Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

The Labelling Theory of Mental Illness

Author(s): T. J. Scheff
Source: American Sociological Review , Jun., 1974, Vol. 39, No. 3 (Jun., 1974), pp. 444-
452
Published by: American Sociological Association

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2094300

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to American Sociological Review

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE LABELLING THEORY OF MENTAL ILLNESS*

T. J. SCHEFF
University of California
Santa Barbara

American Sociological Review 1974, Vol. 39 (June):444-52

The first part of this paper is a response to several recent critiques of labelling theory.
The second part assesses the state of the evidence on the labelling theory of mental
illness. The majority of the studies reviewed support the theory.

T his paper will present an evaluation of the which allows for only a single meaning for
labelling theory of mental illness. To this each concept. He argues that this ambiguity
date, there have been three critiques of leaves open many alternative meanings and
labelling theory, those by Gove (1970a), implications. For this reason, he concludes
Gibbs (1972), and Davis (1972). Gibbs and that the theory in its present state is of little
Davis, for the most part, evaluate formal value.
aspects of the theory; Gove evaluates its I will make two observations about Gibbs'
substance. Gibbs suggests that the labelling argument. First, virtually every other sociolog-
approach is not really a scientific theory, in ical theory lacks denotative definition. In-
that it is not sufficiently explicit and un- deed, Gibbs observes that the concept of
ambiguous. Davis proposes that there are social norm, an important element in labelling
ideological biases in the labelling approach, theory, has never been denotatively defined.
and points to other approaches as alterna- Since this concept is perhaps the most basic
tives. 1 sociological idea, Gibbs' critique is less an
Although the papers by Gibbs and by Davis evaluation of labelling theory per se than the
raise important questions, neither considers at state of social science.
length the most fundamental question that Note that Gibbs' critique is equally appli-
can be asked about a theory: how well is it cable to psychiatric theories. At this writing, I
supported by empirical studies? Gove consid- know of no psychiatric theory of functional
ers this question in his critique, and the mental illness which is based on denotatively
present paper is devoted to it. In the first defined concepts. The four basic components
section of this paper, I will respond to Gove's of the medical model, cause, lesion, symp-
evaluation, and in the second, present my toms, and outcome, as applied to mental
own. illness, are not denotatively defined (Scheff,
First, however, I wish to comment on 1966:180). Nor are such specific concepts as
Gibbs' paper, since it raises a methodological depression, schizophrenia, phobia, and neuro-
question relevant to assessing evidence to be sis. Gibbs' critique of labelling theory, there-
presented here. In his analysis of labelling fore, applies equally well to all of its competi-
theory, Gibbs demonstrates that the concepts tors in the field of mental illness.
used in the theory are ambiguous, since they My second observation is that Gibbs' cri-
are not defined denotatively, i.e., in a way tique implies that there is only one kind of
science, a positivistic one modeled on natural
science. He appears to be saying that a theory
has no value unless it can be unambiguously
*1 wish to acknowledge the helpful advice re-
ceived from Norman Denzin, James Greenley, C. stated. It has been argued, however, that
Allen Haney, Arnold Linsky, and William Rushing, concepts and theories can have a sensitizing
who read an earlier draft of this article. function quite distinct from their literal truth
X For a considered response to the question of value (Blumer, 1954). Theories based on
bias in labelling theory, see Becker (1973). nominal (connotative) definitions can direct

444

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LABELLING THEORY OF MENTAL ILLNESS 445

attention toward new data, or to new ways of be useful and even necessary for scientific
perceiving old data, which challenge taken- progress.
for-granted assumptions, and shatter "the While the labelling theory of mental illness
attitude of everyday life" (Bruyn, 1966; is a sensitizing theory, it can still be used to
Schutz, 1962). In such a view, the very evaluate evidence, in a provisional way. The
ambiguousness of nominal concepts is of proper question to ask is not, as Gove asks,
value, since they have a rich evocativeness whether labelling theory is literally true, but
which denotative concepts lack (Bronowski, whether the relevant studies are more consis-
1965). tent with labelling theory than with its com-
Science may be viewed as a problem petitor, the medical model. I will now turn to
solving activity, with two distinct phases this question.
(Bronowski, 1956). In the first phase, the In his critique, Gove reaches the following
problem is to somehow transcend the tradi- conclusion: "The available evidence . . . indi-
tional classifications and models which impris- cates that the societal reaction formulation of
on thought. In the second, the problem is to how a person becomes mentally ill is substan-
test a new idea meticulously. Sensitizing tially incorrect" (1970a: 881). My own read-
theories are relevant to the first phase of ing of the evidence is contrary to that of
scientific problem solving. They are attempts Gove. First, Gove's interpretation of most
to jostle the imagination, to create a crisis of studies he cites seems at least questionable
consciousness which will lead to new visions and, in some cases, inaccurate. I wish first
of reality. Sensitizing theories are as valuable then to state my objections to several of
as denotative theories; they simply attempt to Gove's interpretations. Secondly, since Gove's
solve a different problem. articles were published, several new studies
The need for new research directions in the have appeared which have bearing on the
study of mental illness has long been appar- controversy. Also, several relevant articles
ent. Although thousands of studies have been which Gove failed to mention were published
based on the medical model, real progress earlier than his article. Later in the paper, I
toward scientific understanding, or even a will review all of these articles.
fruitful formulation of the problem, is lackingGove concluded that the majority of the
(Scheff, 1966:7-9). The sensitizing function evidence failed to support labelling theory
of the labelling theory of mental illness through two kinds of distortion: first, by
derives precisely from its attempt to contra- overstating the implications of those studies
dict the major tenets of the medical model; it he thought refuted labelling theory and, sec-
is less an attempt to displace that model than ond, by misrepresenting those studies he
to clear the air, as I indicated in Being thought supported labelling theory. I will not
Mentally Ill: try to refute all of Gove's interpretations,
since to do so would be to restate labelling
It should be clear at this point that the theory. I will simply indicate some representa-
purpose of this theory is not to reject tive errors that he makes.
psychiatric and psychological formulations
Apropos of Gove's overstatement, let us
in their totality. It is obvious that such
examine how he interprets the study by
formulations have served, and will continue
to serve, useful functions in theory and Yarrow et al. (1955). To study the processes
practice concerning mental illness. The ... through which the next-of-kin come to define
purpose, rather, is to develop a model a person as mentally ill, Yarrow et al. inter-
which will complement the individual viewed wives of men who had been hospital-
system models by providing a complete ized for mental illness. Gove summarizes that
and explicit contrast . . . .By allowing for study as follows: "Only when the husband's
explicit consideration of these antithetical behavior became impossible to deal with
models, the way may be cleared for a would the wife take action to have the
synthesis .. .(Scheff, 1966, 25-27).
husband hospitalized." Gove's interpretation is
questionable for two reasons. First, Yarrow et
It seems to me that none of the three al. studied only those cases of deviance which
critiques discussed here appreciate the point resulted in hospitalization. They did not study
that a sensitizing theory may be ambiguous, all cases of the same type of deviant behavior
ideologically biased, not literally true, and still
which led to hospitalization, in the entire

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
446 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

population. The Yarrow study thus covers able evidence which supported the patient's
only a clinical population and is entirely ex story rather than the next-of-kin's. For exam-
post facto. Gove's interpretation repeats the ple, in one of their cases the psychiatrist
classic fallacy of the medical model, which is indicated that the patient Maya had "ideas of
to assume that hospitalization was inevitable, reference," which supported one of the com-
even though no observations have been made plaints against her. By interviewing the pa-
on the incidence and outcome of similar cases tient, the mother and the father together,
in the unhospitalized population. The history however, Laing and Esterson put this "de-
of physical medicine has many analogous lusion" in quite a different light:
cases. For example, it has been found that
until the late 1940's, histoplasmosis was An idea of reference that she had was that
thought to be a rare tropical disease with a something she could not fathom was going
uniformly fatal outcome (Schwartz and on between her parents, seemingly about
her. Indeed there was. When they were
Baum, 1957). Field investigations discovered,
interviewed together, her mother and fa-
however, that the syndrome is widely preva-
ther kept exchanging with each other a
lent and that death or impairment is highly
constant series of nods, winks, gestures,
unusual. Analogically, it is possible that the and knowing smiles so obvious to the
symptoms reported by the wives in the observer that he commented on them after
Yarrow et al. study, even if accurately report- 20 minutes of the first such interview.
ed, might terminate without medical interven- They continued, however, unabated and
tion. denied (Laing and Esterson, p. 24).
The question of the accuracy of the wives'
report raises the second problem in Gove's Laing and Esterson found many such items of
interpretation. Yarrow et al.'s descriptions of misrepresentation by the next-of-kin in all
the husbands' behavior are based entirely on their cases. Their study suggests that the
the wives' uncorroborated account. Yarrow et uncorroborated account of the next-of-kin is
al. recognize this difficulty, warn the reader riddled with error.
about it, and are unassuming about the This is not to say that Laing and Esterson's
implications of their findings: interpretation is correct and that Gove's is not.
I am saying that Yarrow et al.'s study and the
Ideally to study this problem, one might other studies that Gove cites in this context
like to interview the wives as they struggle were not only not organized to test labelling
with the developing illness. This is pre- theory, but were innocent of any of the
cluded, however, by the fact that the possible interpretations (such as that of Laing
problem "is not visible" until psychiatric
and Esterson) which labelling theory suggests.
help is sought. The data, therefore, are the
Until such time as systematic studies are
wives' reconstructions of their earlier expe-
riences . . . . It is recognized that recollec-
conducted which investigate both clinical and
tions of the prehospital period may well non-clinical populations, and which do not
include systematic biases such as distor- rest entirely on the uncorroborated testimony
tions, omissions, and increased organiza- of one or the other interested parties, interpre-
tion and clarity (p. 60). tations of the kind that Gove makes are
dubious.
Although Yarrow et al. clearly recognize Another example of how Gove distorts the
the limitations of their study, Gove does not. evidence, seeking to discredit studies which
He reports the wives' account of the hus- support labelling theory, is his analysis of my
bands' behavior as if it were the thing itself. article, "The Societal Reaction to Deviance:
Judging from Gove, Laing and Esterson's Ascriptive Elements in the Psychiatric Screen-
(1964) detailed study of the way in which the ing of Mental Patients in a Midwestern State"
next-of-kin sometime falsifies his account and (Scheff, 1964). The study reported in this
colludes against the pre-patient may as well article consists of two phases. In the first,
have never been written. Laing and Esterson preliminary phase, I had hospital psychiatrists
spent an average of twenty-four hours inter- rate a sample of incoming patients according
viewing members of each of the eleven fami- to the legal criteria for commitment, danger-
lies in their study, with a range of sixteen to ousness, and degree of mental impairment. In
fifty hours per family. They found consider- the second phase, we observed, in a sample of

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LABELLING THEORY OF MENTAL ILLNESS 447

cases, the procedures actually used in commit- rated as neither dangerous nor severely impair-
ting patients, particularly the psychiatric ex- ed.
amination and the formal commitment hear- In the second phase of the study, when we
ing. The purpose of the psychiatric ratings was observed the actual commitment procedures,
to provide a foundation for our observations we sought to find out how the psychiatric
in the second phase; they were used to examiners and judges reacted to uncertainty.
determine the extent to which there was any To summarize our observations, we found
legal uncertainty about the patients' commit- that all of the psychiatric examinations and
tability. The second phase of the study judicial hearings that we witnessed were per-
described how the judges and psychiatrists functory. Furthermore, virtually every hearing
reacted to uncertainty. The article stated resulted in a recommendation for commit-
clearly that the study was divided into two ment or continued hospitalization. The con-
parts: clusion of the article is based not on the first
phase only, but on both phases of the study.
The purpose of the description that follows Since the first phase suggests uncertainty with
is to determine the extent of uncertainty respect to the committability of some of the
that exists concerning new patients' qualifi- patients, and the second phase suggests that
cations for involuntary confinement in a the commitment procedures were perfunctory
mental hospital, and the reactions of the for the entire sample, and yet resulted in
courts to this type of uncertainty (p. 402).
continued hospitalization rather than release,
in virtually every case, the study appears to
In the first phase of the study, the psychia-
demonstrate the presumption of illness.
trists' ratings of the sample of incoming
Gove's treatment of this article is some-
patients were as follows:
what irresponsible. By ignoring the second
phase of the study, he takes the first phase
Dangerousness
out of context. Ignoring my argument con-
How Likely Patient Would Degree of Mental cerning uncertainty, Gove suggests that had I
Harm Self or Others Impairment placed the cutting point on the psychiatrists'
Very likely 5% Severe 17% ratings differently, by including as commit-
Likely 4% Moderate 42% table patients rated as moderately impaired
Somewhat Mild 25% and/or somewhat likely to harm themselves,
likely 14% my data "would have shown instead that the
Somewhat Minimal 12% vast majority of committed mental patients
unlikely 20% were mentally ill" (Gove, 1970b). He implies,
Unlikely 37% None 2% therefore, that the results of the study rest
Very Unlikely 18% entirely on my arbitrary choice of a cutting
point.2 In light of all the evidence presented
These findings, it is argued, are relevant to the in the article, where the cutting point in the
question of the legal uncertainty concerning psychiatrists' ratings is placed has little signif-
the patients' committability. The legal rulings icance. Gove disregarded the problem that the
on the presumption of health are stringent. study posed, which was whether or not
The courts "have repeatedly held that there patients were being committed illegally. He
should be a presumption of sanity. The misrepresents my conclusion by imputing to
burden of proof should be on the petitioners me the conclusion that most of the patients
(i.e., the next-of-kin). There must be a pre- are not mentally ill. The study did not make
ponderance of evidence and the evidence this point, since I regard the criteria for
should be of a clear and unexceptional na- mental illness as even more ambiguous than
ture" (Scheff, 1964: 403). Given these the legal standards for commitment.
rulings, it seems reasonable to argue, as the
article did, that the committability of all
patients except those rated at the extremes of 2Gove's criticism of the cutting point applies
more to an early report of some of the initial results
dangerousness or impairment was uncertain.
of the study, a brief note in the American Journal of
The ratings, it was argued, suggested uncer- Psychiatry (Scheff, 1963). That report acknowl-
tainty about the committability of 63% of the
edged that setting the cutting point on the psychia-
patients in the sample, i.e., those patients trists' ratings was problematic (p. 268).

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
448 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

Gove's other criticism of the study con- hospitalization (Greenley, 1972). Labelling
cerns the questionnaire given the psychiatrists theory proposes that the patient's condition is
to obtain ratings of dangerousness and mental only one of a number of contingencies af-
impairment. He suggests that I should have fecting the societal reaction and, therefore,
provided the psychiatrists with descriptions of
the patient's fate. Further contingencies are
the behavior that the scales refer to. This suggested in Being Mentally Ill (pp. 96-7).
criticism begs the question, however, since it Gove's interpretation of labelling theory is
seems to assume that there are precise psy- simplistic and incorrect.
chiatric or legal criteria of committable behav-
SUMMARIZING THE EVIDENCE
ior. In fact, the legal statutes, though they
vary in language from state to state, are all Since most studies of "mental illness" were
vague, general, and ambiguous, They state not designed to test labelling theory, seem-
simply that persons who are dangerous or ingly plausible interpretations of most of
unable to care for themselves may be com- them can be constructed either for or against
mitted if a strong case can be made. No labelling theory. Furthermore, since the con-
statutes or psychiatric statements set forth flict between labelling theory and the medical
behavioral criteria. My study sought not to model engenders such furious partisanship, we
help psychiatrists and judges interpret these should also exclude studies based on casual or
vague laws, but to describe how they reacted unsystematic observations, in which the ob-
to the law's ambiguity. servers' bias are more likely to influence the
Some of Gove's criticism seems based on a results he reports. I have surveyed the research
misunderstanding of labelling theory. He literature, therefore, for studies that meet two
seems to think that showing that the commit- criteria. First, they must relate to labelling
ment rates reported in- various studies are theory explicitly; and, second, the research
considerably less than 100%, somehow refutes methods must be systematic. At this writing I
labelling theory (Gove, 1970a: 877-9). The have located eighteen studies of this type. Of
argument made by labelling theorists that these eighteen only five, those by Gove (1973,
official agents of the societal reaction usually 1974), Karmel (1969, 1970) and Robins
presume illness does not imply that commit- (1966), are inconsistent with labelling theory;
ment will always occur, any more than pre- the remainder, those of Denzin (1968),
suming innocence in criminal courts implies Denzin and Spitzer (1966), Greenley (1972),
that acquittal will always occur. The master Haney and Michielutte (1968), Haney, Miller
question which labelling theory raises with and Michielutte (1969), Linsky (1970a, b),
respect to commitment rates is more complex Rosenhan (1973), Rushing (1971), Scheff
than Gove implies. At what point and under (1964), Temerlin (1968), Wilde (1968), and
what conditions does the process of denial Wenger and Fletcher (1969) are consistent
stop and labelling begin? Gove apparently with labelling theory.
acknowledges that labelling occurs, but only These eighteen studies vary widely in the
in the last stages of the commitment funnel, reliability of the inferences that we can
i.e., in the formal commitment procedure make from them. Four studies among those
itself. I suspect that his formulation is much consistent with labelling theory use zero-
too simple, and that labelling occurs under order correlations-those of Denzin and
some conditions much earlier in the process, Spitzer; Denzin; Haney and Michielutte, and
even in the family or neighborhood; and, Haney, Miller and Michielutte. For example,
conversely, under some conditions, denial Haney reports the correlation between the
may occur late in the process, as some of my decision to commit and social characteris-
studies showed (Scheff, 1966: 135). tics of the patients and petitioners. He
The crucial question we have raised vis-a-visfinds positive correlations between commit-
the medical model concerns contingencies ment rates and these social characteristics.
which lead to labelling that lie outside the For example, he reports a higher rate of
patient and his behavior. Greenley, for ex- commitment for non-whites than whites.
ample, established that, independent of a Although his findings are consistent with
patient's psychiatric condition, the family's labelling theory, they provide only very weak
desire to bring him home seems to be the support since he has not controlled for the
most powerful determinant of his length of patient's condition. We are left with the

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LABELLING THEORY OF MENTAL ILLNESS 449

question that occurs so often in social epide- hospital admissions, as a measure of societal
miology: Are non-whites committed more reaction. I believe that such a ratio will
often because of the societal reaction to their control for gross variations in rates of mental
social status, or because this particular social illness. What the index provides, hopefully, is
status is itself correlated with mental illness? a measure of the most severe societal reaction,
That is to say, are non-whites committed i.e., involuntary confinement, but with the
more often than whites because of their phenomenon of mental illness at least partly
powerlessness, or because there is more mental controlled, assuming that the voluntary com-
illness among them? Haney's studies do not mitments are equally "mentally ill." Perhaps
answer such questions, nor do those of Denzin this assumption should also be investigated.
and Spitzer, Denzin. Both studies show a strong relationship be-
Similar criticism can be made of the two tween powerlessness and commitment rates.
studies by Karmel which fail to support In the study by Wenger and Fletcher, the
labelling theory. Based on interviews with presence of a lawyer representing the patient
patients after their hospitalization, her data in admission hearings decreased the likelihood
fail to show any evidence of the acceptance of of hospitalization. This relationship held
a deviant role predicted by labelling theory. within three degrees of manifest "mental
These are simple correlation studies with no illness."
controls (Bohr, 1970). Gove (1973) studied the Finally, Wilde's study (1968) concerns the
amount and effects of stigma on a sample of relationship between the recommendations
ex-mental patients. His data indicate that the for commitment made by mental health ex-
amount and effects of stigma were not very aminers and various social characteristics of
large, and therefore fail to support labelling the pre-patients, with controls for the pa-
theory. His data are somewhat ambiguous, tient's psychiatric condition. In all five of
however, since there is no control group of these studies strong relationships are reported
similar persons who were not hospitalized. between such social characteristics as class,
A series of much stronger studies, whose and commitment rates, with psychiatric con-
findings support labelling theory, are those of ditions controlled for. These five studies
Greenley, Rushing, Linsky, Scheff (1964), support labelling theory since they indicate
Wenger and Fletcher and Wilde. My study has
that social characteristics of the patients help
already been discussed. Greenley, as indicated determine the severity of the societal reaction,
above, studied the relationship between length independent of psychiatric condition.
of hospitalization and several social and The controlled studies by Robins (1966)
psychiatric variables. He found that even and by Gove (1974) provide data which fail to
when the patient's psychiatric condition is support labelling theory. Robins used psychi-
controlled, there is a strong relationship atric diagnoses of adults who had been diag-
between the family desire for the patient's nosed as children as part of an evaluation of
release and the length of hospitalization. child guidance clinics. Robins noted that some
Rushing and Linsky each did studies on the of the children diagnosed were treated and
relationship between psychiatric commitment some were not. She argues that this data can
and social class and other social character- be used to evaluate the effects of "the severity
istics. Since they indicated that their data of societal response to the behavior problems
only partly overlap, I will cite both studies of the children." She found that, of the adults
(Linsky, 1972; Rushing, 1972). Both used the who had psychiatric treatment as children,
same technique, which I believe controls for 16% were diagnosed as having sociopathic
the patient's condition. It they had merely personalities as adults. Of the persons who did
used commitment rates as their dependent not receive psychiatric treatment as children,
variable, we would be left with the perplexing 24% were diagnosed as having sociopathic
question: are commitment rates higher in the personalities as adults. Since the difference
lowest social class because there is more between the two percentages is not statistic-
mental illness in that class or for other ally significant, the hypothesis that psychi-
reasons? (See the New Haven studies by atric treatment was beneficial is not sup-
Hollingshead and Redlich [1958].) However, ported, but by the same token, neither is the
both Rushing and Linsky used an index made labelling hypothesis that psychiatric treat-
up of the ratio of involuntary to voluntary ment, particularly when involuntary, may

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
450 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

stabilize behavior that would otherwise be The study by Rosehan (1 973) took place
transient. This finding is somewhat equivocal, in real settings-twelve mental hospitals. For
however, because of the sampling problems of this study, eight sane persons gained secret
the original Cambridge-Somerville study. admittance to the different hospitals. They all
With a sample of hospitalized mental pa- followed the same plan. In his initial admis-
tients, Gove (1974) has studied the relation- sion interview, each pseudo-patient simulated
ship between the patient's psychiatric record several psychotic symptoms. Immediately
and his economic and social resources. His upon admission to the ward, the pseudo-pa-
data suggest that individual resources facilitate
tients stopped simulating any symptoms of
treatment, rather than allow the individual to abnormality. In all twelve cases the pseudo-pa-
avoid the societal reaction, and therefore tients had enormous difficulty establishing
support the medical model rather than label- that they were sane. The length of hospitaliza-
ling theory. Some caution is necessary in tion ranged from seven to fifty-two days with
interpreting these findings, however, since an average of nineteen days. The study's
patient characteristics were based on hospital major finding is as follows:
data. For example, he finds that more of the
records of patients with low resources present Despite their public show of sanity, the
the patient as 'never psychiatrically normal," pseudo-patients were never detected. Ad-
than patients with higher resources. Does this mitted except in one case with a diagnosis
mean that low resource patients have been of schizophrenia, each was discharged with
"mentally ill" longer, or that the hospital a diagnosis of schizophrenia in remission.
tends to construct their case histories in this The label "in remission" should in no way
way, retroactively (Goffman, 1961, p. 145)? be dismissed -as a formality for at no time
In any case, Gove's interpretation of his data during any hospitalization had any ques-
contradicts the conclusions of Linsky and of tion been raised about any pseudo-patient's
Rushing. Since the studies do not use the simulation . . . the evidence is strong that
same indices, it is not possible to compare once labelled schizophrenic the pseudo-pa-
them directly. tient was stuck with the label (p. 252).
The final two studies to be discussed
provide still stronger support for labelling Rosehan also collected a wide variety of
theory. The first, Temerlin's (1968), is a test subsidiary data dealing with the amount and
of the influence of suggestion on psychiatric quality of contact between the pseudo-pa-
diagnosis. Temerlin finds that psychiatrists tients and the hospital staff, showing a strong
and clinical psychologists are extremely sug- tendency for the staff to treat the pseudo-pa-
gestible when it comes to diagnosing mental tients as non-persons.
illness. Four different groups diagnosed the This study, like Temerlin's, strongly sup-
patient in the same recorded interview under ports labelling theory. Both provide good
different conditions. One control group diag- models for future studies of labelling theory,
nosed with no prior suggestion, one group was the Rosehan study with its use of actual
given a suggestion that the interviewee was hospital locations, and the Temerlin study
sane, and a third group was told that they with its experimental design.
were selecting scientists to work in research. We can now provisionally summarize the
In the experimental group, it was suggested state of evidence concerning labelling theory.
that the interviewees were mentally ill. The If we restrict ourselves to systematic studies
diagnoses of the control and experimental explicitly related to labelling theory, eighteen
groups differed greatly. In the control groups are available. Of these, thirteen support label-
the great majority made diagnoses of mental ling theory, and five fail to. Although the
health; whereas in the experimental group, studies vary in reliability and precision, the
not a single psychiatrist out of twenty-five, balance of evidence seems to support labelling
and only three out of twenty-five psychol- theory.
ogists, diagnosed mental health. One weakness
of this study is that it takes place in an REFERENCES
artificial setting, with an enacted interview;
Becker, Howard
but it strongly supports the unreliability of
1973 "Labelling theory reconsidered." Pp.
psychiatric diagnosis and the presumption of 177-208 in Outsiders. New York: Free
illness. Press.

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LABELLING THEORY OF MENTAL ILLNESS 451

Blumer, Herbert social characteristics in the adjudication of


1954 "What is wrong with social theory?" incompetency." Sociometry 32 (June):
American Journal of Sociology 19 (Feb- 182-93.
ruary): 3-10. Hollingshead, August B. and Frederich C. Redlich
Bohr, Ronald H. 1958 Social Class and Mental Illness. New York:
1970 Letter to the Editor. Journal of Health John Wiley.
and Social Behavior 11 (June): 52. Karmel, Madeline.
Bronowski, J. 1969 "Total institution and self-mortification."
1956 Science and Human Values. New York: Journal of Health and Social Behavior 10
Harper and Row. (June): 134-41.
1965 The Identity of Man. Garden City, N.Y.: 1970 "The internalization of social roles in
Natural History Press. institutionalized chronic mental patients."
Bruyn, Severyn T. Journal of Health and Social Behavior 11
1966 The Human Perspective in Sociology. (September): 231-5.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. Laing, Ronald and Aaron Esterson
Davis, Nanette J. 1964 Sanity, Madness, and the Family. London:
1972 "Labelling theory in deviance research: a Tavistock.
critique and reconsideration." Sociological Linsky, Arnold S.
Quartery 13 (Autumn): 447-74. 1970a "Community homogeneity and exclusion
Denzin, Norman K. of the mentally ill: rejection vs. consensus
1968 "The self-fulfilling prophecy and patient about deviance. Journal of Health and
therapist interaction." Pp. 349-58 in Social Behavior 11 (December): 304-11.
Stephan P. Spitzer and Norman K. Denzin 1970b "Who shall be excluded: the influence of
(eds.), The Mental Patient. New York: personal attributes in community reaction
McGraw-Hill. to the mentally ill." Social Psychiatry 5
Denzin, Norman K. and Stephan P. Spitzer (July): 166-71.
1966 "Paths to the mental hospital and staff 1972 Letter. American Journal of Sociology 78
predictions of patient role behavior." (November): 684-6.
Journal of Health and Human Behavior 7 Robins, Lee
(Winter): 265-71. 1966 Deviant Children Grown Up. Baltimore:
Gibbs, Jack Williams and Wilkins.
1972 "Issues in defining deviant behavior." Pp. Rosehan, David L.
39-68 in Robert A Scott. and Jack D. 1973 "On being sane in insane places." Science
Douglas (eds.), Theoretical Perspectives on 179 (January): 250-8.
Deviance. New York: Basic Books. Rushing, William A.
Goffman, Erving. 1971 "Individual resources, societal reaction,
1961 Asylums. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday and hospital commitment." American
Anchor. Journal of Sociology 77 (November):
Gove, Walter 5 11-26.
1970a "Societal reaction as an explanation of 1972 Letter. American Journal of Sociology 78
mental illness: an evaluation." American (November): 686-8.
Sociological Review 35 (October): 873-84. Scheff, Thomas J.
1970b "Who is hospitalized: a critical review of 1963 "Legitimate, transitional, and illegitimate
some sociological studies of mental ill- mental patients in a midwestern state."
ness." Journal of Health and Human American Journal of Psychiatry 120
Behavior 11 (December): 294-304. (September): 267-9.
1973 "The stigma of mental hospitalization." 1964 "The societal reaction to deviance: ascrip-
Archives of General Psychiatry 28 (April): tive elements in the psychiatric screening
494-500. of mental patients in a midwestern state."
1974 "Individual resources and mental hospital- Social Problems 1 1 (Spring): 401-13.
ization: a comparison and evaluation of 1966 Being Mentally Ill: A Sociological Theory.
the societal reaction and psychiatric per- Chicago: Aldine.
spectives." American Sociological Review Schultz, Alfred
39 (February): 86-100. 1962 The Problem of Social Reality: Collected
Greenley, James R. Papers I. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
1972 "The psychiatric patient's family and Schwartz, J. and G. L. Baum
length of hospitalization." Journal of 1957 "The history of histoplasmosis." New
Health and Social Behavior 13 (March): England Journal of Medicine 256 (Feb-
25-37. ruary): 25 3-8.
Haney, C. Allen and Robert Michielutte Temerlin, Maurice K.
1968 "Selective factors operating in the ad- 1968 "Suggestion effects in psychiatric diag-
judication of incompetency." Journal of nosis." Journal of Nervous and Mental
Health and Social Behavior 9 (September): Disease 147 (4): 349-53.
23342. Wilde, William A.
Haney, C. Allen, Kent S. Miller, and Robert 1968 "Decision-making in a psychiatric screen-
Michielutte ing agency." Journal of Health and Social
1969 "The interaction of petitioner and deviant Behavior 9 (September): 215-21.

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
452 AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

Wenger, Dennis L. and C. Ritchard Fletcher Yarrow, Marian Radke, Charlotte Green Schwartz,
1969 "The effect of legal counsel on admissions Harriet S. Murphy, and Leila Calhoun Deasy
to a state mental hospital: a confrontation 1955 "The psychological meaning of mental
of professions." Journal of Health and illness in the family." Journal of Social
Social Behavior 10 (June): 66-72. Issues 11 (4): 12-24.

MANUSCRIPTS FOR THE

ASA ROSE SOCIOLOGY SERIES

Manuscripts (100 to 300 typed pages; three copies) are


solicited for publication in the ASA Arnold and Caroline
Rose Monograph Series in Sociology to the Series Editor,
Professor Ida Harper Simpson, Department of Sociology,
Duke University, Durham, North Carolina 27706.

This content downloaded from


193.1.100.108 on Mon, 13 Sep 2021 11:55:16 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like