Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Adaptation: “A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought”

Author(s): Helena Cronin


Source: The Quarterly Review of Biology , Vol. 80, No. 1 (March 2005), pp. 19-26
Published by: The University of Chicago Press
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/431021

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to The Quarterly Review of Biology

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Volume 80, No. 1 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY March 2005

ADAPTATION:
“A CRITIQUE OF SOME CURRENT EVOLUTIONARY THOUGHT”

Helena Cronin
Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science

London School of Economics


London WC2A 2AE England
e-mail: h.cronin@lse.ac.uk

abstract
In his classic Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary
Thought (1966), George Williams showed definitively that our understanding of adaptation, a
central concept of evolutionary theory, must be gene-centered. The purpose of adaptations is to further
the replication of genes. Genes are machines for turning out more genes; and adaptations are the
means by which genes pluck resources from the world to promote this self-replication. Thus adaptations
transform potential resources from part of the indifferent world-at-large into tailor-made environments,
environments brimming with resources for organisms’ distinctive adaptive needs. Systematically dif-
ferent adaptive problems therefore give rise to different environments; and so different species, for
example, have different environments. Thus a gene-centered analysis of adaptations implies a gene-
centered theory of environments. Without genes to specify what constitutes an environment, environ-
ments would not exist. Rather than being separate from biology, an autonomous, independent force,
environments are themselves the products of biology. So a gene-centered view, far from depreciating the
environment, furnishes a rich and precise understanding of its importance.

tered route: “It is at the level of the gene . . .


Some Current Evolutionary that we have the most fundamental and most
Thought—Again universally applicable understanding of adap-
tation” (Williams 1966:71). In recent years, the
A DAPTATION: the design features of liv-
ing things. This striking property of the
organic world is, as George Williams urged in
concept of adaptation has again become
abused, even traduced. The battle this time is
his classic work, Adaptation and Natural Selec- largely about the relationship between genes
tion: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary and environments. Once again, a steadily
Thought, “a phenomenon of pervasive impor- gene-centered analysis is needed.
tance in biology” and a “key . . . concept” of I shall first set out a gene-centered notion
evolutionary theory (Williams 1966:5). But of adaptation, then present the latest miscon-
the concept had become misused and mis- ceptions, and finally illustrate how this per-
understood, even to the point of impeding spective can dispel them.
scientific progress. George’s impetus for writ-
ing the book was to “help to purge biology” What Adaptations Are For
(Williams 1966:4) of such errors. The mathematician Paul Erdös used to
George’s battle was mainly with levels of describe himself as a machine for turning cof-
selection. He showed unequivocally that the fee into theorems. In much the same way,
path to understanding was down the gene-cen- genes are machines for turning stars into a

19

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
20 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 80

bird’s compass; carotenoids into males of daz- the celestial pole is not a regularity. The
zling beauty; facial muscles into signals of true earth’s axis of rotation wobbles considerably
friendship; and oxygen, water, calcium, and in a cycle of about 27,000 years; so the posi-
iron into bears, beetles, bacteria, or bluebells. tion of the celestial pole among the constel-
Genes have been designed by natural selec- lations changes. Thus natural selection
tion to exploit properties of the world that latched on to a deeper regularity and thereby
promote their self-replication; for genes are a far more powerful tool. It endowed bunt-
ultimately machines for turning out more ings with the ability to study particular char-
genes. The means by which genes gain access acteristics of these constellations and then to
to the world’s properties is through adapta- pinpoint the center around which they
tions. In shaping adaptations over evolution- rotate. Thus buntings that migrate today can
ary time, natural selection has seized on reg- use the same instincts and environmental reg-
ularities, features of the world that are stable, ularities as used by their long-dead ancestors,
recurrent, and dependable, features that can fashioning the same precision-built instru-
be relied on, generation after generation, so ment, regardless of where the fickle earth is
that adaptations can do their work. situated in its never-ending cycle.
Consider the indigo bunting (Passerina So every newly-hatched indigo bunting
cyanea). Natural selection faced the problem becomes, in a matter of months, a proficient
of enabling these migratory birds to navigate star-compass navigator. As a nestling, it devotes
from their northern home southwards to a hours to gazing at the stars. By the time it starts
winter residence and then back again. Solving on its nocturnal migration, it can head in the
a navigation problem involves locating a fixed right direction upon leaving the nest; and, as
point. The specialized mental machinery with long as some of the constellations are visible,
which natural selection equipped the birds it can use its compass to maintain its direction
for this task can be envisaged as a set of rules: along the way, confidently keeping its back to
the celestial pole in autumn and flying towards
To find a fixed point, do the following.
it in spring. Fortunately, the winter quarters
Pay attention to the nightly voyage of the
are far enough north of the equator that the
stars. Familiarize yourself with the pat-
circumpolar stars do not disappear over the
terns of the major constellations. And
horizon; so the compass can be deployed
distinguish between the slow and the fast
along the entire route.
travelers—those that trace a tight circle,
Thus, the bunting’s adaptation relies not
barely moving, and those that sweep
only on its species-specific mental machinery
across the sky, scurrying at speed. Pin
but also on the presence of the stellar array.
down the point around which they
Indeed, if buntings are experimentally
revolve. To store where this point is, note
immured in a starless world during the cru-
where it lies in relation to the now-famil-
cial nestling period, they cannot orientate
iar nearby stars. Compass constructed;
themselves when migrating. Stars are as vital
use for finding fixed point.
a part of a bunting’s environment as is the egg
in which it develops or the water that it
Every boy scout knows that the buntings’ drinks. Buntings without stars are destined to
fixed point must be the north celestial pole, be buntings without descendants.
the place towards which the earth’s axis of And so it is for every one of the great pan-
rotation points, and thus the place in the sky oply of adaptations that natural selection has
corresponding to north. But every boy scout ever favored. Resources in the environment
also knows that one of the nearby stars is the need to be there as reliably, in every genera-
pole star, conspicuously bright and within tion, as the information in the genes. Just as
one degree of the pole. Why, then, did natu- an organism requires its genes to be passed
ral selection not simply enable buntings to on intact, so it requires its environment to be
make more direct use of that particular star? unfailingly available down the generations—
The answer is that, relative to evolutionary carotenoids and calcium, smiles and stars.
time, the close proximity of the pole star to Thus, in evolving an adaptation, natural

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
March 2005 SYMPOSIUM IN HONOR OF GEORGE C WILLIAMS 21

selection accumulates in the species’ gene tific analyses should follow in natural selec-
pool an appropriate store of information tion’s wake. Environments are adaptation-
about environmental regularities. Each living generated, adaptation-specific; environments
thing enters the world replete with such infor- should therefore be parsed along systemati-
mation packed into its genes, information cally adaptationist lines.
about the stockpile of resources that natural Consider some examples. Take first a spe-
selection has relied on in the design of its cies’-eye view of environments. Different spe-
adaptations, information gleaned from the cies are clusters of different adaptations; and
environments of its ancestors. From this different adaptations pick out different envi-
archive, the organism can pick out the cur- ronments. So different species necessarily
rent instantiations of those ancestral condi- have different environments. The ethologist
tions, the instantiations that it encounters in Jakob von Uexküll conjured up the image of
its own lifetime of that long, unbroken suc- each species dwelling inside its own soap bub-
cession of past environments. And thus it is ble, “its own world, filled with the perceptions
able to pluck from its environment what it which it alone knows“ (von Uexküll 1934:5).
needs to grow and flourish and reproduce. In the bunting’s soap bubble, for example,
It is in ways such as these that adaptations stars are a crucial element; nevertheless,
transform potential resources from part of although these stars are part of the world-at-
the indifferent world-at-large into the organ- large, a solid and enduring aspect of our
ism’s own tailor-made, species-specific envi- planet’s nocturnal landscape, for animals that
ronment, an environment brimming with do not migrate or are resolutely diurnal, stars
materials and information for the organism’s are not part of these species’ soap bubbles.
own distinctive adaptive needs. Inside a soap bubble, there will be further
In the beginning, natural selection created differences. Within a species, some individ-
genes that could barely exploit the heavens uals face systematically different adaptive
or the earth; their adaptations were meager problems from others; these differences give
and their environments commensurately rise to different environments. Soap bubbles
without form and void. But, down evolution- will differ for, say, males and females or
ary time, genes have bootstrapped themselves embryos and adults. In our species, for exam-
from inchoate nakedness into magnificent ple, what is salient differs for girls and boys;
dwellings, organisms of great sophistication. even one-day-old girls prefer a human face,
They have proliferated adaptations of ever boys prefer a mechanical mobile (Connellan
greater complexity, inventing new technolo- et al. 2000). In the parasitoid fly species Ormia
gies and strategies. They have thereby been ochracea, the female, who lays her eggs on
able to create and exploit ever richer environ- male crickets, finds her victim by his love call;
ments in ever more ingenious ways, trans- her hearing is so finely attuned to his sere-
forming the universe of mere physics and nade that it has converged with the auditory
chemistry into a world of colors and sounds, world of the female cricket and diverged from
friendliness and beauty. that of her own husband. Thus, shaped by
common adaptive problems, the females’
What Constitutes an Environment? environments unite across their species’ soap
This gene-centered understanding of adap- bubbles, transcending deep and ancient tax-
tation deepens our understanding of environ- onomic divides; meanwhile, shaped by differ-
ment. What constitutes an environment? It is ent adaptive problems, the fly and her mate
those aspects of the world, and only those dwell in disparate worlds of sound (Robert et
aspects of the world, that genes have evolved al. 1992, 1994).
to harness for their use; the rest of the world Now consider a gene’s-eye view. For any
is not part of any environment. From the adaptation, its environment consists of what-
potentially infinite ways of gaining access to ever regularities natural selection’s design for
the world’s resources, genes use adaptations the adaptation relies on. For genes, these reg-
to carve out subsets that the organism can ularities are bound to include the behavior of
exploit to solve its adaptive problems. Scien- neighboring genes; this is because, in addi-

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
22 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 80

tion to building proteins, genes influence rather than building on this insight, have, on
other genes, turning them on and off, acti- the contrary, attempted to oust genes from
vating them and silencing them, marshalling center stage in the misguided belief that this
them into and out of activity. And (especially is how to give environment its due. In place
once the organism has emerged from the of George’s analysis, there has been much con-
confines of egg, seed, or womb) genes’ envi- fusion, involving a rash of environmental nex-
ronmental regularities are of course also uses, developmental matrices, ontogenetic
likely to include conditions in the external niches, dynamic systems, interactive complex-
world—temperatures and toxins, love songs ities, holistic epigenetics, constructivist dialec-
and warning calls. tics, ontological reversals, phenotypic accom-
A gene-centered view, far from depreciat- modations, decontextualized problem-solving
ing the environment, furnishes a rich and routines . . . and more. The confusions are
precise understanding of its importance. We epitomized by a favorite rhetorical question:
have noted, for example, that putting genes “Why privilege genes?” Let us see how a gene-
at the center helps us to appreciate the sig- centered analysis deals with some of the stan-
nificance of environmental regularity, the dard positions. (For various versions of these
steady presence of the “expected” environ- arguments see e.g., Oyama 1985, 2000; Grif-
ment down the generations. As a second fiths and Grey 1994; Thelen and Smith 1994;
example, we can now see how the relation- West-Eberhard 2003; for discussions see e.g.,
ship between genes and environments cannot Dennett 1995:115 n. 10, 196–198; Sterelny
possibly be—as is commonly assumed—zero- 1995:162–165; Sterelny and Griffiths 1999:94–
sum, as if the more that environments do the 111; for background see e.g., Popper 1972,
less there is for genes to do. A gene-centered 1990:27–51, 1999:45–56; Tooby and Cosmides
view emphasizes that, far from biology and 1990a:19–22, 1990b:388–389, 408–410, 1992:
environment competing for causal power, 69–73, 82–87; Cosmides and Tooby 1994:98–
adaptations connect them in such a way that 103; Dawkins 1998; Pinker 2004).
the richer and more complex the adapta- • We are all interactionists now. Everyone agrees
tions, the richer and more complex the envi- that natural selection acts on the relationship
ronments they rely on. As a final example, between genes and environments. So we should no
longer single out genes for privileged status. We
recall that what constitutes an environment
should accord parity to genes and environment.
cuts a swathe along a causal chain that invar-
Well, here is a parity test. Try specifying
iably includes both genes and aspects of the
“an” environment without first specifying
outside world. This overturns the naı̈ve view
whether it is the environment of a bunting or
that “biology” stops where “environment”
a human, a male or a female, an adaptation
starts, such that genes are never part of the
for navigation or for language. The task is of
environment, and environment consists
course impossible; the specification must start
exclusively of the world beyond the organism.
in an adaptationist, and therefore gene-cen-
Without genes to specify what constitutes tered, way.
an environment, environments would not And here is another challenge to parity.
exist. Thus environments, far from being Genes use environments for a purpose—self-
separate from biology, an autonomous and replication. Environments, however, have no
independent force, are themselves the prod- purposes; so they do not use genes. Thus
ucts of biology. Environment is therefore— genes are machines for converting stars into
necessarily—a biological issue, an adaptation- more genes; but stars are not machines for
ist issue, a gene-centered issue. converting genes into more stars.
• Gene-environment interaction is so enmeshed
“Why Privilege Genes?” that the influences of genes and environments—in
George has given us not only a gene-cen- both evolution and development—are inextricable.
tered understanding of adaptations but also Thus all attempts to disentangle them are spurious.
a gene-centered theory of environment. How- Inextricable? On the contrary; just ask the
ever, recent discussions of environment, right questions. It is misconceived to ask what

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
March 2005 SYMPOSIUM IN HONOR OF GEORGE C WILLIAMS 23

percentage of the bunting’s compass or a However, this criticism confuses the logic of
human language is the result of genes, and the approach with a claim about the direction
what percentage is the result of environment. of causal arrows. In order to understand the
But it does make sense to ask about the causal pathways between genes and their envi-
design features of an adaptation. For bunt- ronments, we must start from genes; but this
ings, at what ages do the windows of oppor- most certainly does not imply that the path-
tunity for compass-building open and close? ways go only one way.
How important is the pole star; and how The objection is proposed as an alternative
many constellations must a nestling study? to the gene-centered view. But it is not. The
Similarly, for humans, what exactly are the role played by experience is an essential part
instincts and what exactly are the environ- of this view. How could it not be, given that
ments that we need to acquire language? For the entire raison d’être of adaptations is to
example, what is specified in the universal enable genes to use the world’s resources?
grammar? What does a child require from an Therefore what constitutes experience for an
environment of language users, and when? organism, and how it can exploit that expe-
It also makes sense to ask about the causes rience, are part of the design features of its
of individual differences. How much of the adaptations, and consequently part of the
variation in a particular characteristic among design specifications of its genes. So experi-
individuals within a population can be attrib- ence will of course be in the causal chains that
uted to genetic, and how much to environ- turn genes on and off.
mental, differences? For example, what per- Indigo buntings provide an illuminating
centage of the differences in efficacy of example of experience altering physiology,
compasses in a group of buntings or linguistic and consequently, it seems, genes. How do
proficiency in a group of humans is attribut- buntings decide when to migrate and in which
able to differences in genes, what percentage direction? The timing is triggered by changes
to differences in environments? At present, in an environmental factor, day length. The
these questions (the realm of quantitative birds’ experience of this change alters their
genetics, particularly behavioral genetics) physiology; their fat deposits increase, for
tend not to analyze phenotypes or, conse- instance, and they feel migratory restlessness.
quently, environments from an adaptationist In this state, new aspects of their environment
perspective. But the more that they come to become salient; their physiology alters what
do so, the more they will shed light on the constitutes experience. They become sensitive,
detailed workings of both evolution and for example, to slight changes in barometric
development and the respective roles of pressure; this enables them to sense when
genes, environments, and even that elusive pressure patterns augur winds favorable to
player, chance. their odyssey. Similarly, the trigger for whether
• Genes respond to the organism’s experience of to orientate themselves northwards (to home)
the world. Experience regulates which genes are or southwards (to their winter dwelling) is the
expressed and when; the ambient temperature or a changing seasons. But, again, the trigger acts
smiling face can trigger reactions in a great cascade by causing physiological changes. Indeed,
of genes, switching some on and others off. So genes once those changes have occurred, they use
are vulnerable to experience; they are at the mercy their own internal state rather than their exter-
of events in the outside world. nal environment as their cue. Buntings that
It is fundamental to the logic of an adap- were experimentally altered in spring to the
tationist approach that it must start from autumn body-state (by manipulating the ratio
genes, then go to adaptations, and only then of light and dark periods) orientated them-
to environments, organisms, and experience. selves towards the south, blithely oblivious to
But, critics object, this does not give expe- the approaching season and the call of their
rience its due. Experience can influence genes natal home.
as well as genes influencing experience; the Thus a gene-centered understanding not
causal arrows go not only out from genes to only fully incorporates the role of experience
experience but also back again to genes. but also sharpens and enriches the concept,

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
24 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 80

making scientific sense of what is otherwise be vanishingly unimportant in the course of


vague and elusive. evolution.
• Evolutionary change does not have to wait for Third, either way—whether the new phe-
genetic mutations; environments and phenotypes notype is part of the adaptive design or an
working together can take the lead. For example, by extraordinarily improbable response—will
influencing development, an environmental change the phenotypic novelty ever get further than
can bring about phenotypic change; and if the new the existing genetic variability happens to
phenotype is more viable than the old, it will spread allow? The answer is no. For any “really novel
rapidly through the entire population; what is more, adaptations” (Williams 1966:78) to enter the
these new phenotypes will persist down the genera- scene, there must be genetic mutation. There
tions as long as those environmental conditions per- must be a genetic change that makes the
sist. So the outcome will be adaptive change without organism responsive to new aspects of the
genetic mutation. Thus, contrary to orthodox Dar- world-at-large and in such a way as to offer
winian thinking, environmentally induced pheno- new solutions to adaptive problems.
typic novelty can initiate and sustain adaptive evo- Thus, to envisage these phenotypic changes
lution even more readily than can genetic novelty. as evolutionary change is myopic. Indeed, all
George subjected arguments such as these such notions should be obliged to take an eye
to adaptationist scrutiny when they were first test. Could that paradigmatic case of adaptive
in vogue; he found them wanting (Williams complexity, the eye, have come about by a
1966:72–81). The current revivals fare no bet- “phenotype-led” process? A process that fails
ter. Now, as then, three questions immedi- this test cannot be a major protagonist. Or, as
ately present themselves. George succinctly put it, “I question its value
First, is the new phenotype within the design as a model of adaptive evolution” (Williams
of an adaptation? This would be the most likely 1966:75).
case given that it is so well-suited to the new • Under some environmental conditions, some
conditions. After all, adaptations are designed responses that are thought to be instinctive fail to
to be sensitive to differences in environmental
work normally or to come on stream at all. Think of
conditions; and adaptations involved in devel-
Harlow’s experiments with rhesus macaques; daugh-
opment are designed to build different phe-
ters deprived of maternal care were unable, as adults,
notypes under different conditions. It could
to show maternal feelings to their own offspring. This
be that neither the environmental conditions
demonstrates that the standard maternal response is
nor the phenotype is really “new.” The new
not an instinct but is learned, a socially or culturally
phenotype is merely a designed response to
acquired skill. Thus even maternal care, paradig-
these environmental conditions. Indeed, if
the phenotype “shows the unique biological matically an unconditional biological response,
property of adaptive organization” (Williams depends crucially on the environment. So genes must
1966:76), that is most likely to be what is hap- be relatively inconsequential.
pening. Such phenotypes are hardly in the What is behind this argument? It is the idea
vanguard of evolutionary change. that a gene-centered view sees instinctive
Second, could it be that the new pheno- behavior as surfacing full-blown from innate,
types, rather than reflecting adaptations, are endogenous forces, regardless of the state of
expressing hitherto unexpressed genetic vari- the world and without need for learning. To
ation that is present in the population? This correct this putative mistake, the argument
genetic variability would not be part of any emphasizes how crucial a role environment
adaptive design but would just happen to get plays in instinctive behavior.
expressed phenotypically when a change of Admittedly, this notion of instinct did lurk
conditions disrupts the organism’s environ- within certain strands of ethology in its early
ment and changes the course of develop- days; and, although it should long have been
ment. But, if this were how a phenotype came laid to rest, it has proved tenacious.
about, it would be vanishingly unlikely to be But this concept of instinct has no natural
viable at all, let alone more viable than the place in the gene-centered view. On the con-
existing range of phenotypes. And a mecha- trary, it is because adaptations rely on regu-
nism that is vanishingly improbable must also larities in the environment as well as on

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
March 2005 SYMPOSIUM IN HONOR OF GEORGE C WILLIAMS 25

design specifications in the genes that a rely crucially on a physical resource, the stars.
“mutation” in the environment can disrupt So environmental regularities that are social or
normal functioning just as a genetic mutation cultural do not make the learning less innate
can. Think of buntings deprived of stars or . . . whatever that might mean. Alternatively, if
feral children deprived of language speakers. the learning is not an adaptation but an
Similarly, the macaque experiments raise the acquired skill, what are the adaptations that it
questions: What precisely must a female taps into? Reading and writing parasitise mul-
macaque glean from the presence of her tiple adaptations, greedily and eclectically,
mother to equip herself for motherhood? from our language instinct to our opposable
And what are the innate mechanisms that thumb. It is along such lines—across species,
enable her to do this? These experiments genera and phyla—that motherhood should
were too blunt an instrument for tackling be parsed. From the resulting soap bubbles
such intricate questions. But there are cases, would emerge both enduring similarities and
such as tracking down a serendipitous “muta- intricate differences, reflecting the ingenuity
tion” in the environment of the laboratory with which natural selection has solved the
rat, that have nicely demonstrated how to multifarious problems of being a mother.
analyze mothering adaptively (Daly and Wil-
son 1995:1274–1277). Conclusion
Where does this leave the claim that mater- At the end of his magisterial analysis,
nal care is not an instinct but is learned—and, George stated his conviction that the modern
what is more, learned through social or cul- theory of natural selection is “the light and
tural means? To unravel the confusions here, the way” (Williams 1966:273). That is an apt
we need to parse “learning” adaptively. First, is description of George’s own profound con-
the learning an adaptation? Think of humans tribution to evolutionary thinking—not least,
learning a mother tongue or buntings learn- to the concept of adaptation. Only through
ing to construct a star compass. Alternatively, adaptations were environments constructed,
is the learning not an adaptation but a skill and only through understanding adaptations
that uses aspects of adaptations for purposes can we reconstruct them. George’s gene-cen-
for which they were not designed? Think of tered understanding of adaptations and envi-
acquiring the skills of reading and writing. ronments shows us still how to clarify some
Whichever is the case—adaptation or borrow- current evolutionary thought.
ing—learning from the environment is not an
acknowledgments
alternative to instinct; on the contrary, innate
I am grateful to everyone at Stony Brook who orga-
mechanisms are what make learning possible.
nized the George Williams Symposium and who kindly
Second, if the learning is an adaptation, what
invited me to participate. For comments on this paper,
are the innate mechanisms and what are the my thanks to Rosalind Arden, Martin Daly, Thomas E
environmental resources that it relies on? For Dickins, David Haig, Isaac Marks, Steven Pinker, Rich-
learning language, humans rely crucially on a ard Webb, Margo Wilson, and particularly to Aubrey
social resource, a community of language Sheiham and Oliver Curry. Above all, my thanks to
speakers; for building compasses, buntings George for the difference that he has made.

REFERENCES
Connellan J, Baron-Cohen S, Wheelwright S, Batki A, Daly M, Wilson M. 1995. Discriminative parental solic-
Ahluwalia J. 2000. Sex differences in human neo- itude and the relevance of evolutionary models to
natal social perception. Infant Behavior and Devel- the analysis of motivational systems. Pages 1269–
opment 23:113–118. 1286 in The Cognitive Neurosciences, edited by M S
Cosmides L, Tooby J. 1994. Origins of domain speci- Gazzaniga. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
ficity: the evolution of functional organization. Dawkins R. 1998. The ‘information challenge.’ The
Pages 85–116 in Mapping the Mind: Domain Specific- Skeptic 18(4):21–25.
ity in Cognition and Culture, edited by L A Hirschfeld Dennett D C. 1995. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution
and S A Gelman. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon and
sity Press. Schuster.

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
26 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 80

Griffiths P E, Gray R D. 1994. Developmental systems Thelen E, Smith L B. 1994. A Dynamic Systems Approach
and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge
91(6):277–304. (MA): MIT Press.
Oyama S. 1985. The Ontogeny of Information: Develop- Tooby J, Cosmides L. 1990a. On the universality of
mental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge: Cam- human nature and the uniqueness of the individ-
bridge University Press; 2000. Second Edition. ual: the role of genetics and adaptation. Journal of
Durham (NC): Duke University Press. Personality 58:17–67.
Pinker S. 2004. Why nature and nurture won’t go away. Tooby J, Cosmides L. 1990b. The past explains the
Daedalus 133:5–17. present: emotional adaptations and the structure
Popper K R. 1972. Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology
Approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 11:375–424.
Popper K R. 1990. A World of Propensities. Bristol: Tooby J, Cosmides L. 1992. The psychological foun-
Thoemmes. dations of culture. Pages 19–136 in The Adapted
Popper K R. 1999. All Life is Problem Solving. London: Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of
Routledge. Culture, edited by J H Barkow, L Cosmides, and J
Robert D, Amoroso J, Hoy R R. 1992. The evolutionary Tooby. New York: Oxford University Press.
convergence of hearing in a parasitoid fly and its von Uexküll J. 1934. Streifzüge durch die Umwelten
cricket host. Science 258:1135–1137. von Tieren und Menschen. Berlin (Germany):
Robert D, Read M P, Hoy R R. 1994. The tympanal Springer. [Reprint. 1957. A stroll through the
hearing organ of the parasitoid fly Ormia ochracea worlds of animals and men: a picture book of invis-
(Diptera, Tachinidae, Ormiini). Cell and Tissue ible worlds. Pages 5–80 in Instinctive Behavior: The
Research 275:63–78. Development of a Modern Concept, edited by C H Schil-
Sterelny K. 1995. Understanding life: recent work in ler. New York: International Universities Press.]
philosophy of biology. British Journal for the Philos- West-Eberhard M J. 2003. Developmental Plasticity and
ophy of Science 46(2):155–183. Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sterelny K, Griffiths P E. 1999. Sex and Death: An Intro- Williams G C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection: A
duction to Philosophy of Biology. Chicago (IL): Uni- Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought. Prince-
versity of Chicago Press. ton (NJ): Princeton University Press.

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
March 2005 SYMPOSIUM IN HONOR OF GEORGE C WILLIAMS 27

This content downloaded from


152.118.24.31 on Mon, 19 Sep 2022 13:45:41 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like