An Ambiguity in Marx's and Engels's Account of Justice and Equality

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 20

An Ambiguity in Marx's and Engels's Account of Justice and Equality

Author(s): Alan Gilbert


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 76, No. 2 (Jun., 1982), pp. 328-346
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1961113 .
Accessed: 21/04/2013 01:05

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
An Ambiguity in Marx's and Engels's Account of
Justice and Equality'
ALAN GILBERT
University of Denver

Given the widespread moral conventionalism or historicism in contemporary social science and
ethics, many have viewed Marx as arguing either that conceptions of justice simply shift historically
and lack objectivity (relativism) or that notions of justice are to be understood solely as expressions of
class interests (reductionism). Although metaethical ambiguities about the status of conceptions of
justice influenced some of Marx's and Engels 'sformulations, they condemned the "crying contrasts "
of rich and poor. Marx is better understood as defending a version of moral objectivity or moral
realism. The paper begins with an example from the recent debate about justice in the international
distribution of wealth to highlight the implausibility of a relativist or reductionist account. It then
describes alternative views of the status of justice and equality in Marx and Engels and explores the
logical structure of Marx's critique of Proudhon. A fourth section examines the analogy between
Marx's and Engels's realism in the philosophy of science and their realist arguments in ethics, focus-
ing on Marx's and Engels's non-relativist and non-reductionist conception of moral progress. The
conclusion sets Marx's use of concepts of exploitation in the context of his overall moral judgments
and suggests that Marx's social or historical theory rather than his moral standards are the most con-
troversial part of his ethical argument.

Moral ObjectivityversusHistoricism with this theory of history. According to the rela-


tivist and reductionist views, Marx and Engels of-
On Marx's generaltheoreticalhypothesis,sys- fered only a historical critique of prevailing con-
tems of law and related moral conceptions arise ceptions of justice and equality and eschewed
with given systems of production, spur their ad- these concepts except to debunk them. A third
vance, and share in their demise. Such prevailing view, a moral realist one, suggests that Marx and
conceptions are relative to historical epochs; they Engels dialectically reformulated existing pro-
enjoy validity for a limited period but compel no letarian demands for equality and justice.
eternal or universal assent. Thus, in response to According to the relativist view, the Marxist
the claim that payment of interest is a matter of sees as an issue only the historical efficacy of an
natural justice, Marx contended: ethical system to a given mode of production-for
example, a justification of the natural character
The justice of transactionswhichgo on between
agentsof productionrests on the fact that these of slaveholding in ancient Greece or of wage
transactionsariseas naturalconsequencesof the slavery in the contemporary United States-rather
relationsof production.The juridicalforms in than the truth of a moral argument. Claims of
which these economic transactions appear as justice in social theory are incidental to the causal
voluntaryactionsof the participants,. . . as con- role of prevailing economic tendencies, although
tractsthat may be enforcedby the stateagainsta those claims might reinforce or retard economic
single party, cannot, being mere forms, deter- trends, and moral concepts make no distinguish-
minethis content.Theyonly expressit. This con- able contribution to social explanations. Concep-
tent is just wheneverit correspondsto the mode tions of justice differ incommensurably from per-
of production, is adequate to it. It is unjust
wheneverit contradictsthat mode (Marx 1961, iod to period, class to class. (See, for example,
Vol. 3, pp. 339-40;Marxand Engels 1959, Vol. Trotsky 1963, and Fisk 1975). Representative pro-
25, p. 351). ponents of these conceptions, abstracted from
their specific historical settings, would continue to
Three interpretations of justice, each with some defend their own visions of justice, but quarrel
basis in Marx and Engels, might be consistent endlessly. This interpretation is a form of ap-
praiser's-group relativism: that is, an act is judged
by a given appraiser to be right if and only if it ac-
'I am indebted to Nicholas Sturgeon and Richard cords with his society's prevailing moral code
Boyd for helpful criticismsof this paper, and to Allen (Lyons 1976, p. 109).
Wood for several enlightening conversations about Whereas the representatives of different epochs
these issues. take their own visions of justice seriously, Marx-
328

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin Marxand Engels 329
ists do not; they adopt a version of ethical rela- and a revolutionary movement flourishes, at least
tivism and dismiss moral arguments as a muddle. two conceptions of justice clash. How is the
Ethical relativists could still defend their own observer to choose between them? According to
ethical conceptions or those of their epoch, yet Marx's general historical theory, a reductionist
Marxian relativists refuse to endorse such concep- could endorse the new conception because it ad-
tions because they radically differentiate moral vances the productive forces even before new pro-
knowledge from other kinds of knowledge. Such duction relations become predominant. Prevalent
Marxians argue that in natural science and social moral standards lose their validity when the old
theory, investigators can discover approximate production relations retard the productive forces,
truth without reference to the social origins of a and the reductionist could then sanction the use of
point of view. Here ethics suffers by comparison the term unjust by radicals. Either version of
with science. From a scientific standpoint, no reductionism permits a kind of dialectical pro-
moral truth or objectivity exists. Furthermore, gress, a progress in productivity, but at least in
this ethical relativist interpretation denies both Wood's account, no progress in morality or
moral progress and advance in ethical theory, a ethical theory can occur.
view that corresponds to the widespread ethical In subsequent debate, Wood maintained that
relativist, conventionalist, or historicist trend in Marx used other ethical standards, such as politi-
Anglo-American philosophy and social science. cal community, freedom, and self-realization, to
According to the reductionist interpretation, a indict predominant modes of production and
Marxist could not only explain standards of jus- restricted a reductionist argument to concepts of
tice by reference to the mode of production, but justice (Wood 1979, pp. 282-91). This recognition
could endorse them on this basis (Wood 1972, undermines any historicist attempt to reduce
1979, has skillfully defended this argument). This Marx's overall ethical judgments to his critique of
view conflicts with ethical relativism. It relates the prevailing ideas about justice. In comparison to
existing historical variety of conceptions of justice these other ethical goods, Wood regards justice as
to the agent's group; an act is right (at a given unimportant. A reductionist account could, there-
time) if and only if it accords with the moral code fore, acknowledge ethical progress in these other
of the agent's mode of production or social class. goods, but Wood does not. For Marx and Engels,
(Lyons 1976). The reductionist then assesses the however, greater realization of political commu-
validity of these differing conceptions of justice nity, cooperative productive activity, and indi-
not in their own terms but according to their im- viduality distinguishes communism from previous
pact on the productive forces. Thus, observers exploitative societies (Marx and Engels 1962, Vol.
could agree that slavery was just not because 2, p. 24; Marx 1973, pp. 325, 487-8).
slaves were inferior or barbarians lacking mental We might regard this reductionist interpretation
competence, as slaveholders alleged, but because as a version of scientific realism, one that identi-
slavery temporarily stimulated production. In fies which actual relationships have been termed
fact, although temporarily endorsing the slave- justice. But unlike the moral realist interpretation,
holders' judgment about justice, this view seems the reductionist account denies that any concep-
(peculiarly) compatible with the denial of the tion of justice could be true. Like its ethical
slaveholders' reasons. Such an interpretation cousin, relativism, the reductionist interpretation
saves itself from ethical relativism but only at the denies moral truth or objectivity.
expense of reductionism. More strongly than the Some theorists, such as Leo Strauss, have criti-
relativist interpretation, this view debunks all con- cized all modern political thought, liberal and
ceptions of justice. radical, for a putative commitment to moral rela-
In Wood's version of reductionism, the histori- tivism or historicism in contrast to the moral ob-
cal observer concurs with juridical standards if jectivity and loftier political and philosophical
they conform to the relations of production. theory of the ancients (Strauss 1965). In Strauss's
Wood sees justice as a conservative notion that terms, modern liberalism and radicalism must en-
corresponds to the old relations of production dorse a contentless notion of individual freedom.
even when that productive system has gone into If either a relativist or a reductionist account of
decline. Radical critics can never use such concep- Marx's moral judgments is true, such a critic
tions. A new view of justice becomes valid only could identify Marxian theory as part of an his-
after a political revolution has sanctioned new toricist trend.
production relations. Although this interpretation Strauss's critique captures one important strand
attempts to account for Marx's criticisms of the in modern political theory. For example,
use of the term eternal justice by moralistic Hobbes's idea of an anarchy of moral meanings
radicals (Marx 1966, Vol. 1: 84-85), it leaves a which requires the Leviathan of civil society to
crucial question unanswered: in periods when one establish a positive order, is a strongly conven-
mode of production declines, a new one arises, tionalist view; that is, moral ideas mean what the

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
330 The AmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
sovereign says they mean (Hobbes 1962, pp. interpretation, which sees humanity itself as
39-40). Michael Oakeshott offers an elegant refor- epoch relative or contends that no human nature
mulation of Hobbes's conception: a philosophical exists (Fisk 1975, pp. 74-8).
defense of modern individuality reflects current Defending an aspect of moral realism, Husami
European self-understanding and has no further, has challenged Wood's reductionism by dis-
more objective basis (Oakeshott 1975, pp. 325-6). tinguishing Marx's claims about the truth of
John Rawls, a liberal theorist, looks to moral moral judgments from his account of their origins
reasoning in an original position to encourage or "sociology of moral norms" (Husami 1980,
moral objectivity. Yet Rawls draws the relatively pp. 42-53). Husami argues that Marx recognized
pure moral intuitions that play a role in his moral facts about justice under capitalism; how-
"reflective equilibrium" from "our intuitions," ever, he tries to deny Wood's reductionism any
that is, the intuitions which at this historical mo- basis in Marx's own comments on justice. But as
ment moral philosophers happen to have (Rawls Wood (1979 Section III) has responded, Marx not
1971, pp. 19-20, 49-50). In the social sciences, only criticized capitalist standards of justice but
similar notions of moral conventionalism have also the notions of "eternal justice" offered by
become widespread. To take only one example, radicals like Proudhon and Lassalle. Marx some-
Max Weber's conception of legitimacy appeals to times appeared to substitute scientific explanation
what a given population thinks to be just. Weber (and political strategy) for any moral claims at all.
brackets the issue of whether legitimate govern- By rejecting Wood's interpretation outright,
mental practices actually are just or unjust. Fur- Husami has nearly painted Marx as the type of
thermore, Weber viewed different dimensions of moralist Marx criticized, a theorist who offers a
reality, politics and religion for example, as ruled primarily ethical critique of capitalism. Wood in
by clashing demons and denied the possibility of response similarly denies any merit in Husami's
moral objectivity. His "national economics" cele- contention that Marx scathingly indicted the in-
brated the eloquent relativist ideal of Machia- human consequences of capitalist exploitation.
velli's Florentine, who valued his city more highly Taking Husami's and Wood's accounts to-
than his soul (Weber 1958a, p. 126; 1958b, p. 107; gether, Marx and Engels appear to be ambiguous
Gilbert 1981c). The importance of moral rela- about whether or not capitalist exploitation is un-
tivism in contemporary liberal philosophical and just. I will argue, however, that although Marx
social scientific thinking lends some plausibility to and Engels did not regard injustice as the only or
the general Straussian critique. even the main indictment of capitalism, they saw
Nonetheless, Strauss's argument is thoroughly the historic differences between rich and poor, ex-
unfair to the diversity of modern liberalism. He plained by Marx's theory of exploitation, as, in
ignores the hardly contentless liberal and radical Engels's phrase, crying injustices. Thus, the
denial of ancient slavery as a prerequisite for any Wood-Husami debate does not stem from any
morally defensible form of social cooperation and ambiguity in Marx's and Engels's moral judg-
individuality (see Montesquieu 1965, bk. xv; ments or in their condemnation of capitalism and
Hegel 1975, pp. 54, 140; Gilbert 1981b), and he previous exploitative societies but rather from a
fails to identify Marx's moral judgments, if Marx- different ambiguity in Marx's and Engels's ac-
ian social theory is true, as objective or realist count of the status or truth of moral concepts.
claims about human needs and capacities. The difficulty lies not in Marx's and Engels's
Thus, a moral realist interprets Marx's stan- ethics but in their metaethics and its peculiar im-
dards of human goods, including political com- pact on their interpretation of their scientific,
munity, freedom, individuality, friendship, soli- political, and ethical disputes with other radicals.
darity, and scientific and artistic achievement, as On this argument, many readers of Marx, both
stemming from Marx's conception of human sympathetic and unsympathetic, have mistakenly
nature (see also Gilbert 1981a). This human used some of Marx's and Engels's relativist or
nature exhibits certain original capacities and reductionist metaethical statements to ignore their
needs, roughly those identified by Darwin's actual moral judgments.
theory; subsequent historical development has I call my interpretation of Marx's ethical judg-
refined these original capacities or created new ments a moral realist one in analogy with the real-
ones (Marx 1961, Vol. 1, pp. 178, 341: Cohen ist arguments of Putnam (1975), Boyd (1979) and
1979, pp. 151-2). This vision of a historically Kripke (1980) in contemporary philosophy of sci-
modified human nature combined with Marx's ence and language. Moral realism recognizes the
theory of economic and political development objectivity of moral judgments about human
favors a society that fosters the greatest flourish- needs and capacities, progress in morality and
ing of individuality and achievement of poten- moral theory, the dependence of ethical progress
tials. Note that this view contradicts any relativist on advances in social organization and social

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguity in Marx and Engels 331
theory, and the role of moral conceptions, sible. One might even claim that Aristotle ad-
especially true ones in social explanation and vanced such a theory about cooperation and free-
political strategy. dom among those recognized as human, although
Anglo-American philosophy, influenced by em- he wrongly excluded women and slaves (Gilbert
piricism, has stressed a priori analysis of the defi- 198lb). The realist also contends that progress has
nition of moral terms; for example, the ancient occurred in morality, for instance from slave to
Greeks' criteria for using the term good would de- nonslave organizations of society, and in moral
termine its meaning.' Consequently, any change theory. Such advances are heavily dependent on
in the definition of the term good renders moral advances in history and in social theory. The truth
continuity problematic, and a claim that ancient of claims about justice or other moral judgments
Greeks and modern liberals share important con- would influence the destiny of radical movements
ceptions of the good life or freedom is incoherent. and would prove indispensable to an adequate
Thus, this general empiricist conception in the social theory.
philosophy of language leads directly to moral Thus, this paper argues that a moral realist ac-
relativism or historicism (Rorty 1979, pp. 280-1). count provides the most consistent interpretation
In contrast, for the realist, moral concepts refer of Marx's and Engels's judgments about justice
to actual human social and psychological capaci- and the role of ethical judgments in Marxian
ties for cooperation, freedom, and individuality social theory and will show that their occasional
manifested in the course of historical develop- metaethical relativist or reductionist comments
ment. The realist view begins from Aristotle's are misleading. If this argument is correct, it
argument that the Greek polis first demonstrated results in a more sweeping reinterpretation of the
the human potentials for a good life, or of man to status of moral argument in Marx's historical
be a political animal, potentials that were not theory and political strategy and a more funda-
previously recognized in Persian or ancient Greek mental recasting of Marx's relationship to an-
despotism (Aristotle, Politics, 1252b 16-23, cient, liberal, and earlier radical political and
1253a30-31). Later arguments, such as Hegel's moral theory than any previous view.
that in Greece, only male citizens were free, but
modern society has recognized that all males are What Can Marxists Fairly Say About Injustices?
free, or Marx's argument that communism
enables the full realization of social individuality, In One Hundred Countries, Two Billion Peo-
attempt to identify new manifestations of human ple, Robert S. McNamara, then president of the
ethical possibilities. World Bank, made an impassioned plea for inter-
Thus, a realist explanation of the ambiguity in national redistribution. Pointing to the plight of
Marx's metaethics can lead to a much more sym- the most impoverished citizens of India, he con-
pathetic view of justice than relativism or reduc- tended:
tionism. Realism acknowledges some merit in past It is the poorest40% who despitetheircountry's
and current views about justice but offers a theo- gross economicgrowth remainin conditionsof
retical reformulation of those views; it shows how deprivationthat fall below any rationaldefini-
dramatically moral differences between liberals tion of human decency.... When we reflect
and the ancients, for example Montesquieu's re- that of the morethanhalf a billionpersonsliving
jection of Aristotle's social biological defense of on the Indian subcontinent,some 200 million
slavery, or between Marxists and liberals, pivot on subsist on incomesthat averageless than $40 a
issues of social theory rather than on incommen- year, how are we to comprehendwhatthat really
surable ethical premises. The moral realist ac- implies?(McNamara1973, pp. 104-5)
count recognizes historical progress but is not his-
toricist or relativist. Unlike empiricist or neo- One might add that if the lowest 400o7 are so poor,
Kantian moral philosophy, moral realism empha- the circumstances of the vast majority are only
sizes the discovery of moral knowledge a pos- slightly less oppressive and uncertain. By any con-
teriori based on observable human social practice ception of meeting the minimal human needs of
and denies it any a priori status. The realist re- food, shelter, and jobs, let alone health care and
gards an approximately true moral theory as pos- schooling, these inequalities, characteristic of in-
dividual countries and more strikingly of inter-
national society as a whole, seem unjust if not
perverse and outrageous. Furthermore, by
2The empiricist view of moral terms ultimately derives McNamara's own account, inequality of income
from Locke's argument that words refer only to nomi-
nal essences, specified by lists of secondary qualities,
shares is increasing in India as in many other poor
not to real or internal essences. Locke, 1979, bk. 3, chs. nations.
5-6, esp. pp. 442-45. Kripke (1980, pp. 134-40) and For McNamara, the causes of this impoverish-
Boyd (1980) have criticized this view. ment seem unclear; they reside in some absence of

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
332 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
dynamism among entrepreneurs or the masses in capitalist internationaleconomic system, major
poor nations, or perhaps ultimately in some puta- redistributioncannot occur.
tive cultural or psychological deficiency, and do Yet somethingseemspeculiarabout this Marx-
not stem mainly from the heritage of colonialism ian response.AlthoughMcNamaraagonizesover
or the contemporary effects of foreign interven- the arbitrarynatureof this situation,the Marxist
tion. But once a common concern, spurred by says nothing about justice. Perhapsthis Marxist
McNamara's book, becomes widespread among holds the relativist interpretation,according to
policy-making elites, McNamara expects that the which McNamarahas a bourgeoisconceptionof
conditions of the least advantaged will improve. justice, and conceptions of justice are simply a
How might a Marxist respond to McNamara's muddle, or perhapshe has a reductionistconcep-
appeal to justice? In a classic strategy suggested tion, that McNamarais rightthat this distribution
by Engels's The Housing Question (1873), a cri- is unjust (capitalismas a productivesystem has
tique of the German Proudhonist Millberger, a passed its historicalzenith), but wrong about the
Marxist might point to facts about the interaction reasons. Yet the Marxist'ssocial analysis,if true,
of rich and poor which make McNamara's view undermines only McNamara's claim that the
implausible. In the poor nations the new elites World Bank can serve as an instrument for
benefit from skewed income distribution (Tucker redistribution (Taylor 1973); it leaves
1977, pp. 154-5). Furthermore, the elites of the McNamara'sclaim about the glaringinjusticeof
advanced capitalist nations who sometimes supply internationaldistribution, or the "crying con-
economic and military aid to the poor nations trasts" of rich and poor, in Engels's phrase,
have a common interest with these elites in main- perfectlyintact (Engels1966,pp. 173-4).Further-
taining impoverishment (they benefit from cheap more, the Marxist's social theory shows who
labor, for example), and international monetary benefits from these injustices and pinpoints a
institutions sustain their interests. For the Marx- defect of characterin McNamarawho at least
ist, some version of Lenin's theory of imperialism deceives himself.4 Although the Marxist might
or today's dependency theory would appear to ex- contend that the condemnationof injustice can
plain the increase in inequality and to illuminate occur only on McNamara'smoral premise, it is
the gap between at best skewed and unequal hard to see why a Marxist wouldn't share this
economic growth and internal and international premise. Marxistsdo, after all, object to eror-
rhetoric about redistribution (Myrdal 1970, pp. mous disparitiesof wealth and povertyand their
60-1).3 Correspondingly, only mutual support social consequences;an indictmentof these con-
among workers, peasants, students, and intellec- sequencesprovides an importantmotivation for
tuals in both poor and rich nations, offers any socialism. In this case, a common moral concern
hope of securing redistribution to the less advan- lends urgency to the Marxian criticism of
taged (Gilbert 1978b). McNamara'ssolution. Nothing in the social cri-
McNamara's view suggests that the World tique of McNamara'sremedy-calling on con-
Bank, once it recognized the injustice of inter- scientious elites to rectify impoverishment-
national distribution, would welcome attempts at logically requiresa rejection of all concepts of
redistribution in the poor nations. From a Marx- justice.
ian point of view, the World Bank is tied to cer- Beyond this, the Marxist'srefusal to address
tain class interests, and rhetoric notwithstanding, McNamara'smoral assessment of international
would oppose serious attempts at such redistribu- distribution seems ironic, for if anything, the
tion. For example, consider the World Bank's Marxisthas better reasons for calling this situa-
reaction to the election in 1970 of the democratic tion an injustice than McNamara has.
socialist regime of Chilean Salvador Allende. Far McNamara'sargumentmightblamethe victimor
from encouraging this non-revolutionary attempt historical accident, but suppose the citizens of
at redistribution, the World Bank cut its aid from poor nations lack initiativeowing to internalen-
more than twenty million dollars to none. After vironmentalcauses, or supposeno one is to blame
the 1973 coup, the World Bank restored its aid to for internationalinequalities. If people are im-
the Pinochet regime (Cusack 1977, p. 144; Payre poverishedas a result of their own inadequacies,
1975). The Marxist might conclude that the facts no injustice has occurred. And although Rawls
and an accurate social theory show that within a has forcefullydefendedthe fairnessof rectifying
social and naturalarbitrariness,it is hard to see.
blameless arbitrarinessas an injustice (Gilbert
3ThoughI cannot examinethe issue in this paper,the 1978a, pp. 109-10, 117). The Marxiananalysis,
internationaldivision of labor in EasternEurope and
the ThirdWorld, presidedover by the Soviet economic
elite, strikinglyresembles capitalist forms of depen- 'Shklar (1979) rightly argues against exaggerating the
dency. moral significance of such character defects.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin Marxand Engels 333
however, fixes appropriate responsibility on the celebrated as a Christian humanist alternative to
beneficiaries of inegalitarian distribution and the heartless atheist Marx, dismissed the industrial
shows how victimization has occurred. More working class as unready for immediate revolt and
plausibly than McNamara, a Marxist can view recommended a communist uprising by the
contemporary international distribution as unjust. "thieving proletariat" (Wittke 1950, p. 120;
A realist argument demonstrating the grain of Forder 1970, pp. 220-21; Gilbert 1981, chs. 3-4).
truth in McNamara's conception, seems far more In both cases, influential radical opponents of
appropriate than either relativist abstention from Marx relied on moral concepts as the central
moral comment or reductionism. This example feature of their social theory and displayed
highlights the inaccuracy of Marx's and Engels's profound elitist hostility to the working-class
occasional characterization of their own views as movement.
a historical critique of prevailing conceptions of To combat these views, Marx and Engels at-
justice. Since Marxian historical theory leads tempted to distinguish neatly between communist
more decisively than McNamara's to a condemna- political radicalism (designed to make socialism
tion of injustice, this analysis compels a deeper in- and internationalism issues in the midst of active
quiry into the reasons why Marx and Engels class conflict) and moralistic radicalism. In quasi-
found relativist or reductionist formulations positivist fashion, they contrasted their scientific
attractive. arguments with their opponents' ethical or ideo-
logical ones, interpreted on a relativist or reduc-
Three Accounts of Justice in Marx and Engels tionist basis. (In fact, a reductionist reconstruc-
tion of issues of justice is a classic empiricist
Marx's and Engels's metaethical argument move, which begs the question of whether or not
vacillates between relativist or reductionist and the situations people have referred to as unjust
realist conceptions of justice. As I have noted, on deserve our concern (Sturgeon 1980, pp. 31-2)).
Marx's and Engels's historical critique, prevailing A reader may properly ask whether Marx's quar-
conceptions of justice derive from a system of law rel is with all moralities or only with the use of
which suits the needs of a predominant mode of moral concepts by ruling class spokespersons or
production. Pointing to the epoch relativism or by radicals who hold accompanying erroneous
merely functional validity of such moral concepts, theories of capitalism.
this historical theory deflates the grandiose claims Yet Marx and Engels offered another view of
of theorists who seek to recast society according justice and equality. They recognized that
to ideal standards of justice. Ironically, even radi- workers, artisans, and peasants often use moral
cal claims about injustice frequently share in the concepts to criticize a prevailing social order. As
prevailing conceptions and offer no adequate Engels remarked in Anti-Duhring (1878), the de-
analysis of social structure and political alterna- mand for social equality became the battle cry of
tives. In some of Marx's formulations, radicals re- the sixteenth-century German peasant war and ex-
quire only a clear understanding of the internal pressed "the revolutionary instincts of the pea-
conflicts in capitalist society and definite political santry," their "spontaneous reaction against the
strategies to overthrow it. Moral indignation can- crying social inequalities, against the contrast of
not substitute for such analysis and obscures the rich and poor, feudal lords and their serfs, surfeit
need for a patient, realistic strategic perspective and starvation." He noted similar demands in the
(Marx 1961, Vol. 1, 84-5; Marx and Engels 1962, French communist workers' movement and called
Vol. 2, pp. 25, 30). Furthermore, such moral for "the abolition of classes" as the "real con-
views encourage an elitist radicalism that scorns tent" of these demands (Engels 1966, pp. 117-8).
the struggle of the oppressed classes, where the But indignation over inequality between rich
participants might discover the validity of a revo- and poor is a component of justice. In inegali-
lutionary point of view. Moralistic radicals substi- tarian economies, all crises and hardships fall with
tute their own artificial solutions-crotchets, as especial severity on the poor. As class societies,
Marx called them-for real class conflict. Thus, even feudal ones, legitimize expectations of cus-
Proudhon sought to inaugurate a reign of eternal tomary provision of subsistence among the pro-
justice by the formation of cooperative banking ducers, such special hardships often appear as an
arrangements (mutualism) as the guarantor of fair abridgment of the obligations of the non-
exchanges among small propertyholders. He op- producers, or in modern times as a violation of in-
posed unions on the grounds that they violated in- dividual rights. Given that the lives of the pro-
dividual liberty and even defended the French ducers and their families depend on the reliable
government when it shot down striking coal fulfillment of such expectations, their violation is
miners at Rive-de-Gier (Marx 1963, pp. 125-6; a seeming breach of promise and provokes a par-
Proudhon 1924, pp. 377-80, 384-5). Similarly, ticularly vivid sense of outrage, which historically
the German tailor Wilhelm Weitling, sometimes has played an important causal role in popular

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
334 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
revolts (Moore 1965; Thompson 1971; Scott ethical content. More plausibly, science does not
1976). neatly replace ethical evaluation. The revolu-
In contrast to an impoverished conception of tionary demand grows out of the moral content of
justice that confines itself solely to legal relations the workers' original demand and in a Hegelian
and hence cannot, for example, criticize the in- sense recalls it.
justice of laws that sanction slavery, any adequate According to Marx's moral realist line of argu-
conception must assess how given social arrange- ment, ethical indictments by workers, artisans,
ments affect the needs and capacities of all in- and peasants arise from the real experience and
dividuals. Minimally, it would condemn any understanding of a given social system's oppres-
system of distribution that provided superfluity siveness; Marx sought to learn from this popular
for the few combined with starvation for the understanding by studying actual movements
many. Maximally, in Marx's view of communism, (Gilbert 1981, chs. 1-2). Thus Marx's scientific
for example, a just system of distribution would and political critique of Proudhon and the uto-
measure need according to diverse individual pian socialists focused on their refusal to par-
capacity, a view that invokes an ancient concep- ticipate in and learn from class conflict. Unlike
tion of natural justice, such as Aristotle's sugges- such elitists, his theory requires Marxists to take
tion that the best fluteplayer, rather than the the opinions of others seriously and to engage
handsomest or wealthiest, should receive the best them in moral as well as theoretical and political
supply of flutes (Aristotle, Politics, 1282b30- conversation about why, for instance, workers
1283a4; Brecht 1966, p. 128). Thus, Engels and should aim for the abolition of classes rather than
Marx do not reject the proletarian demand for equality. In contrast, according to the relativist or
equality as ideological but justify it in terms of reductionist interpretations, all that a Marxist can
need and reformulate it as a demand for abolition fairly say about concepts of justice is to debunk
of classes. them.
In Marx's Value, Price and Profit (1865), he ad-
vocated participation in strikes and unions that Engels's and Marx's Argument against
could drive up workers' wages at least tempo- Proudhon's "Eternal Justice"
rarily. (Marx drew a new distinction between a
relatively invariant physical element of subsis- In The Housing Question, Engels dismissed
tence and a much more elastic moral or social ele- Proudhon's conception of "eternal justice" as a
ment.) In the long run, however, Marx contended fantasy. As one strategy for making this argu-
that capitalism would undercut these union gains ment, Engels debunked all conceptions of justice
and drive workers to revolt. Through participa- as relative either to a mode of production or to the
tion in their "real movement," he advocated the person holding the specific conception. He con-
substitution of the "revolutionary watchword," tended that "The justice of the Greeks and
abolition of classes, for the "conservative motto Romans held slavery to be just; the justice of the
'a fair day's pay for a fair day's work' " (Marx bourgeoisie of 1789 demanded the abolition of
and Engels 1962, Vol. 1, p. 446). Marxian social feudalism on the ground that it was unjust. For
theory sees the concept of a "fair day's pay" as the Prussian Junker even the miserable District
conservative because that demand does not ques- Ordinance is a violation of eternal justice."' Fur-
tion the existence of capitalism and seeks only a thermore, the concept of eternal justice "belongs
"better rate of exploitation" from the workers' among those things of which Millberger correctly
point of view. According to Marx, the particular says 'everyone understands something differ-
conception of "fairness" invoked in this demand ent' " (Marx and Engels 1962, Vol. 1, p. 624). In
cuts against the workers' real interests. Yet Marx these statements, Engels adopted either an ap-
defended the workers' anger and supported their praiser's-group relativism or a person relativism.
demands with this particular moral gloss re- Engels again seemed to take a positivist stand
moved. He thought that the capitalist division of toward moral concepts; unlike scientific investiga-
rich and poor, characterized by a certain kind of tion in which researchers can ultimately resolve
exploitation in production, justified the workers' disagreements, human beings can never resolve
fight for higher wages and a shorter working day. disputes about justice, which only result in
His own social theory dramatically extended the ceaseless wrangling.
workers' claims to the expropriation of all surplus Earlier, Engels criticized Millberger's wish that
value from the capitalists and the creation of a
classless society. Since Marx's analysis illuminates
and reinforces the workers' indignation, it seems 'See also Marx 1961, Vol. 3, pp. 339-40. Marx, how-
peculiar to view this change of demands as ever, avoided the puzzling inconsistencies, for instance
replacement of an ideological ethics devoid of sci- the endorsement of person-relativism, sometimes found
entific content with a social theory devoid of in Engels's philosophical arguments.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin Marxand Engels 335
rent agreements under capitalism could be "per- Elsewhere in The Housing Question, Engels
vaded by a conception of right . . . carried out condemned miserable housing conditions and
everywhere according to the strict demands of jus- cheating by merchants as examples of the "count-
tice." This "justice" would protect each artisan less small, secondary abuses (Obelstande)" of
or peasant in his ownership of a dwelling. Engels capitalism and stigmatized exploitation
counterposed the facts of capitalist production to (Ausbeutung) of the worker in production as the
Mfilberger's dream. Capitalism persistently up- "fundamental evil (Grundilbel)." Recalling the
roots small propertyholders and forces them into Communist Manifesto, Engels criticized the
large cities; it tends to replace independent prop- Proudhonists in a realist vein: "It is the essence of
ertyholding, including homeownership, with bourgeois socialism to want to maintain the basis
capitalist landlordship: of all the evils of present-day society and at the
same time to want to abolish the evils themselves"
Whatdoes this rigamarolemean?Nothing more
than that the practicaleffects of the economic (Marx and Engels 1959, Vol. 18, pp. 214-5; 1962,
laws which govern present-daysociety run con- Vol. 1, pp. 558-81). Thus, a revolutionary strategy
traryto the author'ssense of justice and that he based on an accurate social theory would strike at
cherishesthe pious wish that the mattermightbe the basic evil in the mode of production.
so arrangedas to remedythe situation. Yes, if Engels analyzed the facts against Proudhon's
toads had tails they would no longer be toads! appeal to "eternal justice" in the light of Marx's
And is thenthe capitalistmodeof productionnot historical theory; his claims depend upon the ap-
'pervadedby a conceptionof right,'namely,that proximate truth of the theory and include a spe-
of its own right to exploit the workers?And if cific explanation of capitalist exploitation, of the
the author tells us that is not his conceptionof
right, are we one step further(Marxand Engels fundamental class conflicts that grow out of it,
1962, Vol. 1, pp. 562-3)? such as the fight over the length of the working
day, of capitalism's tendency to concentrate con-
In this argument, we can see that Engels's claim trol of industry in a few hands and to create a
about the person relativism of justice ("the large propertyless proletariat, and of the tendency
author's sense of right") does not necessarily of the rate of profit to fall and engender crises.
follow from the claim of Marx's historical theory Given this analysis Engels argued that "fac-
about mode-of-production relativism. In fact, tually," capitalism produces its own gravediggers.
Engels uses the conception of right appropriate to Contrary to Proudhon and Miflberger, workers
capitalism to debunk Milberger's personal sense. could not, scientifically speaking, overturn
Furthermore, throughout The Housing Question, capitalism by establishing the "sincerity of ex-
Engels analyzes Millberger's sense of right as a changes" among revivified small propertyholders,
class sense, namely a small propertyholder's or any more than according to Darwin, toads could
petit bourgeois conception of justice, rendered have tails (Proudhon 1923, Vol. 1, p. 258).
anachronistic by capitalist expansion. Thus, from In Capital, Marx gave an ironic twist to this cri-
a Marxian point of view, one could simply drop tique of Proudhonism. Proudhon identified jus-
the person relativist argument and stick with the tice among small propertyowners with the regula-
appraiser's-group relativist one. But given this ac- tion of production and exchange by means of the
count, Engels's argument seems peculiar. Engels equal labor times embodied in commodities. For
characterizes capitalism's "justice" as "its own Proudhon, the violation of such exchanges by
right to exploit the workers"-a description that a large capitalists could occur only through "swin-
capitalist would hardly endorse. (Is this charac- dling," someone taking more than his or her
terization merely an expression of Engels's "own due. Contrary to Proudhon, Marx showed that
sense of justice"?). Engels's comment on ex- the extraction of surplus value and its concrete
ploitation does not follow from his ethical relativ- forms of profit, interest, and rent could occur
ism or reductionism but rather from the realist regularly under capitalism without swindling. He
argument noted above, which Engels used to in- argued that one commodity in use, labor power,
dict capitalism.' creates a greater value (surplus value) than its own
value in exchange (subsistence). But, Marx in-
sisted, the capitalist extracts surplus value without
'Note that Engels'sjudgmentmightbe appropriateto violating the laws of circulation, that is, the juridi-
a form of ethical relativism,namelya defense of one's cal standards of capitalism (Marx 1966, Vol. 1,
own moral views given that this moral position is as
pp. 193-4); in this sense only, capitalist exploita-
validas any other. Engelsdid not endorsethis form of
relativism,however,becauseof his admirationfor sci-
ence at the expenseof ethics. Beyondthis, contraryto
any form of relativism,as we shall see, Engelsthought
divisions of rich and poor were unjust given human and defendeda conceptionof moralprogressand moral
needs, not merelydependingon the specific observer, truth.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
336 The AmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
tion is not "robbery" (Marx and Engels 1959, six; it does not show that all claims of injustice
Vol. 19, pp. 382, 359-60). Satirizing Proudhon, and exploitation are relative to specific modes of
Marx showed that the generalization of commodi- production but just that Proudhon's is nor does it
ty production, characteristic of capitalism, led to show that all claims of justice must be the basis of
the gradual expropriation of small holders, not to (or be based upon) an inaccurate scientific theory
their salvation: "So long as the laws of exchange and an inadequate political strategy. It does not
are observed in every specific act of exchange the rule out, for example, a scientific and moral
mode of appropriation can be completely revolu- theory-say one of exploitation-which could
tionized without in any way affecting the property evaluate social situations over several epochs of
rights which correspond to commodity produc- class society and play a political role in the forging
tion" (Marx 1961, Vol. 1, p. 587). Marx added, of communism. Claims one through six are con-
"We may well therefore feel astonished at the sistent with any of the three interpretations of
cleverness of Proudhon, who would abolish capi- justice described in the introduction. Only claim
talist property by enforcing the eternal laws of seven-an implausible one given Marx's actual
property that are based on commodity produc- argument against Proudhon-would sustain an
tion" (Marx 1961, Vol. 1, p. 587, n. 1) and com- ethical relativist or reductionist account against a
pared Proudhon to an incompetent chemist: realist one.
Furthermore, Marx and Engels undermined
Proudhonbegins by taking his ideal of justice claim seven because their own argument shares a
(Gerechtigkeit),of 'justice eternelle' from the
juridicalrelationsthatcorrespondto the produc- common moral premise with Proudhon's. In
tion of commodities;therebyit may be noted he Anti-Duhring, for example, Engels wrote:
proves to the consolation of all good citizens, If for the imminent overthrowof the present
that the productionof commoditiesis a form of mode of distributionwith its cryingcontrastsof
production as everlastingas justice. Then he want and luxury, starvation and debauchery
turnsroundand seeks to reformthe actual pro- (schreiendenGegensatzenvon Elendund Uppig-
ductionof commodities,and the actuallegalsys- keit, Hungersnotund Schwelgerei),we had no
tem correspondingthereto, in accordancewith betterguaranteethan the consciousnessthat the
this ideal. What opinion should we have of a mode of production is unjust (ungerecht) . .. we
chemistwho, insteadof studyingthe actuallaws shouldbe in a prettybad way. The mysticsof the
of the molecularchangesin the compositionand MiddleAges who dreamedof the comingmillen-
decompositionof matter, and on that founda- nium were already conscious of the injustice
tion solving definite problems,claimedto regu- (Ungerechtigkeit)of classcontrasts(Engels1966,
late the compositionand decompositionof mat- p. 173;Marxand Engels 1959, Vol. 20, p. 146).
ter by the 'eternalideas' of 'naturalit6'and 'af-
finite? (Marx 1961, Vol. 1, pp. 84-5; Marxand Engels commented that "to economic science,
Engels 1959, Vol. 23, pp. 99-100). moral indignation, however justifiable, cannot
Based on his scientific criticism of Proudhon's serve as an argument, but only as a symptom"
theory, Marx made seven claims: (1) he identified (Engels, 1966, pp. 173-4). Engels not only recog-
Proudhon's specific conception of justice as an nized the justification of moral anger, but con-
ideological reflection of capitalist juridical rela- tended,
tions; (2) he argued that conceptions of justice are The indignation(Zorn)whichcreatesthe poet is
transitory (limited to one or several historical absolutely in place in describingthese terrible
epochs) rather than eternally valid as Proudhon conditions, and also in attackingthose apostles
thought; (3) contrary to the Ricardian socialists of harmonyin the serviceof the rulingclass who
and Proudhon, he showed that capitalist exploita- eitherdenyor palliatetheseabuses,but how little
tion occurs without robbery in the process of it can prove anythingfor the particularcase is
commodity circulation; (4) he opposed Proud- evident from the fact that in each epoch of all
hon's overrating of the significance of justice in past history there has been no lack of material
historical explanations; (5) he argued that stra- for such indignation(Engels1966, p. 166;Marx
and Engels 1959, Vol. 20, p. 139).
tegically, workers could not overcome capitalist
oppression by reforming the juridical system to Engels viewed divisions between rich and poor
accord with its corresponding ideal of justice, but as a reprehensible feature of all previous epochs
rather by making political revolution and trans- except early communal society. Although a sense
forming the mode of production; (6) he con- of injustice alone could not do away with these
tended that given the nature of capitalism, appeals divisions, "poetic criticism" had unmasked the
to the moral sense of capitalists would do no good "apostles of harmony" and contributed to a
(Marx and Engels 1962, Vol. 1, pp. 62, 582); and political atmosphere conducive to a more thor-
(7) he criticized all ideas of justice in the name of oughgoing radicalism. Engels suggested that the
science. If Marx's scientific argument is correct, proletarian demand for equality had a double
however, it establishes only claims one through meaning. One meaning grew out of the bourgeois

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin MarxandEngels 337
demand for political equality and had a certain than merely his own "sense of right." The facts of
validity. But Engels stressed the other meaning of capitalism coincided with the ethical need to
equality: the "spontaneous reaction" against divi- create a classless society in which the "richest"
sions of rich and poor as a "simple expression of flourishing of human individuality could occur
the revolutionary instinct" of workers and pea- (Marx 1973, p. 325; Marx and Engels, 1962, Vol.
sants which "finds its justification in that and 2, p. 24).
only in that" (Engels 1966, p. 117). He saw this Marx also justified the moral outrage that
account of equality as separable from its first underlay, in his view, inadequate demands for
meaning and legitimate in its own terms. Finally, social equality. In 1875, for example, Marx
Marx's analysis of exploitation, the extraction of praised Proudhon's "epoch making" What is
gratuitous or unpaid labor, provided a new inter- Property? for "provocative defiance, laying
pretation of the source of these class divisions. hands of the economic 'holy of holies' (large scale
Contrary to Wood's argument, while Marx iden- private property in the means of production),
tified the mistakes in Proudhon's conception of superb paradox which makes a mock of bourgeois
swindling, he also offered a more defensible common sense . . . a deep and genuine feeling of
explanation and indictment of capitalist ex- indignation at the infamy of what exists (and)
ploitation. revolutionary earnestness," though he also noted
It might appear that Engels's appeal to facts to that, while characterizing property as theft,
overcome moral disagreement described a neces- Proudhon had entangled himself in obscure
sary course of social development and displayed a speculations about "true," that is small,
moral neutrality between capitalism and commu- bourgeois property. Marx distinguished Proud-
nism. Yet Marx and Engels always condemned the hon's achievement in What is Property? from the
exploitative features of capitalism and praised pretension to science, caricature of Hegel's dialec-
communism. For instance, in attacking the tics, and lack of anger of Proudhon's Philosophy
Proudhonist conception of the dispossession of of Poverty (1962, Vol. 1, pp. 391-2).
individual homeowners as a retrogression "below Thus, Marx and Engels shared with Proudhon
the savages," Engels contended: a common factual recognition of the division of
The Englishproletarianof 1872is on an infinite- rich and poor and a common moral indignation at
ly higherlevelthan the ruralweaverof 1772with its consequences. All three argued that social sys-
his 'hearthand home.' And will the troglodyte tems should prevent the starvation or extinction
with his cave ... ever accomplisha June insur- of their members and ultimately give individuals
rectionor a Paris Commune(Marxand Engels their due,8 and condemned divisions between rich
1962, Vol. 1, p. 564)?7 and poor which give some abundance while many
others do not receive their due and, at worst,
For Engels, the Paris workers' revolt of June,
starve. Therefore, divisions of rich and poor are
1848, or the first proletarian government, the
infamous and unjust. Agreeing up to this point,
Commune, exemplified a specially admirable
they then add further factual premises to reach
ethical achievement. Marx also spoke of the Coin-
munards, heroic "heaven storming"; he praised their divergent political and moral conclusions.
Proudhon argued that in the capitalist form of
the political action of worker-officials who re-
this division, capitalists regularly violate the laws
ceived only a skilled workman's wage in order to
of commodity exchange by monopoly, swindling
forge a cooperative society (Marx and Engels
1971, p. 153). Engels's celebration of the Com- and usury, and saw the remedy as the establishing
mune is not easy to reconcile with his mode-of- of a society of small, equal propertyholders, regu-
production relativism, for this political communi- lating their economy through a mutualist banking
ty not only accorded with socialist relations of system in accordance with the exchange of equal
production but in Engels's view was "infinitely labor times or the principles of eternal justice.
Marx and Engels maintained that in the capitalist
higher," an example of moral progress. Engels's
form of this division, capitalists regularly extract
indictment of legal justice that protects the capi-
surplus value from workers in ways consistent
talists' "right to exploit" accentuated the Com-
with the laws of commodity exchange, depriving
mune' s positive features. Engels offered this
praise as an accurate assessment of reality rather
'Proudhon had a far narrower sense of what was due
7Notethat Engels's(and Marx's)chauvinismtoward to small propertyholders than Marx's conception of a
savagesand troglodytesis not necessaryto the argu- communist distribution according to need. Marx's con-
ment. A Marxistcould admirethe Communeand yet ception of the Commune as a prerequisite for in-
hail the accomplishmentsof oppressedclasses in less dividuality is analogous in form to Proudhon's concep-
economicallyadvancedsettings,as Engels,for example, tion of (mutualist) individuality. See also Oakeshott
celebratedthe Germanpeasantwar. 1975, p. 319, n. 1.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
338 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
small holders of the means of production, pitting Marx's (and Rawls's) criticism of divisions of
a majority of propertyless proletarians against a wealth and poverty rests merely on a relatively
small number of property owners, and creating in- purified intuition. However altered by social
creasingly harsh conditions for the propertyless. theory and moral principles to achieve a reflective
As Chartism, the June insurrection, and the Paris equilibrium, such a condemnation remains ulti-
Commune demonstrate, working-class solidarity mately "our" (historically limited) judgment. But
and political community is possible. Marx and one might look at such intuitions as embryonic
Engels saw the remedy as the abolition of exploi- moral generalizations and analyze the notion of
tation and ultimately all class divisions and the human nature, needs, and capabilities on which
establishing of a society in which social in- this indictment rests. If one interprets intuitions in
dividuality can flourish. this way, one can argue about whether they are
In summarizing their disagreement with Proud- (empirically) right or wrong. For instance, Ari-
hon, Marx and Engels stressed a drastic conflict stotle offers certain strongly intuitive arguments
between ethical judgment and scientific theory about the "naturalness" of slavery (Politics, Bk.
and surmised that their argument engaged Proud- 1). Given subsequent revolts against slavery and
hon's only with respect to social theory and not the existence of non-slaveholding societies, Mon-
moral judgment. But since Marx and Engels tesquieu, Hegel, and others showed that this intui-
joined with Proudhon to condemn the crying con- tion rested on a mistaken theory about other
trasts of luxury and need, their scientific argu- human beings. Marx would make similar argu-
ment had an inextricable moral component. Marx ments against the naturalness of wage slavery. In
did not disagree with Proudhon about the moral other words, such intuitions could be considered
desirability of opposing capitalism but rather moral observations and might play a role in
about the inadequacy of Proudhon's theory of ethical theory more nearly akin to theory-loaded
mutualism as an effective means of transforma- scientific observations than Rawls envisions. In
tion. In other words, the dispute turned not over that case, the process of observation and theo-
indignation, but over the notion that, in today's retical refinement characteristic of reflective
philosophical jargon, "ought implies can." Con- equilibrium would strongly resemble the process
trary to the positivist impression created by of scientific reflection and alteration of theory to
Engels's and Marx's relativist or reductionist achieve successive approximations to the truth
remarks, they appealed to facts and social theory (Rawls 1971, pp. 49-50).'
to show how moral disputes and indignation at
unjust conditions might at last be successfully Scientific Realism and Moral Realism
resolved.
If the foregoing analysis is correct, it has broad In debating with Mulberger, Engels compares
implications for a comparison of Marx's view the possibility of moral progress, which he ap-
with other arguments about justice. Marx shares pears to deny, with that of scientific progress,
his ethical premise with many contemporary theo- which he vigorously affirms, but here, too, his
rists and would disagree with today's moral argument is more ambiguous than it seems at first
theory mainly over the nature of modern society glance. To combat MUlberger, Engels likened jus-
and the means needed to change it. For instance, a tice to a sort of "social phlogiston":
Rawlsian would object to divisions of income that While in everyday life, in view of the simplicity
fail to benefit the least advantaged, and for utili- of the relations discussed, expressions like right,
tarians, the deprivations of the poor would under- wrong, justice and sense of right are accepted
mine overall or average happiness. But if Marx's without misunderstanding even with reference to
social theory is true and such divisions arise as a social matters, they create, as we have seen, the
fundamental consequence of capitalist exploita- same hopeless confusion in any scientific investi-
tion, then either of these moral arguments would gation of economic relations as would be cre-
justify socialism (Rawls 1975, p. 546). As Wood ated, for instance, if the terminology of the phlo-
giston theory were to be retained. The confusion
has argued, probably any recognizably moral becomes still worse if one, like Proudhon,
principles would lead to the condemnation of believes in the social phlogiston, 'justice' or if
capitalism and its consequences as Marx under- one like MUlberger avers that the phlogiston
stood them; a theory that could condone these
consequences would not be a moral theory at all
(Wood 1972, pp. 281-2). Although Wood does
'I owe this comparison to Richard Boyd. In an impor-
not draw this conclusion, his argument suggests a tant ambiguity, Rawls does not just argue intuitively for
greater objectivity in moral theory than has often political and moral equality but recognizes its basis in
been supposed. facts about human moral capacity-"equality is sup-
Now a Rawlsian might deny this degree of ported by the general facts of nature." Rawls 1971, pp.
objectivity in moral judgments by arguing that 506, 510, 548.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin Marxand Engels 339
theory is as correct as the oxygen one (Marx and modern chemistry provided a better explanation
Engels 1962, Vol. 1, p. 625). for anomalies in a previously mistaken but not
Here again, Engels drew a positivist distinction wholly inadequate chemistry. In today's terms,
between scientific investigation, which achieves Engels adopted a scientific realist attitude toward
agreement on relatively reliable theories, and phlogiston theory rather than that of a relativist
moral clashes, which lead to no resolution. Engels or a Kuhnian.1'
praised MUlberger's person-relativist conception Thus, the analogy of justice with phlogiston
that concerning justice, "everyone understands reflects a realistic hunch on Engels's part about
something different," but refused to commend moral questions, one that might also explain
Milberger's peculiar conception of oxygen-based Engels's claim that matters of right and wrong in
and phlogiston-based chemistry as, scientifically everyday life are not confusing. If this major
speaking, equally valid. In this context, Engels's feature of morality presents no important diffi-
analogy of justice with social phlogiston, moving culties, it is hard to see why we could not ulti-
from ethics to science, views justice, like phlogis- mately hope to achieve similar agreement in moral
ton, as simply part of an inadequate (unscientific) theories about the basic structure of society, since
ethical theory that a purely scientific one has self-interest and rationalizations certainly affect
replaced. Engels's mode-of-production relativist everyday judgments in one's own case. Com-
arguments reinforce this impression. In this set- parable rationalizations, based on class interests,
ting, Proudhon's notion of eternal justice, reflect- might simply render progress in moral theory (and
ing commodity production, seems just so much in moral reality) more difficult, though not insur-
erroneous ideological mist that will dissipate in mountably so, than progress in daily life and in
the sunlight of a socialist mode of production. the sciences (Marx and Engels 1962, Vol. 1, p.
Yet Engels's analogy has another possible inter- 582). We can gauge the strength of this realist ink-
pretation. In a footnote to this passage, he con- ling by examining Engels's most important use of
tended that phlogiston theory pointed to a single the phlogiston analogy, his exploration of the sig-
element involved in combustion, even though it nificance of Marx's discovery of surplus value for
got most of that element's properties backward. political economy and moral argument.
The phlogiston theory contributed importantly to According to Engels, earlier scientific expo-
the discovery of oxygen: nents of a labor theory of value had partially
recognized that capitalists extracted a surplus
Before the discovery of oxygen chemists ex- from the workers. In The Principles of Political
plained the burning of substances in atmospheric Economy and Taxation, Ricardo argued that
air by assuming the existence of a special igneous Adam Smith had confused the value of the labor-
substance, phlogiston, which escaped during the
process of combustion. Since they found that
time incorporated in the production of commodi-
simple substances on combustion weighed more ties with the value of the labor-time which the
after having been burned than they did before, worker's wages could command on the market
they declared that phlogiston had a negative (1948, pp. 5-11). Distinguishing these separate
weight so that a substance without its phlogiston commodities, Ricardo isolated the amount paid
weighed more than one with it. In this way, all for the use of the worker's labor (what Marx
the main properties of oxygen were gradually would call labor-power) and the extra value cre-
ascribed to phlogiston, but all in an inverted ated by the worker in production (what Marx
form (Marx and Engels 1962, Vol. 1, p. 625). would call surplus value). Yet Ricardo never
The phlogiston theory was not even approxi- treated this surplus as a special concept nor at-
mately true. Yet that theory helped to pose the tempted to reexamine previous political economy
issue of the nature of combustion in such a way based on this insight (Marx 1961, Vol. 1, pp.
that a novel theory could explain it. In this sense, 515-6, 537-8). Engels drew an analogy between
Lavoisier's discovery of a new element, oxygen, Ricardo's identification of surplus and Priestley's
which combined with other elements upon burn- and Scheele's discovery of "dephlogisticated air"
ing, grew out of and solved the central problem of or "fire air." As Engels suggested, these chemists,
phlogiston chemistry. In his Preface to Volume 2 although close to discovering oxygen, remained
of Capital, Engels remarked that "this discovery entangled in the "phlogistic categories as they
(phlogiston) sufficed for the explanation of most found them" just as Ricardo remained enmeshed
of the chemical phenomena then known (until the within the older political economy. But the Ricar-
later 18th century) although not without forcing dian socialists and Proudhon abandoned
in many cases" (Marx and Engels 1-962, Vol. 1, p.
470). Compared to Engels's relativist description
of justice as mere shifting ideology, this argument "'A Kuhnian attitude toward science would in fact be
seems strikingly favorable to the scientific accom- far more consistent with ethical relativism than Engels's
plishments of phlogiston theory. For Engels, own position. See Rorty 1979.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
340 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
Ricardo's clear distinction. They asked: what is strated its progress in achieving successive approx-
the value of labor? and answered: the full value of imations to the truth.
the product. They then condemned the appropria- Given Marx's and Engels's realist interpretation
tion of any part of the output by the capitalist as of political economy, Engels's comparison of
injustice or stealing. Here we see a different and justice with phlogiston chemistry seems strikingly
particularly strong motivation for Marx's and favorable to justice. At least popular conceptions
Engels's critique of "eternal justice." Instead of of justice, one might surmise, would serve as a
solving political economy's central problem of the first approximation to the truth, and Marx's
value of labor, Proudhon and others obscured it theory reformulated them. Engels failed to see the
through the use of moral categories. Thus, this force of his analogy in sustaining moral realism
specific disagreement with other radicals in scien- because of his criticism of Proudhon's labor
tific analysis fused with Marx's and Engels's theory as a mistaken solution to the fundamental
general antipathy to Proudhon's moralism; scien- difficulty in Ricardo's political economy, his op-
tific and political critique, focused against the position to Proudhon's focus on the putative
moralists' economic analysis, seemed to go hand "eternality" of justice, and his rejection of moral-
in hand. Engels's phlogiston analogy demon- ism in the radical debates of the time. But
strates the full force of Marx's characterization of although Engels's general account wobbled be-
the moralists, who derived political remedies from tween relativist or reductionist and realist formu-
an inadequate social theory, as bad chemists lations, his specific arguments about moral con-
(Althusser 1965, Vol. 2, pp. 118-26). cepts were strongly realistic.
According to Engels, Marx, like Lavoisier, ap- For instance, he contended that the proletarian
proached the central anomaly in previous theory demand for social equality grew out of the bour-
with fresh eyes; where others "had seen a solu- geois demand for political equality in the Puritan
tion, he saw only a problem." Marx solved this and French Revolutions: "The proletarians took
problem-"placed previous political economy on the bourgeoisie at their word: equality must not
its feet"-with his discovery of surplus value, and be merely apparent, must not apply merely to the
provided new analyses of such crucial difficulties sphere of the state, but must also be real, must be
in classical political economy as the relations of extended to the social and economic sphere"
commodities and money, the character of class (Engels 1966, pp. 117, 24-5). Did Engels see this
conflict under capitalism, and the nature of rent, proletarian extension of the demand for social
profit and interest. For example, Marx explained equality as an inaccurate or ideological one? On
the generally recognized falling rate of profit as a the contrary, this extension improved on the
qualified tendency resulting from a rapid intro- general demand for political equality by identify-
duction of machinery or shift in the organic com- ing the real source of class domination that would
position of capital, whereas older theories had in- corrupt the quality of citizenship. It moved a step
terpreted it as an inevitable result of increasing closer to the true conception as articulated in
population (Malthus) or rising rent (Ricardo) Engels's and Marx's social theory. Thus, Engels
(Dobb 1973, p. 157). Engels contended: concluded that the proletarian demand "draw(s)
more or less correct and far-reaching demands
With this fact (surplus value) as his starting from the bourgeois demand."" Engels reformu-
point, he (Marx) examined all the categories he lated this conception of social equality: "The real
found at hand, just as Lavoisier, with oxygen as
content of the proletarian demand for equality is
his starting point, had examined the categories of
phlogiston chemistry he had found at hand
the abolition of classes. Any demand for equality
(Marx and Engels 1962, Vol. 1, pp. 471-2). which goes beyond that, of necessity passes into
absurdity" (Engels 1966, p. 117).
In the projected fourth volume of Capital, On the basis of Marx's historical theory, Engels
Theories of Surplus Value, Marx examined earlier partially criticized this proletarian slogan-he
theories in political economy to mark their dis- suggested that a demand for absolute equality
coveries and to show how the concept of surplus among human beings denies individuality and
value could resolve their internal problems. Both becomes absurd-but called for the achievement
Marx and Engels viewed political economy-the of an aspect of equality, the abolition of exploita-
study of the real relations of capitalist produc- tion as a prerequisite for (social) individuality.
tion-as a more mature scientific theory than Engels himself used the term equality in precisely
phlogiston chemistry (Marx 1961, Vol. 1, p. 80). this way. Contrary to Wood's interpretation,
Despite the major changes wrought by Marx's dis-
covery of surplus value, political economy had
previously existed as a full-blown scientific enter- "In citing Engels's remark, Wood 1979, p. 282, omits
prise. Thus, they explored the history of this disci- the crucial clause and fails to see a possible realist inter-
pline from a realistic perspective and demon- pretation.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin MarxandEngels 341
Engels contended in "On Marx's Capital" that of human knowledge (Erkenntnis), cannot really
the bad or exploitative features of capitalism be doubted. But we have not yet passed beyond
nonetheless "develop(ed) the productive forces of class morality. A really human morality (wirklich
menschlische Moral) which transcends class an-
society to a level which will make possible an
tagonisms and their legacies in thought becomes
equal development worthy of human beings for possible only at a stage of society which has not
all members of society" (Marx and Engels 1962, only overcome class contradictions but has even
Vol. 1, pp. 468-9).'" forgotten them in practical life (Engels 1966, p.
According to a realist account, the earlier radi- 105; Marx and Engels 1959, Vol. 20, p. 87).
cal theories of Munzer, Fourier, Blanqui, and
Given exploitative class divisions, all moral judg-
Bray about social inequality provided approx-
imately true descriptions of exploitation and the ments, true as well as false, have served class in-
terests; such divisions and the ideologies that they
corruption of bourgeois society. Marx's theory
improves on them and represents a form of moral engender cloud moral argument and prohibit the
progress just as proletarian socialist movements clarity that exists, according to Engels, in the
represent a moral improvement over the Levellers. morality of everyday life. But the removal of such
class divisions and ideologies renders the ethics of
Alternately, these (mainly inadequate) ethical
theories, analogous to phlogiston chemistry, social relations under communism as transparent
posed problems that a better scientific and ethical as those of individual relationships had been. It
theory could solve." Marx's theory of exploita- permits a "genuinely human morality."
tion, class conflict, and the abolition of classes Wood has properly recognized a conflict be-
captures the important grain of truth in the claims tween his reductionist interpretation of Marx on
of injustice of preceding radical theories. Even justice and Engels's argument about a genuine
this weaker claim for the earlier theories recog- non-relativist human morality, but he suggests
nizes the possibility of ethical progress. that in this passage, "Engels denies that the 'pro-
In Anti-Duhring, Engels defended such prog- letarian morality of the future' is 'true' as con-
ress in moral knowledge and compared it to ad- trasted with its predecessors" (Wood 1979, p.
vances in the natural sciences: 291). To concur with Wood's judgment, one
would have to ascribe to Engels the notion that no
... as society has hitherto moved in class an- truth or progress exists in chemistry or political
tagonisms,moralitywas alwaysclass morality;it economy, a view that Engels plainly rejects. Even
has eitherjustifiedthe dominationand the inter- in his most relativist comments on morality,
ests of the ruling class, or, as soon as the op-
Engels disagreed with that contention in Mul-
pressedclasshas becomepowerfulenough, it has
representedthe revolt against this domination berger. In the chapter in Anti-Duhring on moral
and the futureinterestsof the oppressed.That in progress, Engels dismissed the "eternality" of
this processtherehas on the wholebeen progress chemical and biological theory which, he noted,
(Fortschritt)in morality,as in all otherbranches achieve approximate truth only eventually and
after major conceptual changes (Engels 1966, pp.
98-9).14 This critique of an alleged "eternality" of
"In analyzing Marx's Critique of the Gotha Program, scientific theories, analogous to Engels's argu-
Wood 1979, p. 292, argues: "To do away with these ment against Proudhon, hardly rules out the
defects (the defects of equal right) one must 'wholly possibility of true biological knowledge. Wood's
transcend the narrow horizon of bourgeois right' repre- failure to see Engels's scientific realism leads him
sented by all principles of equality. Marx alludes to
Louis Blanc's slogan 'from each according to his abili-
ties, to each according to his needs' precisely because
this is not in any sense a principle of equality, it does not '4Engels argued:
treat people alike or equally from any point of view but
considers them simply as individuals with their own What a long series of intermediaries from Galen
special needs and faculties." Contrary to Wood, Marx's to Malpighi was necessary for correctly establish-
conception of social individuality sees all individuals as ing such a simple matter as the circulation of the
equally free from the exploitation characteristic of pre- blood in mammals . . . and often enough dis-
vious class societies and as "individuals with their own coveries, such as that of the cell, are made which
special needs and faculties." compel us to revise completely all formerly estab-
lished final and ultimate truths in the realm of
"A reductionist though realist view leaves the concept biology, and put whole piles of them on the scrap
of justice in even worse shape than phlogiston. heap once and for all.
Although an atomic analysis of combustion is true even
though phlogiston does not exist, no ethical analysis of Engels rightly used a concept of approximate truth but
the relationship designated by justice is true. Engels's contended carelessly that: "Really scientific works as a
and Marx's refinement of workers' demands for equali- rule avoid such dogmatic and moral expressions as Ifinal
ty or fairness, however, counts decisively against a and ultimate] error and truth." Engels 1966, pp. 99,
reductionist interpretation. 102.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
342 The AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol. 76
to overlook the strong element of moral realism in on their own theory. These interpretations cap-
Engels's account of justice. ture only their critique of prevailing moralities
To illustrate progress in moral theory, we might and of Proudhon's eternal justice but miss their
briefly examine Marx's relation to Hegel. Hegel own fundamental moral realism. Starting from
had argued that the primary ethical difference be- the negative consequences of divisions between
tween the ancient Greek city and the modern state rich and poor, their historical theory, if true,
resides in the modern recognition of subjectivity points to a single ethical resolution: the abolition
(freedom, individuality) as a fundamental compo- of exploitation and the uniting of mental and
nent of universality or political community. In manual labor.
this regard, Hegel contended, "the very status Interestingly enough, Lenin, a not overly senti-
slavery is an outrage on the conception of man." mental Marxist, took up Marx's and Engels's
The complex ethical life of the free individual moral as well as scientific realism. In his note-
developing through family, civil society (the arena books on Hegel's Logic, Lenin contrasted Kant's
for the individual pursuit of economic needs and "empty abstraction of the Thing-in-itself with liv-
interests), and the universality of the state (the ing movement, deeper and deeper, of our knowl-
general legal framework for the realization of in- edge about things" (Lenin, 1974, Vol. 38, p. 91).
dividuality), requires the abolition of slavery. The historical progress of experimental or practi-
Having studied English political experience and cal investigation and theoretical criticism
classical political economy. Hegel already feared engenders theoretical conclusions that increasing-
that the dynamics of the capitalist division of rich ly approximate the truth. In State and Revolu-
and poor would undermine the ethical universality tion, Lenin adopted a similarly realistic interpre-
of the modern state. Starting from this tension in tation of Marx's critique of earlier conceptions of
Hegel's The Philosophy of Right, Marx argued equality and regarded Marx's theory of the phases
that capitalism would use the state against the of communism in Critique of the Gotha Program
workers and that the proletarian movement would as a refined conception of justice:
create the genuine possibility for the flourishing
The first phase of communism, therefore, cannot
of individual achievement, based on political
yet provide justice and equality: differences and
community and the elimination of exploitation unjust differences in wealth will still persist, but
(Hegel 1977, pp. 15, 48, 84, 126-7, 133-4, 148-51; the exploitation of man by man will have become
Avineri 1972, pp. 90-8; Gilbert 1981b). He might impossible because it will be impossible to seize
have reformulated Hegel's dictum: "wage slavery the means of production-the factories, ma-
is an outrage on the conception of man," and chines, land, etc.-and make them private prop-
seen social individuality under communism as the erty. In smashing Lassalle's (early leader of Ger-
realization of Hegel's basic argument on indi- man worker's movement) petty-bourgeois, vague
viduality and universality. phrases about 'equality' and 'justice' in general,
Marx shows the course of development of com-
Hegel had emphasized historical progress in
munist society which is compelled to abolish at
morality: Christianity had helped to create the first only the 'injustice' of the means of produc-
conditions for a development of individuality and tion seized by individuals and which is unable at
the abolition of slavery; post-French-revolution once to eliminate the other injustice which con-
civil society, at least as it existed in Germany, em- sists in the distribution of consumer goods 'ac-
bodied a significant achievement of freedom cording to the amount of labor performed' (and
(Hegel 1977, pp. 31, 129-30). Marx could share not according to needs) (Lenin 1974, Vol. 25, p.
Hegel's judgment about progress since slavery, 466).
but given his analysis of capitalism, he extended
Hegel's argument: only the working class move- For Marx, the first phase of communism would
ment could fully realize human freedom and in- rectify some fundamental grievances, notably ex-
dividuality. On the issue of freedom and moral ploitation, which workers previously referred to
progress, Marx by no means rejected but criticized as injustice. Yet the initial communist principle of
and refined Hegel's vision. justice results in further inequalities since it bene-
Given this conception of a dialectical moral fits those who work harder or more skillfully and
progress, one might see Engels's phlogiston those who have smaller families. The principle of
analogy as providing an accurate interpretation of to each according to her work fails to recognize
the relation of Marx's historical theory to individual differences and needs; the original
previous political economy, of the relation of its complaints about injustice stemmed from the
ethical component to previous demands for denial of such needs. As Marx put it, "In order to
equality, and of the relation of Marx's ethical and avoid all these defects (Misstande), justice (Recht)
political theory to previous ones. In this sense, would more often have to be unequal than
Engels's and Marx's mode-of-production rela- equal." Although full recognition of these dif-
tivism or reductionism serve as misleading glosses ferences by distribution according to need in a

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin Marxand Engels 343
sense goes beyond justice, the higher stage of political effectiveness of demands for justice and
communism also realizes that people have meant equality stems from their truth.
by justice. In the Critique, Marx suggested that:
"Justice can never be higher than the economic Conclusion
form of society and the cultural development
determined by it" (Marx and Engels 1962, Vol. 2, As I have argued elsewhere, Marx's moral judg-
pp. 24, 21; Marx and Engels 1959, Vol. 19, pp. ments might cohere in a eudaimonist framework
21, 18). This statement, marking the limitations of moral argument which focuses on the quality
on realizing justice in differing forms of society, of individual lives and the consequences of dif-
recognizes moral progress from the lower (class ferent social structures on a broadly conceived in-
divided societies) to the higher (communism). dividual happiness (Gilbert 1981a). Here Marx
Lenin provides a straightforward realist reading envisioned such intrinsic goods as political com-
of the Gotha Program (Marx and Engels 1962, munity, development of human productive
tribution and need in Anti-Da/hring and Critique powers, friendship, and artistic achievement,
of the Gotha Program (Marx and Engels 1962, which composed an ideal picture of communist
Vol. 2, pp. 22-4). social individuality. These goods were achieve-
Written just before the October Revolution, ments of a historically developing human nature.
Lenin's "Can the Bolsheviks Retain State Human beings could realize some intrinsic goods
Power?" strikingly affirmed a Marxian concep- even in fundamentally exploitative societies, for
tion of justice. Peshekhonev, a government instance, the Greek political community, which
minister, had opposed such Bolshevik programs Marx admired despite its roots in slavery, the
as those for shorter hours of work, nationaliza- solidarity of Roman slave revolt led by Spartacus,
tion of factories, and an end to the supression of or scientific discovery. For long periods of
national minorities in order to maintain Russian history, however, Marx thought that human prog-
participation in World War I. Yet he acknowl- ress could not occur mainly through intrinsically
edged the justice of Bolshevik demands: "They good activities. Yet such progress, bought at the
are the claims of the working people, the claims of price of widespread suffering, laid the basis for
the cheated and oppressed nationalities. It is not the ultimate possibility of communism. Marx
so easy, therefore, for the democracy to break therefore extenuated such progress with a concep-
with the Bolsheviks, to reject these class demands, tion of merely instrumental goods and dis-
primarily because in essence these demands are tinguished communist progress which fused in-
just." Although Lenin stressed the economic and trinsic and instrumental goods from previously
political conditions that would make justice alienated or mainly instrumental progress. Thus
realizable, he insisted on the revolutionary power he saw a socialist political community like the
of such proletarian claims against opponents who Paris Commune as good in itself and as furthering
dismissed the efficacy of moral argument: the emergence of communism. Despite his
acknowledgment of the productive achievements
For him (Peshekhonev)'justice' is merely an of exploitative societies, Marx severely restricted
emptyphrase.For the massof semi-proletarians, his extenuation of alienated progress. A rhetoric
however,and for the majorityof the urbanand of indictment resounds as the predominant moral
ruralpetite bourgeoisie(as well as the workers) tone in Marx's analysis of early capitalist accumu-
who havebeen ruined,torturedand wornout by lation and colonialism. Since in Marx's view
the war, it is not an empty phrase, but almost Greek political community or philosophy could
acute, most burning and immense question of
death from starvation,of a crust of bread.... only arise at the cost of slavery and a mechanized
Justiceis an emptywordsay the intellectualsand economy from capitalist exploitation, Marx never
those rascalswho are inclinedto proclaimthem- reached any overall moral judgment of these
selves Marxistson the lofty grounds that they societies. In assessing them, however, he dis-
have contemplatedthe hind parts of economic tinguishes between good and bad features: Greek
materialism(Lenin 1974, Vol. 26, pp. 128-30). science was praiseworthy; slavery was not. In this
sense, Marx's sometimes exaggerated restraint in
Lenin envisioned that the justice of Bolshevik the use of moral concepts reflects the character
demands and specific historical circumstances and difficulty of the cases under examination, not
would lead to a broad revolutionary alliance of as Marx and Engels sometimes inclined to think,
workers and other oppressed classes. In stressing the impossibility of objective moral assessment.
the radical impact of ethical concepts, Lenin In general, moral conceptions not only lead to
recalled Marx's early remark: "Ideas become a evaluation but point to action. Even in these hard
power when they grip the people." In a Marxian cases, Marx's standards allow, semantically
social theory of revolution, such moral concepts speaking, a specification of moral conflicts, for
play an important explanatory role, and the instance, between the progress of science and

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
344 The AmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
egalitarianism, and counsel action to create in the point of view of assessing its truth. In analyzing
long run a society that no longer necessitates such ideologies, Marx defended only the consequence-
conflicts (Miller 1978). At the point when his- dependence of moral principles-the notion that
torically socialism becomes possible, Marx ad- in class societies, moral judgments, true or not,
mired the main features of a revolutionary would tend to serve specific classes-rather than
political movement and working class political an origin-dependence, the conception that the
community. At this point, already characteristic claims of moral argument to truth can simply be
of the time when Marx wrote, standards of intrin- debunked by pointing to their social or class
sic goods, previously subordinate or merely nega- origin. In Marx, arguments on exploitation and
tive (exhibited mainly in Marx's condemnation of equality, like his conceptions of political com-
their denial), became primary. Given the par- munity, freedom, friendship, and individuality,
ticular difficulties of the concepts of justice and are components of an ethical picture that is a con-
equality, Marx confined himself even in the first tender for moral truth. Such conceptions, as I
phase of communism to specifying how the socie- have argued elsewhere, also play an important
ty is mainly just by abolishing exploitation and political role in the conflicts over the development
secondarily unjust by failing to distribute accord- of the working-class movement and the mainte-
ing to need. As Wood has suggested, equality dif- nance of socialism (Gilbert 1981a).
fers from intrinsic goods such as political commu- Many contemporary philosophers and social
nity, freedom, and the realization of individual- scientists have imagined that an unbridgable gulf
ity; equality, reformulated by Marx as the aboli- must exist between descriptive historical theory
tion of classes, is a means to secure these other and prescriptive moral judgment and that con-
goods (1979, pp. 281-2). flicting moral arguments, for instance Ari-
The context of Marx's larger moral judgments stotelian and Marxian ones, must derive from ir-
provides a new perspective on his concepts of reconcilable moral premises. This view ignores the
justice and equality. Such concepts always played intertwining in any nonanalytic moral theory be-
an important role in Marx's historical arguments; tween social theory and moral judgment (Lyons
he detested the exploitation of man by man and 1977, pp. 128-9). To the degree that investigators
regarded all class-divided societies before social- can agree on historical analysis, for instance that
ism as exploitative. Marx's own conception of ex- no natural slavery exists, the scope of moral dis-
ploitation served as a standard to indict the legal agreement is narrowed (Miller 1978).15 The fore-
and moral concepts generated by prevailing going argument suggests that disagreements over
modes of production. Even though Marx empha- social theory and facts are often far more funda-
sized this aspect of social development, however, mental than the original moral disagreements or
his historical theory extenuates alien or merely in- perhaps even conceal original moral agreement.
strumental forms of social progress. In effect, he Few would argue that abundance for a heedless
restrained his moral criticism for historical minority accompanied by starvation for many or
periods in which he regarded alien development as that the widespread denial of individual capacities
necessary or no revolutionary movement as pos- is morally desirable. To give a different example,
sible (Gilbert 1979). Looking at Marx's overall take those who would want to quarrel, given the
moral judgments in relation to his historical many dimensions of moral progress and possible
theory, we can see a new reason, beyond his cri- conflicts among them, with Marx's ethical vision
tique of moralism or his specific argument with and psychological judgments about the possibility
Proudhon, for his caution in using concepts of of a flowering of human achievement and multi-
justice, namely an objectively limited possibility competent individuality under communism. If
of overall moral judgment for several historical these theorists concurred with Marx's social
epochs. This restraint accounts for the grain of theory, they would have to agree with many of
truth in Wood's emphasis on Marx's refusal to of- Marx's moral and political conclusions although
fer a simple indictment of pre-socialist class socie- they might still conclude that social individuality
ties. Wood's interpretation becomes exaggerated would prove less grand in its accomplishments
only when he ignores the ever-present (even when than Marx had hoped or value different types or
subordinated) hatred of exploitation and its con- balances of activity than Marx did. These remain-
sequences which runs like the proverbial red ing differences, however, seem far less striking
thread through Marx's historical argument.
Marx and Engels offered an ethical argument
closely linked to their historical or scientific argu- 'Agreement about natural science may sometimes
ment. Their moral argument makes a specific con- play a similar role. Consider the effect on Aristotle's
tribution in examining the problem of justice not argument of the modern astronomical observation that
only from the point of view of explaining his- there are no unchanging celestial beings who engage in
torical controversies about justice but from the ceaseless contemplation. (Strauss 1965, p. 8).

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 An Ambiguityin Marxand Engels 345
than the wide area of common agreement; pre- Fisk, Milton. 1975. History and reason in Rawls' moral
sumably, once socialism had reached a certain theory. In Norman Daniels, ed. Reading Rawls.
stage, empirical study could even resolve many of New York: Basic Books.
these disagreements. Correspondingly, the most Forder, Herwig et al. 1970. Der Bund der Kommu-
powerful denial of Marx's vision would be a suc- nisten: Dokumente und Materialen. Berlin: Dietz.
cessful defense of the functioning and conse- Gilbert, Alan. 1978a. Equality and social theory in
Rawls' A theory of justice. The Occasional Review,
quences of capitalism (as opposed to those of 8:95-117.
socialism) coupled with at least roughly similar 1978b. Marx on internationalism and war.
moral premises. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 7:346-69.
Marx and Engels sometimes overstressed the 1979. Social theory and revolutionary activity
importance of their scientific theory at the ex- in Marx. The American Political Science Review,
pense of moral argument. Yet their scientific view 73:521-38.
turns out to be the most debatable part of their 1981a. Historical theory and the structure of
ethical argument. According to Marxian theory, moral argument in Marx. Political Theory, 9:
straightforward moral rationality-the idea that a 173-205.
1981b. Moral realism, individuality and justice
lucid exposition of moral concepts will persuade in war. Unpublished.
all reasonable people-does not work; for exam- 1981c. Social science and the common good in
ple, the most eloquent persuasion alone would not Weber and Lenin. Proceedings of the American
get European, American, and Japanese banks and Political Science Association. Ann Arbor: Univer-
corporations to stop investing in South African sity of Michigan.
apartheid. Clashing class interests as well as con- 1981. Marx's politics: communists and citizens.
flicting social theories prevent any easy ethical New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press and Ox-
agreement. Historical analysis and political stra- ford: Martin Robertson.
tegy, not moral argument or philosophy as a Hegel, G. W. F. 1975. Lectures on the philosophy of
world history: introduction. Trans. H. B. Nisbet.
separate enterprise, play the primary role in Marx- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
ian theory. Nonetheless, someone who holds a 1977. The philosophy of right. Trans. T. M.
realist interpretation of Marx's moral argument Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
should have no hesitancy about engaging in moral Hobbes, Thomas. 1962. Leviathan. Ed. Michael
as well as theoretical and political dialogue with Oakeshott. New York: Collier Books.
proponents of other points of view. Husami, Ziyad I. 1980. Marx on distributive justice. In
Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel and Thomas Scan-
lon, ed., Marx, justice and history. Princeton:
Princeton University Press. Reprinted from Philoso-
References phy and Public Affairs 1978.
Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and necessity. Cambridge,
Althusser, Louis. 1965. Lire le capital, 2 vols. Paris: Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Maspero. Kuhn, T. S. 1967. The structure of scientific revolu-
Avinero, Shlomo. 1972. Hegel's theory of the modern tions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
state. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lenin, V. I. 1974. Collected works, 45 vols. Moscow:
Boyd, Richard N. 1979. Metaphor and theory change: Progress.
what is 'metaphor' a metaphor for? In Andrew Or- Locke, John. 1979. An essay concerning human under-
tony, ed. Metaphor and thought. Cambridge: Cam- standing. Ed. Peter Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon
bridge University Press. Press.
1980. Scientific realism and naturalistic epis- Lyons, David. 1976. Ethical relativism and the problem
temology. Unpublished. of incoherence. Ethics, 86:107-21.
Brecht, Bertolt. 1966. The Caucasian chalk circle. 1977. Human rights and the general welfare.
Trans. Edward Bentley. New York: Grove. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6:113-29.
Cohen, G. A. 1979. Mrx's theory of history: a defense. Marx, Karl. 1961. Capital, 3 vols. Trans. Samuel Moore
Princeton: Princeton University Press. and Edward Aveling. New York: International.
Cusack, David. 1977. Revolution and counterrevolution 1973. Grundrisse. Trans. Martin Nicolaus. New
in Chile. Denver: Graduate School of International York: Vintage.
Studies Monograph Series. 1963. The poverty of philosophy. New York:
Dobb, Maurice. 1973. Theories of value and distribu- International.
tion since Adam Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich. 1962. Selected works,
University Press. 2 vols. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing
Engels, Friedrich. 1966. Herr Eugen Duhring's revolu- House.
tion in science. New York: International. 1959. Werke, 39 vols. Berln: Dietz.
1962. Preface to the second volume of Capital 1971. Writings on the Paris Commune. Ed. Hal
in Marx and Engels. Selected works. Moscow: For- Draper. New York: Monthly Review.
eign Languages Publishing House. McNamara, Robert S. 1973. One hundred countries,
1962. The housing question. In Marx and two billion people. New York: Praeger.
Engels. Selected Works. Miller, Richard W. 1978. Aristotle and Marx: the unity

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
346 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
of two opposites. Proceedings of the American Daedalus, 108:1-25.
Political Science Association. Ann Arbor: Univer- Strauss, Leo. 1965. Natural right and history. Chicago:
sity of Michigan. University of Chicago.
Montesquieu, Charles Louis de Secondat, Baron de. Sturgeon, Nicholas. 1980. Brandt's moral empiricism.
1965. Spirit of the laws. Trans. Thomas Nugent. Unpublished.
New York: Hafner. Taylor, Charles. 1973. Neutrality in political science. In
Moore, Barrington. 1965. Social origins of dictatorship Alan Ryan, ed. The philosophy of social explana-
and democracy. Boston: Beacon. tion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Myrdal, Gunnar. 1970. The challenge of world poverty. Thompson, Edward P. 1971. The moral economy of the
New York: Pantheon. English crowd in the eighteenth century. Past and
Oakeshott, Michael. 1975. On human conduct. Oxford: present, 50:76-136.
Clarendon Press. Trotsky, Leon. 1963. Basic writings. Ed. Irving Howe.
Payre, Cheryl. 1975. The debt trap. New York: New York: Harper and Row.
Monthly Review. Tucker, Robert W. 1977. The inequality of nations.
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph. 1924. De la capacitL poli- New York: Basic Books.
tique des classes ouvridres. Paris: Riviere. Weber, Max. 1958a. From Max Weber: essays in sociol-
1923. Systeme des contradictions &'conomiques ogy. Ed. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New
ou philosophic de la misere. Paris: Riviere. York: Oxford University Press.
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. Collected philosophical papers, 1958b. The Protestant ethic and the spirit of
2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. capitalism. Trans. Talcott Parsons. New York:
Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, Scribner's.
Mass.: Harvard University Press. Wittke, Carl. 1950. The utopian communist: a biogra-
Ricardo, David. 1948. The principles of political econ- phy of Wilhelm Weitling. Baton Rouge: Louisiana
omy and taxation. London: J.M. Dent. State University Press.
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the mirror of Wood, Allen W. 1979. Marx on right and justice: A
nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press. reply to Husami. Philosophy and Public Affairs,
Scott, James C. 1976. The moral economy of the 8:267-95.
peasant: rebellion and subsistence in Southeast Asia. 1972. The Marxian critique of justice. Philoso-
New Haven: Yale University Press. phy and Public Affairs, 1:241-82.
Shklar, Judith N. 1979. Let us not be hypocritical.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Sun, 21 Apr 2013 01:05:18 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like