Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 17

MAYANTHI L.

FERNANDO
University of California, Santa Cruz

Reconfiguring freedom:
Muslim piety and the limits of secular law and public
discourse in France

A B S T R A C T fter a long period of détente, France’s national debate about

A
Through an analysis of the practice of veiling, I first the Islamic headscarf in public schools—first begun in 1989—
examine how pious Muslim French women reconcile emerged anew in 2003 and culminated in September 2004 with
the dominant secular oppositions between personal the enactment of a law banning “conspicuous religious signs”
autonomy and religious authority, and between the in French public schools. In early 2004, a group of Muslim, Sikh,
“true” self and religious norms, as they constitute and secular activists formed the One School for All Collective (Collectif
themselves as religious subjects. I then turn to the Une Ecole pour Tous et Toutes) to contest the proposed law and to pro-
2004 law banning headscarves in public schools, and vide legal counsel and educational support for students who would be ex-
to the attendant public debates, exploring how this pelled as a result of the law. I was a member of the collective, opting to
Muslim French religiosity was rendered sit on the legal subcommittee alongside Corinne and Nadia, two second-
incommensurable in secular law and unintelligible in generation pious Muslim women; Malika, a self-declared Algerian feminist;
public discourse. In so doing, I bring into focus Ikhram, a Franco-Tunisian lawyer; and Jaswant, an energetic middle-aged
both the underlying assumptions and exigencies of Sikh man.1 (One of the unintentional targets of the new law was the Sikh
French secularity as well as some of its aporias. turban, precipitating the participation of the small Parisian Sikh commu-
[Islam, France, secularism, religious liberty, religious nity in protests against the law.) We met weekly in a café in the 11th ar-
subjectivity] rondissement of Paris in the late winter of 2004, gathered around a black
metal table near the window, copies of legal codes and conventions piled in
front of us, trying to find legal challenges to the law. Most of us on the sub-
committee regarded the proposed law as an attack on religious freedom2
and, consequently, felt that the best and most relevant challenge to the law
lay in advocating for the fundamental right to conscience, a right ostensi-
bly protected by the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen,
the European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms,
and other international conventions to which France is a signatory.
It turned out we were wrong. As we began to delve deeper into French
and European law, we discovered that both the French Constitution and
the European Convention on Human Rights make a distinction between
the right to conscience, which is inalienable, and the right to expressions or
manifestations of conscience, which can be subject to restriction. Neither
Corinne, Nadia, nor Jaswant understood practices like veiling and wearing
the turban as optional expressions of belief; rather, they considered them

AMERICAN ETHNOLOGIST, Vol. 37, No. 1, pp. 19–35, ISSN 0094-0496, online
ISSN 1548-1425. C 2010 by the American Anthropological Association. All rights reserved.
DOI: 10.1111/j.1548-1425.2009.01239.x
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

religious duties, as did most of my other pious Muslim bilities, and ritual and hermeneutical practices. Moreover,
French interlocutors. As Jaswant put it, the five Ks of in France, this diversity is complicated by generational di-
Sikhism “are not optional—they are the faith [ils sont le vergences.5 I therefore do not ascribe the particular reli-
culte].”3 Nonetheless, regarded by many French as expres- gious subjectivity under discussion to all participants in
sions of conscience—“signs,” in the language of the pro- the Islamic revival (and certainly not to all Muslims in
posed law—the headscarf and the turban fell outside the France). Most of my interlocutors for this article were “sec-
purview of the inalienable right to conscience. After a se- ond generation,”6 that is, the children of immigrants from
ries of meetings, we came to the conclusion that we sim- the Maghreb and, to a lesser extent, sub-Saharan Africa; a
ply had no recourse to challenge the law via a defense of few were converts (or “reverts”). All of them had been born
religious liberty, and we turned our attention and resources or grown up in France in the blue-collar suburbs (banlieues)
elsewhere. of Paris, Rennes, Nantes, and Lyon. In addition, though their
This article unpacks the conundrum we faced, tracing parents were or had been part of a proletarian workforce,
the ways in which secular assumptions about freedom, au- most of my interlocutors had or were studying for post-
thority, choice, and obligation—assumptions that underpin secondary-school degrees, often in communications, ac-
French political discourse about religion and French and counting, or social work. The practices and sensibilities I
European law pertaining to religious freedom—preclude describe here, then, are particularly salient to those I call
the public intelligibility of the kind of religiosity inhab- “Muslim citizens,” that is, women and men committed to
ited by Corinne, Nadia, and other Muslim citizens who practicing Islam as French citizens and to practicing French
are part of the French Islamic revival. I begin by examin- citizenship as Muslims, women and men who often identify
ing how much of the debate about the French Islamic re- as citoyens français de confession musulmane (French citi-
vival, and about the Islamic veil4 specifically, depends on a zens of Muslim faith) and who comprise a demographically
series of oppositions between choice and constraint, per- and politically significant aspect of the revival.
sonal autonomy and religious authority, and self-realization In taking up the religiosity of these Muslim citizens,
and “external” norms. Yet, as I go on to argue, many pi- I bring together and build on the anthropology of the Is-
ous Muslim citizens challenge the viability of these binaries lamic revival, the anthropology of minorities in Europe, and
by conceptualizing practices like veiling, praying, and fast- a burgeoning anthropology of secularism. Saba Mahmood’s
ing both as modalities of personal freedom and as author- (2005) seminal ethnography of the women’s mosque move-
itatively prescribed acts necessary to becoming a proper ment in Egypt expanded anthropological theories of ethi-
Muslim subject. Taking up one dimension of the kind of cal self-fashioning, uncoupling women’s agency from resis-
religiosity constituted in the French Islamic revival, I ex- tance to relations of domination and disengaging women’s
plore how the simultaneous goals of personal autonomy participation in (often patriarchal) piety movements from a
and submission to God, considered contradictory by nor- desire, even a subconscious one, for autonomy. Drawing on
mative secular French standards, are reconciled by Muslim Mahmood, other scholars have begun to take seriously pi-
citizens for whom religious authority does not exist in op- ous women’s desire to constitute themselves as ethical sub-
position to one’s “true” or inner self but, instead, is con- jects by submitting to forms of social and religious authority
ceived of precisely as the means to the self’s cultivation and (Haq 2008; Jouili and Amir-Moazami 2006)—an approach I
realization. I then return to the oppositional relation be- pursue here. Yet I take equally seriously my interlocutors’
tween choice and constraint, and between autonomy and simultaneous desire for personal autonomy, and their es-
regulatory authority, detailing how these binaries underpin pousal of a discourse of freedom and self-realization akin
secular European and French law and French political dis- to secular conceptions of the self and of individual agency.7
course about religious freedom, and how, as a consequence, This desire for autonomy should come as no surprise, given
it becomes difficult, even impossible, for many pious my interlocutors’ embedment in a French context domi-
Muslim citizens to articulate what it means to wear the veil nated by the imperatives of liberté (freedom) and volonté
in a way that is intelligible within dominant legal, political, (individual will). Like Lara Deeb (2006) and Gregory Starrett
and ethical frameworks. By examining, then, how a distinct (1998), then, who have focused on Islamic revivalists’ in-
form of religious subjectivity is rendered incommensurable terpellation by and engagement with modernist ideologies,
with secular discourse and law, I bring into focus both I am interested in what effect the fact that these Muslim
the underlying assumptions and exigencies of French sec- citizens have been—literally—schooled in French republi-
ularity as well as some of its aporias—aporias that are de- can epistemologies and ontologies has on their engagement
ferred onto and disproportionately borne by pious Muslim with the Islamic tradition. I am equally interested, however,
citizens. in how Muslim citizens, drawing simultaneously on certain
As in the rest of the Middle East and North Africa, ethical practices and epistemologies of self central to the Is-
the Islamic revival in France encompasses a broad swathe lamic tradition, speak back to, disrupt, challenge, and re-
of doctrinal trends, ethical, religious, and political sensi- configure dominant secular–republican assumptions.

20
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

I hope, too, to deepen recent analyses of France’s post- in the Middle East, the Islamic revival in France entails the
colonial predicament. Most relevant studies have either ex- unprecedented engagement with scholarly texts and theo-
plicitly focused on questions of race and ethnicity (Fassin logical reasoning by people not necessarily trained at tradi-
and Fassin 2006; Hargreaves 1997; Silverstein 2004) or col- tional religious institutions (Hirschkind 2006), resulting in
lapsed race, ethnicity, and religiosity into one overarching various forms of publicly engaged religiosity (Deeb 2006).
category of “difference” (Keaton 2006; Scott 2007; Touraine Over the past 15 years, France has witnessed the prolifera-
2005; Wieviorka 1997). In contrast, I analyze the specific tion of Islamic bookstores, Islamic youth associations, and
problems the “difference” of Muslim religiosity poses, both forms of Islamic dress, as well as Muslim demands on the
for Muslim citizens and for the secular French state. I un- state for funds to build mosques and a school calendar that
derstand secularity here not simply as a political doctrine incorporates Muslim holy days—demands that most non-
separating religious and political life but also as a set of le- Muslims find inimical to French republican norms (Bowen
gal and political practices of government with concomitant 2006; Laborde 2008).
ethical and political attitudes (Asad 2003, 2006; Jakobsen The major point of contention between secular re-
and Pellegrini 2008a; Taylor 2007). Talal Asad has written publicans and Islamic revivalists has concerned the head-
that because these elements form the epistemological and scarf. The first “headscarf affair” occurred in 1989, when
ontological basis of modern life, the secular is not easy to three Muslim schoolgirls of Tunisian and Moroccan de-
grasp directly, and must be pursued “through its shadows” scent refused to remove their headscarves in class, provok-
(2003:16). I take him to mean that examining the shadow ing a national political crisis. Ultimately, the High Court
cast over Muslim French women by the secular republi- (Conseil d’Etat) ruled that headscarves were permissible in
can project, and particularly by the ban on headscarves public schools as long as they were neither “ostentatious”
in public schools, can tell us a great deal not only about (ostentatoire) nor accompanied by proselytism. Despite
the specificity of Muslim “difference” but also about the the court’s 1989 decision, a new law was passed—almost
secular itself—the sensibilities it seeks to cultivate, the eth- unanimously—in 2004 banning the display of “conspicu-
ical imaginary it produces, the relationship between auton- ous” (ostensible) religious signs in public schools.9 As John
omy and authority on which it depends—as well as its lim- Bowen (2006), Cécile Laborde (2008), and Joan Scott (2007)
its and aporias. Moreover, like Elizabeth Povinelli, I explore have demonstrated, various arguments emerged as justifi-
how these aporias—akin to what she calls the “impasses cations for the law: the headscarf violated the avowedly sec-
of late liberalism”—are borne by minorities and subalterns ular, neutral space of the public school;10 it represented an
caught in contradictory mandates that put them ontolog- unacceptable form of communalism (communautarisme)
ically and politically at risk (2002:3). By illuminating the and was just the tip of the iceberg of a larger Islamist threat;
shadow spaces of laı̈cité (French secularism), I inquire into and it symbolized the submission of women to patriarchal
a prevalent form of Muslim religiosity being constituted in religious authority and, therefore, had no place in the sec-
France, the nature of French secularism, and the ways in ular public school, the “crucible” (Noiriel 1996) in which
which secular law and politics can undo the viability and French children are supposed to be emancipated from the
intelligibility of certain nonsecular subjects and forms of yoke of ostensibly retrograde religious and cultural tradi-
religious life. tions. Given its disproportionate affective weight in this de-
bate (Bowen 2006), as well as its legal efficacy, I will con-
centrate here on the third argument—that the headscarf
Opposing conceptions of the Islamic
is a sign of women’s submission—which itself has taken
revival in France
two forms. Some critics (more in 1989, fewer in 2003 and
Originating in the Middle East in the 1970s, Islamic revival- 2004) have argued that young girls in headscarf are be-
ism is now a global phenomenon. In France, those involved ing forced to wear the veil by their fathers, brothers, or
are primarily the children and sometimes grandchildren Muslim community leaders, and that they need to be eman-
of working-class immigrants from Algeria, Morocco, and cipated by the secular Republic and its laws (Augé 2004;
Tunisia who were recruited by the French government and Long and Weil 2004). Other critics, mindful of studies that
French industry as the cheap manual labor needed to re- have shown that many young women choose the headscarf
build France after World War II. Participants also include themselves, have advanced a more nuanced argument (one
young people of West African descent, white and Antillean that has reappeared in current French debates about out-
converts, and older first-generation immigrants who came lawing face veils). These critics argue that the veil, even if
to France as either laborers or foreign students. Various es- it is chosen freely by the wearer, perpetuates normative re-
timates put the number of people involved in the French ligious authority, polices female sexuality and prescribed
Islamic revival—which, as I noted earlier, encompasses var- gender roles, and reinforces patriarchal communal norms
ious trends—at between 250,000 and 500,000 people out of not only on the veiled woman in question but also on all
a population of about five million Muslims in France.8 As Muslim women in her social orbit (Kintzler et al. 2004;

21
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

Rojtman et al. 2004; Weil 2004). Underpinning all these crit- sion of women to patriarchal authority, these aforemen-
ics’ arguments is a clear opposition between emancipation tioned sociologies of French Islam have done valuable work
on the one hand and religious authority on the other hand, in trying to normalize the headscarf, portraying Muslim
and an understanding of the headscarf as fundamentally women as modern, even quasi-feminist subjects. Nonethe-
nonemancipatory because it is worn, even by choice, as a less, these scholars reproduce the same analytical schema
religious prescription. as republicanist critics of the headscarf, in which choice
In contrast to those who see the headscarf as a form constitutes the opposite of constraint, such that autonomy
of submission to religious authority, numerous French so- emerges in resistance to or in the absence of normative au-
ciologists have, in recent years, begun to regard the veil as thority. It is true that many young Muslim French women
a form of empowerment and emancipation (Gaspard and valorize the goal of personal freedom and conceptualize hu-
Khosrokhavar 1995; Khosrokhavar 1997; Tietze 2002; Venel man agency as the capacity to author one’s own life without
2004). Many of these analysts argue that by becoming a outside interference. But it is important to recognize that
practicing Muslim and participating in Islamic civil asso- they simultaneously also seek to submit to God’s will by un-
ciations, young women are able to cloak their desires—for dertaking certain normative, obligatory practices like veil-
work, for education, for freedom—in, if you will, a veil of ing, praying, and fasting. While I recognize, then, the po-
Islamic legitimacy, enabling them to escape traditional cus- litical efficacy of arguing that the veil is a personal choice,
toms like forced marriage and domestic servitude without not an imposition, such a reading of the practice of veiling
breaking completely with their families and community. misses crucial aspects of a certain kind of Muslim subjectiv-
Nancy Venel, for example, writes: “Under the cover of re- ity being constituted in France.
ligion and altruism, [young veiled women] enjoy a relative Accessing the precise nature of that subjectivity is im-
autonomy. . . . Through the veil, young women get around portant for two reasons. First, as social and cultural an-
[se dédouanent de] all parental suspicion with regards to alysts of human behavior, it behooves us to understand
their chastity and the rectitude of their conduct. The veil our subjects’ practices on an emic level, rather than apply-
allows them to occupy a space of liberty outside the fam- ing an interpretive schema that may be familiar to us but
ily cell . . . and to invert the traditional relations of authority that may have little resonance with the subjective orienta-
within the family” (2004:188). These writers also emphasize tions of the people with whom we work.11 Second, propa-
that not only the headscarf but also the kind of rigorous gating a secular heuristic that regards personal autonomy
Islam practiced by second-generation youth more gener- as the opposite of social and religious authority, and in-
ally is the result of a willed, individual choice, not the ha- ternally generated choice as the opposite of externally im-
bitual reiteration of parental norms. In fact, a number of posed constraints, ironically does an ultimate political dis-
analysts hold that, rather than the reinscription of com- service to pious Muslim French women. Although framing
munal custom, the defining feature of the French Islamic the headscarf as a freely chosen expression of the wearers’
revival is the individualization of religiosity (Khosrokhavar religious belonging may serve to mark these Muslim women
1997; Roy 1999, 2007; Venel 2004). Olivier Roy, for instance, as ostensibly “modern” religious subjects, it simultaneously
maintains that the absence of Islamic religious authori- severely restricts their ability to articulate what it means to
ties who could “state what is the norm,” and the lack of wear the veil not as a choice or a personal preference but,
social, communal, customary, and juridical coercion have rather, as a religious duty.
all made religiosity a fundamentally individual experience
(1999:70) so that, “at the end of the day, it is the believer
who decides, not the law, and not the society” (1999:91).
Redefining freedom
Although Roy does not reference them explicitly, he echoes
the kind of modern religious self described by both repub- Khadija is a practicing Muslim, part-time journalist, and
lican philosopher Marcel Gauchet (1997, 1998), who draws masters student in communications; her parents came to
on the Rousseauian tradition (Bowen 2006), and commu- France from Tunisia in the 1970s, and Khadija has lived in
nitarian philosopher Charles Taylor (2002), who draws on the Paris metropolitan region all her life. Like many other
William James (1999). According to this understanding, young Muslim French women whom I knew, Khadija con-
modern religiosity entails following one’s inner voice, rather sidered veiling a necessary element in the cultivation of
than conforming to the “exterior” rules of religious author- a relationship with God. Like other young Muslim French
ity (i.e., the church). One’s religion therefore cannot be pre- women, Khadija was also adamant that the headscarf must
scribed but must instead be chosen, guided by a voice felt be a choice, and that the decision to veil must emerge from
and heard within rather than outside the self. the internal desires of the practitioner and cannot be im-
In the political and cultural climate of contemporary posed by an outside authority. “I would never tell a woman
France, where the vast majority of the French public views to veil obligatorily, no way,” Khadija said. “Because it’s really
the headscarf as the symbol par excellence of the submis- something between you and God.” As I was told repeatedly

22
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

by a number of young Muslim women and men, quoting the and lived alone in Rennes (she has since moved to Paris
Quran, “there is no compulsion in religion.”12 for professional reasons). Hélène explained that her deci-
Khadija’s comments were echoed by members of the sion to veil was not driven by external factors like her fam-
Muslim Women of Rennes, a local association that does ily because they were Christian. Rather, “It is truly the de-
civic outreach work and meets biweekly to read and dis- sire [la volonté] to apply what I consider as emanating from
cuss the Quran and Quranic exegesis. When I worked with the Transcendent . . . that makes me wear the veil,” she told
them, most of the women were between 18 and 35 years old me. She noted that it had been difficult because the head-
and from varying backgrounds: of my primary interlocu- scarf poses such a problem for French society, “but I really
tors, three were Franco-Iraqi, one was Franco-Maghrebi, disregard how others look at me because it is my relation-
one was Antillean, one was African, and three were white ship with God that is in question in my choice to wear the
converts. One evening, we were gathered at the home of veil. I believe it’s important, in order to become the subject
Monique, a convert and stay-at-home mother of two small of one’s life [devenir sujet de sa vie], to not conform to the
children, discussing the role of the individual in interpret- opinion of others, because to do otherwise would be self-
ing God’s will, particularly with regards to the obligation alienation [parce que sinon, c’est s’aliéner]. Thus, the impor-
of the headscarf. Amira, a feisty high school student with tance, for me, in holding fast to my convictions.”
a cherubic face, took the lead in our conversation. Amira Hélène’s sense that becoming a full subject entails the
exudes independence—the 18-year-old daughter of Iraqi authorship of her own life was reiterated by Saida Kada,
Shiites who had fled Saddam Hussein’s regime in the 1980s, then a member of the activist group Collective of French
she had grown up in the Rennes banlieues with her sisters Muslims (CMF), which coformed the One School for All Col-
and has had a contentious relationship with her parents. lective. Kada is in her late thirties, highly articulate, and
She described how she came to wear the headscarf: attractive, and she often appears on nationally televised
debates to represent a pious Muslim perspective. She is
For me, personally, my approach with the headscarf also regarded by many Muslim French women as a model
was to study the position of the schools, Sunni and Shi- Muslim citizen: a pious working mother and wife who is
ite, to research religious scholars’ opinions. And you also active in political and civic life. In a collaborative trea-
know what, there’s a certain unanimity on this ques- tise with anthropologist Dounia Bouzar on Muslim women
tion. Now, these scholars are men, they are interpret- in France, Kada contends that “To be modern is to say ‘I’—
ing in a political context that we must not ignore, but to not let the clan decide for you, to use reason to put into
they nonetheless have proof, they are relying on the question ancestral traditions” (Bouzar and Kada 2003:199).
sources. [Amira paused] There was a time when I re-
“Freedom,” she continues, “comes with the access to knowl-
ally questioned the veil, but then I asked myself: Is it
edge, and liberation with the ability to speak [in our own
really me asking these questions? Is it me who is inter-
rogating my faith, is it me who is asking myself whether name]. . . . We [Muslim women] must not let others speak
I want to wear the veil and whether I am sincere, or isn’t in our place” (2003:15). For Kada, freedom means the abil-
it really society? . . . And it was this that led me to keep it ity to speak for oneself, to be the subject of one’s own life
[the veil], because I said to myself that it isn’t really my story, and not the object of someone else’s version. What
faith doing the questioning, it’s Western society in gen- Kada, Khadija, Amira, and Hélène all invoke is a sense of
eral and French society in particular that are always sin- autonomous human agency as fundamentally grounded in
gling me out [qui me pointent toujours du doigt]. . . . But the capacity to lead one’s life in accordance with one’s own
at the time, I really had a moment where I wanted to desires and choices, a conception of agency familiar to sec-
take it off because I thought, this is something imposed ular republican and liberal sensibilities.
by men, I am obeying because I fear God, and men are
These women’s attitudes toward veiling seemingly val-
using my fear of God to make me submit to a com-
idate the sociological analyses of the Islamic revival I dis-
mand. . . . But then I realized that when I pray and when
I put on my veil, everything makes sense [tout reprend cussed earlier, which regard the headscarf as very much a
du sens]. The headscarf, for me, makes sense. . . . And choice as well as part of a more general form of highly indi-
that’s when I said to myself that while it was legitimate vidualized religiosity that privileges following one’s “inner
to ask myself all these questions, I was putting into voice” over conforming to the “external” rules of religious
question something that does me good [quelque chose authority. Yet a closer look at the beliefs and practices of
qui me fait du bien]. women like Khadija, Amira, and Hélène demonstrate that
they ultimately upend such a distinctly oppositional rela-
Amira’s emphasis on fulfilling her own spiritual needs tionship between the self and authority, between personal
and desires regardless of, and sometimes against, the freedom and norms. By conceptualizing self-realization
wishes of others was reiterated by Hélène, another mem- as the realization of the transcendent will—the enact-
ber of the group and a convert of Guadeloupian descent ment of which requires submission to certain religious
in her mid-twenties. At the time, she was a social worker obligations—these Muslim French women fundamentally

23
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

reimagine the relationship between norms and the self, of the ‘ulema (religious scholars) to a public domain, reli-
such that the “true self” is cultivated and realized not gious authority has not necessarily been shattered; rather,
against social and religious authority but, rather, through it. in Europe, it has been resituated in nontraditional figures
Recall Amira’s earlier description of how she came to like Tariq Ramadan (a popular Swiss scholar) and his fel-
wear the headscarf. On the one hand, her comments in- low preachers and preacher–intellectuals.13 Moreover, the
dicate the extent to which she watches over herself in or- availability of religious manuals—in the French vernacu-
der to distinguish her own desires from those of others. In lar to cater to an audience of second-generation Muslims
fact, she reaches a point in her life at which she almost and converts—actually helps to propagate authoritative
takes off the headscarf because she feels that it may have and normative modes of being a proper Muslim, as Amira’s
been imposed on her by a patriarchal male elite. On the and Khadija’s religious transformations attest.
other hand, however, she ultimately recognizes veiling as One of the texts that most influenced Khadija to veil
an obligation, accepting the authority of religious schol- was Fatima Naseef’s Rights and Duties of the Woman in Is-
ars to interpret the sources correctly. Although her accep- lam (Droits et devoirs de la femme en islam, 1999). Another
tance of this obligation relies on her internal feelings of popular book is Being a Muslim Woman Today: The Legal
self-fulfillment—“when I put on my veil, everything makes Status of the Muslim Woman According to Islam (Être Musul-
sense,” as she affirmed—Amira is equally persuaded by the mane aujourd’hui: statut juridique de la femme musul-
arguments and authority of established religious scholars. mane selon l’islam, 1999) by Malika Dif, a French convert
Consider, too, the following explanation by Khadija as and influential speaker on the Islamic conference circuit
to how and why she decided to wear the veil: in France. These and other manuals detailing the role of
women according to the Islamic tradition (essentially, what
I understood from the books [I read] that I had to cover is expected of a woman and what she should expect from
[my hair], and during the first year of university, I said others) possess two particularly striking features. The first is
to myself, “Khadija, you can’t stay like this [i.e., un- their constant reference to “the Muslim woman” (la femme
veiled].” I talked to the sisters, I read books, and the musulmane), indicating that there is clearly a correct model
books were clear, they said that God had written in of female piety, derived from the Quran, the Sunna, and
the Quran that the headscarf was obligatory. . . . And the
the behavior of the Prophet’s wives, a model of piety that
fact that God required it, and that there was a logical
ordinary Muslim women should emulate. The second, re-
explanation—well, I said to myself, “Khadija, you’re go-
ing to veil.” And I put on a simple headscarf, where you lated feature of these texts is the frequent occurrence of
could see my neck. You know, I had a real problem at the verb devoir, which means “must,” “to have to,” or “to
the beginning. And then, little by little, at the end of a have a duty to” (devoir as a noun means duty) as in: “The
year, I started to wear the headscarf like this [i.e., a piece woman must, above all, surround her family with attention
of thick fabric covering her head, neck, and ears]. and care. . . . She must watch over the physical and psycho-
logical health [of her family]” (Dif 1999:41). The prevalence
Amira’s and Khadija’s accounts elucidate how many pi- of the word devoir highlights the fact that certain types of
ous Muslim citizens understand the relationship between behavior, including certain practices like veiling, are nec-
choice and normative authority. Quite significant, for exam- essary to becoming the kind of Muslim woman delineated
ple, is their reliance on the authority of accepted texts. One in these texts. Texts like those of Dif and Naseef underscore
of the most salient features of the Islamic revival in France the lacuna in analyses of Muslim French religious revival-
is the production, circulation, and consumption of reli- ism that herald the individualization of religion, the end of
gious manuals and video and audio cassettes by preachers, normative authority, and the emphasis on unconstrained,
many of whom have no classical training at religious insti- individual choice. While it is indeed “the believer who de-
tutions; these audio-visual and written manuals often detail cides” (Roy 1999:91), the believer is nonetheless guided by
the proper Islamic behavior for men, women, and children. religiously authoritative texts and arguments that explicitly
Olivier Roy (1999, 2007) contends that the increased avail- state the norm. According to these norms, the headscarf,
ability of texts and modes of Islamic reasoning, as well as the like other practices, is both a choice and, importantly, an
absence of state and judicial enforcement of religious law, obligation, a divine prescription incumbent on all Muslim
has shattered traditional authority in Europe. He thereby women.14 The choice here lies in whether or not to accept
reiterates arguments about the democratization of author- the obligation of veiling.
ity through mass media circulation of religious knowledge The following example of a conversation with Nawel
advanced by analysts of the Islamic revival in the Mid- nicely elucidates the particular relationship between indi-
dle East and North Africa (Eickelman and Anderson 1997; vidual choice and obligation at work in Muslim French re-
Eickelman and Piscatori 1996; Starrett 1998). However, ligiosity. At the time, Nawel was a 20-year-old student of
while the mass circulation of religious knowledge has in- Tunisian descent getting a professional degree in commu-
deed shifted religious authority from the restricted domain nications and working as an intern for the influential Union

24
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

of Islamic Organizations of France (UOIF). She and I were ney” (cheminement spirituel) by reading, attending confer-
having coffee when I asked her why she wore a simple head- ences, and talking to friends and acquaintances with bet-
scarf tied in a large knot at the nape of her neck that cov- ter knowledge of the Islamic tradition. They then usually
ered only her hair, rather than a fuller headscarf that cov- began praying intermittently, increasing over time the reg-
ered her neck as well, or even the niqab, the face veil. She ularity of their prayers to five times a day (many found
responded: “The niqab, it’s not my thing, although I respect it difficult initially to rise for the dawn prayer [fajr], but
the girls who wear it, just as I respect those girls who don’t they slowly brought themselves to do so every day). They
wear anything [to cover their hair].” Nawel thereby reaf- also began to dress more modestly and to change other
firmed the importance of respecting individual believers’ forms of behavior—eating halal, for example, and carrying
personal choices, including the decision to veil or remain loose change to give to homeless people—often taking their
unveiled. I then said, referring to the practice of veiling, “So cues from those more advanced on their “spiritual jour-
you have to cover the hair, and if you want, the neck and neys.” The temporal gap between beginning to pray and
ears.” Nawel interrupted me sharply. “It’s not ‘If you want,’ ” beginning to veil was common to most of the practicing
she said. “It is the ears and the neck [that have to be cov- Muslim women I knew, who prayed regularly for months
ered].” Nawel’s point was that one does not simply veil ac- and sometimes years before putting on the headscarf. Such
cording to one’s personal predilections. Proper veiling, an a gap highlights the intellectual and bodily disciplinary pro-
obligation in itself, has a specific, authorized form—the act cess through which these young Muslim women worked on
of choosing lies in whether one opts to follow the divine in- themselves by undertaking one step in a series of necessary
junction or not. In fact, the general goal for pious French practices to induce the desire for the next step toward be-
Muslims like Nawel is to undertake willingly what is neces- coming a properly pious Muslim.
sary. In Rights and Duties of the Woman in Islam, for exam- What women like Khadija, Amira, Hélène, and Nawel
ple, Naseef writes that it is a woman’s duty to maintain her enact, then, is a complex relationship between norms and
house in proper order, and that this duty must be assumed desire in which social and religious authority does not ex-
voluntarily: “In the authentic hadiths about women’s work ist in opposition to the “true” self but is rather the means to
in her household, it is said that the wife must accomplish the latter’s cultivation and realization. While self-realization
these household tasks willingly [de plein gré] and without and self-liberation remain fundamentally important goals
any compulsion” (1999:185). In other words, religious obli- for women like Khadija, Amira, and Hélène, the two princi-
gations should become integrated into one’s desire, so that ples are anchored in the Islamic concept of fitra, the natural
the desire to perform what are in fact duties flows naturally faculty within each individual to know God; self-realization
from within the self. is therefore understood as the rediscovery of one’s original
Khadija used texts like those by Naseef and Dif to knowledge of God, and self-liberation as the enactment of
work on herself, and the transformation she underwent God’s will. When Hélène asserts that becoming the “sub-
evokes the process of ethical self-cultivation theorized ject of one’s life” means not conforming “to the opinion of
by Mahmood (2005) in her ethnography of the Egyptian others,” she articulates the idea that liberation from others
women’s piety movement.15 Recall that Khadija began by is fundamental to self-realization, and that it is achieved
wearing a simple headscarf covering her hair because al- by submitting to God’s will, made knowable to humans
though she realized that veiling was obligatory, she was not through the Quran and the Sunna. Tariq Ramadan, an in-
ready—because she did not have the inner desire—to wear fluential European Muslim intellectual, puts it in similar
a fuller veil. As she said, “You know, I had a real problem at terms. Muslim spirituality, he writes, is the return to one’s
the beginning. And then, little by little, at the end of a year, true, God-connected self, which is a form of liberation, but
I started to wear the headscarf like this [i.e., covering her one that requires awareness, discipline, and constant ef-
head, neck, and ears].” Khadija’s desire to veil came about fort (2004:119). “Islamic teaching,” he continues, “has given
as the result of purposefully working on herself, inducing in us concrete tools to help us succeed in this work on our-
herself the desire to veil properly, as well as the necessary selves. . . . The daily requirements of Muslim practice give
love of God, through other “ethical practices” (Hirschkind us the direction and the first steps along the way to free-
2006; Mahmood 2005) like praying, reading, and discussing dom” (2004:120). In other words, self-realization is only pos-
the headscarf with other young Muslim French women. sible by actively submitting to religious discipline and re-
Over the course of a year, Khadija disciplined her desire so making oneself according to the norms extracted from the
that the obligations considered necessary to being a pious revealed texts through centuries of authoritative interpre-
Muslim woman would be undertaken sincerely and “freely.” tation. Moreover, practices like praying, veiling, and fasting
Khadija had once noted to me that cultivating piety are not only signs that intentionally index a Muslim identity
“is a whole path,” and over the course of my fieldwork, I but also, as Ramadan reiterates, are necessary to the cultiva-
came to recognize the basic steps of this path. Most of my tion of the Muslim self.16 Ramadan and the Muslim French
interlocutors began what they called their “spiritual jour- women to whom he appeals conceptualize self-realization

25
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

as the realization of the transcendent will, and as dependent and practice is a semiotic relationship of signification. For
on, rather than constituted in opposition to, social and reli- them, religious practices like veiling are outward manifes-
gious authority. They therefore subtly but fundamentally re- tations of an already constituted conscience. According to
configure secular notions of personal autonomy and mod- this logic—which was heavily prevalent in French debates
ern religiosity such that normative religious authority and about the headscarf—banning a practice (understood as a
inner, individual desire are not constituted by a relationship sign) does not constitute a violation of religious liberty be-
of opposition, but rather are inextricably linked.17 cause it has no effect on the believer’s conscience. Although
Yet the kind of religiosity inhabited by these Muslim cit- Muslim girls (and other religious students) would no longer
izens, with its distinct configuration of personal autonomy, be able to manifest their beliefs in certain ways as a result
authority, and the self, was rendered unintelligible on the of the law, proponents of the ban argued that they would
discursive and legal terrain on which debates about the ban nonetheless remain free to believe whatever they wanted
on headscarves were waged. Muslim French women were to believe, thus continuing to exercise their right to con-
compelled to defend the headscarf as either a choice or science. As Laı̈di noted, Muslim girls could continue to wear
an obligation—a conundrum I explore in the following sec- the headscarf “on the inside.”
tion on public-sphere discussions concerning whether the This logic is not only dominant in French public dis-
headscarf ban constituted a violation of religious liberty. course about the headscarf; it also undergirds French and
European legal conventions pertaining to religious liberty.
According to Article 10 of the Rights of Man and Citizen,
Secular law and religious liberty
“None shall fear for his opinions, even religious, as long as
If we on the legal subcommittee of the One School for All their manifestation does not trouble the public order as es-
Collective felt sure that the ban on headscarves in pubic tablished by the law.” The European Convention on Human
schools constituted a violation of religious freedom (la lib- Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, to which France is a sig-
erté religieuse), proponents of the law were equally insis- natory, echoes the Rights of Man. Article 9(1) guarantees
tent that it did not, and, moreover, that it constituted an to all “the right to freedom of thought, conscience and re-
important defense of religious liberty. They did so by draw- ligion” as well as the right “to manifest [one’s] religion or
ing on two key themes that permeate both French political belief, in worship, teaching, practice and observance,” but,
discourse and French and European law: a semiotically in- like the Rights of Man, places certain limitations on the lat-
formed understanding of practice as the expression of be- ter freedom. According to Article 9(2), “Freedom to manifest
lief,18 and, relatedly, a notion that freedom of conscience one’s religion or beliefs shall be subjected to such limita-
constitutes freedom of choice. tions as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a demo-
Time and again, French politicians and intellectuals cratic society in the interest of public safety, for the protec-
supportive of the ban argued that restricting the wearing tion of public order, health or morals, and for the protection
of the headscarf and other religious “signs” did not con- of the rights and freedoms of others.” In other words, both
stitute a violation of religious liberty because the believer the Rights of Man and the European Convention on Hu-
could continue to believe—on the inside. For Gisèle Halimi, man Rights distinguish between conscience and its man-
an influential feminist writer and lawyer, “Faith, thought, ifestation or expression. According to European jurispru-
conscience, as a matter of fact—domain of the subjective— dence, “Article 9 primarily protects the sphere of personal
can be expressed. Behaviors, religious ‘prescriptions,’ basi- beliefs and religious creeds, i.e. the area which is sometimes
cally signs and insignia, practice, in other words—domain called the forum internum” (Evans 2001:72). Thus, as Car-
of the objective—must be banned” (Halimi 2003:66). It re- olyn Evans notes, “the emphasis in the interpretation of Ar-
mains unclear how Halimi expects faith to be expressed if ticle 9 is on the [protection of the] internal: private thought,
not through behavior and signs (words, perhaps? But are conscience, and religion of the individual” (2001:72). While
words not signs?), though she is quite clear in making a the realm of the forum internum is inviolable and the right
distinction between conscience and practice. Zaki Laı̈di, to conscience inalienable, the right to manifest one’s con-
a political theorist and professor at the National Institute science is alienable. Moreover, as a result of the clear dis-
of Political Sciences (Sciences Po), provides some clarifica- tinction made between internal conscience and external
tion of Halimi’s basic argument. In an editorial in the daily manifestation—essentially a distinction between belief and
Libération praising President Jacques Chirac’s call for a law practice—a restriction on the manifestation of conscience
banning religious signs in public school, he writes: “There (i.e., practice) is not considered a restriction on conscience
are a thousand ways for a Muslim woman who aspires to itself.19
wear the veil to wear it on the inside without wearing it on Underpinning this distinction between conscience and
the outside [de le porter en elle sans le porter au regard des its manifestation is a specific, secular understanding of the
autres]” (Laı̈di 2004:159). Both Laı̈di and Halimi draw on relationship between belief and practice, one that high-
the assumption that the relationship between conscience lights the imbrication of Protestant epistemologies and

26
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

sensibilities with the development of modern secularity vidualized religiosity both assume an oppositional rela-
(Keane 2007; Taylor 2007). While bodily practices were once tionship between autonomous and authority-imposed ac-
considered integral to cultivating the necessary dispositions tion. According to the terms of this relationship, individ-
of the religious self, they are now thought of as expressions ually inspired choices emerge in the absence of authority
of belief (Asad 1993; Bynum 1987; Mahmood 2005). And if (religious or otherwise), and religious obligations (or “re-
religious practices are neither as integral to religion as are quirements”) are understood as nonautonomous behav-
beliefs nor constitutive of belief, then a restriction on prac- ior defined and compelled by established normative au-
tice would not, by this logic, constitute a violation of reli- thority. We have returned, then, to the same interpretive
gious liberty. Of course, as I demonstrated earlier, my pi- paradigm so common to analyses of Muslim religiosity,
ous Muslim French interlocutors do not share this notion of in which the veil is regarded as either actively compelled
practice as a second-order contingent expression of belief. by religious authorities and, therefore, not a legitimate in-
Yet for nonsecular religious subjects like the Muslim French dividual choice, or as “chosen” according to a “personal
women with whom I worked, there is simply no room in reading of religion” (Venel 2004:86) and, therefore, a form
the law to defend conscience-impelled practices under the of individualized self-expression unmediated by religious
aegis of the inalienable right to religious liberty. authority.
Interestingly, there does exist one exception in Euro- Within such a paradigm, central to European analytical
pean law under which the manifestation of conscience and legal understandings of modern religiosity, it becomes
(rather than simply the forum internum) is considered an difficult, even impossible, to articulate a practice like veiling
inalienable form of religious liberty: when certain practices in a way that makes sense to most secular republicans. For
are required by a religion.20 The apparent capacity of Euro- Muslim citizens like Khadija, Amira, and Hélène, the veil is
pean law to protect “required” practices and acts of worship both an individual choice and a religious duty. Veiling, for
would seem to bode well for practicing Muslims who claim these women, cannot be imposed by an external author-
the veil as a religious duty. However, the European Com- ity and must be undertaken willingly, according to the dic-
mission and European Court of Human Rights have under- tates of individual conscience, but veiling is also a neces-
stood the notion of “required” practice in a very particular sary means of cultivating the kind of pious self delineated
way. The commission and court have generally been unwill- by religious authorities. However, these women are consis-
ing to accept the so-called subjective assessment of individ- tently compelled by secular public discourse and law to cat-
ual applicants about whether certain behaviors or practices egorize the veil as either a choice or an obligation. Consider
are required of them by their religion, preferring instead to the following exchange, which took place during a January
rely either on the opinion of recognized religious authori- 2004 televised debate on the proposed law banning head-
ties or on the commission’s or court’s own definition of what scarves.21 Leila Babès, a sociologist and vocal critic of veil-
counts as a required practice. (Note that this means that a ing, insisted that the headscarf was not a religious prescrip-
secular political authority makes what is essentially a the- tion. Quoting verses of the Quran, she maintained that the
ological decision.) As Peter Edge (2000) and Evans (2001) hijab was meant only for the Prophet’s wives and was not
both point out, this approach to what is religiously required a major pillar of the faith, and that the Quran advocated
privileges members of hierarchically structured and heav- only modesty, not the headscarf, for Muslim women. Saida
ily centralized religious traditions (like Catholicism) at the Kada, the Muslim French activist mentioned earlier, replied
expense of less institutionally centralized traditions (like Is- that “what Leila Babès says about the veil not being a reli-
lam or Buddhism). It also acts to the disadvantage of mem- gious prescription is her point of view; other women have
bers of minority religions, whose tenets probably remain a different point of view.” She added that she had no de-
unfamiliar to European judges. Finally, it diminishes the sire to impose the veil on anyone, and that the hijab was,
claims of an individual who either does not accept all the for her, the culmination of her own spiritual journey in
teachings of an established religion or who believes that which she came to realize that the headscarf was an obli-
his or her religion places additional demands than those gation. Kada’s last point was completely ignored; the de-
deemed necessary by the court or by court-recognized re- bate’s moderator turned to the unequal status of women in
ligious authorities. Muslim countries, Babès claimed that the Quran advocates
The commission’s and court’s approach to what is re- the cutting off of thieves’ hands, philosopher Elizabeth
ligiously required, and its privileging of religious authori- Badinter (another long-time opponent of veiling) noted
ties to define the religious norm, ostensibly contradicts the that young Muslim girls were now at the “rear-guard” of in-
secular affirmation of modern religiosity as a fundamen- tegration and that “we have to defend the young girls we
tally individual enterprise, in which an individual should never hear from,” and Bernard Stasi (head of the commis-
be able to interpret for herself what is religiously required. sion that first proposed the law) lamented “the return to
On second review, however, the court’s approach to re- religion, [to] fundamentalism”—a regressive return seem-
ligious requirement and the secular affirmation of indi- ingly embodied by the “fundamentalist” Kada.

27
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

This exchange highlights two important elements cen- rests in the fact that it gives priority to the protection of
tral to the problem Muslim French women face in claim- individuals by the state against any religious group pres-
ing the headscarf as a religious duty. First, the vigorous de- sure” (2004:147). In fact, historically, laı̈cité has entailed
bate surrounding the doctrinal status of the hijab, and the the protection of individuals against state-directed pressure
open question as to whether the headscarf is “really” a reli- or coercion in religious matters by separating the Catholic
gious prescription, is precisely, as I just noted, what disqual- church and the French state and demanding that the state
ifies it as a religious requirement that would be protected by remain neutral with regards to religion, thus leaving in-
the European Convention. Ironically, then, Muslim French dividuals free to practice according to their conscience.
women’s commitment to the validity of internally gener- Nonetheless, Weil’s emphasis on the state’s primary duty
ated desire and their refusal to dictate the headscarf for all to protect individuals from religious groups is telling. Weil
Muslim women—that is, the subjective dimensions that un- admits that the veil “remains for some an individual sign
derscore their immersion in secular liberal and republican of [religious] belonging [that is] freely chosen” (Long and
ethical norms—are precisely what disqualify their religious Weil 2004:86), and he also notes that the European Con-
practices from the law’s protection. Second, the exchange vention on Human Rights “recognize[s] the right to pub-
exemplifies a certain secular tone-deafness to what Bowen licly express one’s religious beliefs” (Weil 2004:143). How
calls the “multivocality of [the term] ‘obligation’” (2006:176). and why, then, should the headscarf be restricted? Because,
When Muslim French women say that they wear the head- Weil argues, “in the schools where some girls are wearing
scarf because it is a religious obligation, secular critics as- the headscarf, Muslim girls who do not wear it are subject
sume either that it is compelled by fathers, brothers, and to strong pressure to do so [by religious groups]. . . . In the
other male religious leaders, or that these women believe view of these groups [who apply such pressure], composed
that the veil should be imposed on all women, or both.22 mainly of males, these girls are ‘bad Muslims’ or ‘whores,’
As became apparent over the course of the exchange cited who should follow the example of their sisters and respect
above, which is metonymic of the general tenor of public the prescription of the Koran” (Weil 2004:143).23 Weil con-
and private debates about veiling, secular critics could not tinues: “Muslim girls who do not want to wear the scarf also
conceive of veiling as a truly autonomous choice (i.e., the have a right of freedom of conscience, and they constitute
result of following one’s inner desire) if it was (also) an obli- the large majority” (2004:144). It remains unclear how, if the
gation, for any reference to obligation entailed either the large majority of students do not (and do not want to) wear
negation of one’s personal autonomy or the negation of all the headscarf, it constitutes such an enormous source of
women’s freedom. There was simply no room in the secular pressure, since it would seem that there would exist more
French imagination, or in European and French law, to con- peer pressure not to veil. Nevertheless, Weil’s point is that
ceptualize obligation, at least in this instance, as a personal the headscarf impinges on the freedom of conscience of
commitment. Consequently, to speak publicly of the head- nonveiled girls. He therefore concludes that while numer-
scarf as a religious duty or obligation was, essentially, to de- ous international conventions “recognize the right to pub-
clare oneself a “fundamentalist” and to disqualify oneself licly express one’s religious beliefs” (2004:143), they also au-
as a legitimate interlocutor in public debates about the law. thorize “the limitation of the expression of religious faith,
Not surprisingly, then, most Muslim French women speak- especially in the case of problems of public order or at-
ing about the headscarf to a secular audience did so through tacks on the rights and on the freedom of conscience of
a language of personal choice and individual freedom. (As others” (2004:144). Weil was certainly not alone in making
should be clear by now, such language was not disingen- this argument: the notion that the headscarf impinged on
uous but, rather, the foregrounding of one dimension of the consciences of nonveiled girls and constituted a viola-
the practice of veiling.) Yet, as will soon become clear, ar- tion of their religious liberty was one of the most rhetori-
ticulating the veil as purely a choice (rather than also an cally and legally effective justifications of the headscarf ban.
obligation) ironically undermined their case for the right to As Loubna Méliane, an antiracist activist, put it, “we live
religious liberty. in a secular republic that guarantees the respect for every
To illustrate how this happened, I turn to the second person and for his or her convictions. . . . Unfortunately, the
assumption fundamental to secular republicans’ insistence young girls who demand to wear the veil in school are pros-
that the ban on headscarves upheld religious liberty: that elytizing and making the other young girls feel guilty [cul-
of freedom of conscience as freedom of choice, an assump- pabilisent les autres jeunes filles].”24
tion best exemplified by Patrick Weil’s defense of the 2004 Weil, Méliane, and other like-minded proponents of
law. Weil, a historian, was a member of the presidentially the ban here understand freedom of conscience as the
appointed Stasi Commission, which first proposed the law freedom to choose, but as political philosopher Michael
in 2003. In laying out the commission’s approach to the Sandel (1998) has argued, these two concepts are not iden-
question of religious freedom, Weil notes that “the histori- tical. (Although Sandel refers to the American legal tradi-
cal success of the French model of secularization—laı̈cité— tion, his analysis holds for the distinction I am trying to

28
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

make.) Sandel argues that freedom of conscience has tra- walked from the Place de la République to the Place de
ditionally meant the freedom to exercise religious liberty la Bastille, they sang the Marseillaise and chanted slogans
without suffering civil penalties, protecting those who are such as: “France bien aimée, respectez ma liberté” [My
constrained by duties they cannot renounce, even in the beloved France, respect my liberty] and “Voilée, dévoilée,
face of conflicting civil obligations. But when religious lib- c’est ma liberté” [Veiled, unveiled—it’s my liberty]. Many
erty comes to mean simply the right to choose one’s be- of the young women held up homemade cardboard signs
liefs, freely, the result is a devaluation of claims by those reading: “Foulard, Croix, Kippa: Laissez nous le choix” [Veil,
for whom religion is not a matter of choice but, rather, Cross, Kippa: Leave us the choice] and “Le voile est un choix
of duty.25 When religious convictions are understood as personnel. N’otez pas mon droit essentiel” [The veil is a per-
choices or personal preferences, and religious liberty as sonal choice. Don’t deprive me of my essential right]. I saw
the capacity to choose freely with regards to religion, per- only one much older woman who made any reference to
forming a religious duty is reduced to making a religious the obligation of the headscarf or to the Quranic suras from
choice. which that obligation is derived—and she was conspicu-
The reduction of freedom of conscience to a more ously shunned by the younger demonstrators.
narrowly conceived freedom of choice underpins Patrick Herein lies the rub. In framing the veil as a freely un-
Weil’s arguments in favor of the headscarf ban, for he dertaken choice, the women in this demonstration were de-
clearly understands freedom of conscience as the right to manding that the government respect their right to choose
choose without any external pressure or social coercion. their religion and, thereby, protect their right to religious
According to this logic, any external pressure (here, in the freedom. Yet having to articulate the veil exclusively as a
form of veiled girls) diminishes the right of individuals to personal choice (rather than as both a choice and a reli-
choose freely, violating their freedom of conscience. Given gious duty) paradoxically undermined their case for reli-
the present-day hegemony of this logic in France—that is, gious liberty because it enabled policy makers like Weil to
that religious liberty concerns the right to choose freely— consider veiling as simply a choice (really, a personal pref-
it became discursively and politically impossible for Mus- erence) rather than a religious duty. For Weil and the Stasi
lim French women to defend the wearing of the head- Commission, the right of one group of girls to exercise their
scarf as anything but a choice. In fact, many did defend religious choices seemingly impinged on the capacity of an-
the headscarf as an internally driven choice, unmediated other group of girls to make their own religious choices in
by any form of external authority. Kada maintained that an unconstrained manner (Asad 2006). Because one per-
veiled women in France “would simply like to be able to live son’s freedom ends where another’s begins, the decision
out their choices, without having someone impose some was made to protect unveiled girls’ freedom of religion—
kind of truth on them, whatever it may be” (Bouzar and understood as the right to choose freely in the absence
Kada 2003:26). In a similar vein, an editorial on the website of the ostensibly constraining pressure produced by other
oumma.com by another writer, Felwine Sarr, voiced outrage girls’ headscarves.
at the denial of the fundamental right to choose one’s be- I want to emphasize how much this predominant un-
liefs for oneself. “The question here is not about knowing derstanding of conscience as choice relies on an opposi-
whether the veil is a Quranic prescription or obligation,” tional relationship between personal autonomy and social
Sarr wrote. “We only need to say that these Muslim women and religious authority. There exists no discursive space
who want it (wearing the veil must not be imposed on any- in which to conceptualize or articulate practices like veil-
one) have the freedom to wear it, whatever their own read- ing, which pious Muslim French women consider a reli-
ing of the Text, and as long as their freedom does not in- gious duty, one that cannot be coerced, and that entails a
fringe on that of another” (Sarr 2003). Sarr’s point is that the very different relationship between desire and social and
question as to whether or not the veil is a Quranic prescrip- religious authority. When the practice of veiling is turned
tion should be irrelevant before the law—that question re- into a “free choice,” as it must be to make it discursively
mains, of course, absolutely relevant to practitioners of veil- and legally intelligible to the secular majority—to claim the
ing since it forms the basis for the practice. Yet Sarr’s to- headscarf is an obligation is to out oneself as a bona fide
tal excising of the question of obligation in her defense of “fundamentalist”—Muslim French women lose the capac-
veiling constitutes an instructive indication of the contem- ity to express the stakes of what it means to wear the head-
porary political landscape on which pious Muslim French scarf as a religious obligation, enabling lawmakers to argue
women must make their claims. that restricting headscarves in schools does not constitute a
Kada’s and Sarr’s defense of the freedom to choose violation of religious liberty. In having to defend the veil as
was reiterated in a December 2003 demonstration against a choice, it becomes impossible for them to articulate, in a
the proposed law. The demonstration consisted of about way that is intelligible to a secular public, the fact that it is
three or four thousand women, many of them in red, white, indispensable to their religiosity and their sense of self, and
and blue headscarves, and most of them under 40. As they to convey the sense that a restriction on veiling is not simply

29
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

a limitation on personal preference but, rather, a profound (Althusser 1971; Asad 1993; Butler 1993; Foucault 1978,
disarticulation of their very selves.26 1991). Nonetheless, I find the hegemonic espousal of this
Yet framing the headscarf as both a personal deci- opposition between freedom and authority particularly cu-
sion and a religious obligation constituted, and contin- rious in a country like France, where the state’s explicit
ues to constitute, a kind of “double talk” (un double dis- role in forming free citizens has consistently blurred any a
course), representative of either an incoherent subjectivity priori boundary between government and individual free-
or an insidious plot to mask a “fundamentalist” agenda with dom. Laı̈cité is and has been a modality of government,
liberal–republican language. As Bowen writes, “the multi- with concomitant practices, authorizing discourses, and
vocality of ‘obligation’ has become a frequent sign of the political and legal institutions that aim to create partic-
‘double-talk’ of Muslims who say, to other Muslims [and ular kinds of ethical and political sensibilities and forms
non-Muslims], that wearing hijâb is a divine injunction and of sociality (Asad 2006). Since the Third Republic made
obligation, and, to non-Mulims [and Muslims], that there schooling compulsory for boys and girls in 1882, for ex-
is no compulsion in Islam, and that it is up to women to ample, the secular school has been a privileged institution
decide what to do” (2006:176). Of course, Muslim French for producing normative, albeit “free” subjects inculcated
women’s understanding of the hijab as both an internally in a secular morality based on the positivist–humanist val-
driven choice and a religious duty makes sense when one ues of reason, freedom, and equality (Baubérot 2000; Surkis
conceptualizes self-realization and religious normativity as 2006; see also Durkheim 1961). The school is a place where,
linked. Within the secular republican imaginary, however, through a series of disciplinary techniques, individuals are
where self-realization emerges against normative authority, to be stripped of their “passions” and regional and reli-
and autonomous choices are made in the absence of con- gious customs and imbued with the particular moral, social,
straint, women like Khadija, Amira, and Hélène occupy a and political values and commitments—to patriotism, civic
no-man’s-land of discursive and legal unintelligibility. equality, liberty, and social solidarity—that make men and
women French citizens (Baubérot 2000; Silverstein 2004;
Weber 1976).
Conclusion
Joan Scott has already proposed that the recent
By way of conclusion, I want to return briefly to the method- headscarf crisis indexes a deep-seated anxiety about the
ological import of Asad’s call to analyze the nature of problem that sexual difference poses for republican po-
the secular through its shadows (2003:16). I take from his litical universalism (2007, esp. ch. 5). My analysis brings
proposition that the shadow cast by French secularism onto me to a parallel conclusion about a different set of anxi-
Muslim French citizens reveals a great deal about laı̈cité it- eties and the deferral of a different problem. I wonder if
self, including its limits and aporias. In this instance, the the kind of criticism of the religious authority and norma-
secular-republican criticism of Muslim citizens’ submission tivity of Islam expressed by Dounia Bouzar—who is repre-
to explicit norms and “correct” behavior draws on and rein- sentative of a wider discursive terrain—entails a deferral of
forces, yet also unintentionally problematizes, a dominant tensions inherent in a secular–republican project that os-
conception of personal autonomy. This process is nicely il- tensibly emancipates individuals from various forms of au-
lustrated by Dounia Bouzar’s recent book “Mr. Islam” Does thority (the church, custom, etc.) by bringing the normative
Not Exist (“Monsieur Islam” n’existe pas), in which she at- disciplinary authority of the school to bear on its subjects.
tacks the “normativity” of the Islamic revival in France. I want to suggest that by disturbing the viability of a strict
Bouzar argues that young Muslims, in accepting the princi- distinction between normative authority and personal au-
ple that norms are to be found in texts, both revealed and tonomy, pious Muslim French women reveal the intensely
exegetical, are not “putting the norm into question” but, intertwined relationship between government, discipline,
rather, transforming it into a life ethic, an attitude she finds and freedom that has been fundamental to the secular–
antithetical to what she claims is the “critical spirit” and republican project. Could it be, then, that the consternation
“individual thinking” of secular modernity (2004:94). What about ostensible Muslim unfreedom in fact helps to sustain
Bouzar puts into play in her discussion of the Islamic re- a secular fantasy of personal autonomy, deferring an under-
vival is, once again, a series of oppositions between eman- lying anxiety about the very interconnectedness of auton-
cipation and religious tradition, individual autonomy and omy and authority that continues to haunt the Republic?27
authority, and conscience and the norm—oppositions cen- In asking these questions, I also want to gesture to their
tral to the self-narrative of secularism generally (Jakobsen import—and to the relevance of my analysis of laı̈cité—
and Pellegrini 2008a), and especially to laı̈cité. beyond the specific context of France. After all, the as-
I am obviously not the first to point out the tenu- sumptions I outlined earlier about religious practices be-
ousness of these distinctions. Numerous poststructural- ing expressions of belief and about freedom of conscience
ist critics have argued that “inner” desire, even for free- as freedom of choice are not restricted to France or even
dom, is produced through disciplinary or regulatory powers to Europe; they undergird American law as well (Evans

30
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

2001; Sandel 1998; Sullivan 2007). In fact, pious Muslim and applicable to considerations of secularity more broadly,
citizens’ difficulty articulating the practice of veiling as given the ensconcement of a specific French secularity
both a personal choice and a religious duty within secular (emerging out of a particular set of historical circumstances,
French public discourse and European law mirrors a sim- interpellating a particular instance of Muslim religiosity)
ilar conundrum faced by the Catholic American, Protes- within a larger set of subjectivities, values, and political
tant American, and Jewish American plaintiffs in Warner practices that constitute secularism. This tension between
v. Boca Raton (Sullivan 2007). That case concerned the the local and the global is one that must inform any an-
First Amendment protection of grave markers and decora- thropological consideration of the secular, which has the
tive memorials in a cemetery in Boca Raton, markers and following analytical task: to provincialize secularity’s claim
memorials that had been outlawed by local cemetery regu- to transcend the particular while simultaneously attending
lations but that the plaintiffs argued were necessary to the to the increasing hegemony of the epistemologies, sensibil-
practice of their faith as they understood it. After hearing ities, political discourses, and legal arrangements that con-
from institutionalized religious authorities and consulting stitute secularism as a project.
religious texts—“talking theology,” as the presiding judge
put it—the state court determined that the grave memori-
als fell outside the protection of the First Amendment right Notes
to free exercise of religion because they were not explicitly Acknowledgments. Fellowships from the Social Science Research
required by Catholic, Protestant, or Jewish doctrine. What Council and the Chateaubriand Foundation allowed me to com-
both the Warner decision and the French case illustrate— plete the fieldwork necessary for this article. Parts of the article
along with a number of other cases (Evans 2001)28 —is the were written with the help of a National Science Foundation Grad-
inability of the law in each instance to countenance per- uate Fellowship and a Charlotte W. Newcombe Doctoral Disserta-
tion Fellowship. I would like to thank my fellow participants in the
sonal or individual religious commitments that are not ex- Workshop in Politics, Ethics, and Society as well as other colleagues
plicitly set forth by doctrine or compelled by established re- at Washington University in St. Louis, where I profited greatly from
ligious authorities. the intellectual and institutional support afforded me by an Andrew
In considering these two examples, one cannot help W. Mellon Postdoctoral Fellowship in Modeling Interdisciplinary
but ask how two very different instantiations of secular- Inquiry. I am grateful to Leora Auslander, Dorian Bell, Jean
Comaroff, Enseng Ho, Lisa Rofel, and, especially, Saba Mahmood,
ity in France and the United States can nonetheless re- for their comments at various stages of the article. I am particularly
flect such similar conceptions of personal autonomy and indebted to Neda Atanasoski, Caetlin Benson-Allott, and Megan
religious authority, and of the relationship between con- Moodie for their keen insights and encouragement. Finally, this ar-
science and practice. These similarities suggest the need for ticle would not have been possible without the incredible generos-
an approach to secular formations in various national con- ity of my friends and interlocutors in France.
1. This article draws on fieldwork I conducted between 2002 and
texts beyond that of “local secularisms” provided by Janet 2004 in Paris, Nantes, and Rennes. All names of nonpublic figures
Jakobsen and Ann Pellegrini (2008b). Jakobsen and Pelle- are pseudonyms.
grini want to provincialize secularism’s claims to transcend 2. There was a significant divide within the collective between
the particular by locating its purported universality and ra- practicing Muslim and Sikh members who framed the law as a vio-
tionality in particular European and American histories and lation of religious freedom and other, more secular members who
considered it primarily an attack on the right to education.
in specific religious genealogies. Considering various na- 3. According to Jaswant, practicing Sikhs are bound to wear the
tional instantiations of secularism (“local secularisms”) and Kakaars (or Five Ks) at all times. The five Kakaars are kesh (un-
their relation to different religious traditions, they advocate cut hair), kanga (small comb), kara (heavy silver bracelet), kir-
replacing the singular category “secularism” with the plu- pan (small ceremonial dagger), and kacha (long undergarments).
ralized analytic of “secularisms.” While I certainly appreci- Although the turban became the major issue in French schools,
conflicts in Britain and North America have mostly focused on the
ate such efforts and agree that secularism is neither unidi- carrying of the kirpan, which violates many schools’ public safety
rectional nor uncontested in various spaces, I nonetheless policies banning weapons.
worry that such an analytic deemphasizes the globalizing 4. What is referred to as “the veil” (le voile) in France is usually a
power of the behaviors, knowledges, sensibilities, and headscarf either tied at the back of the neck (covering the wearer’s
political arrangements that have come to comprise the hair and ears) or pinned at the throat (covering the wearer’s hair,
ears, and neck). While there are women who wear the full face
secular (Asad 2003; Keane 2007). That my Muslim French veil (niqab), such an occurrence remains quite rare among young
interlocutors and the plaintiffs in Warner are rendered un- women in France. While I appreciate John Bowen’s (2006) deci-
intelligible in similar ways in two countries whose contem- sion to use the French term voile in order both to underscore
porary secular formations nonetheless have quite differ- the specificity of French usage and to mark the symbolic politics
ent historical genealogies suggests a certain effectiveness the term voile implies, I translate the term into English. I do so
largely because the terms voile and voilée (veiled) have become
to secularity’s normalizing force—its projectness—that an normalized in Muslim French vocabulary to refer to the hijab (the
analytical pluralization fails to adequately capture. Thus, generic Arabic term for modest head-covering). I also use—often
the claims I make about laı̈cité are both specific to France interchangeably—the terms headscarf (foulard in French) and veil

31
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

rather than hijab, following the language of my informants, who al- 14. Most Muslims who consider veiling a divine prescription
ternated between foulard and voile and rarely used the term hijab. point to two suras (chapters) of the Quran, Sura 24 (Surat an-Nur)
5. Killian (2007) describes the generational differences between and Sura 33 (Surat al-Ahzab). Sura 24:31 states: “And say to the be-
first- and second-generation Maghrebi-origin Muslims in France lieving women that they should lower their gaze and guard their
with regards to religious sensibilities and, especially, with regards modesty; . . . that they should draw their veils over their bosoms and
to veiling. not display their beauty except to their husbands, their fathers” [the
6. I employ the term second generation with caution, using it to Quran then lists all those before whom a woman may remain un-
mark these Muslims’ relationship to the Maghreb (rather than to veiled]. Sura 33:59 states: “Oh Prophet! Tell your wives and daugh-
France) and to distinguish them from first-generation immigrants ters, and the believing women, that they should cast their outer
(rather than from “native” French) who, having grown up in their garments over their persons . . . so that they shall be known and
countries of origin, often inhabit a different set of religious and po- not molested.” Unlike scholars such as Bowen (2006) and Winter
litical sensibilities, particularly with regards to their relationship to (2008), I have no interest in taking a position on whether or not
France (Killian 2006). In other words, I do not use “second genera- the obligation of veiling constitutes a correct interpretation of the
tion” to detract in any way from these citizens’ Frenchness, as can sources.
sometimes be the case in public and political discourse in France. 15. According to Mahmood, “The women I worked with did
7. Joan Scott alludes to this phenomenon in her discussion of the not regard trying to emulate authorized models of behavior as
headscarf law, noting that in their defense of the headscarf as an in- an external social imposition that constrained individual freedom.
dividual choice and, therefore, an individual right, Muslim French Rather, they treated socially authorized forms of performance as
women “at once invoked individualism in terms familiar to republi- the potentialities—the ground if you will—through which the self
can discourse and spiritual commitments that rest on a very differ- is realized” (2005:31). Of course, as I noted earlier, Muslim French
ent notion of individual choice” (2007:141). However, because her women valorize freedom in a way that their Egyptian counterparts
focus concerns republican discourse rather than the women them- do not and, therefore, imagine the relationship between freedom,
selves, she does not explore this intersection further. authority, and the self in a distinctly different way.
8. According to Dounia Bouzar (personal conversation, May 21, 16. I want to be clear that I am not claiming that headscarves
2004), the Renseignements Généraux estimates that 5 to 10 percent are never worn intentionally as signs meant to signal one’s Is-
of France’s Muslim population participates in some form of Islamic lamic identity to others, which has been the predominant analyt-
revivalism. ical frame for interpreting the headscarf both in France and else-
9. For more on the evolution of legal and political argumenta- where in the Muslim world (cf. Göle 1996; Moallem 2005; Moore
tion concerning the headscarf from 1989 to 2004, see Bowen 2006, 2007). I do, however, want to examine the headscarf as something
Eberhard et al. 2005, Laborde 2008, and Winter 2008. more than a sign, particularly because the majority of my infor-
10. Kathleen Moore (2007) and Katherine Pratt Ewing (2000) mants understand it primarily as an ethical practice. In fact, it is
have taken up the question of neutrality and the relationship be- precisely the hegemonic categorization of the headscarf as a sign
tween state and church(es) in their considerations of secularism that makes the kind of religiosity inhabited by many Muslim citi-
and religious freedom in France. I would hold, however, that con- zens unintelligible within public discourse and incommensurable
ceptions of state neutrality, and attendant notions of public and with certain exigencies of secular law. To expand the dominant an-
private, public order, and “legitimately religious” practices, rely on alytical framework beyond its semiotic basis is therefore to take a
prior assumptions about constraint and choice, authority and au- step, albeit a small one, in loosening the binds of public discourse
tonomy, and the relationship between belief and practice. on Muslim French women. For another critique of the veil as a sign,
11. This is, of course, a basic anthropological principle. With re- see Asad 2006.
gards to religious practices and religious sensibilities, Asad (1986), 17. Charles Hirschkind’s study of civic virtue and religious rea-
Bynum (1987, 1992), and Mahmood (2005), among others, have soning in Egypt comes to a parallel conclusion. Hirschkind con-
argued that religious practices cannot be understood without ref- tends that rational deliberation and religious discipline are not, as
erence to the underlying network of concepts that give them is often held, contradictory processes, but that in the piety move-
meaning. ment in Egypt, deliberation requires the cultivation of certain re-
12. Given that practices like veiling must be driven by one’s own ligious virtues through disciplinary practices like prayer, Quranic
desire, Muslim citizens argue that such practices must also be the recitation and memorization, hadith study, and da‘wa (2001:20).
result of active, reasoned, conscious choice and not the repetition 18. For a cogent analysis of the broader semiotic ideology of
of habitual actions, and that the practitioner must understand the laı̈cité, see Asad 2006.
reasons behind a practice—its doctrinal basis and its pragmatic or 19. Evans points out that this division “between belief and prac-
theological function—in order for the practice to be meaningful tice (the first being inviolable and the second open to limitation)
and effective. They thereby reaffirm a central feature of modern re- has become part of the orthodoxy of First Amendment case law” in
ligiosity (James 1999; Smith 1962) and of the contemporary Islamic the United States as well (2001:74).
revival (Deeb 2006; Eickelman and Piscatori 1996; Starrett 1998). 20. In her study of religious liberty in the European Convention
Moreover, given such a relation between intention and meaningful on Human Rights, Evans writes that the “necessity test” was first
practice, these young Muslims find it not only ethically problematic explicated in the commission’s 1978 Arrowsmith v. the United King-
(because no human being should be forced to do anything against dom decision, when it upheld the arrest of Pat Arrowsmith, a com-
her will) but also pragmatically useless to force anyone to pray, veil, mitted pacifist arrested for distributing leaflets to British soldiers
or fast. urging them not to accept a tour of duty in Northern Ireland. In that
13. In addition to new figures of authority (like Tariq Ramadan) decision, Evans writes, the commission “held that not all actions
who have not received the classical training of traditional ‘ulema, which are motivated by religion or belief are covered by the pro-
the latter have also retained their authoritative status in the Islamic tection in Article 9. . . . By excluding actions that are merely moti-
revival. In studying the scholarly position on veiling, Amira read vated or influenced by belief, the commission suggested that a very
both Ramadan as well as translations of work by traditional ‘alim direct link is needed between the belief and the action if the action
like Yusuf Qaradawi and Ali Shariati. is to be considered a ‘practice’ under Article 9” (Evans 2001:115). To

32
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

appeal for protection under Article 9, applicants must “show that Asad, Talal
they were required to act in a certain way because of their religion 1986 The Idea of an Anthropology of Islam. Washington, DC:
or belief” (2001:115). Center for Contemporary Arab Studies.
21. 100 Minutes Pour Comprendre, January 19, 2004, France 2. 1993 Genealogies of Religion. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univer-
22. This (mis)construal of “obligation” (as either compulsion sity Press.
or as incumbent on all) undergirds the argument, examined be- 2003 Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity.
low, that the headscarf constitutes an illegitimate form of social Stanford: Stanford University Press.
pressure on nonveiled women, thereby violating their freedom of 2006 Trying to Understand French Secularism. In Political The-
conscience. ologies. Hent de Vries, ed. Pp. 494–526. New York: Fordham
23. Like the Stasi Commission report itself (Commission de University Press.
Réflexion sur l’Application du Principe de Laı̈cité dans la Augé, Marc
République 2003), Weil never names “these groups.” 2004[2003] Entendre les voix de la laı̈cité. In La laı̈cité dévoilée:
24. “Le foulard à l’école; laı̈cité en danger?” on Ripostes, Chat Le Quinze années de débat en quarante “Rebonds” (Les dossiers
Monde (Lemonde.fr), October 10, 2003. Interestingly, the concep- de Libération). Jean-Michel Helvig, ed. Pp. 212–216. Paris:
tions of agency concomitant with the discourse of social pressure is Libération/Editions de l’aube.
highly gendered: while Franco-Maghrebi and Franco-African girls Baubérot, Jean
are thought to be particularly susceptible to the outside influences 2000 Histoire de la laı̈cité en France. Paris: Presses Universitaires
of a social milieu that ostensibly impinge on their agency and de France.
“real” desires, Susan Terrio (2009) has demonstrated how Franco- Bouzar, Dounia
Maghrebi and Franco-African male juvenile delinquents are in- 2004 “Monsieur Islam” n’existe pas. Paris: Hachette.
creasingly held to be fully responsible before the law for their crim- Bouzar, Dounia, and Saida Kada
inal actions. Where juvenile delinquency was once understood as 2003 L’une voilée, l’autre pas. Paris: Albin Michel.
the product of various factors—flawed parenting, bad influences, Bowen, John
teenage immaturity—courts, politicians, and police now ascribe 2006 Why the French Don’t Like Headscarves. Princeton: Prince-
conscious intention, even total responsibility, to the nonwhite male ton University Press.
juvenile offender. Butler, Judith
25. Sandel offers as an example the 1985 case of Thornton v. Cal- 1993 Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of “Sex.” New
dor, Inc., in which the U.S. Supreme Court struck down a Connecti- York: Routledge.
cut law that gave all workers the right to one day off each week but Bynum, Caroline Walker
guaranteed only Sabbath observers a right not to work on their Sab- 1987 Holy Feast and Holy Fast: The Religious Significance of Food
bath. The court found that “other employees who have strong and to Medieval Women. Berkeley: University of California Press.
legitimate, but nonreligious reasons for wanting a weekend day off 1992 Fragmentation and Redemption: Essays on Gender and the
have no rights under the statute” (in Sandel 1998:88). As Sandel ar- Human Body in Medieval Religion. New York: Zone.
gues, the court here “confuses the right to perform a duty with the Chouder, Ismahane, Malika Latrèche, and Pierre Tevanian
right to make a choice. Sabbath observers, by definition, do not se- 2008 Les filles voilées parlent. Paris: La Fabrique.
lect the day of the week they rest; they rest on the day their religion Commission de Réflexion sur l’Application du Principe de Laı̈cité
enjoins” (1998:88). In other words, the observance of Sabbath is not dans la République
the exercise of a choice but the performance of a duty, one that, for 2003 Laı̈cité et République (Rapport au Président de la
observant orthodox Jews and Seventh-Day Adventists, goes to the République). Paris: La Documentation Française.
very heart of what it means to be an observant Jew or Seventh-Day Deeb, Lara
Adventist. 2006 An Enchanted Modern: Gender and Public Piety in Shi‘i
26. In Les filles voilées parlent (The Veiled Girls Speak) and Des Lebanon. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
filles comme les autres (Ordinary Girls), women who were forced to Dif, Malika
unveil in schools speak of feeling humiliated, exposed, and phys- 1999 Être musulmane aujourd’hui. Lyon: Tawhid.
ically and psychically violated, feelings that were reiterated in a Durkheim, Emile
number of personal conversations during fieldwork. See Chouder 1961[1903] Moral Education: A Study in the Theory and Applica-
et al. 2008 and Lévy and Lévy 2004. tion of the Sociology of Education. Everett K. Wilson and Her-
27. Rousseau (1988) was one of the earliest republican thinkers man Schnurer, trans. New York: Free Press of Glencoe.
to grapple with this problem of “how to make men what they ought Eberhard, Christophe, Mayanthi Fernando, and Nawel Gafsia
to be” without depriving them of their freedom. 2005 Droit, laı̈cité et diversité culturelle. L’État français face
28. Another very similar example is the European Commission’s au défi du pluralisme. Revue Interdisciplinaire d’Études Ju-
1978 Arrowsmith v. the United Kingdom decision; for more on that ridiques 54:129–169.
decision, see N. 20. Evans 2001 also cites a number of other compa- Edge, Peter W.
rable cases decided by the European Court or European Commis- 2000 Law and Religion in Contemporary Society: Communities,
sion on Human Rights, namely X v. the United Kingdom, Valsami v. Individualism and the State. Burlington, VT: Aldershot.
Greece, Efstratiou v. Greece, and Kokkinakis v. Greece. Eickelman, Dale F., and Jon Anderson
1997 Print, Islam, and the Prospects for Civic Pluralism: New Reli-
gious Writings and Their Audiences. Journal of Islamic Studies
References cited 8(1):43–62.
Eickelman, Dale F., and James Piscatori
Althusser, Louis 1996 Muslim Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
1971 Ideological State Apparatuses. In Lenin and Philosophy Evans, Carolyn
and Other Essays. Ben Brewster, trans. Pp. 127–186. New York: 2001 Freedom of Religion under the European Convention on
Monthly Review. Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

33
American Ethnologist  Volume 37 Number 1 February 2010

Ewing, Katherine Pratt tion of Religion in France. Sociology of Religion 68(3):305–


2000 Legislating Religious Freedom: Muslim Challenges to the 320.
Relationship between “Church” and “State” in Germany and Kintzler, Catherine, Pierre-André Taguieff, Bernard Tepe, and
France. Daedalus 129(4):31–54. Michèle Tribalat
Fassin, Didier, and Eric Fassin 2004[2003] Contre tout signe religieux à l’école. In La laı̈cité
2006 De la question sociale à la question raciale? Representer la dévoilée: Quinze années de débat en quarante “Rebonds” (Les
societé française. Paris: La Découverte. dossiers de Libération). Jean-Michel Helvig, ed. Pp. 36–39.
Foucault, Michel Paris: Libération/Editions de l’aube.
1978 The History of Sexuality: An Introduction. Robert Hurley, Laborde, Cécile
trans. New York: Pantheon. 2008 Critical Republicanism: The Hijab Controversy and Political
1991 Governmentality. In The Foucault Effect: Studies in Govern- Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
mentality. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller, Laı̈di, Zaki
eds. Pp. 87–104. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 2004[2003] Laı̈cité: Le bon choix de Chirac. In La laı̈cité dévoilée:
Gaspard, Françoise, and Farhad Khosrokhavar Quinze années de débat en quarante “Rebonds” (Les dossiers
1995 Le foulard et la République. Paris: Seuil. de Libération). Jean-Michel Helvig, ed. Pp. 156–162. Paris:
Gauchet, Marcel Libération/Editions de l’aube.
1997 The Disenchantment of the World: A Political History of Lévy, Alma, and Lila Lévy
Religion. Oscar Burge, trans. Princeton: Princeton University 2004 Des filles comme les autres. Paris: La Découverte.
Press. Long, Marceau, and Patrick Weil
1998 La religion dans la démocratie. Paris: Gallimard. 2004[2003] La laı̈cité en voie d’adaptation. In La laı̈cité dévoilée:
Göle, Nilufer Quinze années de débat en quarante “Rebonds” (Les dossiers
1996 The Forbidden Modern: Civilization and Veiling. Ann Arbor: de Libération). Jean-Michel Helvig, ed. Pp. 85–90. Paris:
University of Michigan Press. Libération/Editions de l’aube.
Halimi, Gisèle Mahmood, Saba
2003 Légiférer, pour que gagne le droit. Le Monde 2, November: 2005 Politics of Piety: The Feminist Subject and the Islamic Re-
66. vival. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Haq, Maimuna Moallem, Minoo
2008 Reading the Qur’an in Bangladesh: The Politics of “Belief” 2005 Between Warrior Brother and Veiled Sister: Islamic Funda-
among Islamist Women. Modern Asian Studies 42(2–3):457– mentalism and the Politics of Patriarchy in Iran. Berkeley: Uni-
488. versity of California Press.
Hargreaves, Alec G. Moore, Kathleen M.
1997 Immigration, “Race” and Ethnicity in Contemporary 2007 Visible through the Veil: The Regulation of Is-
France. London: Routledge. lam in American Law. Sociology of Religion 68(3):237–
Hirschkind, Charles 251.
2001 Civic Virtue and Religious Reason: An Islamic Counterpub- Naseef, Fatima
lic. Cultural Anthropology 16(1):3–34. 1999 Droits et devoirs de la femme en islam. Lyon: Tawhid.
2006 The Ethical Soundscape: Cassette Sermons and Islamic Noiriel, Gérard
Counterpublics. New York: Columbia University Press. 1996 The French Melting Pot. Minneapolis: University of Min-
Jakobsen, Janet R., and Ann Pellegrini nesota Press.
2008a Introduction: Times like These. In Secularisms. Janet R. Povinelli, Elizabeth A.
Jakobsen and Ann Pellegrini, eds. Pp. 1–35. Durham, NC: Duke 2002 The Cunning of Recognition: Indigenous Alterities and the
University Press. Making of Australian Multiculturalism. Durham, NC: Duke
Jakobsen, Janet R., and Ann Pellegrini, eds. University Press.
2008b Secularisms. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Ramadan, Tariq
James, William 2004 Western Muslims and the Future of Islam. Oxford: Oxford
1999[1902] The Varieties of Religious Experience. New York: Ran- University Press.
dom House. Rojtman, Suzy, Maya Surduts, and Josette Trat
Jouili, Jeanette S., and Schirin Amir-Moazami 2004 Contre le racisme et pour les femmes. Libération (January
2006 Knowledge, Empowerment and Religious Authority among 27). http://eleuthera.free.fr/html/232.htm, accessed October
Pious Muslim Women in France and Germany. Muslim World 16, 2009.
96:617–642. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques
Keane, Webb 1988[1755] Discourse on Political Economy. In Rousseau’s Politi-
2007 Christian Moderns: Freedom and Fetish in the Mission En- cal Writings. Alan Ritter, ed. Pp. 58–83. New York: W. W. Norton.
counter. Berkeley: University of California Press. Roy, Olivier
Keaton, Trica Danielle 1999 Vers un islam européen. Paris: Esprit.
2006 Muslim Girls and the Other France: Race, Identity Politics, 2007 Secularism Confronts Islam. New York: Columbia Univer-
and Social Exclusion. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. sity Press.
Khosrokhavar, Farhad Sandel, Michael J.
1997 L’islam des jeunes. Paris: Flammarion. 1998 Religious Liberty: Freedom of Choice or Freedom of Con-
Killian, Caitlin science? In Secularism and Its Critics. Rajeev Bhargava, ed. Pp.
2006 North African Women in France: Gender, Culture, and Iden- 73–93. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
tity. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Sarr, Felwine
2007 From a Community of Believers to an Islam of the Heart: 2003 Le port du voile: Un rapport à sa propre corporalité.
“Conspicuous” Symbols, Muslim Practices, and the Privatiza- Oumma.com, December 18. http://oumma.com/article.

34
Reconfiguring freedom  American Ethnologist

php3?id article=826&var recherche=Felwine+Sarr, accessed Touraine, Alain


December 19. 2005 Un nouveau paradigme: Pour comprendre le monde au-
Scott, Joan jourd’hui. Paris: Fayard.
2007 The Politics of the Veil. Princeton: Princeton University Venel, Nancy
Press. 2004 Musulmans et citoyens. Paris: Presses Universitaires de
Silverstein, Paul France.
2004 Algeria in France: Transpolitics, Race, Nation. Bloomington: Weber, Eugen
Indiana University Press. 1976 Peasants into Frenchmen: The Modernization of Rural
Smith, Wilfred Cantwell France, 1870–1914. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
1962 The Meaning and End of Religion: A New Approach to the Weil, Patrick
Religious Traditions of Mankind. New York: Macmillan. 2004 Lifting the Veil. French Politics, Culture and Society
Starrett, Gregory 22(3):142–149.
1998 Putting Islam to Work: Education, Politics, and Religious Wieviorka, Michel
Transformation in Egypt. Berkeley: University of California 1997 Culture, société, démocratie. In Une société fragmentée: Le
Press. multiculturalisme en débat. Michel Wieviorka, ed. Pp. 11–60.
Sullivan, Winnifred Fallers Paris: La Découverte–Poche.
2007 The Impossibility of Religous Freedom. Princeton: Prince- Winter, Bronwyn
ton University Press. 2008 Hijab and the Republic: Uncovering the French Headscarf
Surkis, Judith Debate. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
2006 Sexing the Citizen: Morality and Masculinity in France,
1870–1920. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Taylor, Charles accepted August 20, 2009
2002 Varieties of Religion Today. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni- final version submitted September 7, 2009
versity Press.
2007 A Secular Age. Cambridge, MA: Belknap. Mayanthi L. Fernando
Terrio, Susan J. University of California, Santa Cruz
2009 Judging Mohammed: Juvenile Delinquency, Immigration, Department of Anthropology
and Exclusion at the Paris Palace of Justice. Stanford: Stanford Social Science 1
University Press. University of California
Tietze, Nikola Santa Cruz, CA 95064
2002 Jeunes musulmans de France et d’Allemagne. Paris:
L’Harmattan. mfernan3@ucsc.edu

35

You might also like