Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 3

Ethical principles

When you are writing that something is an ethical issue you need to say what ethical principle it is opposed
to.

For example, why is ‘hacking’ an ethical issue? (That is, is it an invasion of privacy, or stealing or neither of
those – is it something else?) If you think it is an ethical issue, what ethical principle (or principles) are
relevant? How do you know that ‘privacy’ for example, is an ethical issue?

Some ethical principles that we have talked about, and that are written down in various codes of ethics, are
given below.

General principles
• Respect for others
• Treat others as equal
• Keep your word (promises)
• Respect the property of others
• Act honestly (truthful)
• Act with integrity (honest, truthful)

Principles from ethical theory


(for a summary of ethical theories used in this module see next page).
• ‘Treat others as you would want to be treated yourself’ (i.e. recognise all are equal and have equal
rights)
• ‘Act in a way that brings the greatest happiness/benefit to the greatest number’

Human Rights
• Recognise human dignity
• everyone has a right to:
• life, liberty and security of person
• privacy, honour and reputation
• own property (and not be deprived of their property)
• freedom of thought, conscience and religion
• freedom of opinion and expression

Health Sector
For IT professionals working in the UK health sector (i.e. health informatics professionals)
The following taken from Kluge (2003)1.
• Principle of Autonomy;
• Principle of Equality and Justice;
• Principle of Beneficence;
• Principle of Non-Malfeasance;
• Principle of Impossibility (this relates to the assumption that it must be possible to meet the rights
and duties that are expressed by the preceding four).

Notes:
Autonomy, definition from the Oxford Encylopedic English Dictionary “The right of self government;
personal freedom, freedom of the will”
Beneficence: doing good, promoting good.
Non-Malfeasance: do no harm

1
Kluge E-H (2003) A Handbook of Ethics for Health Informatics Professionals. London: Health Informatics Committee,
British Computer Society
ETHICAL THEORIES
(an extract from Duquenoy P., Jones S., Rahanu H., Diaper D. (2005) Social, Legal and Professional Issues
of Computing. Middlesex University Press 2005.)

Ethical theories are the same as other theories in that they try to explain aspects of the world we
live in. Some theories are a good fit with what appears to happen in the world (for example
Einstein’s theory of relativity), and some are not so good. Theories are put forward, assessed,
discussed and either generally accepted, revised, or thrown out. There is also usually more than one
theory put forward on a specific topic, and some people will be convinced by one and not another.

In all of these respects ethical theory follows the same pattern. Ethical theories attempt to explain
the sense of ethics that humans have based on what humans do (in an ethical sense). Ethics falls
within the domain of philosophy, and, as with other theories, many different philosophers have
come up with different ethical theories. It would be impossible, and unnecessary, to cover here the
many different types of theory. Most books on computer ethics have a chapter dedicated to ethical
theories, and we would recommend looking at those rather than covering the subject extensively
here.

For the purposes of this module we cover two of the most influential western ethical theories.
These theories are useful as tools for making ethical decisions, and they are also helpful in providing
a basis for critical thinking. Taking different perspectives on an issue provokes thinking, and helps to
form opinion.

The two theories we will be using are Kantianism (a theory provided by Immanuel Kant), and
Consequentialism (sometimes called Utilitarianism).

Kantianism
We will not attempt here to go into the detail of Kant’s theory, but will summarise the essence to
give the general perspective. Kant says that how we behave ethically comes from within us, and the
things that we decide are “good” or “bad” are based on whether we could imagine everyone doing
them. So for example, it would be logically inconsistent to say that breaking a promise is good –
because if everyone broke their promises there would be a loss of trust in promises, and the whole
nature of a promise would be lost. Therefore, he says, that certain things cannot be “universalised”
(i.e. they would not work if everyone did them), and these things are wrong. Examples are: killing
others, lying, stealing, breaking promises. Moreover, in Kant’s view, things that we view as wrong
are “essentially wrong” – that is, they are always wrong and there is never any circumstance where
they would be right. This conflicts directly with the theory of consequentialism, discussed next.

Consequentialism
Consequentialism, as its name suggests, deals with consequences of actions rather than the actions
themselves (in contrast to Kant’s theory). So, for example, it could be argued that stealing could
sometimes be the right action to take provided the outcome is for the “good”. What “good” is has
always been a matter for extensive discussion amongst philosophers, but for our purposes we use
the definition provided by utilitarianism (which is a type of consequentialism). Utilitarian theory
says that a good outcome is that which brings “the greatest benefit to the greatest number of
people”. Therefore stealing, for example, is a morally permissible act if it brings greater benefit to
the greatest number. Consider, for instance, that a dictator has a warehouse full of food when most
of the people in the country are starving. In this instance stealing the food to distribute it to the
starving people would be the right thing to do.
Discussion of the theories
Both of the above theories have points in favour and points against.

In favour of Kant’s theory is that it assumes equality. It is based on logic and rationality (on the
premise that human beings are rational agents). Therefore, if something is good enough for one
person, it (logically) must be good enough for another person. Arguments against this theory are
that it does not take into account conflicting priorities, or special circumstances, such as those given
in the paragraph above regarding stealing food. To claim that stealing food from someone who has
more than enough is wrong seems to go against our intuitions.

Consequentialism, on the other hand, takes into account different circumstances, and can
accommodate conflicting priorities (as the example of stealing shows). However, a major argument
made against this type of theory is that it does not take into account the individual, or
accommodate minority groups. This theory, as we have said, looks for the greatest benefit for the
greatest number of people. The result of this approach would ignore groups such as the disabled, to
give just one example. On this view, it is therefore morally acceptable to produce computers that
some people with disabilities cannot use (thus denying them access to information technology and
all the benefits that may bring). This outcome just does not seem to be ‘morally correct’.

In summary, both of these theories have something to offer but are by no means perfect. They do
however provide a useful means of thinking about ethical issues, and help to clarify muddled
thinking. Some people tend to side with Kant’s view; others will opt for consequentialism.

(Note for students: you might think about which position you favour as the module progresses.)

You might also like