx foot, Lincoln indicated. Eugene Baptist, ter, 2019), 6–7.
and Engels, Selected Correspondence, The Half Has Never Been Told, 413–14;
80. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in
213–14. See also Karl Marx and Fred- Marx and Engels, The Civil War in the
the United States, 179–82.
erick Engels, Selected Correspondence United States, 133.
(Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1975), 81. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in
76. Blackburn, An Unfinished Revolu-
213; Marx and Engels, Collected Works, the United States, 153–57.
tion, 11–12; Patterson, “On Slavery and
vol. 43, 384. Slave Formations,” 53–54. 82. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in
72. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in the United States, 165–66.
77. It is for this reason that Marx’s most
the United States, 47. profound analyses of the economics of 83. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in
73. Johnson, River of Dark Dreams, 8. slavery occur in the Grundrisse, the Eco- the United States, 186–87; Du Bois,
nomic Manuscript of 1861–1863, and “Karl Marx and the Negro,” 218; Du
74. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in
the parts of the Economic Manuscript of Bois, Black Reconstruction, 354.
the United States, 17, 44–47, 55–58;
Robin Blackburn, An Unfinished Revo- 1863–1865 that constituted the drafts 84. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 93; Du Bois,
lution: Karl Marx and Abraham Lincoln for the second and third volumes of Cap- “Karl Marx and the Negro,” 219; Marx
(London: Verso, 2011), 9; Cairnes, The ital. By the time Marx turned to drafting and Engels, The Civil War in the United
Slave Power, 11–21. Capital, vol. 1, the U.S. slave system was States, 167.
in the past tense, though it was succeed- 85. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 93, 414.
75. Genovese, The Political Economy
ed by new forms of racial capitalism. The
of Slavery, 85–99, 281–82; Marx and 86. Marx and Engels, The Civil War in
issue in 1867, as Marx made clear in
Engels, The U.S. Civil War, 166; William the United States, 189; Du Bois, “Karl
the preface to Capital, vol. 1, was Recon-
Henry Seward, “On the Irrepressible Marx and the Negro,” 219.
struction. See Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 93.
Conflict” (speech, Rochester, New York, 87. Du Bois, “Karl Marx and the Negro,”
October 25, 1858). Seward here intro- 78. Tom Jeannot, “Marx, Capitalism,
and Race,” Radical Philosophy Today 5 219.
duced the “two political systems” view.
Marx’s view as to why the Civil War was (2007): 72; Marx and Engels, The U.S. 88. W. E. B. Du Bois, Darkwater: Voices
an “irrepressible conflict” was of course Civil War, 17, 22–23, 121. Translation from within the Veil (1920; repr. Mine-
somewhat different, seeing it as two la- here follows Du Bois, Black Reconstruc- ola: Dover, 1999), 97; see also, Wilson
bor regimes within a single system, pro- tion, 354. J. Moses, “The Poetics of Ethiopianism:
moting different political structures (see 79. Foner, British Labor and the Amer- W. E. B. Du Bois and Literary Black Na-
Marx and Engels, The Civil War in the ican Civil War, 11–13, 39–40, 57–62, tionalism,” American Literature 47, no. 3
United States, 55). Genovese presented 84–85; John Spargo, Karl Marx: His Life (1975): 418–23.
both a traditional Marxist and revised and Work (New York: B. W. Huebsch, 89. Du Bois, Darkwater, 113.

~
If resistance to the Slave Power was the reserved watchword of
your first election, the triumphant warcry of your re-election is
Death to Slavery.
—Karl Marx, on behalf of the International Working Men’s Association, to
President Abraham Lincoln, November 22, 1864.

View publication stats

You might also like