Robust Immoralism

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

A. W.

EATON

Robust Immoralism

Several years after the end of the HBO series The Not only am I pleased “to find the limits of vice
Sopranos, I still miss the characters. In particu- and virtue so much confounded,” but I deliber-
lar, I miss the protagonist, Tony, who feels like an ately pursue this peculiar form of pleasure.
old friend. This affection of mine for the fictional What does this say about me and the many
mob boss gives me pause. After all, Tony Soprano other lovers of rough heroes? Perhaps that we
is a murderer, a liar, a thief, an extortionist, and have a dark side that these works elicit. Or maybe
a womanizer; he is pathologically callous, selfish, that we have especially flexible and expansive
bigoted, racist, homophobic, and self-centered. So imaginations that allow us to put ourselves in the
why do I sympathize with him? Why do I admire shoes of others whose ethical views differ starkly
him? What makes me like him so much? from our own.
David Hume famously wrote: I argue that this phenomenon reveals less about
the audience than it does about the artworks.
What it reveals is a peculiar sort of aesthetic
where vicious manners are described, without being
achievement that has its basis in the immorality
marked with the proper characters of blame and disap-
of the work in question. In a nutshell, I argue that
probation; this must be allowed to disfigure the poem,
the capacity to make an audience feel and de-
and to be a real deformity. I cannot, nor is it proper I
sire things inimical to their considered views and
should, enter into such sentiments; and however I may
deeply held principles is for this very reason and
excuse the poet, on account of the manners of his age,
to this extent an aesthetic achievement. In this
I never can relish the composition. . . . We are not in-
way, moral flaws of a particular kind can make
terested in the fortunes and sentiments of such rough
a significant contribution to a work’s aesthetic
heroes: We are displeased to find the limits of vice and
value.
virtue so much confounded: And . . . we cannot prevail
My account, which offers new arguments and
on ourselves to enter into his sentiments, or bear an af-
evidence for the immoralist position first pro-
fection to characters, which we plainly discover to be
posed by Daniel Jacobson, proceeds as follows.3
blameable.1
Section I makes a new distinction between two
very different forms that an artwork’s immorality
Insofar as Hume intends an empirical claim, he can take. Section II develops the Humean con-
is wrong. I—and I am hardly alone here—can cept of the rough hero and gives an account of the
and sometimes do enter into the vicious sen- moral flaw that attends vivid portrayals of these
timents of fictional characters, and I do some- heroes. Section III examines the role of imagi-
times bear a strong affection for characters whom native resistance in moralism and in criticisms of
I plainly consider blameworthy.2 I am charmed moralism. Section IV explains how the particu-
by Humbert Humbert and revere Milton’s lar sort of moral flaw previously outlined can be a
Satan. I delight in the exploits of Bonnie and Clyde significant aesthetic achievement and specifies the
and their contemporary incarnations, Mickey and conditions under which this is so. Section V con-
Mallory, rooting for them as they flee the po- cludes by showing how my view improves upon ar-
lice. I am enamored of Tyler Durden and admire guments for immoralism by Matthew Kieran and
Hannibal Lecter, even in their darkest moments. Jacobson.

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 70:3 Summer 2012


c 2012 The American Society for Aesthetics

282 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

i. two kinds of immorality A work can prompt an attitudinal response


without actually succeeding in producing that re-
Recent conversations in the philosophy of art sponse. This is because prompts are context de-
about the relationship between ethical and aes- pendent in the sense that what serves as a cue for,
thetic value often appear to take for granted the say, fear can vary diachronically and synchroni-
very notion that artworks are candidates for moral cally. A particular diegetic element (or feature of
assessment in the first place. Moral judgments are a diegetic element) can be expected to elicit a par-
directed primarily at persons and actions, but art- ticular type of attitude only for the work’s target
works, after all, are inanimate. The fact that art- audience—the audience addressed by the work—
works often represent persons and actions does and suitably similar audiences. The very same fea-
not solve the difficulty, since a moral judgment ture’s failure to elicit that type of attitude in audi-
directed at a work’s content is distinct from one ences other than the target audience should not be
directed at the work itself. For instance, Goya’s fa- taken to mean that the feature is an unsuccessful
mous painting, Third of May, 1808 (1814, Museo prompt (or not a prompt for that type of attitude
del Prado, Madrid), depicts something appalling at all).
but is not itself an appalling painting. How, if at To sum up, an artwork’s perspective makes it a
all, can an artwork itself be the proper object of legitimate candidate for moral concern, and this
moral judgment and concern? perspective is manifest in the attitudes the work
There are several different ways to answer this prescribes to its audience. Consider these con-
question. One might locate a work’s moral va- trasting cases. Dickens’s novel David Copperfield
lence in its effects on its audience, in the artist’s and The Sopranos both portray immoral charac-
intentions, or in the conditions under which the ters: Uriah Heep and Tony Soprano, respectively.
work was produced. Since it is not the point of Heep’s character is imbued with vivid prompts for
this article to argue against these positions, I sim- disgust and repulsion: he is portrayed as clammy,
ply gesture at the reasons why each is unsatisfac- slimy, and writhing. In this way, the novel offers a
tory: the first, because a work can be misused in disapproving perspective of a morally blamewor-
ways that ought not redound to its discredit; the thy character, and herein lies the novel’s morally
second, because it accords too much authority to upstanding valence. The character of Soprano, by
artistic intention; the last, because the conditions contrast, is given many prompts for admiration,
of production need not morally taint the product sympathy, and affection: he is portrayed as savvy,
itself. charismatic, bold, daring, and resolute, to name
A more promising approach, recently pursued only a few. In this way, The Sopranos adopts an
by Noël Carroll and Berys Gaut, among others, approving perspective of its protagonist, even as
locates moral valence in a work’s perspective.4 he commits heinous crimes. In the words of the
By ‘perspective’ one means the work’s evalua- Motion Picture Production Code of the 1930s (also
tive attitude toward diegetic elements (elements known as the Hays Code), The Sopranos “throw[s]
of the world represented), such as persons, ac- our sympathy to the side of crime, wrongdoing, or
tions, events, and situations. Although ‘perspec- evil.”6 Insofar as The Sopranos endorses a morally
tive’ might sound overly mentalistic, it can be blameworthy character, the series is morally de-
explained without either attributing mental states fective. I argue, however, that this moral defect is
to artworks or deferring to the psychology of at the same time an aesthetic achievement.
artists. An artwork manifests a perspective toward I begin to make this case by drawing a distinc-
one or more diegetic elements by prescribing to its tion between two very different forms that an art-
audience attitudes toward these elements.5 ‘Atti- work’s moral valence can take. I say that moral
tude’ is meant to be vague in order to capture judgment is extrinsic to a work just in case moral
propositional attitudes, emotions, and other af- judgment is not a component of the work’s per-
fective responses. A work prescribes an attitude spective—that is, moral judgment is not among the
toward diegetic elements by imbuing them with responses prescribed by the work—but this per-
traits that are prompts for the attitude in ques- spective is nevertheless subject to second-order
tion, where a prompt is a feature (or set of fea- moral approval or disapproval. Consider, for in-
tures) that aims to stimulate and elicit a particular stance, Titian’s Rape of Europa, a painting that
type of attitude under appropriate circumstances. prescribes an erotic response to, and in other ways
Eaton Robust Immoralism 283

endorses, rape.7 Although we today consider rape condemnation of the bombing of innocents, Lolita
morally reprehensible, the painting itself does not is intrinsically immoral in its sympathetic and com-
invite moral disapproval of Europa’s rape. (We mending perspective of a pedophilic rapist; one
are not, it should be noted, the painting’s target whom, I hasten to add, we are supposed to see as a
audience.) But nor does the painting invite moral pedophilic rapist. This is an important difference:
approval of the event depicted; rather, taking the whereas Rape of Europa is not supposed to be
painting on its own terms means suspending moral immoral from the perspective of its target audi-
judgment of any sort altogether.8 This is not to say ence, yet happens to be immoral from a contem-
that moral judgment is misplaced in such cases, porary perspective, Lolita is supposed to be im-
but it does mean that when we bring our twenty- moral from the perspective of its target audience.
first century moral concerns to bear in this way, Only in the latter case, I shall argue, can a moral
it should be done with the awareness that we are flaw of the sort outlined here also be an aesthetic
disregarding the work’s perspective. virtue.
Moral judgment is intrinsic to a work, by con-
trast, just in case moral judgment is among the
responses prescribed by the work; that is, when ii. the rough hero
moral judgment is a component of the work’s per-
spective. Taking such a work on its own terms I begin to make the case that a moral flaw can
means making moral judgments about characters, be an aesthetic merit in a work—that is, that an
actions, or other diegetic elements. Two examples immoral feature of an artwork can make a signif-
illustrate the different forms that this can take. icant positive aesthetic contribution precisely in
First, it is a requirement of properly understand- virtue of its immorality—by developing the con-
ing and appreciating Picasso’s Guernica that the cept of the rough hero mentioned by Hume in the
viewer feel moral outrage at the fascist bombing passage quoted at the start of this article. I argue
of the Basque village represented in the paint- that the rough hero is a distinct character type that
ing. If the painting left you feeling morally neu- sheds new and surprising light on the question of
tral about the events depicted or, worse, if it led the aesthetic value of immoral art.
you to approve of them, then you would have en- To get a sharp sense of characteristic markers
tirely missed the point of the painting and, fur- of the rough hero, it will be useful to contrast it
ther, would be unable to appreciate some of its with a similar and more familiar character type,
most artistically valuable features.9 Second, it is namely, the antihero. As the name suggests, the
also a requirement of properly understanding and antihero lacks traditional heroic qualities like con-
fully appreciating Vladimir Nabokov’s Lolita that viction, courage, physical prowess, or intelligence.
one judge Humbert to be morally reprehensible. Further, the antihero is plagued by human frailties
If the reader for whatever reason were left feel- such as weakness, arrogance, cowardice, doubt,
ing morally neutral about Humbert or, worse, if envy, indolence, or stupidity. (Consider, for ex-
she morally approved of him, then she would not ample, Don Quixote.) But these flaws do not fa-
only miss the point of the book, but would also tally condemn the antihero in the audience’s eyes.
miss one of its major artistic achievements, or so I This is because the flaws are (a) mild in the grand
argue. scheme of things, (b) peripheral to the core of the
Despite obvious differences in medium and hero’s personality, (c) forgivable or at least excul-
genre, Guernica and Lolita are similar in that pable (because, for instance, they result from some
moral judgment is intrinsic to both; specifically, wrong done to her in the past), and (d) outweighed
each work manifests a perspective that prescribes by some virtue(s) that the antihero possesses. As
moral disapproval of central diegetic elements. Carroll puts it: “no matter how anti-social the
The works are importantly dissimilar, however, [antihero] appears at first glance, he or she is
in their overall perspectives: whereas Guernica quickly revealed to be pro-social at heart. More-
wholeheartedly condemns the horrific scene it de- over, this is how it should be if sympathy is to
picts, Lolita simultaneously undermines its con- take hold across a diverse audience whose like-
demnation of Humbert by making him likeable, liest point of convergence is apt to be morality,
sympathetic, and even admirable. So, whereas very generously construed.”10 We return to this
Guernica is intrinsically morally laudable in its last point about sympathy shortly.
284 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

The rough hero is like the antihero in that he Süskind, Das Parfum, 1985), Hannibal Lecter
is also a flawed protagonist. But unlike the anti- as played on-screen by Anthony Hopkins, and
hero, the rough hero’s flaws are, first, grievous: Dexter Morgan from the Showtime series Dexter.
he is usually a sociopath, an outlaw, a murderer, The likeable sex criminal includes rapists and
a sex criminal, a sadist, or Satan incarnate. Sec- child molesters. The most famous example is the
ond, the rough hero’s flaws are an integral part of charismatic and seductive Humbert (Lolita, 1955),
his personality rather than peripheral failings or whose intelligence, wit, and rhetorical gifts lure us
foibles. Even his intellectual virtues—for example, into liking and sympathizing with him and con-
his cunning and shrewdness, his precise execution doning his actions. Other examples include Sade’s
of well-laid plans, and his ability to outsmart ad- four protagonists in The 120 Days of Sodom (1785)
versaries—are inextricably tied to his morally bad and Benigno in Talk to Her (Pedro Almodóvar,
character. He is at the core a sociopath who dis- 2002).13
plays a pervasive pattern of disregard for the rights The sympathetic sadist is a group that includes
and feelings of others. Third, the rough hero often Alex from A Clockwork Orange (Stanley Kubrick,
fully intends to do bad and is remorseless about 1971); the torturers of Sade’s so-called libertine
his crimes. Fourth, the audience’s forgiveness is novels: Justine, Juliette, and Philosophy in the Bed-
not prescribed, nor are we offered reasons to dis- room; and Patrick Bateman from American Psy-
miss his misdeeds as the result misfortune, weak- cho (Bret Easton Ellis, 1991, and the film directed
ness, folly, or ignorance. Finally, the rough hero’s by Mary Harron, 2000).14
vices are not outweighed by some more redeem- The appealing mean-spirited person includes
ing virtues; although he is not entirely bereft of protagonists who are manipulative, petty, self-
such virtues—more on this in a minute—they far ish, ill-tempered, duplicitous, malicious, or cruel:
from surpass his vices in gravity or importance. Becky Sharp of Vanity Fair (William Makepeace
Here are some examples of types of rough hero. Thackeray, 1848), Heathcliff of Wuthering Heights
The admirable devil is arguably the oldest vari- (Emily Brontë, 1847), and the Underground Man
ation of the rough hero type appearing in Milton’s from Notes from Underground (Fyodor Dosto-
Paradise Lost (first edition 1668), a work that, de- evsky, 1864).
spite its stated purpose, prescribes our wonder, The list is admittedly incomplete, but it never-
reverential admiration, and respect for the grand theless captures the variety and depth of the rough
but evil being.11 Other sympathetic or admirable hero type. Despite significant differences between
devils include some versions of Mephistopheles the works just mentioned, in each case the audi-
in the Faust legends and Woland in Nikhail Bul- ence is supposed to be acutely aware of the protag-
gakov’s The Master and Margarita (1941), which onist’s profound and irredeemable moral flaws.
was likely an inspiration for The Rolling Stones’s This is one important mark of the rough hero:
“Sympathy for the Devil” (Beggar’s Banquet, to use a concept developed earlier, he is intrin-
1968).12 sically immoral. This means that the failure to
The glorified criminal includes gangsters, gun- morally condemn the rough hero, at least on the
slinging cowboys, bank robbers, and drug dealers. one hand, would mislead the audience’s intellec-
Consider, for example, Bonnie and Clyde (Arthur tual and emotional engagement with the work. For
Penn, 1967) and their contemporary incarnations, instance, an unrepentant pedophile who admired
Mickey and Mallory from Natural Born Killers Humbert and his exploits would miss the narra-
(Oliver Stone, 1994), Michael Corleone from The tive mode in which the novel is written, namely
Godfather trilogy (Francis Ford Coppola, 1972, unreliable narration.15 (A different way of putting
1974, 1990), Omar Little from the HBO series the point is that unrepentant pedophiles are not
The Wire, Gus Fring from the AMC series Break- Lolita’s target audience.) In cases where the rough
ing Bad, Vincent and Jules from Pulp Fiction hero is not the narrator, such as The Sopranos,
(Quentin Tarantino, 1994), William Munny in Un- the audience who found no moral fault with him
forgiven (Clint Eastwood, 1992), many characters would also fail to “get” the work because they
in Sergio Leone’s so-called spaghetti westerns, would fail to find it difficult to have the prescribed
and, of course, Tony Soprano. positive affective responses toward the protago-
The congenial murderer includes charac- nist; in other words, it would be too easy for such
ters such as Jean-Baptiste Grenouille (Patrick an audience to like the rough hero. Since, as I
Eaton Robust Immoralism 285

argue below, overcoming the audience’s imagina- hero. Rather, the point I am making is conceptual
tive resistance is a major artistic achievement of and normative: just as we must be vividly aware
works in which the rough hero appears, the audi- of the rough hero’s depravity in order to “get”
ence who failed to condemn the rough hero would the work in which he appears, so we must also,
miss out on these works’ remarkable achievement. as Hume puts it, “take an interest in [his] fortunes
It is not enough, then, to merely recognize that the and sentiments” in order to be properly invested in
rough hero is morally condemnable in the eyes of the work. If, for instance, I simply despised Tony
other characters; we the audience must condemn Soprano and desired his downfall, then I would
him ourselves in order to understand and appre- not root for him in key chase scenes and would
ciate the work in which he appears. feel disappointment rather than relief when he
But this is far from the whole story. Although narrowly escapes from the FBI; that is, my emo-
the rough hero is supposed to be morally hate- tional engagement would be misaligned in a way
ful, he is also supposed to be a hero; that is, that would yield fundamental misunderstandings
a sympathetic, likeable, and admirable protago- of the work.
nist. Many techniques achieve this effect. First,
the rough hero is often vividly imbued with hu-
manizing and idealizing traits. For instance, the iii. moralism and imaginative resistance
rough hero can be affectionate, caring, and loyal
toward family, friends, children, or animals; he We have just seen that proper engagement with
can be suave, charming, and charismatic, features works featuring rough heroes demands that the
that are enhanced in moving images by the use of audience adopt conflicting attitudes, finding him
magnetic and often sexually attractive actors; he simultaneously agreeable and abhorrent, likeable
can be highly learned, intelligent, perceptive, and and repugnant, congenial and malevolent. Tak-
shrewd; he is often witty, funny, or affable.16 Sec- ing their cue from Hume, who thought that this
ond, the rough hero’s standing can be improved redounds to a work’s aesthetic discredit, modern-
by sharp contrast with enemies who are made out day moralists like Carroll and Gaut argue that
to be unlikeable and often more immoral than works of the sort under discussion here are aes-
the rough hero himself (for example, Clare Quilty thetically marred, not simply because of the dis-
of Lolita or Ralph Cifaretto of The Sopranos). cord at the heart of their principal character,
Third, in some cases, the rough hero has a quasi- but importantly because of the unwarranted re-
moral code to which he rigidly adheres: for ex- sponses the work prescribes.
ample, Dexter Morgan’s “Code of Harry,” Tony Since the argument for moralism is familiar, I
Soprano’s “rules,” Omar’s (The Wire) refusal to offer only a brief summary.19 We begin with the
“turn his gun on a citizen” (that is, on someone observation that representational artworks often
who is not involved in the drug trade). Finally, prescribe responses to diegetic elements. Failure
not only are we made to take the rough hero’s to warrant a prescribed response is one kind of
side, to want him to commit crimes, and to take aesthetic defect; for instance, the thriller that does
a strange satisfaction in his morally repugnant not warrant a sudden and sharp feeling of excite-
deeds, but our sympathies are also turned against ment fails to this extent and on its own terms. Some
the forces of good. Consider, for instance, Bonnie artworks are morally flawed in the sense that they
and Clyde (Arthur Penn, 1967) where the police prescribe responses that we have good moral rea-
are made out to be foolish, inept, and corrupt. son to reject; works featuring rough heroes, for
It is not surprising that at the film’s Hollywood instance, prescribe approbatory feelings toward a
premier, at the point where Bonnie and Clyde are morally unworthy character. Such a work is aes-
gunned down, one viewer reportedly stood up and thetically flawed, so the argument goes, in that it
loudly yelled, “Fucking cops!”17 These are just a prescribes a response that is unwarranted, and in
few of the techniques by which we are lured— this way the work itself gives us good reason to
or as Lionel Trilling puts it, seduced—into feeling eschew a response upon which the work’s own
not just fondness and concern, but also admira- aesthetic success depends. Rather than conclude
tion and respect, for an abhorrent and malevolent that all moral defects are aesthetic flaws, moralists
character.18 restrict their claim to only this particular sort of
Note that this is not an empirical claim about moral flaw, namely, prescribing a response that is
how actual audiences in fact respond to the rough unwarranted on moral grounds.
286 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Jacobson, drawing on his work with Justin oxygen mask). It would be wrong to deny that such
D’Arms, makes a trenchant criticism of this argu- a painting was visually beautiful—that is, to deny
ment that has not been sufficiently appreciated.20 that it warranted visual pleasure—despite the fact
They convincingly show that moralism conflates that the painting possessed elements inhibiting vi-
two importantly distinct ways in which a senti- sual pleasure. Similarly, a moral flaw might impede
mental response to an object, in this case a work access to a work’s aesthetically praiseworthy fea-
of art, can be warranted (or unwarranted). First, tures, but the praiseworthy features would remain
a response can be warranted in the sense that it appreciable by anyone willing and able to over-
fits its object; that is, when the object possesses look the moral blemishes. Moralism shows only
the evaluative features that the response correctly that a work’s aesthetically praiseworthy features
tracks. (Likewise, a response would be unwar- can be rendered inaccessible by its moral flaws,
ranted when it fails to fit its object.) Second, in a not that a work’s moral flaws yield or amount to
distinct sense, a response to an object can be war- aesthetic blemishes.
ranted because it would be the right response to Moralism may have a way around this problem.
have for reasons unrelated to whether the object As Jacobson and D’Arms themselves note, some,
possesses features picked out by that response; for though not all, emotions have a “moral shape”:
example, for prudential or moral reasons. In such for example, basic emotions like contempt, anger,
instances, the sense in which a response is war- and guilt, to which I would add affective responses
ranted and so appropriate (or unwarranted and so like affection and disaffection, sympathy and an-
inappropriate) is logically distinct from epistemic tipathy, and admiration.24 An affective state has
concerns about whether the work possesses the a “moral shape” just in case moral features of its
features that the response picks out. It can be true object can legitimately be invoked to support or
both that I have a reason (prudential or moral) not contest its fittingness. For instance, moral flaws in
to be amused by a play and that the play possesses a person (whether real or fictional) can make her
features correctly picked out by the response of unworthy of affection, admiration, and sympathy
amusement. Conflating these two kinds of reason, and, if the flaws are grievous enough, legitimately
as moralists do, falls prey to what Jacobson and warrant antipathy, contempt, anger, and disaffec-
D’Arms call the moralistic fallacy: a faulty infer- tion. Taking this as a starting point, the moralist
ence from the claim that it is morally wrong to might concede, as I think he must, that while the
have a given emotional response toward some ob- immorality of a joke does not make it less funny,
ject to the claim that the response does not fit that the immorality of a personage (whether fictional
object.21 Without this inference, the argument for or not) can make her less sympathetic and like-
moralism collapses. able, and even render her contemptible and an-
The moralist might protest that her argument tipathetic.25 In the cases where we are prescribed
does not rest simply on this inference. Rather, the to feel sympathy, admiration, or affection for such
idea is that when a prescribed response does not a character—that is, a character who does not merit
obtain, and this failure is due to some intrinsic fea- these responses precisely because she is immoral—
ture of the work, the work is in this respect and to the work would fail to merit on moral grounds
this extent aesthetically marred.22 the very responses that it itself prescribes. This
But this qualification does not circumvent Ja- is the conclusion that the moralist wants, though its
cobson’s objection, for even an intrinsic obsta- scope would be considerably diminished (it would
cle can be irrelevant to the response’s fittingness. not apply to, for instance, jokes).26
To see how, imagine a visually beautiful paint- But what does this rejoinder mean for my ac-
ing made of putrid materials emitting an intol- count of the rough hero, which holds that we are
erably nauseating stench.23 Such a painting would made to feel sympathy, admiration, and affection
be almost completely inaccessible to anyone with for a character not only despite but sometimes
sound olfaction, but this would not mean that even because of his immorality? The appearance
the painting was therefore less visually beautiful. of conflict between my account and this restricted
Although the stench would block access to the form of moralism disappears once one notices that
painting’s visual beauty, the work’s visual features the affective responses in question have a partially,
would remain untouched, appreciable by anyone rather than a wholly, moral shape.27 Although, as
who could skirt the stench (perhaps by wearing an has been observed since Aristotle, moral virtue
Eaton Robust Immoralism 287

in a character strongly tends to garner the audi- come this substantial imaginative resistance and
ence’s sympathy, admiration, or affection, moral make the audience feel something that it resists
virtue does not suffice to garner these (nor does feeling on moral grounds.
moral depravity suffice to incite their contraries). It takes considerable artistry and finesse to
Although a character’s moral viciousness strongly meet this challenge. The character must be con-
tends to generate imaginative resistance on the au- vincingly monstrous or depraved yet simultane-
dience’s part to sympathy, affection, benevolence, ously likeable, sympathetic, and even admirable.
or admiration for the character, this imaginative For instance, foregrounding Humbert’s perver-
resistance can be overcome in certain rare cases.28 sion and brutality too much, perhaps by including
The rough hero, I argue in the next section, is one graphic sex scenes, would sabotage his charm, like-
such case. ability, and sympathetic nature. However, mini-
Before we proceed, there are two points worth mizing Humbert’s flaws too much would render
making about the sort of morally motivated imagi- him benign. Thus, a delicate equilibrium must
native resistance of interest here. First, I here con- be struck between the sympathetic and the mon-
strue imaginative resistance as reluctance, rather strous, the attractive and the vile, the comfort-
than inability, to engage in a prescribed imagi- ing and the disturbing, the praiseworthy and the
native activity that is, from the audience’s per- abhorrent.
spective, morally deviant. Second, it is rarely In saying that the rough hero overcomes our
noted that morally motivated imaginative resis- imaginative resistance, I mean ‘overcome’ in
tance admits of degrees: the more abhorrent the something like the Hegelian sense of aufheben:
character, the greater our resistance to liking, ad- imaginative resistance is generated and sur-
miring, or sympathizing with her. mounted but in a way that nevertheless keeps that
resistance in play so that we continually feel its
pull. In this way, the rough hero trades on our
iv. a peculiar sort of aesthetic achievement moral convictions while simultaneously turning us
against them, thereby putting us in conflict with
I have thus far isolated the specific kind of moral ourselves.
defect attending the character type I call the rough The second dimension of the rough hero’s
hero. This moral defect is not the mere repre- aesthetic achievement is that this state of dividing-
sentation of morally corrupt characters and their ourselves-against-ourselves that such works in-
despicable actions; rather, works featuring rough duce in their audience is aesthetically valuable.
heroes are morally flawed in virtue of their per- Unlike purely pleasurable aesthetic states, this
spective that endorses moral depravity by ren- is a state of conflict and strife that is tinged
dering it sympathetic, likeable, praiseworthy, and with displeasure due to the contradictory attitudes
glamorous. I now argue that a moral defect of this elicited. We are torn between our positive feel-
sort can be a significant aesthetic achievement of ings for the rough hero, on the one hand, and
two related sorts. our strong disapproval of him, on the other. This
First, the rough hero type sets up and then skill- tension cannot be resolved by noting that the con-
fully solves an ambitious and artistically interest- tradictory attitudes attend to different parts of the
ing problem: namely, to overcome the audience’s character—as in, “I like him in this respect but de-
imaginative resistance. In order to do this, the spise him in a totally different respect”—because,
rough hero must generate the imaginative resis- as noted earlier, the rough hero’s moral flaws are
tance in the first place. This is achieved by imbu- an integral part of his overall personality; his bad-
ing a deeply immoral character with sympathetic, ness not only touches many of the parts that we
likeable, and admirable traits, as discussed above. like, admire, and find sympathetic, but we some-
The target audience is one who would be strongly times like him because of his badness. The result
reluctant to direct evaluatively positive affective is that we are pulled in opposing directions with-
states toward a morally undeserving character. out hope of relief and left to linger in a delicious
(Recall that the rough hero’s moral flaws are state of irresolvable conflict with ourselves.29 This
grievous, and so the imaginative resistance here indefinitely protracted state of ambivalence is
will be considerable.) The challenge that works precisely what makes certain immoral works
with rough heroes set themselves, then, is to over- compelling (an important aesthetic merit). We
288 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

are captivated by and savor this ambivalence; it ment of a morally depraved character, that makes
makes these works haunt us and keep us awake at the work so good. In this way, the very same fea-
night. ture of a work is both a moral blemish and an
In making this case for aesthetic value of a cer- aesthetic merit.
tain kind of immorality in art, I have implicitly It is worth noting, however, that as I write this
conceived of an artwork as a solution to a set of essay there has been a veritable flood of rough
problems. An artwork, on this view, is the result of heroes in movies and television, many of which
a design process that addresses and aims to solve were listed in Section II. This has prompted one
a set of problems.30 I do not claim that this is the critic to suggest that the recent overabundance of
only way to think about art, but it does have the (what I call) rough heroes diminishes the genre,
credential and advantage of providing the foun- although he does not explain why.31 But we are
dation for much art criticism by offering a way to now in a position to see the truth of the ob-
appreciate and evaluate artworks on several lev- servation: with so many spellbinding models to
els. First, the problem set offers a benchmark for follow, constructing compelling rough heroes no
evaluating the work. Does it solve the problems it longer constitutes much of a challenge. As for the
set out to solve? Second, we evaluate the manner audience, overexposure to what one might call
in which the work solves its problems. How well “the rough hero conundrum” erodes the imagi-
does the work solve its problem? Is the solution native resistance that is, I have argued, essential
original or hackneyed, elegant or clumsy, clever or to the genre’s compellingness, thereby threatening
obvious, handily achieved or labored? to render these works boring rather than riveting.
However, solving a problem well is not neces- As with many forms of aesthetic achievement—
sarily a mark of aesthetic success. A work might consider, for instance, the case of linear perspec-
solve the problem it set for itself yet neverthe- tive—the aesthetic accomplishment of the rough
less be a mediocre work because the problem is hero genre is a historical phenomenon whose time
uninteresting or easy to solve. That is, we do not may soon pass.
just evaluate works based on whether they solve
their problems; we evaluate the problem itself.
Is it an interesting problem? Does it constitute v. weak immoralisms
a genuine challenge? Is it a problem worth solv-
ing? When a work fails to provide satisfactory an- Taken at the most general level, my position that
swers to these questions, it can be a mediocre or artworks’ moral flaws can also be aesthetic merits
even bad work despite the fact that it achieves its is not new. Both Kieran and Jacobson have already
goals. argued for this conclusion, although their posi-
I have argued that a certain kind of immoral tions differ significantly in key respects. I now ex-
artwork—namely, works that prescribe both moral plain how the view I endorse here improves upon
disapproval of and also sympathy, affection, or ad- both.
miration for its characters—is aesthetically good Kieran has developed a view that he calls cog-
precisely because such works solve a difficult and nitive immoralism (hereafter CI): the thesis that
interesting artistic problem, namely, to get the au- when an artwork’s moral value is aesthetically rel-
dience to feel things that it is strongly disinclined evant, moral flaws enhance the work’s aesthetic
to feel. Further, this problem is worth solving in value.32 Although some proponents of moralism
that the state of ambivalence produced by such have criticized CI, they have missed what I take to
works makes them deeply compelling, where the be the view’s fundamental weakness.33 I briefly ex-
power to compel is understood as an important plain CI below and offer a new criticism that gets
aesthetic property. The general conclusion I sup- at its core defect. Unlike recent critics of immoral-
port, then, is this: an intrinsically immoral art- ism, however, my aim is not to support moralism
work that succeeds in making its target audience but, rather, to produce a stronger and more com-
adopt its immoral perspective is to this extent pelling version of immoralism.
morally flawed and also for this reason (and to Kieran’s argument begins from the view that
this extent) aesthetically good. To set the immoral- he and others call ‘aesthetic cognitivism’: the
ism of this thesis in relief, I emphasize that it is idea that some cognitive virtues of artworks are
precisely a work’s moral flaw, namely, its endorse- aesthetic virtues. More precisely, insofar as a work
Eaton Robust Immoralism 289

increases or deepens our knowledge in appropri- ample, The Sopranos, Lolita, The Godfather, or
ate ways, it is aesthetically good. The 120 Days of Sodom. Further, this restriction
Whereas it might seem that the rough hero risks including works that are aesthetically marred
genre fosters a kind of ignorance by making im- by didacticism or moral righteousness: for exam-
moral characters sympathetic and likeable, Kieran ple, some of Charles Dickens’s novels, many of
argues that prescribing immoral responses in this Norman Rockwell’s paintings, or Jenny Holzer’s
manner in fact makes a positive contribution to the Truism series.
audience’s understanding in several ways. First, CI’s second problem is that it disarms immoral
by providing firsthand acquaintance with perspec- art by emptying it of the very thing that makes
tives that are different from, and perhaps even in- it so disturbing and threatening, namely, its im-
imical to, the audience’s, immoral artworks chal- morality. On Kieran’s account, the apparent men-
lenge us to examine our own most deeply held ace of immoral works is merely provisional since
beliefs and thereby help us to become more open- they ultimately serve to improve their audiences
minded. Second, Kieran argues, a complete un- morally. After all, on Kieran’s account it is moral
derstanding and appreciation of moral goodness knowledge that immoral art offers, and, although
requires firsthand experience of moral badness, its methods are oblique, immoral art arrives at its
which is precisely what immoral works offer.34 moral lessons by first drawing the audience into
So, although it may seem that the genre of the an immoral perspective, its effects coincide with
rough hero threatens to pervert our morally rele- those of moral art: to make us more open-minded
vant sentiments, according to Kieran such works and tolerant, to refine our capacities to distinguish
in fact enlarge our perceptual and emotional ca- the good from the bad, and to instill a proper
pacities and in this way offer substantial cognitive understanding and appreciation of the human
gains. This increase in our understanding is, per condition.
aesthetic cognitivism, an aesthetic merit. I mean to suggest, then, that CI is not just
While Kieran makes a convincing case that im- an anemic form of immoralism, but that it ac-
moral art has the potential to enlarge its audi- tually collapses back into moralism, the very
ence’s understanding, as an account of immoral position that Kieran adamantly opposes.37 This
art’s aesthetic value the argument is unsatisfac- happens in two ways. First, in an attempt to
tory for two reasons. show that many highly acclaimed “immoral” art-
First, in failing to distinguish between intrinsi- works are not counterexamples to their theory,
cally and extrinsically immoral artworks, CI cap- moralists employ a similar strategy to redeem
tures too much. Given a sufficiently sophisticated, morally dubious art. Moralists argue that be-
self-aware, and virtuous audience in the right cir- cause so-called immoral art manifests moral un-
cumstances, any immoral work has the potential derstanding that yields cognitive gains, great so-
to serve as an occasion for the kind of learn- called immoral artworks like Lolita (Gaut) or The
ing Kieran so ably describes.35 Even a work like Sopranos (Carroll) turn out upon closer inspec-
Triumph of the Will (Leni Riefenstahl, 1935) is tion to be morally virtuous.38 Interpreting these
amenable to such an interpretation: for a twenty- works as complex morality tales overlooks pre-
first century audience morally opposed to both cisely what makes them compelling and unsettling,
fascism and anti-Semitism, the film can help us to namely, their unrepentant and irredeemable im-
see the dangerously strong appeal of charismatic morality. Like moralism, CI saps immoral art of its
leaders and to recognize what Susan Sontag iden- threat and menace, rendering it not just benign but
tified as our own “fascist longings.”36 However, even morally beneficial. Second, on CI’s account,
this benefit depends on the audience’s prior con- what makes an artwork aesthetically good is not
demnation of Nazis, and this is not at all the film’s the immoral feature per se but, rather, the moral
target audience; put another way, Triumph does insight that it yields. Despite Kieran’s claims to
not aim to enlighten in this manner. the contrary, immoral art is not, on this view, valu-
In order to systematically exclude works like able in virtue of its immoral perspective; rather,
Triumph of the Will, one might limit CI to only the immoral perspective is but a means to achiev-
those works that aim to deepen our understand- ing moral insight, and it is in virtue of the lat-
ing. But this would fail to capture the deeply ter that a work has aesthetic value on Kieran’s
troubling works that CI means to explain, for ex- account.39
290 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Now let us turn to Jacobson’s immoralism, of moral and aesthetic value” that gives an ac-
which has two prongs: (1) strong arguments count of the “systematic difference between the
against moralism (discussed above) and (2) the role that moral defects and virtues of an artwork
suggestion that moral flaws in an artwork can be play in constituting aesthetic value.”47
aesthetic merits.40 The focus throughout Jacob- Jacobson makes it sound as if the only two op-
son’s provocative articles on this topic has been tions were (a) law-like generalizations involving
(1), whereas actual arguments for (2) are sorely very general properties (such as “moral flaws in
lacking. artworks”) or (b) vague existential claims offer-
What, exactly, makes immoral art aesthetically ing little more than trivial truths. But this is a false
valuable according to Jacobson? It cannot be the dilemma. I do not propose a universal and excep-
Kieran-esque answer he appears to give, namely, tionless counterfactual supporting generalization
that immoral art has the capacity to acquaint us about the relation of moral and aesthetic value
with ethical perspectives that diverge from our tout court, nor am I simply asserting that some-
own and thereby precipitate our overcoming dog- times moral defects are aesthetic merits while
matism.41 While surely an important humanistic other times they are not. Rather, I have shown
function that gives us a moral reason to engage that something general and systematic can be said
with immoral art, by Jacobson’s own lights this is about the aesthetic value of a specified kind of
a decidedly nonaesthetic reason and so redounds moral defect in art. Here, by way of conclusion, is
neither to a work’s aesthetic credit or discredit. a summary of my theory.
Jacobson briefly gestures at a more compelling Some artworks have what I call an intrinsically
answer; namely, that good immoral art, like good immoral perspective, which contrasts with an ex-
caricature, succeeds at getting us to see things ac- trinsically immoral perspective. I have isolated a
cording to its perspective, even, at times, despite genre, which I call the rough hero, that is char-
our considered moral convictions.42 But he does acterized by an intrinsically immoral perspective
not explain how this applies to cases other than in the sense that the audience is supposed to find
caricature, nor does he tell us why this should be a work’s principal character both morally abhor-
considered an aesthetic achievement, nor does he rent and also sympathetic, likeable, and even ad-
offer convincing examples of immoral artworks mirable. Such works endorse a morally abhorrent
that succeed in just this way.43 These are things character, and this is a moral defect. I have argued
that I have provided in this essay, and in this way that this particular sort of moral defect, and only
I offer argument and support for Jacobson’s tan- this sort, is at the same time an aesthetic achieve-
talizing suggestion. ment in that it sets up and then skillfully solves
I disagree with Jacobson, however, in my un- an ambitious artistic problem and induces in its
derstanding of the scope and force of the claim audience a complex and enduring sort of plea-
that some immoral artworks are morally flawed sure. I have offered many concrete examples in
and aesthetically meritorious for the same rea- support of the following generalization that holds
sons. Although Jacobson is often taken to be a ceteris paribus: an intrinsically immoral artwork
proponent of immoralism, he repudiates this la- that succeeds in making its target audience adopt
bel when interpreted strictly because “an ‘ism’ its immoral perspective is to this extent morally
implies a theory. . . [and] there is no true theory flawed and also for this reason, and to this extent,
of the relation between moral and aesthetic value, aesthetically good.48
although there are of course some true propo-
sitions about it, such as the weak claim and its A. W. EATON
immoralist counterpart.”44 The “weak claim” re- Department of Philosophy
ferred to here is Carroll’s idea that a moral defect University of Illinois at Chicago
in an artwork can sometimes count as an aesthetic Chicago, Illinois 60607
defect, while the “immoralist counterpart,” which
Carroll also embraces, holds that a moral defect internet: eaton@uic.edu
can count as an aesthetic merit.45 Jacobson em-
braces both of these claims; what he denies is that 1. David Hume, “Of the Standard of Taste,” in Essays
they amount to a theory.46 A theory, to Jacobson’s Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapo-
mind, must be “a general thesis about the relation lis: Liberty Classics, 1987), p. 246.
Eaton Robust Immoralism 291

2. As is well known, The Sopranos enjoyed tremendous 16. Consider the following castings: Faye Dunnaway
popularity for six seasons, from January 1999 to June 2007. and Warren Beatty as Bonnie and Clyde, Brad Pitt as Tyler
It was the series’ overwhelming popularity that prompted a Durden, Christian Bale as Patrick Bateman, Al Pacino
flood of likeable bad guys, such as Jack Bauer of 24, Dexter as Michael Corleone, and Anthony Hopkins as Hannibal
Morgan of Dexter, and Don Draper of Mad Men. Lecter.
3. Daniel Jacobson, “In Praise of Immoral Art,” Philo- 17. Todd Gitlin, The Whole World Is Watching: Mass
sophical Topics 25 (1997): 155–199, at pp. 172–199. Media in the Making and Unmaking of the New Left (Uni-
4. For Noël Carroll, see “Moderate Moralism,” The versity of California Press, 1980), p. 199.
British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (1996): 223–238; “Art, Nar- 18. In his 1958 review of Lolita, Trilling aptly captures
rative and Moral Understanding,” in Aesthetics and Ethics, this phenomenon: ‘‘we find ourselves the more shocked
ed. Jerrold Levinson (Cambridge University Press, 1998); when we realize that, in the course of reading the novel, we
and “Art and Ethical Criticism: An Overview of Recent have come virtually to condone the violation it presents. . . .
Directions in Research,” Ethics 110 (2000): 350–387. For We have been seduced into conniving in the violation, be-
Berys Gaut, see “The Ethical Criticism of Art,” in Aes- cause we have permitted our fantasies to accept what we
thetics and Ethics, ed. Jerrold Levinson (Cambridge Uni- know to be revolting.” Griffen, August 1958, reprinted in
versity Press, 1998), pp. 182–203; “Art and Ethics,” in Nabokov: The Critical Heritage, ed. Norman Page (London:
The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, 2nd ed., eds. Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1982), p. 95.
Berys Gaut and Dominic McIver Lopes (New York: 19. Although both Carroll and Gaut insist that their
Routledge, 2005), pp. 431–443; Art, Emotion and Ethics (Ox- views diverge significantly, I agree with Jacobson that the
ford University Press, 2007), especially chap. 6. structure of their arguments is the same. See Daniel Ja-
5. A work can also manifest a perspective through overt cobson, “Ethical Criticism and the Vice of Moderation,” in
proclamation. Kendall Walton, for instance, gives the ex- Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of
ample of a photograph of a mixed race couple entitled Art, ed. Matthew Kieran (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006),
“Shame!” in Kendall Walton and Michael Tanner, “Morals p. 349.
in Fiction and Fictional Morality,” Proceedings of the Aris- 20. Jacobson, “In Praise of Immoral Art,” pp. 172–199.
totelian Society, supp. vol. 68 (1994): 27–66, at p. 40. Since This argument is fleshed out in Justin D’Arms and Daniel
art rarely operates through the controlling guidance of ex- Jacobson, “The Moralistic Fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’
plicit evaluation, I do not explore this mode of manifesting of Emotions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
a perspective here. 61 (2000): 65–90. Although Carroll appears to miss the
6. The Motion Picture Production Code, “General point when directly addressing Jacobson’s criticism (Carroll,
Principles,” 1930 version of the Code. “Art and Ethical Criticism,” pp. 375–376), his suggestion
7. I make this case in A. W. Eaton, “Where Ethics and that some emotions have “moral warranting conditions”
Aesthetics Meet,” Hypatia 18 (2003): 158–188. could be a promising response, as discussed below. Gaut
8. One might object that the indifference to rape pre- develops precisely this line of response to Jacobson, argu-
scribed by the painting is itself a moral perspective. But this is ing that a wide range of responses, including humor, have
to miss the distinction I make here. The painting itself does moral warrant conditions (Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics,
not prescribe moral judgment of Europa’s rape, although pp. 237–251). While I find Carroll’s and Gaut’s line of re-
the painting’s indifferent perspective can be subjected to sponse promising, I see two problems. First, while I agree
second-order moral assessment. that some emotional and quasi-emotional responses have
9. Here the notion of target audience is crucial. what D’Arms and Jacobson call a “moral shape,” Car-
Guernica is not addressed to hardened fascists who would, roll’s and Gaut’s formulation in terms of “moral warrant-
let us imagine, support the bombing even in the face of the ing conditions” is too strong, for reasons explained below.
human suffering depicted in the painting. Second, I think that the scope of responses that have a
10. Noël Carroll, The Philosophy of Motion Pictures moral shape is considerably narrower than Gaut and Carroll
(Oxford: Blackwell, 2008), p. 182. maintain.
11. Although the poem’s stated purpose is to “Justify 21. D’Arms and Jacobson, “The Moralistic Fallacy,”
the ways of God to man” (Book 1), the poem’s sympathetic p. 75.
portrayal of Lucifer or Satan suggested to many perceptive 22. Noël Carroll makes this qualification in “Moderate
readers, like William Blake, that Milton was “of the Devil’s Moralism,” pp. 232–233. The qualification is important be-
party without knowing it” (William Blake, The Marriage of cause it excludes factors extrinsic to the work—for example,
Heaven and Hell [Oxford University Press, 1975], p. xvii). a fact about the judge or the circumstances in which she
12. Aimée Baldridge suggested the Bulgakov example. encounters the work—but it nevertheless does not forestall
13. I discuss Benigno as an example of immoralism in Jacobson’s objection, as I explain.
A. W. Eaton, “Almodóvar’s Immoralism,” in Talk to Her, 23. The example, which is mine, is meant to illustrate
ed. A. W. Eaton (New York: Routledge, 2008). Jacobson’s argument in “In Praise of Immoral Art,” pp.
14. Alex, in Anthony Burgess’s 1962 novel A Clock- 170–179.
work Orange, however, is not an example of the rough hero 24. The states on the D’Arms–Jacobson list are typically
since the novel ends with Alex’s moral redemption, which considered “basic emotions” in the psychological literature.
Kubrick omitted. Nothing hangs on whether the kinds of states I would add to
15. For the concept of unreliable narrator, see this list count as emotions, feelings, or some other kind of af-
Wayne Booth in The Rhetoric of Fiction (University of fective state; all that matters is that they are affective states
Chicago Press, 1961), at pp. 300–308. Humbert Humbert’s and have what D’Arms and Jacobson call a “moral shape.”
epistemic unreliability is most often due to his moral de- D’Arms and Jacobson explain “moral shape” in “The Moral-
pravity. Michael Smith suggested this point. istic Fallacy,” pp. 87–88.
292 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

25. I take it that this is what Carroll means when he says 37. Kieran forcefully concludes: “Thus cognitive im-
that sympathy has “moral warranting conditions” (Carroll, moralism holds and ethicism cannot but be false,” in
“Art and Ethical Criticism,” p. 377). As I explain below, “Forbidden Knowledge,” p. 72.
however, this formulation is too strong since sympathy has 38. Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, pp. 194–202. Noël
only a partially moral shape. Carroll, “Sympathy for the Devil,” in The Sopranos and
26. Gaut argues for the moral warranting conditions of Philosophy, eds. Richard Greene and Peter Vernezze (Peru,
humor in Art, Emotions, and Ethics, pp. 242–251. IL: Open Court, 2004), pp. 121–136.
27. I again draw from D’Arms and Jacobson, “The 39. Just as this essay goes into press, I learned of an
Moralistic Fallacy,” p. 88. essay by Kieran that addresses some of the concerns outlined
28. There is now quite a large literature in aesthetics here, though not, I think, my central worry. See Matthew
and psychology on imaginative resistance. For an excel- Kieran, “Emotions, Art and Immorality,” in The Oxford
lent overview, see Tamar Gendler, “Imagination,” in The Handbook of the Philosophy of Emotion, ed. Peter Goldie
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 edition), (Oxford University Press, 2010), pp. 681–703.
ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ 40. See D’Arms and Jacobson “The Moralistic Fal-
spr2011/entries/imagination/, especially Section 5.2. lacy,” pp. 65–90; Jacobson, “In Praise of Immoral Art,”
29. It would be interesting to pursue how certain as- pp. 155–199; Jacobson, “Ethical Criticism and the Vice of
pects of this state as I describe it—in particular its mixture Moderation,” pp. 342–355.
of pain with pleasure and its protraction—are reminiscent of 41. Daniel Jacobson, “Sir Philip Sidney’s Dilemma: On
Kant’s sublime. the Ethical Function of Narrative Art,” The Journal of Aes-
30. This is a view championed by, among others, thetics and Art Criticism 54 (1996): 327–336, at p. 335; also
Michael Baxandall, Patterns of Intention: On the Histori- Jacobson, “In Praise of Immoral Art,” pp. 192–194.
cal Explanation of Pictures (Yale University Press, 1983), 42. Jacobson, “In Praise of Immoral Art,” p. 187.
especially pp. 12–73. 43. Much of Jacobson’s view is expressed by way of
31. Joshua Alston, “Too Much of a Bad Thing,” analogy with immoral jokes—of which, alas, he also offers
Newsweek, January 12, 2009. (Most of the characters to no examples. Of the few examples of immoral artworks
which Alston refers are what I call “rough heroes,” rather that Jacobson does give, few are convincing, as Noël Carroll
than “antiheroes” as Alston describes them.) observes (Carroll, “Art and Ethical Criticism,” p. 380,
32. Matthew Kieran, “Forbidden Knowledge: The note 34). Jacobson responds in his 2006 article with one
Challenge of Immoralism,” in Art and Morality, eds. José example, the poem “This Be the Verse” by Philip Larkin
Bermúdez and Sebastian Gardner (London: Routledge, (2003). Like Carroll, I am hard pressed to see the immoral
2003), pp. 56–73; Matthew Kieran, Revealing Art (London: perspective promoted by this poem, which Jacobson simply
Routledge, 2005), pp. 148–204; and Matthew Kieran, “Art, quotes but does not explain.
Morality and Ethics: On the (Im)Moral Character of Art 44. Jacobson, “Ethical Criticism and the Vice of Mod-
Works and Inter-Relations to Artistic Value,” Philosophy eration,” p. 346.
Compass 1/2 (2006): 129–143. 45. As noted above, Carroll doubts that there are com-
33. Robert Stecker, “Immoralism and the Anti- pelling examples. See Carroll, “Art and Ethical Criticism,”
Theoretical View,” The British Journal of Aesthetics 48 pp. 379–380.
(2007): 145–161; and James Harold, “Immoralism and the 46. “In fact, my own view is simply that a moral defect
Valence Constraint,” The British Journal of Aesthetics 48 of an artwork can figure as an aesthetic merit: I expressly
(2008): 45–64. allow that it can also be an aesthetic flaw or aesthetically
34. See Kieran, “Forbidden Knowledge,” especially irrelevant (Jacobson 1997).” Jacobson, “Ethical Criticism
Section III, “Experiencing what’s bad to understand the and the Vice of Moderation,” p. 346.
good,” pp. 63–67; and Kieran, Revealing Art, pp. 191–192. 47. Jacobson, “Ethical Criticism and the Vice of Mod-
35. Harold, “Immoralism and the Valence Constraint,” eration,” p. 346.
p. 60, makes a similar point, although he does not consider 48. I would like to thank Eva Dadlez, Berys Gaut,
its implications for Kieran’s CI. Daniel Jacobson, Brian Soucek, Rachel Zuckert, and anony-
36. Susan Sontag, “Fascinating Fascism,” New York Re- mous referees for this journal for comments on earlier ver-
view of Books, February 6, 1975. sions of this article.

You might also like