Book Reviews: Color and Its Reproduction, 2 Edition, by Gary G

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 3

BOOK REVIEWS

Color and Its Reproduction, 2nd Edition, by Gary G. tains a long list of landmark developments without the
Field, GATF Press, Pittsburgh, 1998. 486 pp. $65 benefit of theory, which comes later, or diagrams to
clarify what the inventions entailed. I found some errors
This is a substantial hard-backed book with 455 pages, a in the early chapters, but will only mention two here.
thorough list of references and a comprehensive index. As
you would expect from a book of this title the quality of the a. In the diagrams to illustrate 3 color vision theories on
printing is excellent, with large, easily-read typescript on page 52 there seems to be no signal passed from the
coated paper and copious color illustrations. One of the red-sensitive cones to the brain.
references is Prof. Robert Hunt’s book ‘The Reproduction b. The diagram of the gamut of a good commercial process
of Colour’, 5th Edition, Fountain Press, 1995, and it was to ink set on the CIE chromaticity chart on page 135 and on
this volume that I naturally turned in order to make com- the front cover of the book shows white at its center.
parisons. This is unfortunate in view of the fact that subtractive
Field states in his preface that his book “is primarily mixtures will only produce grey or black, and tradition-
directed to those involved in the production of printed ally it is in diagrams illustrating additive mixture that
color reproductions; notably, skilled prepress and print- white is placed at the center.
ing personnel, quality analysts and production manag-
ers.” Hunt’s book, on the other hand, puts equal emphasis There are some surprising omissions in the book too. I
on colour photography and television, and leaves colour would have expected to see a diagram to illustrate a
printing until last. A comparison of the indices of the two cross-screen grid and another to show how halftone im-
books confirms the impression. Field has 29 references ages are produced from a continuous tone negative early
including some whole sections on ‘dot gain’ whereas on in the book. Mention of a diffraction grating when
Hunt has 2. ‘Density’ has 49 in Field and 19 (but divided discussing means of producing the spectrum is surely
into categories such as actinic, analytical, diffuse etc.) in essential. When discussing color order systems and at-
Hunt. It would be frustrating to locate the type of density lases I thought a printer would at least mention the
of interest in the former case! ‘Coloured couplers’ gets 7 Pantone System. The lack of a single chemical formula or
mentions in Hunt’s index, along with one on ‘Colour mathematical equation except in the Appendices is also
development, dye coupling’ but there is no sign of the surprising.
subject at all in Field’s. ‘Color separation’ has 47 men- In conclusion I have to admit that I am not in a position
tions in Field and a whole chapter devoted to the subject, to make much comment on the graphics content of this
whereas it does not feature at all in Hunt’s index. There book, but from what I can glean it is excellent.
is just one on ‘Separation negatives’. The 2 books are
clearly very different, which goes to show that you can-
not judge a book by its title. DR. CHRIS HAWKYARD
However, Field, on page 1, states that the color repro-
duction process “includes making photographic color trans-
parencies and prints, television images, computer monitor Color and Meaning: Art, Science, and Symbolism by
displays and printed reproductions.” It is a pity, therefore, John Gage, University of California Press, 1999. 320 pp.
that the subjects of photography, television and monitors are Cloth $55; paper $35
so skimpily covered.
There are 15 chapters in Field’s book, chapters 7-15 I view color as somewhat fluid and untenable as opposed to
being about color printing on paper. One might expect a color as completely quantifiable and determinate. For this
chapter entitled ‘Color Communication’ (chapter 14) to be reason, I appreciate the writings of John Gage, who empha-
broader than this, but it is entirely centered on printing. sizes that color in its full form can only be examined with a
Chapters 1-6 are about the history of color reproduction, multidisciplinary viewpoint, because there are no exact so-
color theory, perception, measurement and specification, lutions to color problems. For example, the quantification of
with a rogue chapter, chapter 3, inserted on the subject of a specific color leads us no closer to understanding how a
feed-back and control systems for color management in culture attaches meaning to that color; formal art analyses
printing companies. This would have been better placed do not answer the questions of how a public interacts with
near the end of the book, but is clearly a specialism of the color on a daily basis. And this is the theme of his book,
author. Color and Meaning: Art, Science, and Symbolism. Gage
Chapter 1, on the history of color reproduction, con- succinctly and wonderfully outlines this theme:

382 COLOR research and application


“[Colour]. . .is like all formal characteristics ideologi- An account of the development of the prism, called by
cally neutral. It can be seen to have served a very wide Christopher Merrett in 1662 “the fool’s Paradise” takes the
range of aesthetic and symbolic purposes; and the same reader through a lineage starting with investigations of the
colours or combinations of colours can, for example, colors passing through hexagonal stones in the 1270s and
be shown to have held quite antithetical connotations culminating with the publication of Jodocus Trutfetter’s
in different periods and cultures, and even at the same Philosophie Naturalis Summa of 1517. Here, the predeces-
time and in the same place.” sors to Newton’s experiments are found in Trutfetter’s
optical experiments in a darkened room, where he allowed
Gage presents the larger picture from the perspective of light to enter through a single hole in the shutter. He then
an art historian, who strips colors of their presumed mean- passed through the light a variety of optical devices includ-
ings so they exist as indifferent constituents. He is equally ing a glass rod, a mirror, and a hexagonal stone. Although
comfortable presenting Medieval assumptions that color Trutfetter does not mention a triangular glass or prism (the
was not primarily a matter of hue, the rudiments of contex- prism was evidently not seen before the middle of the 16th
tual theory. To read Gage is to meander with him on less century), Newton’s own experiments of 1666 echo the
trodden paths. Published on the heals of Color and Culture, methodology of these experiments. Upon viewing the spec-
this is a compilation of material that Gage says did not find trum, Newton attempted to articulate the exact number of
a place in that book. From a chapter on William Blake’s discrete colors cast by the prism: first citing eleven, then
interest in optics to synaesthesia, Gage provides his readers five, and finally deciding upon seven. It is Gage’s preoccu-
fascinating glimpses into the diverse aspects of color. A pation not merely to relate a well-known historical mile-
section on shot fabrics, for example, those woven with warp stone, but to enlarge it. This inquiry into the historical
and weft threads of different colors, is one such rewarding context and the way interest in light cast by hexagonal
digression. Often enamored by the Renaissance painters stones by numerous researchers predating Newton certainly
such as Andrea del Sarto, the shifting of colors on shot broadens the narrative. Newton’s settling upon seven colors
fabrics led to the invention of the painterly technique called was a correlation with seven tones of the Western musical
cangiantismo, the representation of shadows on fabrics with scale, indicating a preoccupation with a viewpoint that
color changes rather than value changes as a way to intro- suggested the number of colors should fit with a greater or
duce more luminous colors into the paintings. Gage mines more divine ordering system. Gage demonstrates how such
such topics with extensiveness and perspicacity as open- a viewpoint was not new; around 1355 the three colors gold,
ended questions, which documents from history can eluci- scarlet, and green were suggested as colors relating not only
date. to the Trinity and a correlative triad, but also found in the
The second theme that appears from such an approach is observed colors of nature such as on a peacock’s tail. These
echoed in the book’s title. There exists historically a po- colorful explorations and foundations are wonderfully ex-
lemic between those who approach color understanding plored by Gage’s careful research and engrossing writing.
scientifically and those who regard color as an intuitive Those interested in color-ordering systems cannot fail to
procedure. Gage writes: note how early models were bounded by regular polygons,
a natural extension of the proposition that a divine and
“Since Newton the science and the art of colour have perfect universe must in its parts be beautifully ordered. The
been usually treated as entirely distinct, and yet to treat philosophical premise of William of Ockham, called Ock-
them so is to miss many of the most intriguing as- ham’s Razor, states that “Entities are not to be multiplied
pects.” beyond necessity,” or, put in another way, nature takes the
simplest course to get something done. This is one of the
At an 1817 dinner party, Benjamin Haydon remarked that delights in reading Gage; by using other texts contempora-
Newton believed nothing unless it was as clear as three neous to early investigations of color, he broadens the
sides of a triangle. Another member of that discussion was foundation of influence. He suggests that Ockham’s Razor
the poet Keats, who went home to pen lines in his Lamia plays a larger role in the perception of and ordering of
attacking Newton, “Do not all charms fly at the mere touch colors. Thus, Newton’s antagonist Robert Hooke sought to
of cold philosophy?” and that his theories “. . .Unweave the apply the reductive premise by constructing a theory utiliz-
rainbow.” ing only two primary colors. These reductive theories even-
We may be tempted to delegate such positions to history. tually confounded painters, as well as those who attempted
However, ask artists how they choose their colors, and a to create practical color models and unified color theories.
large number will remark that they choose them by intu- One may ask if Gage reaches his goal of presenting a case
ition. They consider, and I think incorrectly so, that theory strong enough to unify the polarized disciplines of color
is nothing but a dry exercise that can kill any innate talent study. He attempts and succeeds in showing that the lines
for color usage. Investigations into how color study evolved between art and science, between the operations of nature
into two antithetical viewpoints provide exciting reading. and the activities of artists, were linked since pre-Socratic
Gage pursues this question by reexamining the broad-based times and that the rift between the two is relatively recent.
mutual influence found in artistic and scientific discoveries. Twentieth-century developments of color theory and re-

Volume 25, Number 5, October 2000 383


searches into the eye/brain system are not Gage’s forté, even a real strength of Gage’s work. His reliance on sources and
though the connection between creative endeavors and color the presentation of original documents rather than relying
science has proven a very valuable impetus for many twen- on later interpretations appears in some cases radical, be-
tieth-century artists and researchers. Thus, while Gage fi- cause the conclusions contradict many poorly researched
nally suggests that recent technological advances can only books. Gage’s care in researching material sets a model for
help artists, thus reuniting the two, it is a determination how art historians should approach color.
gleaned from a potpourri of essays and presentations of A fascinating chapter suggests that Matisse shifted from
historical positions. Or in his words: a position of conceiving black as a dark value to that of
colored light. This idea is crowned by his title page for the
“If there is a unifying thread running through these 1943 “De la Couleur” in which a black sun sends forth her
chapters, it is that since colour has a vivid life outside rays. Matisse is said to have remarked that when he didn’t
the realm of art, its problems even within that realm know what color to use he would apply black, but Gage digs
cannot be understood exclusively from within the his- further. Matisse attributes his use of black to black ground
tory and theory of art itself; or rather that at least in monotypes he did about 1914. In the same year, we learn
respect of colour, that history and that theory must be that he may have seen black conte crayon drawings by
seen to be part of a larger picture.” Seurat that Felix Fénéon had in his collection, as well as
Picasso’s Harlequin of 1915, a painting containing a black
Detailing the point of some Byzantine mosaics: he rec- ground. But why Matisse later seemed to view black as a
ognizes that the optical result caused by small tesserae light is deeper than artistic influences and, according to
arranged with staggered colors is a mingling to the eye, Gage, perhaps fueled by contemporary interest in black light
which creates soft edges and shimmering color. The late as a physical phenomenon, as developed by Gustave Le Bon
Floyd Ratliff approached the experience of viewing small starting in 1896. Le Bon’s premise was that the visible
pieces of color from a psychophysical perspective by pro- spectrum formed less than one-tenth of the whole, and he
ceeding with the physiological process and moving toward showed that infra-red and other radiations due to invisible
the psychological. Gage immediately focuses on the artistic phosphorescence could act like light while remaining invis-
function of the colors. To him they invite a “. . .continual ible, a fact he demonstrated with the use of photography.
advance and retreat by the spectator,” because they never Whether Matisse was aware of Le Bon’s work is debatable;
completely fuse to one single color. This is an obvious fact he possibly read an article on the subject in 1913. Gage
to anyone who has ever stood before a mosaic or a neo- presents a case of possible influence upon a portrait Matisse
impressionist painting, and a fact in contradiction to a did of his wife in 1913. Here the eyes are blackened out, and
number of art historians who blindly posit that the small another portrait of 1914 shows arching rays emanating from
marks blend to a solid color with any viewing distance. the sitter, a concept described by Le Bon in his article of
There are many such trenchant expositions in this book 1913.
and it’s hard to find anything to disagree with. A few readers In his essay “Color Has Not Yet Been Named: Objectiv-
may feel their hair bristle upon reading Gage’s pronounce- ity in Deconstruction,” Stephen Melville offers this unpur-
ment that the work of Berlin and Kay is “remarkably in- sued overview:
consequential.” Their groundbreaking work sparked exten-
sive research into the connections between language and “Subjective and objective, physically fixed and cultur-
color, a debt owed to them by many researchers. Further- ally constructed, absolutely proper and endlessly dis-
more, Gage suggests Berlin and Kay’s research is not par- placed, color can appear as an unthinkable scandal.
ticularly relevant to everyday life, where we are far more The story of color and its theory within the history of
concerned with nuances of color rather than primaries. My art is a history of oscillations between its reduction to
experience in the classroom with hundreds of beginning charm or ornament and its valorization as the radical
painters and students of color directly contradicts this state- truth of painting. From these oscillations other vibra-
ment. To them a sky is blue, a tree green — their mental tions are repeatedly set in motion that touch and disturb
conception corresponds more with Berlin and Kay’s eleven matters as purely art-historical as the complex inter-
basic colors, and this reduced notion appears to circumvent locking borders among and within the individual arts
their early ability to perceive color nuances. Their difficulty and as culturally far-reaching as codings of race and
in describing colors in terms of hue, value, and saturation, gender and images of activity and passivity.”
further suggests, at least to me, the ways in which linguistic
categorization of colors influences perceptions.
Color and Meaning is profusely illustrated with color and Taken as a challenge for research, the paragraph could
black-and-white plates, and this makes for pleasurable read- easily sum up Gage’s brilliant work. Color and Meaning is
ing, because the work in question is represented. Thirty-four a magnificent read and an impeccable resource.
pages of notes and a 6-page selected bibliography allow
readers to look up the source being discussed. Indeed, this is CHRISTOPHER WILLARD

384 COLOR research and application

You might also like