Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Book Reviews

hyman, john. The Objective Eye: Color, Form, and jectivism. Hyman then goes on to give independent
Reality in the Theory of Art. University of Chicago reasons in support of qualified forms of objectivism
Press, 2006, xiv + 286 pp., 8 color + 97 b&w illus., about each of these topics.
$80.00 cloth, $35.00 paper. Hyman’s account of color begins from the funda-
mental principle that an object’s color is part of how
Why do two-dimensional configurations of lines it looks. Unlike the shape of an object, which can be
and colors sometimes strike us as being realistic de- understood independently of how it looks, the color
pictions of three-dimensional states of affairs? Most of an object cannot be so understood. This fundamen-
contemporary philosophers, psychologists, and art tal principle has several important implications, chief
theorists find it nearly irresistible to think that this among them the following: (1) the causal efficacy of
must be because of something about us. Either it is be- colors is limited to their effects on the thought and
cause these configurations produce a distinctive kind behavior of beings capable of seeing them, and (2)
of psychological effect on our minds, or because of the final arbiter of the colors of things is the sense
our familiarity (or lack thereof) with the conventions of sight. These implications support the insight that a
used to construct them, or because they reproduce physiological explanation of how color experience is
the geometric structure of our retinal images. John produced need not invoke colors as the cause of this
Hyman seriously doubts whether any of these sorts of experience; the absorption of light by our retinae suf-
explanations are correct. And, in contrast to all such fices. But subjectivists mistakenly take this insight to
subjectivist accounts of pictorial realism, he thinks imply that the objective world, as it is independently
that there is something right about the idea, first in- of our experience of it, does not contain any colors.
troduced in Plato’s Cratylus, that a realistic picture This mistake is based on the false presupposition that
depicts a state of affairs by copying its form and color. for colors to be part of the objective world, they must
Hyman’s argument proceeds not only by introducing be theoretical posits that are invoked to explain how
and examining distinctions that subjectivist accounts our experience of them is produced. This presuppo-
overlook or misunderstand, but also by introducing sition is falsified by Hyman’s fundamental principle,
a number of his own basic principles of pictorial re- which limits the causal efficacy of colors and restricts
alism (that is, principles that relate configurations of them from functioning as theoretical posits. As Hy-
lines and colors to the states of affairs they realis- man puts this point: colors, like aches, lie too securely
tically depict). What is striking about the principles within the ambit of experience for them to function
that Hyman introduces is that they make no refer- as theoretical posits, so their existence cannot be de-
ence to the psychological effect that configurations cided by experimental science (p. 25).
of lines and colors have on our minds. As such, his Hyman’s account of color is among the most sen-
aim is to show just how far it is possible to explain sible of those currently on offer, but it appears to beg
pictorial realism in purely objective terms. the question against an influential strand of thinking
Hyman critiques subjectivism on three fronts: with within contemporary philosophy of color, and one
regard to color, depiction, and pictorial realism. His that indirectly motivates subjectivism. Hyman’s ar-
approach to these topics is remarkably evenhanded. gument rests on the fundamental principle that an
In each case, he concedes that there is a genuine in- object’s color cannot be understood independently of
sight that subjectivists are right about. The problem how it looks, but physicalism about color is predicated
is that subjectivists misunderstand the implications of precisely on the possibility that an object’s color can
their insights and wrongly conclude that they imply be so understood, and anti-physicalist subjectivism
subjectivism, when in fact they are consistent with ob- is largely motivated by arguing that this possibility is

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65:4 Fall 2007


418 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

coherent but not actual. Of course, if the fundamental tion of predicates to novel cases could be correct or
principle is correct, then both physicalism and anti- incorrect and (2) how predication is possible at all—
physicalist subjectivism are predicated on an inco- since referring to an object and predicating a property
herent supposition, but this only presses the question of it involves more than just juxtaposing two labels.
of whether the fundamental principle is correct, and The tenor of Hyman’s criticism of Goodman is a good
Hyman offers virtually no support for this principle illustration of the mood of the book as a whole. I can
itself. He suggests it is a conceptual truth, but skep- think of no better way to describe this mood than to
tics about conceptual truth (such as most physicalists say that it reminds me of George Orwell’s nonfiction,
and anti-physicalist subjectivists) will hardly be con- in that Hyman adamantly refuses to be taken in by
vinced by this suggestion. In short, I worry that more the disingenuous rhetoric of others or to deploy such
must be said at this crucial point in the argument. rhetoric himself. He consistently cuts to the heart of
Hyman’s account of depiction begins from the con- the matter and is quite blunt with his criticisms of ri-
cept of occlusion shape, a concept he traces to Eu- val views as well as with the limitations of his own
clid’s Optics. If you close one eye and look at an ob- view.
ject through a window, the shape of the mark you Hyman takes this direct approach toward an idea
would need to make on the window in order to block that has influenced thinkers from Descartes to David
all of and only your view of the object is that object’s Marr, the thought that we can explain the workings
occlusion shape. Although this implies that occlusion of pictorial techniques (such as Renaissance perspec-
shapes are relative to points of view, it does not imply tive) by comparing the geometry of pictures pro-
that they are in any sense illusory or merely apparent. duced using these techniques with the geometry of
Nor does it imply that they are in any sense subjective, retinal images. A glib formulation of Hyman’s criti-
since neither their existence nor identification de- cism of this idea is that it involves taking something
pends on the experience of observers. Given an object we do see (pictures) and comparing it to something
and a point of view on that object, its occlusion shape we do not see (retinal images) in order to explain
can be identified solely in terms of Euclidean geome- how we visually make sense of the things we do
try. Having thus articulated the concept of occlusion see. Hyman’s less glib formulation of this criticism
shape in purely objective terms, Hyman draws on it to involves reminding us of two crucial differences be-
spell out a basic principle of depiction: namely, that a tween pictures and retinal images. First, the geome-
picture represents an object by copying its occlusion try of two-dimensional pictures is fundamentally dif-
shape (or, one might say, its form). This principle suf- ferent from the geometry of retinal images—since
fices to undermine the subjectivist contention that the retina is a curved three-dimensional surface—
it is only because configurations of lines and colors and flattened-out retinal images do not look any-
produce a distinctive kind of subjective effect on our thing like two-dimensional pictures produced using
minds that they depict anything at all. That said, how- Renaissance perspective. Second, our relationship to
ever, Hyman concedes that subjectivists are right to pictures is fundamentally different from our relation-
note that one and the same occlusion shape can depict ship to retinal images, since we do not in any sense
different objects, such as in the case of the duck/rabbit see retinal images nor do they play any role in our
figure. However, they mistakenly take this to imply perception of the world. They are produced by the
that occlusion shape tells us nothing about depiction, light reflected by our retinae, whereas it is the light
whereas a more sensible conclusion is that it is insuf- that is absorbed by our retinae that enables us to see.
ficient, in itself, to fully explain depiction. Because philosophers persistently tend to forget or
Hyman’s account of pictorial realism draws on not overlook these differences, Hyman thinks that ceas-
only the concept of occlusion shape, but several other ing to compare pictures and retinal images is a neces-
principles of realistic depiction as well, chief among sary first step toward thinking clearly about how the
them perspective and (what Hyman calls) modality. perception of pictures actually works.
In his discussion of these principles, Hyman once The final principle of pictorial realism that Hy-
again opposes those who think that these principles man introduces is the concept of modality, which he
only work to produce realistic-looking pictures be- defines as “the extent of the range of questions it is
cause of something about us. He begins with an ex- possible to ask about a depicted scene” (p. 200). On
tended criticism of Nelson Goodman’s view that it is Hyman’s account, the larger the range of questions
only our familiarity with a system of pictorial repre- we can ask about a picture’s content, the more real-
sentation that makes pictures produced within that istic it is. Since Hyman accords this concept a central
system look realistic to us. Hyman’s chief criticism of role in his account of realism—he goes as far as say-
Goodman’s view is that it presupposes a form of nom- ing it is “the key to understanding the evolution of
inalism that is demonstrably false. It is false because realism in pictorial art” (p. 200)—it is fitting to ap-
it assimilates referring expressions and predicates to proach it with the same critical rigor with which Hy-
labels, which makes a mystery of (1) how the applica- man approaches the views of other philosophers. For
Book Reviews 419

instance, Hyman criticizes Goodman’s claim that pic- latter being understood as a stepping beyond the fa-
tures are dense symbol systems on the grounds that miliar. He utilizes three concepts: invention, singu-
Goodman does not provide a way of ordering symbol larity, and alterity. These are unpacked as follows:
systems such that we can measure their relative den- creativity or “invention” is success in allowing a con-
sity. However, one might ask a similar question about frontation with “alterity”—that which lies beyond the
Hyman’s own concept of modality, namely: How can established horizons of a culture—to take place. A
we measure the range of questions we can ask about reading is, accordingly, an opening up to alterity, an
different pictures? Of course, it seems intuitive to say encounter occasioned by the work. Noting and ar-
that the more realistic a picture is, the more ques- ticulating alterity cannot be willed into existence. It
tions we can ask about it, but I wonder whether this is involves a mix of activity and passivity, permitting a
generally true. A large, but unrealistic, picture might self-remaking enabling perception and formulation
sustain more questions than a small, but realistic, pic- of the hitherto unthought or unfelt. “Singularity” en-
ture. Or they might both sustain an endless series of ters the picture as a regulative concept, separating
trivial questions. The problem is that although the uniqueness (the work’s mere difference from others)
concept of modality is intuitively appealing, in the ab- from the novelty that we look for in literature. More
sence of some way of distinguishing between trivial than simply differing from other works, singularity
and nontrivial questions and a way of measuring the is “a difference that involves the irruption of other-
relative number of nontrivial questions we can ask of ness or alterity into the cultural field” (p. 136). The
artworks, this concept does not rise to Hyman’s own inventiveness of (good) literary works does not re-
high standards of philosophical rigor. side in producing the merely new, but in bringing out
What it is for a picture to be realistic is an im- otherness.
portant topic not only within aesthetics. Since Plato, In assessing this account, I was worried less by
philosophers have invoked pictures as models for un- an overly tight circular interdependence of the three
derstanding truth, knowledge, and the representa- cardinal concepts and more with the nagging suspi-
tional character of thought (among other things). The cion that some crucial normative ingredient was be-
problem is that pictures have turned out to be as hard ing neglected. Like “novelty” or “originality,” “oth-
to understand as any of these other topics, and con- erness,” too, is a parasitical value (after all, exposing
fusions about the nature of pictorial depiction have exclusion should not automatically prompt us to re-
corrupted our philosophical accounts of these other instate that which was excluded). But how to win-
topics. As such, as long as these confusions persist, it now out the wheat of omitted matter that should
is hard to imagine how our philosophical understand- be importantly exposed from the chaff of the right-
ing of any of these topics will improve. The Objective fully discarded, which should justifiably remain in cul-
Eye is the best available clarification of these confu- tural oblivion? Otherness, characterized as implying
sions. It should be required reading for many, many “a wholly new existent that cannot be apprehended
philosophers. by the old modes of understanding, and could not
have been predicted by means of them” (p. 29), fig-
ZED ADAMS ures both in the book’s account of the creative act
Department of Philosophy and in its description of reading. Yet even if such
University of Chicago nomenclature adequately captures the essentials of
the creative act, since experiential extension as such
attridge, derek. The Singularity of Literature. New insufficiently characterizes powerful literature, look-
York: Routledge, 2004, 192 pp., $90.00 cloth, $29.95 ing for literature’s singularity within a set of parasit-
paper. ical attributes—creativity, novelty, originality, inno-
vation, or alterity—suggests a partial account at best
The Singularity of Literature is a thoughtful and dense and risks misplaced emphasis. Here, the book’s dis-
meditation on creating literature and reading it. The sociation from explicitly political approaches works
slimness of the volume belies its richness and its ca- against it. For political criticism, the occluded other
pacity for inducing readers to ponder anew their re- is associated with the culturally repressed (and op-
lation to literature. The writing is honest and open, pressed). Demarginalization presents a clear and un-
importing Emmanuel Levinas’s formulations into lit- contested moral objective, clarifying precisely what
erary theory in an intelligent and rewarding manner, aspects of alterity merit exposure and why. “Singular-
and the range of the ideas put forth transcends liter- ity,” by contrast, seems to me to be too thin to guide
ature and is applicable to other forms of art. and explain the value of creativity or of perceiving
Derek Attridge aims to respect literature’s re- alterity as such.
silience to its own definition and exhaustive theo- Ironically, the extensive stress Attridge places on
retical elucidation. Instead of a definition, he under- creativity and inventiveness increasingly alerted me
scores the ties between literature and creativity, the to the (surprisingly) limited role that the originality
420 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

of the work and its exposure of otherness play in really enter the picture. Yet this speech is surely one
my own strong experiences with good literature. To of those moments in which it happens.
begin with, Attridge’s ideal readers are thoroughly Accordingly, for me, The Singularity of Literature
steeped in the cultural matrix within which the work is best perceived as elucidating one modality of liter-
was produced. Otherwise, they would be unable to ature’s unique capacities, not a comprehensive the-
experience the work’s novelty in sensing and express- ory on literary value or literature’s singularity, or cre-
ing otherness. Yet while familiarity with the work’s ativity in literature in general. In its more cautious
formative context can amplify pleasure, overempha- moods the book denies that it provides a compre-
sizing the import of such acquaintance runs counter hensive explanation of singularity, or that it attempts
to the impression that much of our delight and need to reduce aesthetic merits to locating alterity. In its
of literature is unrelated to text-context comparison. more cautious moods, the book presents creativity as
Nor does it square with my own reading experience a daily occurrence rather than some profound discov-
of canonical or noncanonical literature, both as a sea- ery. Weakening the thesis in these ways could prob-
soned reader and as an inexperienced one. Some of ably cover all the counterexamples that I marshaled
the best novels I have read in recent years, by authors above. Nevertheless, the thrust of the book surely
such as Vikram Seth, Rohinton Mistry, Zadie Smith, translates literature’s contributions into the exposure
Tristan Egolf, and Michael Chabon, do not provide of an alterity lying outside cultural horizons. After al-
me merely with crude pleasure. Nor can I bring my- lowing for the qualifications and restrictions Attridge
self to dismiss them as instances of “making” rather adds, I still fear that such extensive reliance on alterity
than “creating” (a distinction invoked by Attridge is too limiting.
to describe producing according to tested formula in As for the weaker version of the argument (accord-
opposition to genuine creation). Yet my admiration ing to which some literature operates in the ways At-
for these novels does not spring from them open- tridge specifies), here the problem is that harping on
ing up a cultural blind spot. I will not be surprised if literature’s capacity to step beyond the cultural ma-
critics would expose such merits. But my pleasure in trix risks ignoring the fictionality of what a “cultural
reading these had little to do with discovered alter- matrix” is. Talk of “cultural horizons,” “limitations,”
ity, and was pieced together from altogether different “lacunas,” and such is never simply descriptive, but is
qualities (being finely written, complex, insightful, a fabricated image that is hooked onto an incomplete
richly characterized, patient, subtle, funny, intense, collage of texts. Although Attridge would surely ac-
moving, witty, multilayered, alarming, absorbing, knowledge this, his emphasis on response to alterity
and so on). seems to rely on the kind of simplified realism that, if
How about canonical literature? In the first Shake- examined as such, he is bound to reject. The implica-
speare class I attended as an undergraduate, we read tion is that we are never in the hypothetical location
some moments from the first act of Richard II. I was Attridge requires us to inhabit in order to appreci-
struck by Mowbray’s response to his banishment, his ate the singularity of literature. We can never know
sense of dissociation not, as could be expected, from what these horizons and limitations are. Intellectual
friends and kin, but from language as such: “The lan- maps are imposed, and once this is conceded, pressing
guage I have learnt these forty years, My native En- us to look for the singularity of literature in remold-
glish, now I must forgo . . . Within my mouth you have ing boundaries sounds more unstable than what first
engaoled my tongue, Doubly portcullised with my meets the eye.
teeth and lips” (I.3). Appreciating the striking images One intriguing component Attridge throws into
in this speech has nothing to do with refashioning con- his account of literary singularity is the idea of perfor-
ventions of lament. I was taken by the liveliness of the mance. Literature is an event, enacted—performed—
lines and the imaginative leaps that they make in per- by the reader. Specifically, Attridge proposes that
ceiving teeth as a portcullis of the tongue, construing salient aspects of reading—relating to the text as
displaced existence as a physically disrupted wish to referring to some reality, or as facilitating forms of
speak. I recently had occasion to revisit these lines— witnessing, or as truth-telling, or as disclosing emo-
this time as a teacher. What I can now find in them is tional intensity—are all performances of language by
how they subliminally comment on and criticize the a reader as enabled by a particular text. Literature
dull, limited, and militant images of “England” pro- does not, for example, provide truths: “We learn from
vided by some of the play’s principal characters. Yes, literature, not truth, but what the telling (or denying)
it is possible to argue for some growing/emerging na- of truth is . . . literature does not present themes as
tionalism in Shakespeare’s England to which the lines such but rather takes the reader through a process of
respond, but doing so is unnecessary, and the power thematization” (p. 97). In a similar tack, while literary
of the images does not depend on such argument. works can be testimonies, their specific contribution
Cultural horizons are not being refashioned, for us lies not in recording distressing events but in staging
or for Shakespeare’s audience, and alterity does not “the activity of witnessing” (p. 97).
Book Reviews 421

One would want to know more about this process, to mention considerably fewer literary gifts. It is natu-
and to see some elaborate examples of such perfor- ral for a philosopher focusing on Shakespeare’s art to
mativity (the book offers two samples from poetry, attribute philosophical ideas to Shakespeare, to see
and Attridge refers us to his book on Coetzee, J. M. in his scripts a proclivity for philosophical inquiry,
Coetzee and the Ethics of Reading: Literature in the and finally to come to think of Shakespeare’s works
Event [University of Chicago Press, 2005]—which I as embodying a philosophy, if only in a loose and
have not read—for examples from prose). But what breezy sense of the word.
he provides here is suggestive and worthy. The nov- Colin McGinn explicates philosophical topics in
elty resides in what Attridge is positively ascribing to some of Shakespeare’s most extraordinary writings
the act of reading. Others (such as Peter Lamarque for the theatre. After a brief preface, McGinn’s study
and Stein Haugom Olsen in their Truth, Fiction and begins with a chapter on “General Themes” and then
Literature: A Philosophical Perspective [Oxford Uni- proceeds to detailed examinations of Shakespeare’s
versity Press, 1997]) have already distinguished be- A Midsummer Night’s Dream, Hamlet, Othello, Mac-
tween comprehending thematic content and assert- beth, King Lear, and The Tempest, before turning
ing that it is true (literature, in their opinion, as in to a suite of essays on specialized topics, including
Attridge’s, extends to the former and not the latter). “Shakespeare and Gender,” “Shakespeare and Psy-
What I find in Attridge on this front is an impor- chology,” “Shakespeare and Ethics,” “Shakespeare
tant exposure of a further facet of literature, situated and Tragedy,” and “Shakespeare’s Genius.” The book
in between comprehending and asserting. “Perfor- concludes with notes, bibliography, and an index.
mativity” here designates the following through of Throughout, McGinn demonstrates great sensi-
a process that is configured by the text and under- tivity to a variety of narrative nuances in Shake-
gone by the reader. We can thus distill three layers speare’s plays. In the course of presenting sharply
of the relationship between literature and concep- focused overviews of plot lines and character devel-
tual/philosophical outcroppings: the first relating to opment in the works he discusses, McGinn identifies
thematizing, the second to asserting that the thema- three major categories of philosophical preoccupa-
tized content is true, and the third to the process of tion. Shakespeare, he claims, is particularly interested
weaving together the truth-claims as such. And while in epistemological problems of knowledge and skep-
Attridge downplays the import (or the specifically ticism, citing A Midsummer Night’s Dream and Oth-
literariness) of the first two functions, center-staging ello as prime examples; the concept of self , treating
the third, I see nothing to prevent welcoming his con- Hamlet, among other works, as illustrating his the-
tribution into more comprehensive accounts of the sis; and the metaphysics of causality, especially in
relationship between literature and knowledge. Shakespeare’s King Lear. McGinn retells the essen-
Hopefully, the counterthoughts that I have formu- tial details of these plays as they relate to his argument
lated in response to Attridge convey the book’s ca- that they exemplify interest in a specific problem of
pacity to invite engagement and further investigation. philosophy. He gathers evidence from the texts to
In all, The Singularity of Literature is a wise and im- make the case that Shakespeare was engaged in the
portant exploration into the distinctiveness of litera- literary exploration of contemporary philosophical
ture. questions in epistemology, philosophy of mind, and
metaphysics.
TZACHI ZAMIR Thus, in describing the role of Puck at the conclu-
Department of English sion of A Midsummer Night’s Dream, McGinn writes:
The Hebrew University of Jerusalem “The epilogue to the play, spoken by Robin Good-
fellow (Puck), reminds the audience of its own role
mcginn, colin. Shakespeare’s Philosophy: Discov- in imaginatively generating the play it has just wit-
ering the Meaning Behind the Plays. New York: nessed, and toys with precisely the dream skepticism
HarperCollins Publishers, 2006, viii + 230 pp., invoked by Descartes and Montaigne: ‘If we shad-
$24.95 cloth. ows have offended, Think but this, and all is mended:
That you have but slumbered here, While these vi-
Trying to pinpoint exactly what makes William sions did appear; And this weak and idle theme, No
Shakespeare’s plays so timelessly absorbing is a long- more yielding but a dream, Gentles do not repre-
standing problem of aesthetic criticism and philo- hend. If you pardon, we will mend.’ Robin is suggest-
sophical reflection. There is evidently something ing that the audience has itself been dreaming—and
more to the Stratford bard than an evening’s enter- how, indeed, can they be certain they did not dream
tainment of tortured prose. Shakespeare’s works are the whole thing? Surely, as Descartes would insist,
intellectually stimulating in ways that far surpass the it is logically possible to dream that you have been
escapism afforded by comedies and dramas produced watching a play about dreaming, taking it to be real-
by lesser talents with less serious preoccupations, not ity” (p. 33).
422 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This single passage illustrates McGinn’s general there is little evidence that Shakespeare, despite wide
method in discovering and documenting all three reading in history, geography, and literature, visited
of the philosophical themes he attributes to Shake- many other philosophers’ pages with serious intent.
speare. Spending time at the theatre is indeed a kind If the argument for Shakespeare having a philosophy
of holiday from reality, as are fantasy and dreams. is in part that he read, sometimes even cribs from, and
When Robin proposes conditionally that the audi- weaves reflections from Montaigne’s Essays and the
ence members might consider that they have been Defense of Raymond Sebond into his plays, we must
sleeping and rapt in dreams during the play’s perfor- further ask whether and in what sense Montaigne is
mance, he does indeed sound a philosophical theme or has a philosophy. Some commentators today are
that Montaigne, Descartes, and later philosophers willing to extend this label to the essayist, while oth-
have entertained. McGinn identifies these lines of ers are more skeptical. What is not in doubt is that
dialogue or situation in which a Shakespearean char- Montaigne and Shakespeare examine in literary fash-
acter as spokesperson in some sense for the author’s ion ideas that are in one way or another the common
ideas can reasonably be construed as caught up in property of every thinking person, part and parcel,
considering a philosophical subject. McGinn then so to speak, of the human condition. Iago deceiving
characteristically proceeds to attach a higher level Othello by concealing his true thoughts, and Othello
of contemporary professional philosophy’s concerns being unable to know this other conspiring revenge-
with the topic than it appears plausible to ascribe to ful mind as well as he understands his own beliefs and
Shakespeare himself. intentions is, of course, a problem of interest to episte-
In the above quotation, for example, Robin Good- mologists and philosophical psychologists. Whether,
fellow does not challenge the audience to prove that in portraying such commonplace occurrences, shared
it has not merely been dreaming. He merely invites by innumerable works of fiction whose authors one
those in attendance to consider that they may have would not dream of classifying as philosophers or as
dreamt the events of the play if the performers have having a philosophy, Shakespeare should be ranked
in any way offended them, entirely, it appears, as a way in this way is a matter about which McGinn in the end
of assuaging the possibility that they might otherwise does not entirely persuade a reader who is looking for
have taken the comedy too seriously or literally. In ef- something more definitive of genuine philosophical
fect, Robin says, if you are annoyed by what you have reflection.
seen, treat it as though the scenes were played before It is worth remarking also in this connection that
you in a dream. This strikes me as a rather far cry from McGinn finds in Shakespeare precisely the kinds
saying that Shakespeare was questioning the episte- of philosophical topics that McGinn himself, among
mology of sense certainty in light of the logical possi- others, has actively pursued in his own philosophi-
bility that the contents of sense experience might be cal writings. Other Shakespeare critics, such as Terry
nothing more substantial than a well-ordered series Eagleton in his celebrated 1967 Shakespeare and
of dream images. This is, as McGinn rightly remarks, Society: Critical Studies in Elizabethan Drama
something that Descartes would have insisted was (Schocken), William Shakespeare (Rereading Liter-
conceivable, at least until Meditation III in his Med- ature) (Blackwell, 1986), and Literary Theory: An In-
itations on First Philosophy, when the “solution” to troduction (Blackwell, 2nd ed. 1997), have looked at
skepticism appears in the existence of God as guar- some of the same plays as McGinn and found rather
antor of the veracity of all our clear and distinct per- different topics of equally general “philosophical” in-
ceptions. But is it also true of Shakespeare? Robin terest. Where McGinn considers Lear and Hamlet as
Goodfellow does not mention the concept of cer- deep probings of the concept of self, a chapter in verse
tainty when he playfully proposes to the audience of inquiry into the philosophy of mind and the limita-
in jest that it discount whatever may have failed to tions of knowledge, Eagleton finds evidence of social
please it in the play as though the same were merely instability and a breakdown of the feudal order, lead-
the product of a dream. An equally if not more credi- ing to the rise of capitalism in Shakespeare’s time,
ble interpretation of the epilogue is that Shakespeare interpreting the assassinations of royalty as emblem-
is indulging in simile, declaring through Robin that atic of the general social upheaval. Where McGinn,
watching a play unfold is rather like a dream; not that quite insightfully, in my opinion, characterizes Ham-
we cannot tell the difference between the two, let let and Macbeth as diametrically opposed in char-
alone that we cannot do so to a high degree of epis- acter portrayal when read as studies of personhood
temic certainty. Shakespeare barely skins these philo- in relation to the theory of action, Eagleton over-
sophical issues, where McGinn adds many a pound of looks these differences for the sake of the underlying
flesh. unity of political turmoil and disorder the two dramas
McGinn knows that Shakespeare read Montaigne. represent. Shakespeare’s narrative poem “Lucretia,”
Beyond his early education memorizing the pithy not mentioned by McGinn, is another good case in
pronouncements of classic Latin authors, however, point, with a political moral presented as a human
Book Reviews 423

drama. The infamous rape of a virtuous woman by have depended on his plays, as opposed to his poetry,
Sextus Tarquinius represents royal abuse of power for securing his literary fame. Yet the poems, inter-
more generally, and leads historically to the perpe- esting as they are as classical mythological set pieces
trator’s undoing by an outraged public, and subse- in their own right, and the enigmatic sonnets, if these
quently to the dismantling of the royal house and represent Shakespeare’s own sense of his importance
founding of the republic in ancient Rome. Richard as a serious writer, have nothing particularly philo-
Louis Halpern’s Shakespeare Among the Moderns sophical about them, nor does McGinn devote any
(Cornell University Press, 1997) offers yet another space in the book to their consideration.
choice of topics that are interesting to philosophers, Rather than expressing a philosophy, McGinn’s
on the strength of which we would be equally hard- own remarks on Shakespeare’s plays evince instead,
pressed to describe Shakespeare as a philosopher or and far more convincingly, a penetrating grasp of
as possessing a philosophy in anything like the man- a variety of aspects of psychology. Indeed, a more
ner of such contemporaries as Francis Bacon or Nic- accurate title for the book would be precisely this.
colo Machiavelli. It is one thing to pick up philosoph- McGinn seems to recognize the theme in many places
ical ideas from others and lace them into a work of throughout his discussion, and especially in the essay
literature, and quite another to address philosophical on “Shakespeare’s Psychology.” Another important
problems philosophically as original contributions to psychological theme McGinn touches on in several
philosophy. places is that of every person as adopting a mask or
Moreover, there are serious gaps in McGinn’s crit- literal persona for social interaction. In many of the
ical methodology that make it difficult to share his plays McGinn explores, Shakespeare seems to antic-
enthusiasm for Shakespeare as a philosopher. For ipate an attitude, as McGinn notes, that is more fully
one thing, McGinn does not venture far enough into developed by Erving Goffman in his 1959 study, The
the historical background of the works he exam- Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (Doubleday).
ines. He does not look into the precursor sources Shakespeare’s personal involvement as an actor and
of plays written by other authors that, in many in- author of so many distinctive three-dimensional char-
stances, Shakespeare adapted. Shakespeare is well acters, together, perhaps, with the need during his life-
known and widely appreciated as having made bet- time to disguise his own Catholic religious beliefs in
ter use of source material when rewriting in his own a generally Protestant community, makes the discus-
idiom extant plays that were already available in sion of persons appearing masked in society an im-
manuscript or playbooks of the time. An in-depth portant connecting thread in many of McGinn’s chap-
and authoritative examination of Shakespeare’s pre- ters. McGinn, on the other hand, who surely knows
decessors is made, among others, by Park Honan in better, nevertheless confuses things terminologically
his Shakespeare: A Life (Oxford University Press, by referring to the problem of subjective opacity as
1998). There, we learn important details about the the problem of other minds, a label more standardly
content of plays by other writers that Shakespeare used to designate the epistemic difficulty of know-
assimilated and improved on in producing scripts for ing whether other subjectivities exist posed by the
the theatre. Nor, of course, was Shakespeare alone conceivability of solipsism, or by the outright meta-
in this practice at a time when writing for the stage physical denial that minds other than one’s own exist.
was not regarded as legitimate literature and when The real theme of Othello, I would say, in any case,
plays evolved as they still do today through improvi- from a psychological point of view, and contrary to
sation and additions made by actors in the course of McGinn, is not the title character’s jealousy or the
their actual performance. If it turns out that some of universal epistemic limitations to which he and every
the philosophical ideas touched on in Shakespeare’s other thinker is limited, but his unruly pride.
plays are part of the sources from which he borrowed, Having criticized the premise of McGinn’s recent
then at most we can make the case for his choices as exposition of Shakespeare’s oeuvre, I now want to
reflecting a certain philosophical disposition, rather say that none of these misgivings makes any differ-
than as the original product of a creative philosophi- ence with respect to the enormous value of McGinn’s
cal intellect. These vital topics, again, do not occupy book. That Shakespeare makes reference to many
McGinn in identifying what he takes to be the main aspects of human life that are of interest to philoso-
lines of Shakespeare’s philosophy. phers is something we may have suspected before
The question of Shakespeare’s own attitude to- reading McGinn. What we gain from McGinn is im-
ward his plays, as opposed to his narrative poems measurably worthwhile if we take from it not a con-
and sonnets, raises yet another problem about the viction that Shakespeare is himself a philosopher, but
extent to which Shakespeare can seriously be consid- rather the insights of McGinn’s own philosophical de-
ered to have developed a philosophy, or even to have liberations on an interrelated set of topics by which
scrounged one from Montaigne. In keeping with the Shakespeare’s dramatizations are uniquely illumi-
attitudes of his time, Shakespeare is known not to nated. When we read McGinn on Shakespeare we
424 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

are prepared to reread Shakespeare with a new un- unifying theme to the book—in fact, the editors take
derstanding and deeper appreciation of the artistry, pains to explicitly reject the existence of any unifying
profound perception of human character, and com- theme and to point out that some of the essays deploy
plexity of Shakespeare’s achievement. We may read arguments that contradict arguments found in other
Shakespeare thereafter through the eyes of a philoso- essays.
pher, even if we are not equally tempted to read much The editors do, however, express a belief that the-
philosophy into Shakespeare. ater and philosophy are “kindred disciplines”—that
they share important similarities of method and telos.
DALE JACQUETTE Specifically, “[t]he critical link that holds theater and
Department of Philosophy philosophy together is the act of seeing. Observing
The Pennsylvania State University events, actions, responses, gestures, and behaviors,
along with hearing sounds, voices, tones, and rhythms,
krasner, david, and david z. saltz, eds. Staging Phi- brings us closer to understanding the realities that un-
losophy: Intersections of Theater, Performance and derlie surface appearances. . . . Both theater and phi-
Philosophy. University of Michigan Press, 2006, losophy represent humans actively engaging with and
344 pp., $70.00 cloth, $28.95 paper. in the world, and a basic technique both employ to
that end is dialogue” (pp. 3–4). The dialogue referred
Although canonical philosophers such as Plato, Niet- to is not only that of certain philosophical works, such
zsche, and Rousseau were very much interested in the as those by Plato or Hume, but the dialogue with one
form and substance of theater, this ancient art form another through which professional philosophers re-
has been mostly neglected by contemporary aesthet- fine their ideas and further various inquiries. This lat-
ics, especially analytic aesthetics, even as the other ter type of dialogue, the editors contend, is an “action
narrative arts have received a great deal of attention performed within a dramatic exchange of arguments
in recent years. Many different professional philoso- and assertions” (p. 4)—just like the dialogue that fur-
phers have analyzed film, literature, and even televi- thers the action in many theatrical performances.
sion in a variety of ways, but “very few professional The view that there is a link between theatrical per-
philosophers have focused in depth on questions per- formance and philosophy is intriguing and has an an-
taining to the phenomena of theater or performance” cient pedigree. For instance, the French philosophes
(p. 1). The near total silence on theater is particu- believed that theater, especially comedy, not only
larly strange in the context of the still raging moral- served the same purpose as philosophical ethics, but
ism/autonomism debate in analytic aesthetics, since did a better job of achieving that purpose (Jean-
of all the arts theater has the richest and longest his- François Marmontel, “Encyclopedia: Comedy,” in
tory of conflict with morality in its various forms— Dramatic Theory and Criticism: Greeks to Grotowski,
secular, religious, and philosophical (see my “What [Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1974]). Perhaps most
Rousseau Teaches Us about Live Theatrical Perfor- famously, Nietzsche characterized theater (or, more
mance,” JAAC 62 [2004]). precisely, tragedy) and philosophy as two antagonis-
However, this state of affairs may be changing. The tic competitors for the same prize: each of them at-
2007 Annual Meeting of the American Society for tempts to conceptually structure human culture, but
Aesthetics will feature a panel on the aesthetics of in fundamentally different ways (as in his The Birth
theatrical performance. In December 2007, Kansas of Tragedy). Theater’s medium is emotion and de-
State University will be hosting a symposium on “The sire, whereas philosophy deploys logic and reason.
Art of Performance.” And since late 2006, a number On this view, the Platonic dialogues represent phi-
of philosophical works on theater have been pub- losophy’s triumph, and it is no coincidence that they
lished, including James Hamilton’s The Art of The- usurp theater’s form in the process.
ater (Blackwell, 2007), my “What is a Theatrical Per- Though Staging Philosophy contains no unifying
formance?” (JAAC 64 [2006]), and the book being theme or thesis aside from the link between phi-
reviewed here. losophy and theater discussed above, four of the
Staging Philosophy is a collection of fifteen essays essays—as it happens, the first essay in Section 1,
by fifteen different scholars. The essays represent a the first two in Section 2, and the first in Section
variety of disciplines, including analytic philosophy, 3—take up a theme that is central to the philoso-
continental philosophy, performance studies, and lit- phy of theater: the ontological character of theatri-
erature, and are grouped into three main thematic cal performance. Are theatrical performances inter-
categories: “History and Method,” “Presence,” and pretations of their scripts and therefore secondary
“Reception.” The editors’ aim in compiling this col- to the art of literature, or are they a separate,
lection of essays, as stated in their Introduction, is to primary art form that cannot be reduced to any writ-
“examine key issues in theater and [live] performance ing? Each of the four essays is concerned with this
from a philosophical perspective” (p. 2). There is no question, but in completely different ways. Julia A.
Book Reviews 425

Walker’s “The Text/Performance Split Across the means (as Walker puts it, “to understand something
Analytic/Continental Divide” analogizes the onto- fully, we must inhabit both ‘inside’ and ‘outside’ per-
logical question to the debate between different styles spectives while interpolating the difference between
of philosophy. Philip Auslander and Noël Carroll, in them in a reduction ad absurdum” [p. 38]). Though an
back-to-back essays entitled “Humanoid Boogie: Re- analogy can be drawn between the debate about the
flections on Robotic Performance” and “Philosophy ontology of theatrical performance and the debate
and Drama: Performance, Interpretation, and Inten- about the proper method and scope of philosophy,
tionality,” respectively, engage each other from oppo- we must be careful not to carry it too far.
site ends of the ontological debate over the status of The “Presence” section of the book begins with
theatrical performance. And in “Infiction and Outfic- a fascinating debate between Philip Auslander and
tion: The Role of Fiction in Theatrical Performance,” Noël Carroll about whether or not live performance
David Saltz attempts to reconcile the two sides of the is aesthetically significant. The point of departure for
question by preserving the value of theater’s unique Auslander’s argument is a work called Abacus by
liveness while at the same time explaining the role Sergei Shutov, which was displayed in the Russian
of interpretation in understanding theatrical perfor- pavilion at the 2001 Forty-Ninth Venice Biennial In-
mances after the live moment has passed. ternational Exposition of Art. The work consists of
In the “History and Method” section of the book, “forty crouching figures draped in black, which face
Julia A. Walker superimposes what she calls the an open door and pray in numerous languages rep-
“text/performance” split onto the divide between resenting a multitude of faiths while making the rev-
continental and analytic philosophy. Walker believes erential movements appropriate to prayer” (p. 87).
that the clash in philosophy of theater between those The figures are robots, but Auslander nevertheless
who privilege the script versus those who privi- claims that the artwork is a performance. On his view
lege the live, embodied performance is essentially (which he derives from a distinction first proposed by
the same clash we find in twentieth-century West- Stan Godlovitch), performers can have either inter-
ern philosophy between the “analytical tradition of pretative skills or technical skills. Interpretive skills
Bertrand Russell,” which privileges “the formal rela- create meaning, either emotional or cognitive, for the
tions among propositions in statements made about audience. Technical skills create actual, physical ef-
the world,” and the “phenomenological tradition of fects. In music, technical skill governs the manipula-
Edmund Husserl,” which privileges “the knowing tion of musical instruments such that the appropri-
subject who engage[s] in [formal] relations with the ate range of sound is produced. In theatrical perfor-
world” (pp. 25–26). mance, the actor’s body and voice are the instruments,
Walker’s analysis is interesting and sugges- which are skillfully deployed to create the appropri-
tive. However, I would point out that the ate range of gestures, poses, and mannerisms. Aus-
text/performance debate in philosophy of theater is lander argues that the Abacus robots, while bereft of
not about different approaches to a particular prac- interpretational skills, possess technical skills, “since
tice but about the proper ontological account of the- their actions cause the effects that constitute the
atrical performance. The question at the heart of content of the piece” (p. 89). He compares this al-
the split is: Are theatrical performances essentially leged performance to certain mass-produced theatri-
scriptable such that they are either interpretations cal performances. Are the Abacus robots so different
of written plays or, in the case of certain improvised from the touring company production of The Lion
works, the genesis of written plays, or is there some- King, where human actors give exactly the same me-
thing aesthetically significant about the live event that chanical performance—the same choreography, the
is more than just an interpretation of a script and, same line readings, the same blocking—night after
because of the ephemeral and event-specific condi- night? The implication of Auslander’s view for the
tions of the life performance, cannot be completely ontological question is that liveness cannot be used
captured in words after the performance has ended? to aesthetically distinguish theatrical performances
Walker is correct that there is something of this di- from their scripts because liveness has no aesthetic
chotomy in the methodological split between ana- significance.
lytic and continental philosophy. Painting with a very Carroll’s essay in response covers much of the
broad brush, we can say that analytic philosophers, same ground regarding theatrical performance he has
as a general rule, have faith in the ability of the third- already covered in A Philosophy of Mass Art (Oxford
person perspective of objective reason to capture University Press, 1998) and “Interpretation, Theatri-
the truth about the world, whereas many continental cal Performance, and Ontology” (JAAC 59 [2001]).
philosophers (particularly phenomenologists) main- He believes that scripts are the “recipes” for live per-
tain that an aspect of the world—the subjective, first- formances. Every performance of a play is a token of
person point of view—will always be hidden from ob- that play, just as every screening of a film is a token
jective reason and must be approached through other of the film. The difference between play-types and
426 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

film-types is the process by which their particular to- by side with the fictional story of its script, the fic-
kens are generated. Film-tokens are generated by tional story structures the real event of performance.
means of a mechanical “template,” whereas play- He calls this the “infiction” of a performance—
tokens are generated via the interpretive acts of the- ”the fictional schema that structures the performance
ater artists: templates are functions of nonintentional event.” A theatrical performance also has “outfic-
mechanical or electrical processes, whereas interpre- tion,” which is the “narrative content that we extract
tations are the actions of agents. from the performance event through an act of in-
To this account Carroll adds the notion that “ac- terpretation” (p. 214). Thus Saltz’s view attempts to
tors adjust their performances to live audiences; they explain the role of interpretation in theatrical perfor-
assay the temper of the crowd, and reinterpret their mance and thereby put what I have called the on-
lines appropriately. Tonight add a dash of irony; to- tological question to rest. According to Saltz, per-
morrow, be a pound more serious” (p. 119). The claim formances do not interpret scripts. They use scripts
is that in theatrical performance, “liveness” is not sim- to structure the performance event for both actors
ply a matter of living people up on stage. Rather, and audience, and thus make the performance in-
“liveness” stands for the fact that during the course telligible. Audiences may interpret the performance
of every live theatrical performance, actors and audi- in such a way that the story of the script is de-
ence have to contend with each other in shared phys- rived. However, “the infiction alone is often suffi-
ical space. If this is an accurate account of “liveness” cient to render a moment meaningful in the theater”
(and I believe it is, since it is the exact same account (p. 216).
of liveness I present in “What is a Theatrical Perfor- Staging Philosophy is an important contribution
mance?”), then Auslander’s analogy between robot to the philosophy of theater, and to theater studies,
performers and mechanical human performers col- that will hopefully spark further scholarship in this
lapses. Regardless of how mechanical a human per- underexplored field. Though not all the essays will
former is from night to night, he or she still has to con- appeal to all readers, the book is recommended.
tend with the live audience and, more importantly,
the live audience has to contend with him or her. DAVID OSIPOVICH
This is a capacity automatons simply do not have. To Department of Philosophy
put the same point in a slightly different way: when University of Iowa
a human performance is characterized as mechani-
cal, this is merely an axiological, not an ontological, ridley, aaron. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to
consideration. Nietzsche on Art. London: Routledge, 2007, 208
“Reception”—the final section of the book— pp., $90.00 cloth, $24.95 paper.
opens with David Saltz’s attempt to explain the role
of fiction in theatrical performance. His thesis is that Aaron Ridley’s stimulating new book testifies bril-
theatrical performance does not comprise a fictional liantly to the dynamic interpretive growth in English-
world that facilitates the audience seeing through to language Nietzsche studies during the past twenty
some reality that the fictions stands for or signifies; years. In this text aimed at nonspecialists, Ridley as-
rather, theatrical performance is a real event, and it is sembles many of the major voices to have spoken to
this reality that allows theater to survive in the “film Nietzsche’s views on art and considers their contri-
age.” Saltz argues against a view he calls “dualism.” butions to the most prominent and distinctive ques-
According to this view, “the events that actually tran- tion to sustain his critical engagement, that of art’s
spire in the theater assume significance only insofar necessity. Given their variety and detail, Nietzsche’s
as they apprise the audience of some other event, of- views on art through the years of his writing appear
ten fictional, always absent. The audience looks at unlikely to underwrite a single prevailing philosoph-
the stage in order to look beyond the stage. In per- ical thesis, and Ridley eschews such an exegetical
formance, actors cease to exist as or for themselves, course. The book instead considers the question con-
and become instead the stand-in for an absent and cerning art that most occupies Nietzsche’s attention
perhaps nonexistent other” (p. 204). There is also a through successive periods of his work and that elic-
modified, weaker version of this view that conceives its varying responses as the metaphysical, ethical, and
the fictional and performative (real) aspects of a per- broader aesthetic commitments of his texts continue
formance as existing side by side, but in such a way to fluctuate. In introducing this question and exam-
that an audience member can focus only on one or the ining its significance, Ridley outlines an element of
other at any given moment: either I am conscious of Nietzsche’s thought in a way likely not only to clarify
Olivier playing Hamlet, or I am conscious of Hamlet, for nonspecialists the character of Nietzsche’s rela-
but I cannot be conscious of both at the same time. tion to the arts, but further to stimulate ongoing work
Saltz’s alternative to these views is that, rather than on Nietzsche’s treatment of art by Nietzscheans and
a theatrical performance signifying or existing side aestheticians alike.
Book Reviews 427

To ask, as Nietzsche does, whether art is necessary we commonly employ (p. 32), this ability is not ad-
and why that should be so, invites several rejoinders mired through all the moments of his thought, as for
that Ridley sets out to consider. Which arts? And instance when the artists (Künstlers) in guilt feelings
necessary for whom? From the vast cultural array of make their appearance in the final essay of On the
artists, media, audiences, through the movement of Genealogy of Morals (cf. p. 81). Falsity, then, modi-
historical epochs, we might expect necessities to di- fies Nietzsche’s understanding of the necessity of art,
verge, and it is this multiplicity of answers that Niet- revealing distinct meanings for different artists, spec-
zsche’s writing on art endeavors faithfully to appreci- tators, and interpreters. Whether and why such falsifi-
ate. The necessities for a Sophocles as a tragedian may cation is necessary speaks to the health and the deca-
differ from those of a Wagner, as may those of their dence with which it is sought, questions that come
principal audiences, while the tragic forms properly more fully into view as Ridley’s discussion of the fig-
may lend themselves rather to a range of necessities ures and periods paramount in Nietzsche’s reflections
distinct from those of the other dramatic arts. Once unfolds over the course of a half dozen chapters.
a bearer of the return of healthy Dionysian forces In surrounding the arts with such issues as neces-
into European culture, Wagner becomes associated, sity, truth, decadence, health, production, and con-
for Nietzsche, with the necessities of his culture’s sumption, Nietzsche’s writing also raises broader
decadence, its requirement for no less than a saturat- questions about the proper province of the arts and
ing narcosis in the face of exhaustion. Alongside the the ethics that may accompany our relations to it. One
decadent, healthy artists and their interpreters and of the virtues of Ridley’s analysis appears in the at-
spectators have their necessities as well: to cultivate tention he affords to the aesthetic considerations that
the interests and perspectives that return an intensity come to govern the relation to the self in Nietzsche’s
to their willing activity—evidence the Renaissance. later work. An art of the self, discussed sometimes
Against these two pictures of health and decadence, as “self-creation” in the secondary literature, draws
Nietzsche examines artists and the arts, and Ridley’s Nietzsche’s interest through a sequence of develop-
discussion of the “need for art” (p. 78) leads through ments Ridley catalogues, most emphatically in the
the shifting incarnations of his thought to provide a Gay Science section “One Thing is Needful.” Here,
portrait of one of the most striking themes of this Nietzsche declares that a project of giving style to
engagement with art, that of falsity. one’s own character can begin to be defined, com-
As falsity remains an issue that has occupied the plete with the characteristic ironies such dispensa-
attention of numerous commentators and colored Ni- tion implies and the quality of the “needfulness” that
etzsche’s reception within the philosophical commu- may be involved. As a topic already familiar, certainly
nity, Ridley is no stranger to the debates over truth for readers of Ridley’s work, the “self-stylization” (p.
and the so-called perspectivism through which it here 131) sections of the book reflect something of the
is framed. Indeed, one of the particular strengths of ground that is covered in the present account. Here,
Ridley’s account is his handling of the broad assort- an art of the self, together with a conception of char-
ment of interpretive positions concerning these is- acter as itself a work of art, raises challenging ques-
sues to appear in recent literature. Given the abun- tions regarding our capacity for aesthetic relations
dance at times of more labored readings of Niet- toward human character, our tendencies to falsify, fic-
zsche’s perspectivism, Ridley approaches the ques- tionalize, conceal, and rearrange that character, and
tions of truth, falsity, and perspectives through their the relative decadence and affirmative amor fati with
treatments from within Nietzsche’s texts, beginning which our style emerges in this creative process. Ap-
with “On Truth and Lies in an Extra-Moral Sense” parent tensions over this mixture of falsification and
(in The Birth of Tragedy). This exegetical work gen- yes-saying come into view here, perhaps more clearly
erates a series of questions about art and falsity that than elsewhere in Nietzsche’s thinking, and Ridley
would be perhaps less likely to emerge from perspec- again develops a range of responses that add to the
tivist orthodoxies of the past—to wit, whether falsity literature as it presently stands.
is necessary, at times due to our decadence, at times Perhaps one of the most compelling discussions in
for our health, and whether the arts afford us admis- the book engages Nietzsche’s own attempt at self-
sion to perspectives from which such falsehoods may expression in the vexed and daunting Zarathustra
best be entertained. Falsification can make “bear- that begins the later period of his work. Why, in-
able” the meaning of realities (p. 85, cf. pp. 44, 139), deed, was Zarathustra necessary at all? Here, Rid-
particularly those that support our static reactivity. It ley’s analysis proves increasingly instrumental, as he
can also express a creativity whose “patterns of need pries apart Nietzsche’s efforts to impart to his audi-
and feeling” may be unfamiliar within the perspec- ence a prophetic sense of amor fati from the activity
tives to which we have become accustomed (p. 75). of other prophecy or ethical teaching against which it
While at times Nietzsche lauds our ability through might be compared. Rather than prophesy that “un-
art to “adopt a perspective that is external” to those hinges” (p. 81) its adherents from the interests and
428 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

affects their activities reveal, Nietzsche’s text draws bonds, mark evan. Music as Thought: Listening to
its audience to a way of seeing it has developed an the Symphony in the Age of Beethoven. Princeton
“ingrained tendency to reject” (p. 99). These difficul- University Press, 2006, xx + 169 pp., $29.95 cloth.
ties are compounded by the problems of a form of
art that tends to portray its leading character as it- When Arturo Toscanini conducted concertos with
self needing to believe the doctrine of eternal return. the NBC Symphony in the 1940s, the radio audience
To Ridley, the instabilities here are too great, and heard something they would never hear today. What
the text never resolves these tensions. Yet the project they heard was applause—the live audience clapped
does achieve an affirmation of Nietzsche’s sense that after the first movement. Applause between move-
art’s power “to invade and colonize the soul” of an ments was reported in Vienna in 1938 when Bruno
audience is unique (p. 111), and not the business of Walter conducted Mahler’s Ninth Symphony—one
philosophy, or philology, or the natural and human of his last performances before the Anschluss (al-
sciences to curry to themselves. Art may be necessary, though the clapping was removed from the ultimate
but it also makes itself necessary, and its perspectives recording of this concert). By the 1950s, though, audi-
may be difficult to unsettle; hence the challenges for ences no longer clapped between symphonic move-
new creative lines wherever the arts are at play. ments, setting aside a loud and lusty practice that was
My criticism of Nietzsche on Art would be its centuries old. Some ascribe the first suggestions of
brevity. Such themes as these call for heavily de- this change to Richard Wagner’s “Bayreuth Hush”—
tailed exposition of original texts, historical influ- a moment of golden silence before the downbeat,
ences, and surrounding interpretive literature, all of while others blame the band of silence placed on
which Ridley handles adroitly. Yet at times the issues mass-produced vinyl LPs. (And there are those who
at stake invite a more extensive consideration. This fault conductor Leopold Stokowski, who signaled the
may be forthcoming in a subsequent work, and at audience for silence between movements in the late
times the book takes on the appearance of precursor 1920s.)
to a larger project. Particularly provocative are some Concern about historically informed performance
of the larger questions of tensions that surround Ni- practice has become rather commonplace. We don’t
etzsche’s conception of falsification in the arts. Their use pianos for Bach basso-continuo if we can help
resolution may be well underway in the book already, it, and we worry which note should start the trill
but lengthier treatment would be welcome. As Niet- and whether the ornament is on or off the beat.
zsche says in his own nostalgic reminiscence at the (The issue of how to present an operatic castrato
closing of Beyond Good and Evil, there is a moment part authentically is still a sticky wicket.) However,
of felt failure in the dullness of the “painted thoughts” recreating a historically informed listening practice—
he has recorded, almost a falseness in his “truths,” understanding the historical context in which music
that would seem also to drive him onward. Tensions was heard—is relatively new territory.
over truth run through Nietzsche’s work to the end, Mark Evan Bonds’s thesis is that “people began
and associating them with an account of the arts may to listen to music differently in the closing decades
give a view of his concerns that properly incorporates of the eighteenth century, and this change in listen-
the place of truth and falsity in the creative processes ing opened up new perceptions toward music itself,
of thinking Nietzsche has sought to embody and particularly instrumental music” (p. xiii). For his orig-
examine. inal project, funded by the National Endowment for
Aaron Ridley exhibits Nietzsche’s evolving the Humanities, he translated an array of commen-
thought on art in a manner suited to stimulate de- taries on the symphony between 1720 and 1900. He
bate regardless of specialization. The details of his was a DaimlerChrysler Fellow in the fall of 2002 at
account attest to the progress in Nietzsche studies’ the American Academy in Berlin, where he was able
treatment of many of these questions that surround to observe “the immediacy of the continuing artistic,
the arts over the past two decades. That his account social, and political traditions that link an orchestra
speaks as well across lines of specialization attests and its listeners” (p. xi).
to a further dimension of what Nietzsche might con- Bonds is not the first to point to the year 1800 as a
sider progress in interpretation during this time. As pivotal moment in music history, but few accounts
the need for careful and creative understanding of Ni- bridge social, political, philosophical, and artistic
etzsche’s thought continues, Nietzsche on Art invites events as successfully as his Music as Thought: Lis-
future returns to Ridley’s work. It’s an argument to tening to the Symphony in the Age of Beethoven. The
health. gradual shift in performance venues from aristocratic
salons to public concert halls is at the crux of his ar-
TOM MEYER gument, and this momentous change in music’s re-
Department of Philosophy ception is too often ignored. The symphony became
Temple University an expression of a communal voice—a spiritual link
Book Reviews 429

between performers and listeners in these specially In Hoffmann’s own words: “Yet how does the matter
constructed places. It is not an accident, he argues, stand if it is your feeble observation alone that the
that Beethoven’s early decades in Vienna coincide deep inner continuity of Beethoven’s every compo-
with this move from private to public venues (al- sition eludes? If it is your fault alone that you do not
though some scholars have pointed to London for understand the master’s language as the initiated un-
a clearer example of this change, fascinatingly wit- derstand, that the portals of the innermost sanctuary
nessed in the newspaper articles of the time; see Si- remain closed to you? . . . [A]nd at the center of the
mon McVeigh’s and Alyson McLamore’s work in this spirit realm thus disclosed the intoxicated soul gives
area). ear to the unfamiliar language and understands the
The new symphonies for orchestra were expensive most mysterious premonitions that have stirred it”
to publish and required a large number of musicians (p. 36).
for performance. As Bonds writes, “[t]he emergence For the first time, Bonds states, in this one criti-
of the symphony as the most prestigious of all instru- cal review, we have an image of music as an organic
mental genres in the closing decades of the eighteenth whole, where a work encompasses “the unfolding of
century was in many respects an unlikely develop- a central musical idea, the close integration of con-
ment” (p. 1). Possibly, the expanded musical range trasting gestures, a trajectory leading from struggle
of the symphony was a natural result of improve- to triumph, all within a general framework of the
ments in the instruments themselves. In the early sublime” (p. 57). Hoffman’s urgent tone asserts that
nineteenth century, timpani began to have chromatic Beethoven’s Fifth and large symphonic works like it
pedals, valves became common on brass instruments, are perceived no longer as vehicles of entertainment
and woodwinds developed more efficient fingering but as vehicles of truth—a perception that has per-
systems. There was also a growing (and fortunate) sisted today. We don’t end the Olympic Games with
realization that organized rehearsals were essential a Mozart symphony. We end them with Beethoven’s
to good performances of large-scale pieces. Ninth and the “Ode to Joy.”
At the vortex of Music as Thought is this question: Hoffmann’s now infamous Romantic review is
What caused the transformation of attitude that oc- made to do some fairly heavy lifting here. A little
curred between Kant’s Critique of Judgment in 1790 E. T. A. Hoffmann goes a long way, but not nearly
and E. T. A. Hoffmann’s review of Beethoven’s Fifth far enough to shore up a comprehensive argument
Symphony in 1810—from Kant’s view of instrumen- for such a sea change in musical reception. To help
tal music as “more pleasure than culture” to Hoff- make his case, Bonds points to a number of contem-
mann’s assertion that music is the highest of all art porary writers and clothes the beginnings of Ideal-
forms (p. 8)? Bonds’s belief is that Hoffmann stated ism in meticulous social and political documentation.
a new paradigm, applied by virtually all subsequent Ample support is presented from the works of Jo-
commentators, in which Beethoven’s music created a hann Gottlieb Fichte, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von
new aesthetic: Listeners were now compelled to rise Schelling, August Wilhelm Schlegel, Wilhelm Hein-
to the level of the composer (p. 9). In Hoffman’s re- rich Wackenroder, Ludwig Tieck, Johann Gottfried
view, Mozart and Haydn act as individuals, leading us, Herder, and Christian Friedrich Michaelis, as well as
but Beethoven is invisible, opening up to us: “Thus from Hegel, Novalis, and Goethe. (Twentieth-century
Beethoven’s instrumental music also opens up to us music philosophers such as Theodor Adorno, Peter
the realm of the monstrous and immeasurable. Burn- Kivy, and Jerrold Levinson are mentioned only in
ing rays of light shoot through the deep night of this passing.) Bonds identifies the principal social ideals
realm, and we become aware of giant shadows that in early nineteenth-century Germany as a paradox-
surge back and forth, closing in on us in ever nar- ical blend of cosmopolitanism and nationalism. The
rower confines until they destroy us, but not the pain state, having previously been seen as a machine, is
of endless longing” (p. 35). now viewed as an organic conception: the individual
On Bonds’s view, Hoffmann’s idealism prioritizes should self-realize to the maximum so that he or she
spirit over matter. Special importance has now been might in turn contribute in the fullest manner to soci-
placed on the active nature of aesthetic perception, as ety as a whole (p. 71). Beauty, and especially musical
Bonds puts it: “the true essence of the artwork could beauty, develops the spirit of the individual and the
be grasped only through the power of imagination— community.
Einbildungskraft—a faculty capable of mediating be- Bonds parses these contemporary reviews and ac-
tween the senses and reason” (p. 12). Hoffmann’s counts to find a sense of exertion on the part of the au-
Beethoven review “articulates the shift from the En- dience, seeking the beginnings of an Idealism requir-
lightenment’s perception of music as a language, op- ing active listening and the reconstruction of musical
erating under the principles of rhetoric, to Romanti- works in the mind for full aesthetic effect. He makes
cism’s perception of music as a source of truth, op- believers of us—the musical discourse in German-
erating under the principles of philosophy” (p. 34). speaking lands during Beethoven’s lifetime certainly
430 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

seems extensive enough that we can reconstruct these ical of his general thoroughness: he does not restrict
earlier modes of musical perception at least in broad himself to a single type of reason, but acknowledges
outline (even though most of these writers speak only contributing philosophical, historical, economic, and
very generally to music’s affect, and do not usually art-historical factors. Specifically, these are (1) differ-
discuss specific works in detail). ences between gardens and artworks that are taken
Aestheticians are conversant with many of the as paradigmatic by philosophers of art—here he ac-
philosophical writings featured here, particularly knowledges my contribution; (2) the success of the
those of Kant and Hoffmann, and the argument for “museum conception of art” (as John Dewey called
the year 1800 as a pivotal point in Western music is it), to which gardens are stunningly in-apropos; (3)
familiar. Bonds’s contribution is in his wide embrace the philosophical influence of Hegel; and (4) the in-
of sociopolitical as well as philosophical sources. A creasingly divergent developmental paths of gardens
lagniappe is insight into the intrepid beginnings of and other arts during the “late modern” period.
musical criticism as such. It is this sort of rejection of the usual disciplinary
(and cultural) confines that permits the greatest
strengths of the book. His examination is exemplary
JENNIFER JUDKINS and the answers he provides are by and large con-
Department of Music vincing. If taken seriously, A Philosophy of Gardens
University of California, Los Angeles will move the field forward.
Let me begin with a brief summary of its many
cooper, david e. A Philosophy of Gardens. Oxford strengths. (There are no significant weaknesses; com-
University Press, 2006, 184 pp., 9 b&w illus., $35.00 ments on a few limitations appear at the end of this
cloth. review.)
As a scholar of Aristotle as well as the author of
David E. Cooper’s A Philosophy of Gardens is the a book on Buddhist ethics and environment, Bud-
first major contribution in nearly a decade to what dhism, Virtue and Environment (Ashgate, 2005), and
should be a burgeoning subfield field of philoso- fully conversant with the phenomenological litera-
phy, the study of gardens. (The last was Stephanie ture as well, Cooper brings a valuable range of philo-
Ross’s What Gardens Mean [University of Chicago sophical resources to bear on the topic.
Press, 1998].) It is an intricately argued, beautifully Cooper rounds up a lively bunch of garden writers
nuanced, and highly sensitive analysis of what gar- from across the centuries (and around the globe) to
dens mean and what sort of enterprise they are. provide the insights that provide the foundation for
Most important, it tackles the big questions about his analysis—although his use of his own first-person
gardens and gardening: How should we conceptu- experience is also evident and valuable. There are
alize the relations of gardens to “nature” (however wonderful quotations—including some that made me
that is conceptualized) and to “art”? Why do people laugh out loud.
garden? What is its relation to “the good life”? And The argumentation is rigorous. Cooper seems to
what are its relations to ethics? What is the meaning acknowledge all possible arguments and counter-
of “The Garden” (as he eventually phrases it)? And arguments. (At times this is as exhausting as it is
how does this meaning of “The Garden” relate to the exhaustive; there were a couple places, especially
various other kinds of meaning that people notice in Chapters 2, “Art or Nature?” and 3, “Art-and-
and describe in gardens? Nature,” where it began to feel a bit maze-like
Because of the importance of its central argu- even for me, but the sense of this as overly meticu-
ments, its applicability to garden traditions around lous scrupulosity disappeared entirely in subsequent
the world, its accessible style, and its insistence on chapters.) If he overlooked an opportunity to present
exploring the meaning of gardens to ordinary peo- the arguments for an assumption or premise he uti-
ple who garden and enjoy gardens (rather than, say, lized, or a conclusion he drew, I missed it.
to the field of philosophical aesthetics or the profes- The focus is on ordinary rather than “great” gar-
sion of landscape architecture), this book should be dens (which are unsatisfactory as the object for our
taught in every landscape architecture, architecture, philosophical analysis because they comprise such
city planning, and aesthetics program where students a numerically small portion of garden/ing encoun-
speak English. ters; also because they are not representative of en-
The book begins with a comment about the still counters that might be considered either “typical” or
great gap between the importance of gardens and gar- deeply significant personally). It is, ultimately, a study
dening (by virtually any measure) on the one hand of why people garden, of the significance of garden
and the relative paucity of philosophical examina- practices, rather than of end products—on garden-
tions of the topic on the other—a gap many have ing practices rather than final products (which are, in
remarked. Cooper’s handling of this question is typ- the case of gardens, a notoriously difficult stasis to
Book Reviews 431

achieve, after all). This means on the one hand that it plifying the degree to which, more subtly, experience
speaks to everyone’s everyday experience; it thus is of the natural environment depends upon human cre-
both more inclusive and more pertinent than an ac- ative activity. When combined, the two themes de-
count of “great gardens” would be. It also means that liver the idea of The Garden as embodying a unity
the study of gardens is set up in such a way that their between human beings and the natural world, an inti-
relations with ethics—in several forms—become per- mate co-dependence” (pp. 135–136). Oddly, he seems
spicuous and logical, rather than another or a special unaware that something very like the reciprocality he
category of the ethical dimensions of art. posits between human beings and nature has been the
The book is one of the rare works of Anglo-U.S. subject of a vast literature in Chinese philosophy, art,
philosophy that does not proceed solely on the basis and religion. Use of some of these Chinese ways of
of Western examples, but draws its basis of data from formulating the issues might have been valuable.
around the world, and not simply after the fact (just His more radical proposal is that “this co-
enough to make it “cross-cultural”), but in ways that dependence itself embodies or refers us to the
are allowed to shape the analysis from the beginning. co-dependence of human existence and the ‘deep
Cooper faces head on four persistently thorny is- ground’ of the world and ourselves. By embodying
sues in the philosophical study of gardens. First, the something that itself embodies something further, the
fourth chapter, “Gardens, People, and Practices,” is a Garden—in one of [Nelson] Goodman’s ‘chains of
fine study of the question whether the object of philo- reference’—embodies this ‘something further.’ The
sophical analysis should be the finished garden, the Garden, to put it portentously, is an epiphany of
“product” or artwork (if it is one), or the process of man’s relationship to mystery. This relationship is its
gardening itself. And if the latter—as he decides— meaning” (p. 145).
what processes are important? Here, he reaches a Although Cooper does not explicitly avow a Bud-
conclusion that moves the field forward: what counts dhist philosophical methodology or logic, it is not only
is not just the actual gardening, the creation of the as data—Buddhist examples of gardens and ways of
work, but the various mental and social practices that using gardens—that Buddhism shapes the argument.
are enabled by the process and the “finished” work Buddhist ways of thinking are crucial to his solution
(or work in progress, as is usually the case). of the basic problems in two ways; first, in his will-
The second vital issue is whether gardens should be ingness to reject dichotomous habits of thinking (be-
considered “art” or “nature.” Cooper bites the bul- tween product and process, and art and nature), and
let and argues that gardens occupy a unique position second, in the ultimate emphasis on the processes of
beyond the purely aesthetic and different from that gardening (gardening practices) rather than the final
of “wilderness.” product.
Ultimately (third) he is interested in the meaning Still, it stops far short of being a “Buddhist” analy-
of the garden, which, of course, can be answered only sis. Although he mentions the “ineffable,” he does
after (fourth) one has figured out how to determine not develop it. His rejection of the art/nature di-
what counts as an answer (pp. 131 ff). Cooper dis- chotomy is empirical rather than based on Buddhist
tinguishes the significance of the garden from seven logic. That is, he rejects it because it happens, on em-
modes of meaning commonly discussed in relation pirical grounds, not to fit the case, not because gar-
to gardens: the philosophically uninteresting “mere- dens can in principle be “neither art nor nature, nor
ological” and “instrumental”; two modes of repre- both art and nature.” Nothing is made of central Bud-
sentational meaning—“depictive” and “allusive”; ex- dhist notions such as transience, detachment, and il-
pression; “symptomatic meaning” (Paul Grice’s “nat- lusion.
ural” meaning, a symptom or sign by reason of a The following are meant less as criticisms of what
causal or contingent connection); and “associative.” is a major contribution to the field, than as caveats
None of these, he concludes, account for the sense of that he has not done everything.
significance we attribute to gardens, which is, for him, First, in spite of the fact that gardens seem to
inseparable from the question of the ethical contri- have been invented (both as a phenomenon and as
butions of the garden. These he situates within the an idea) as a contrast to the farm (no less than to
classical framework, namely, Aristotelian eudaimo- “wilderness” and the city), Cooper does not even al-
nia—although he also relates it to other traditions lude to the many important—and increasingly well-
and draws comparisons with Buddhist ethics. understood—connections between gardening and
Ultimately, Cooper argues for two versions of a agriculture. These connections need to be integrated
unique capability that gardens have. The “Modest into our thinking about gardens. They have particu-
Proposal” is that “The Garden exemplifies the mas- larly important implications for our understanding of
sive, but often unrecognized dependence of human how “virtues” have historically been associated with
creative activity upon the co-operation of the natural gardens and gardening, one of Cooper’s important
world . . .. [T]he second theme is The Garden’s exem- themes.
432 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Second, his version of “allusion” is misleading in a looked and underappreciated by philosophy. This
book that draws so heavily on Japanese material. (His matters more with an author who otherwise willingly
first example of allusion is of rocks in Japanese gar- rethinks the disciplinary assumptions so profoundly.
dens.) As he defines it, allusive meaning is the ability In a similar vein, the possibility of gardens’ contri-
of a physical/visual object (or formal arrangement of butions, by means of their sophisticated formal or-
objects) to suggest or represent something physical, ganization of somatic and kinaesthetic experience,
an idea (“impermanence or honor and fate” [p. 116]), to the historical development of ideas is utterly
or an affective state: “[r]ocks in Japanese gardens rep- ignored—a more notable omission in one who cites
resent islands and mountains . . . [or] ‘symbolize time Merleau-Ponty than it would be in the work of others.
in its longest imaginable extent, and therefore the This also (again, and as usual) leads philosophers
impermanence of all things’” (p. 117, quoted from away from the fundamental rethinking of vision and
Sunniva Harte, Zen Gardening [Sterwart, Tabori and visual organizations (artistic and other) of experience
Chang, 1999]). The mention of affective states then such as those that are routinely undertaken by psy-
turns him to a discussion of expression. But in the choanalysts.
study of Japanese arts and culture, allusion—often These are less flaws than oddities in a book that so
contrasted with symbolism—usually means referring masterfully moves us from the minutia of everyday
to another subjective experience (often of art), which experience to an explanation of the achievement of
may include ideas or affective states—one’s own or gardens to address ultimate issues and transform our
that of another person—and, especially, an experi- lives.
ence that has been captured in a work of art or liter- David E. Cooper has written a book that anyone
ature. A poem or painting of cherry blossoms alludes who wants to understand gardening, our relation-
to other artistic representations of cherry blossoms as ship with nature, and the arts will want to read. It’s
experienced by someone, it is the capturing of the re- the book I wanted to read (needed to read) twenty-
spective layers of subjective response that comprises five years ago; if it had existed then I wouldn’t have
the allusion. needed to write The Garden as an Art. His success
Third, his analysis of symbols is unduly restricted— with the most important of the issues will revitalize
although ultimately it gets him where he wants to the field.
go, to the idea of “something ‘spiritual,’ and possibly
ineffable, [that] ‘shows itself’ in sensible form, and MARA MILLER
thereby enables human beings to gain a sense of un- Philadelphia, Pennsylvania
derstanding of it” (p. 130)—which he calls, ultimately,
“epiphany.” quacchia, russell. Julia Morgan, Architect, and the
Finally, his analysis of gardens’ ability to repre- Creation of the Asilomar Conference Grounds.
sent or convey ideas suffers from the fact that he as- Philadelphia, PA: Xlibris, 2005, 253 pp., 75 b&w
sumes any idea a garden represents (such as “liberty” illus., $21.99 paper.
in eighteenth-century England) must already exist—
and in an already-settled linguistic form—rather than The appearance of Russell Quacchia’s book on Ju-
be an early form that is capable of influencing the lia Morgan has a special significance for members of
way the idea develops in the first place. In other the American Society for Aesthetics. Since the 1960s,
words, didn’t the eighteenth-century ideas of liberty the Pacific Division of the society has been meeting
develop partly in response to their at first dimly per- on a yearly basis, always in the spring, at the Asilo-
ceived intuitions that gardening was very like edu- mar Conference Grounds designed by Morgan. It is
cation and the political process—much as the early no doubt the exceeding beauty of the architecture
ideas of the modern self and the value of the individ- as well as the coastal setting in Pacific Grove that
ual were shaped by the development of Renaissance prompted the Pacific Division to make this location
one-point-perspective in painting? This is, perhaps, the permanent home for its conference. This is prob-
an arcane point (albeit one I argued for in The Gar- ably also the reason why the conference has never
den as an Art [SUNY Press, 1993]), but there are three been strictly regional, its participants coming from
implications of this view. throughout the world. Quacchia, a San-Francisco-
First, if one does not acknowledge the possibility based architect who was a partner in John Funk & As-
of originary contributions to intellectual thought by sociates and, later, architectural project manager for
gardens, one is reduced—as he is—to seeing those Stanford University, started visiting Asilomar during
“ideas” that one finds in gardens as little more than the 1960s and presented his first paper there on Julia
allegory—a conclusion he reaches that forces him to Morgan in 1977. A regular participant in Asilomar
dismiss the importance of ideas in gardens. meetings, he also gave presentations on Morgan’s ar-
This means that (second) the contributions of vi- chitecture at the ASA Asilomar meetings in 1999 and
sual arts to the history of ideas continue to be over- in 2004.
Book Reviews 433

Julia Morgan, born in San Francisco in 1872, was Asilomar buildings—“Artistically Considered” and
the first woman to receive a civil engineering degree “Experientially Considered.” There is also a series of
at University of California, Berkeley (1894), the first appendixes and an extensive bibliography. The book
woman to be accepted into the Ecole des Beaux Arts is well illustrated with historical photographs.
in Paris (she tried and failed to be accepted for two I will summarize Quacchia’s take on Morgan’s aes-
years before success in 1898), the first woman to grad- thetic assumptions at Asilomar and then make some
uate from that institution with a degree (1901), and brief comments. Although not much given to theo-
the first woman to receive an architecture license in rizing, Morgan favored A. W. N. Pugin’s formula-
the State of California (1904). She is one of the most tion of the essence of architecture as “Commodity,
famous and well-loved architects in the state’s history. Firmness, and Propriety.” “Propriety” here refers to
Having studied under and worked with well-known “observing decorum, aptness, fittingness or rightness,
Californian architect Bernard Maybeck when she was in both a moral and non-moral sense” (p. 38) and
still an undergraduate, Morgan became a strong prac- has the special implication that the architect could
titioner of the “Arts and Crafts” style in architecture, follow an eclectic style. In accord with this eclecti-
although, as an architect who practiced eclecticism, cism, Morgan kept a library of reproductions and
she was also a master of the “Mediterranean” and plans to which she constantly referred. She usually
the “Classical” styles. The Arts and Crafts Movement followed the desires of her clients closely, as she
stressed harmony, utility, simplicity, and economy and saw the architect as an anonymous servant seeking
encouraged dissolving the distinction between fine to meet the client’s aesthetic and practical needs (p.
and applied art. Having started in England, the move- 37). Thus, although in the case of the Asilomar Con-
ment gained an architectural foothold in northern ference Grounds she was allowed to follow her own
California in 1876 when Joseph Worcester, a Swe- taste, she gave the campus an overall ethos of simple
denborgian minister, built his home in Piedmont us- modesty appropriate to the institutional client’s need
ing unpainted shingles on the exterior and unpainted (p. 107).
redwood boards in the interior. Influenced by Span- Much that we approve of in architecture today is
ish design and by observation of miner’s cabins, his found in Morgan’s work at Asilomar. In particular,
house was intended to exemplify the simple, natural she was an early advocate of site specificity. Trained
life. This was in part inspired by his friendship with as a landscape architect, Morgan designed, as archi-
naturalist John Muir. The next important work in this tect Walter Steilberg said, “from the inside out,” and
tradition was Maybeck’s house for Charles Keeler this included the out of doors (p. 106). Her pathways
(1894), which was distinctive for leaving the struc- were created to shape the experience of those who
tural system of the house exposed. came to Asilomar. Moreover, she would not cut away
Among Morgan’s buildings are the Hearst Greek hillsides, but would instead situate buildings on the
Theater at UCB (which she helped design in 1902); natural contour of the landscape. Even the buildings
the Campanile (or El Campanil) and the Margaret located around the “commons” were all at slightly
Carnegie Library at Mills College, Oakland (1905); different elevations. This is where the historical pho-
restoration of the Fairmont Hotel, San Francisco tographs illustrating this book come in handy, as some
(1907); Saint John’s Presbyterian Church, Berkeley of the site-specific features have been lost over time.
(1910); the Hearst mansion at San Simeon (1919– For example, the original stone and concrete terrace
1947); the Phoebe Apperson Hearst Memorial Gym- and stairs of the Phoebe Hearst Social Hall were
nasium for Women, UCB (1927, with Bernard May- replaced by a wooden deck, thereby eliminating the
beck); and the Berkeley Women’s City Club (1930). sense that the building was “on and with” the site,
She was made the architect for the YWCA Asilo- making it seem “above and apart” (p. 176). Another
mar Camp in 1912, completing her buildings there site-specific feature associated with Arts and Crafts
between 1913 and 1928. All in all she designed more style is her “adoption of local uses of form, rusticity
than 700 buildings. For an excellent illustrated web- of materials, and . . . blending of colors and textures
site, see Julia Morgan Index at http://www.bluffton. with those native to the site” (p. 79). The campus
edu/∼sullivanm/jmindex/genericindex.html. was also created with an eye to what Quacchia calls
The current book includes a short biography (Mor- “casually interested observations” (p. 107). For ex-
gan left very little information about herself when she ample, although many of the buildings are formally
died in 1957), chapters on the Ecole des Beaux-Arts symmetrical, Morgan designed pathways so that one
during the time of Morgan’s training there, the Arts would have to approach the buildings asymmetrically
and Crafts Movement, the formative years of the San (p. 188).
Francisco Bay region, a comparison of Asilomar and We should be cautious, however, in attributing all
Hearst Castle (her other major work), the history of the features of Asilomar to Morgan’s architecture in
Pacific Grove, the founding of the Asilomar Confer- general. Quacchia nicely contrasts Asilomar to Mor-
ence Grounds, and two concluding chapters on her gan’s other major project, the Hearst Castle at San
434 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Simeon. San Simeon is organized hierarchically, with a power that has been “repressed by an externalized
the “Casa Grande” in the center, reflecting Hearst’s quotidian life” (JAAC 49 [1991], p. 338). This was
power over his kingdom, with an emphasis placed on exemplified in Eisenman’s La Guardiola House, in
self-indulgence. Asilomar, by contrast, is set out in a which there were windows in the floor and one had
way symbolic of egalitarian arrangements and social to overcome obstacles to get from one room to the
solidarity (p. 105). In each case, Morgan reflected the next. As Goldblatt observes, Eisenman calls for a dis-
purposes of the client. location of the architectural self to achieve a deep
Central to Morgan’s aesthetic was the concept exploration of meaning. This was precisely not Julia
of developing “a feeling” that was unique to the Morgan’s direction at Asilomar. There is much to be
site. Buildings should have a certain personality that said for the explorations characteristic of deconstruc-
would resonate in the experience of the users. In tionist architecture, but one suspects that this is just
particular, she sought to create the kind of feeling one pole of legitimate architectural experience, the
that Maybeck would create in his buildings. But how other of which has not been represented strongly in
is this feeling to be characterized more specifically? recent architectural discourse, and that may even be
At one point, while discussing Asilomar’s main hall, seen as a kind of kitsch. But just as Robert Solomon
Quacchia mentions a feeling of “warmth and com- argued famously for the value of the sweet sentiments
fort.” He also speaks of the foyer-lobby of the Lodge represented by kitsch (“Kitsch,” JAAC 49 [1991]), so,
building as “a very pleasant restful place.” The feel- too, one could say a word for the feelings of comfort,
ing achieved is not only organized but harmonious. functionality, harmony, simplicity, and “feeling” that
Quacchia quotes critic Allan Temko that no build- are perhaps represented best in the Asilomar archi-
ings by Morgan “had more warmth, strength and sure tecture of Julia Morgan. As Quacchia says: “In so
feeling for the land than Asilomar” (p. 189). many ways, while always attentive to formal qual-
This stress on feelings of warmth, pleasantness, ities of design, she treated the design of buildings
comfort, and restfulness in architecture has brought in their expressive capacity as metaphors, reflective
aestheticians back to Asilomar again and again. of human character, revealing of what we are or, al-
Perhaps this fact has some bearing on the aesthetics ternatively, wish to be” (p. 188). Reflection on such
of architecture itself. It is arguable that the last really sentiments might be recommended to aestheticians
significant movement in architecture was deconstruc- as they visit Asilomar in the future. I recommend
tivism. David Goldblatt nicely describes the motives Russell Quacchia’s book as an on-site guide to this
behind this movement in his article “The Disloca- thought.
tion of the Architectural Self.” Goldblatt describes
how Peter Eisenman rejected the aesthetics of com- THOMAS LEDDY
fort and function as “a way, in Derrida’s phrase, of Department of Philosophy
‘letting other voices speak’” and in order to express San Jose State University

You might also like