Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Conflict and Factionalist Dispute

Author(s): Bernard J. Siegel and Alan R. Beals


Source: The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland, Vol. 90
, No. 1 (Jan. - Jun., 1960), pp. 107-117
Published by: Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2844220
Accessed: 03-11-2015 14:54 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley and Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Conflict and Factionalist Dispute
BERNARD J. SIEGEL & ALAN R. BEALS
StanfordUniversity,
California

ANALYSES
OF SOCIAL generally take a stable model as a point of departure.'
SYSTEMS
A group is interpreted in terms of certain structuralpropertieswhich are considered to
be reflected in the functioning of social usages or customs. Emphasis is placed upon
forms, linkages, and alignments such as family, kinship, age, sex, friendship, and other
relationships, and then move to the mechanisms for ensuring conduct appropriate to
the maintenance of these alignments and values and beliefs which support them. The
social system, then, is regarded as a set of techniques for mobilizing and organizing
individual energies to cope with group problems. It maps appropriatebehaviours and,
like other cultural sub-systems,inhibits random self-seeking.In most depictive or func-
tionally oriented interpretationsof social structuresattention tends to be directed to the
way the system works; rarely is attention directed towards the presence of disruptive
formsof social relationshipssuch as the presenceof pervasiveconflict.
It is true that if conflict in human interaction were the rule and organizationlargely
absent, social life could scarcely exist. The case of the Kaingang, described by Jules
Henry (Henry I94I), appears to be an illustration of this. The virtual absence of struc-
tural regularitieswithin this group at the time of Henry's observationsappeared to be
leading the Kaingang toward their extinction. Such examples, perhaps, explain why the
assumptionis frequently made that a social system, if viable, tends to correct centrifugal
behavioural tendencies to accord with prevailing normative expectations. Nevertheless,
not all groups fit this model very closely. Dobuans appear to be pathologically mis-
trustful of each other (Fortune I932); the Alorese are in continual and aggressive
disagreement(DuBois I 944); and the disruptiveeffects of clan feuding have been widely
observed. It is difficult to interpret conflict of this kind in terms of a crystalline model
of structureand function. In fact, so dubious is the functional value of such behaviours,
that it appearsprobable that such organizational types would have little survival value
in the face of new and critical problemsor stresses.2
It is suggested here that what is needed for an understandingof conflict in groups is
a dynamic model which views conflict as an outcome of the interaction of external
stresses and internal strains. Using such a model it is possible to classify conflict in
several different ways. Attention is given here to a particular type of non-adaptive
inter-personalconflict which we have called factionalism.3
ATTRIBUTES OF FACTIONALISM

It has been suggested above that factionalism is a phenomenon which occurs within
groups. We use the word group to refer to an intercommunicating aggregation of
sub-units (individuals or sub-groups) having the conscious intention of perpetuating
their existence and achieving certain goals. A group consists of people assembled to-
gether for the purpose of achieving co-operation towards a common set of goals.
I07

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
io8 BERNARD J. SIEGEL & ALAN R. BEALS

Although the differencebetween factionalismand war or feud relationshipsis not always


clear-cut, it is possible in most cases to define the group in terms of the attitudes of those
concerned. Warfare is not generally considered to divide a pre-existing group, while
factionalismis considereddivisive by all concerned.
In saying that factionalisminvolves a conscious awarenessof a division in the group,
we have suggested another attribute of factionalism, namely, that it is invariably a form
of overt conflict. It requires two or more individuals or groups consciously engaged in
verbal or physical aggression against each other. This relationship of overt conflict
is a reciprocalrelationshipin which those concerned have a clear and public awareness
of attack and counter-attack. The various forms of covert conflict do not involve such
an awareness, or if there is awareness, not all parties to the conflict possess it. Covert
conflict never becomes public knowledge and its existence is unrecognized. Examples
of such covert conflict would be the 'line' as used by Negroes in the American South,
witchcraft practised secretly (giving a man the evil eye when his back is turned), or
practicesanalogousto the psychoanalyticconcept of 'over-protection'.
A third characteristic of factionalism is that it takes place between sub-units of a
group in a manner which does not conformto expectations and which does not maintain
but disrupts the co-operative enterprise. Factional conflict is not satisfactorilyresolved
or regulated. It has a tendency to intensify and to interfere in ever increasing degree
with the ability of the group to achieve its goals. There is a difference between party
conflict and factionalism, for party conflict, although overt, tends to conform to expec-
tations, tends to maintain rather than disrupt the co-operative venture and tends to
be permanentlyor periodically resolved. Examples of party conflict are conflict between
political parties, between football teams, between intermarrying kinship groups
(exemplified in the Potlatch at marriage among the Kwakiutl of the north-west coast
of North America), between sodalities (e.g. the Lumpwoods and Foxes among the
Crow Indians of Montana), or between moieties (e.g. the town division among the
CreekIndians in south-easternNorth America).
Factionalism can also be considered to differ from the expression of overt mech-
anismsof social control. Where a dominant sub-unit within the group punishes or levels
malevolent accusations at a subordinate group or individual in a manner which con-
tributes to the maintenance of the group and the success of the co-operative enterprise,
the situation may resemblefactionalism,but its resultsare quite different.
Factionalismthus differsfrom conflict between groups, party conflict, and the appli-
cation of overt social sanctions. It can be defined as overt,unregulated(unresolved)conflict
which interfereswith the achievementof the goals of the group. The isolation of factionalism
as a particular type of conflict is not, however, intended to obscure the probable fact
that all forms of overt display of agressive behaviour are closely interrelated. Some of
these interrelationshipswill be discussedlater under the heading of strain.
Within the frameworkof the definition proposed above, it is possible to locate two
extremesof factionalism-schismatic and pervasive. Schismaticfactionalism is conflict be-
tween well defined and cohesive sub-groups within the larger group. Such conflict
would appear to be the result of a partial failure of mechanisms for resolving conflict
within the group. That is, there is a failure only of the mechanisms which tie together
the larger sub-units and conflict is restrictedto a limited sphere. Examples of this might

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CONFLICT AND FACTIONALIST DISPUTE IO9

be the American Civil War or the factions described by Oscar Lewis (I954). Pervasive
factionalism is conflict which occurs not only between larger sub-units of the group, but
also within the sub-units. It reflects a failure, in most cases a partial failure, of mech-
anismsfor resolvinginter-personalconflict generally. Although similaritiescan be found
between pervasive factionalism and some aspects of 'anomie' or 'disintegration', a
conceptual distinction can be made, for factional conflict, whether pervasive or
schismatic, always involves a recognition of a need for preservationof the group. The
motivation underlying factional conflict is the re-establishment of the co-operative
venture. Factionalismis a disagreement overthemeansto be employed, not over the goal to
be achieved. The factional struggle is a struggle to punish or eliminate other members
of the group in such a way that the group can be reconstructed along the 'proper'
lines. The struggle is maintained in terms of the group and the value of group unity
or cohesivenessis never questioned.
STRESS OR SITUATIONAL FACTORS
Inasmuch as factionalism, in varying degree, appears to be characteristic of a broad
variety of human groups, it may prove worthwhile to examine some of the factorswhich
appear to be involved in the development of factionalism. First, consideration will be
given to those factors or forces externalto thegroupwhich may play a role in its develop-
ment. These factors, for the purpose of the present exposition, will be labelled stress.
The concept of stressimplies the existence of a dichotomy between the group viewed as
a system and the external environment. It also implies a continuity between the group
and the external environment. The view of a group and its culture in terms of stressis
taken from a position which reveals the group as neither a closed system nor a com-
pletely open system, but as a system which is always partially self-regulatingand always
partially subject to external regulation. The group is viewed as a system within a larger
external system. At this point, it should be emphasized that the view of the group as a
partially self-regulatingmechanism is not analogous to the view of the group as a servo-
mechanism or as an equilibrium seeking organization. After exposure to stress, the
group does not necessarilyrestore itself to its previous condition, and, when there is no
change in the external situation, groups actively seek to create changes. Human
motives of curiosity, exploration, and escape from boredom are all contrary to any
notion of a desirefor, or automatic seekingof, equilibrium.
At the same time, the concept of equilibriumis a useful means of arriving at a defini-
tion of stress. Two systematically organized entities, the group and its situation or
environment can be imagined. As long as the interrelationshipsbetween these two en-
tities maintain a normal, patterned, and predictablecharacter,the situation is incapable
of altering the normal behaviour of the group in any way. Change in the behaviour
of the group always implies changes in the relationship of the group and the situation.
Such changes, which can take place either as a result of problem seeking behaviour on
the part of the group or as a result of some change in the situation, are defined as stress.
Stress is any changein the group-situationrelationshipwhich has a finite efect upon the behaviour
of thegroup.
Stress is not necessarily any kind of thing which is perceived by the group. It is a
finite interruptionof the group-situationrelationshipand has an impact upon the group

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
IIO BERNARD J. SIEGEL & ALAN R. BEALS

regardlessof the nature of the group's perception of it. The effects of this impact are in
varying degree dependent upon the nature of the group and the nature of the group's
perceptions of the stress. Defined in such a way, stress impliesthepresenceof an outside
observer
whose perception of the nature of stressrepresents,theoretically at least, a closer
approximationto reality than can ordinarily be achieved by the group. For those who
consider reality to be definable only in terms of perception, stress can be regarded
as being theperceptionwhich would be entertainedby the group if it had access to all relevant
and could deal with it impartially.
information

DIMENSIONS OF STRESS
The finite nature of a stress can be described in terms of at least six dimensions:
covertness,randomness,complexity,duration,curtailment,and selectivity.The first four of these
refer primarily to the finite perceptibility of the stress and the last two refer primarily
to the impact of the stress. Covertnesscan be defined as the relative ease with which a
stressmay be perceived. A change in genotype would be more covert than a change in
phenotype; hookworm epidemics are more covert than whooping-cough epidemics. As
these examples suggest, 'absolute covertness',while it may exist, is greatly affected by
the nature of the aids to sensory perception available to a particular group. Micro-
scopes, hearing aids, and eyeglasseswould greatly increase a group's potential ability to
renderstressovert.
Randomnessis closely linked to covertnessand might be consideredto be a part of it.
Randomness refersto the regularity with which a stress appears and could be expected
to have a direct effect upon the predictability of a stress and consequent effects upon
perceptibility. The daily reappearance of the sun, the periodical return of the tax
collector, and seasonal epidemics are far less random in nature than are thunder
showersor epidemicswhich are not seasonal.
Some kinds of stress present problems which can be solved in a few steps; others
present a large number of separateproblems all of which must be solved before the stress
can be dealt with adequately. This dimension of stressis referredto here as complexity.
The problem presented by an unattached stranger, for example, would be far less com-
plex than the problem presented by a stranger who was an ambassadorof a powerful
outside group.
Duration appears to have effects differing somewhat from those of covertness,
randomness, and complexity. These last three dimensions seem to be directly related
in more or less linear fashion to the perceptibility of a stress and to the ability of any
group to solve the stress. The relationship of duration to these factors is not easily
predicted. Very short duration would presumably make both resolution and perception
of stressdifficult and could bar any kind of solution including a fantasy solution. A stress
of long duration would presumablybe an unresolvablestressand would almost certainly
lead to the development of a fantasysolution.
The four dimensions listed above can be applied to situations in general. They are
relevant to a definition of stressonly when curtailment occurs. Curtailmentrefersto the
impact of a stress-specifically, the extent to which the normal activities of the group
are limited or affected. A volcanic eruption or a famine would be highly curtailingwhile
a complicated crosswordpuzzle would rank low on curtailment. More than any other

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CONFLICT AND FACTIONALIST DISPUTE III

dimension of stress, curtailment determines the group's possible choice of problem-


solving techniques, but it has no necessary effect upon solvability or perceptibility as do
the firstfour dimensions.
If duration is of sufficientlength to permit adjustment to a stress and if covertness,
randomness,complexity, and curtailment are maximized, then it is expected that the
probability that the group would be incapable of finding a realistic solution to the
stresswould be correspondinglyincreased. The maximization of these dimensionswould
compel the group to choose 'unrealistic'solutions (i.e. solutionswhich do not remove the
stress or its undesired consequences), but in no way would they compel the group to
choose between factionalism, individualistic solutions, dissolution of the group, or
fantasy solutions. In other words, the maximation of these dimensions increases the
probability that factionalism will develop in the sense that they limit the group to
'unrealistic' problem solutions, only one of which is factionalism. The only exception
to this, which calls perhaps for a more detailed definition of curtailment, is a situation
in which dissolutionof the group is prevented by the nature of the stress.
The sixth dimension, selectivity, stands out as the most important possible deter-
minant of factionalism. Selectivity is the extent to which a stressgives unequal treatment
to sub-units within the group. A highly selective stress would give different sub-units
different experiences of the stress. To the extent that these different experiences give
rise to differingperceptionsof the stressand varying ideas conoerningpossiblesolutions,
disagreementsconcerning the methods to be used in dealing with it could be expected.
When selectivity is of such a nature as to accentuate existing strains and cleavages
within the group, the group is compelled to choose between factionalism or individual-
istic solutions leading to dissolution. Even this choice may prove not to be a choice, for
some degree of factionalism may be a necessary antecedent to the individualistic
solutions.
Selectivity tends to have about it the appearance of purposiveness. Impersonal
stresses, such as famine, disease, catastrophe in the physical environment, and 'over-
population', evidently lack the kind of purposivenesswhich might make them selective.
It ig possible to find, as among the Kota where an epidemic selectively attacked the
religious structure (Mandelbaum I94I), examples of selectivity in impersonal stresses,
but such selectivity would appear to be on the whole improbable.
It is necessary in most cases to seek the source of selectivity in stresseswhich are
imposed by an outside group. Even here, a great many possible acculturative stresses
must be regarded as basically impersonal. Gradual diffusion of new values, beliefs, and
techniques would not ordinarilybe selective in nature or particularlyhigh on the other
dimensionsof stress. Of somewhat more interest is the kind of situation where diffusion
appearsto be almost calculated to accentuate internal strain. The introduction of highly
effective public health techniques without concurrentintroduction of improved techno-
logies in other fields is almost certain to lead to 'over-population' and a maximization
of stress. Such an occurrence could accentuate existing cleavages when they proved to
be more advantageousto one social class than to another.
Situations of 'forced cultural change' are again not necessarilyselective and may be
quite impersonal. Imprisonment on reservations, the prevention of emigration, the
forbidding of certain kinds of acculturation, the banning of head-hunting or the forced
H R.A.T. J.

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
II2 BERNARD J. SJEGEL & ALAN R. BEALS

introduction of Christianity carry with them no necessary implication of selectivity


and may even contribute to cohesiveness rather than reduce it. A highly overt stress is
not likely to be conducive to factionalism. On the other hand, it appears likely that
force need not be, in fact usually is not, applied in an impersonal manner.
It can be concluded that the situationmost likely to lead to the developmentoffactionalism
is one in which a dominantexternalsociety selectivelyinfluencesthe group in a mannerwhich is
covertand which tends to accentuateexisting cleavageswithin the group. While it would not be
surprising if factionalism occurred under other conditions, we should ordinarily expect
to find it in acculturation situations where a subordinated group is being selectively
influenced by a group or groups capable of exercising high constraint over a consider-
able period of time in a covert, random, and complicated manner.

THE ROLE OF STRAIN IN SOCIAL SYSTEMS


Although the nature of stress may contribute greatly to the development of factionalism,
it is probable that stress alone cannot make the development of factionalism inevitable.
Under even the most extreme pressures of the kind most conducive to factionalism,
certain groups may not develop it. Other groups may develop factionalism under the
application of relatively mild stresses. This kind of differential response to external
stress appears to be traceable to the kind and variety of strains in a particular social
system. The word 'strain' is usedhereto referto potential conflictsconcerningacceptabletechniques
for thesolutionof eithertraditionalproblemsor stresses.
However stable a social system may be, the norms of (or models for) conduct will
often accord differential satisfactions to sub-units of the group or impose dilemmas in
role-playing for which there are no clear-cut definitions of appropriate behaviour.
Firth, for example, records the case of a Tikopian man who found himself simul-
taneously in the position of kinsman to a bride and in affinal relationship to the groom.
Conflicting role responsibilities necessitated personal choice in this situation (Firth
I95I, pp. 57-6I). Role expectations and interaction between brothers in an East
Indian village may also involve strain when loyalty to the older brother comes into
conflict with other expectations of the younger. In the eastern pueblos of New Mexico,
authority relationships between generations are marked and generally effective, but
many young men give evidences of frustration and disagreement with the decisions with
which they feel they must ultimately comply. In general whenever individuals are
subjected to social sanctions for the wrong choice of response in such ambiguous or
unequally rewarding role-playing situations, the relationship can be considered to
involve strain. It could be said that the universal existence of punitive sanctions is
evidence for the existence of strain, for they would be unnecessary if sub-units within
the group were not placed in situations where appropriate behaviours were ambigu-
ously defined.
Similarly the existence of any kind of overt conflict can be taken as evidence of the
existence of strain. Where there are patterns of feud and warfare, the presence of an
external threat is frequently used as a mechanism to support powerful punitive sanctions
in the existing social system. The removal of the external threat then necessitates a
major reorientation. Where overt conflict exists between moieties or political parties
and is periodically resolved by means of overt social controls, the removal of these

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CONFLICT AND FACTIONALIST DISPUTE II3

controls leads to the development of unregulated conflict. Hence, although overt


conflict may often have a functional value under certain conditions, a relatively minor
change in the nature of the stress to which the group is subjected will provoke major
changes in the social organization of the group.
Strains such as those described above reflect potential social cleavages inherent in
key role and group alignments. They appear to become functionally important when a
group is subjected to stress. Consequently an analysis of types of reaction to new prob-
lems posed for the group must take into account the interdependence of these factors.
Our feeling, based on this exploration into the subject, is that varying stress-strain
patterns will lead to different reaction tendencies. Our special concern here is to suggest
in hypothetical terms the particular patterns that are likely to eventuate in factionalism.
Initially, therefore, it will be necessary to designate recurrent classes of strains charac-
teristic of different social systems. We do not pretend to have exhausted these types, but
wish to suggest some of the types most frequently encountered in the anthropological
literature.
Taking as a point of departure the theoretical analysis of political systems provided
by Fortes & Evans-Pritchard (I 940), let us first consider lineage-clan or segmentary
systems. Societies of this kind tend to consist of a number of separate but equal unilineal
kinship segments with rights and duties similarly distributed among them. External
controls are weak or lacking, and conflict is regulated by jural and moral considerations
or by mutual group interest. A recurrent kind of tension in segmentary matrilineal
societies is derived from divided loyalties in the avunculo-matrilineal and paternal role
expectations of males. Residence norms and unilineal kin alignments in most of these
cases appear to involve uneasy compromises with the realities of developing emotional
ties. Such a situiation is described in Fortes' 'Time and Social Structure: An Ashanti
Case Study' (I949, pp. 54-84). Other sources of conflict may stem from within the
family or lineage where a headman or council may manipulate the conduct of others
or where quarrels occur between agnates. The potential lines of cleavage, then, are
between segments, kin ordinates, and affines.
A second kind of potential cleavage exists in communities where a common denomi-
nator of marked overt controls is generalized through family, religious, and political
alignments. Spanish American societies and most eastern pueblos in the south-western
United States are examples of this. Among the former, the male family head's relation-
ship to family members has a direct counterpart in the priest-follower and patron-
employee relationships. Conflict based on role frustrations is always possible in any
of these relationships and as a matter of fact nearly all appear to require the support
of actual or supernatural punitive sanctions.
Where rank differences play an important part in regulating conflict and in the
shaping and sharing of values, splits can occur where disagreement about role expecta-
tions, outlook, privileges, and responsibilities come to be openly expressed (see Bateson
I935, pp. I8I-3). Certain kinds of ranked interdependencies-particularly feudal,
quasi-feudal, and caste or caste-like systems-appear to be stable over rather long
periods of time. This can be attributed to the presence in such groups of a well-defined
hierarchy of power holders and the presence of reciprocating responsibilities linking
individuals in ranks above and below themselves. Barring the introduction of stresses,

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
II4 BERNARD J. SIEGEL & ALAN R. BEALS

latent schisms in such societies are likely to remain subordinated to shared feelings about
the common welfare.
Strain in general tends to make itself felt along lines of prescribed discrimination
in succession to rights, particularly rights to property or to positions in which decisions
are made. Conflict between brothers in East Indian villages appears to be derived from
this as did the fights for the throne in certain African and European kingdoms. Similarly
where the social distance between sub-units in the group is very great and the oppor-
tunities for upward mobility in the hierarchy of social ranks are minimal, tensions are
likely to be endemic. This is often the case in stratified societies in which several
intervening strata separate individuals at the top and bottom of the hierarchy and where
interaction tends to be formalized and infrequent.
As a final consideration, societies in which overt controls have a critical function in
supporting and regulating individual habit systems (internalized controls) face special
problems in maintaining the configuration of control. The same function appears to
be served by the kind of controls described by Adams in connexion with conflict in an
Egyptian village (Adams I957). There, conflict appears to be controlled by certain
overt cues embedded in a strict code of manners: tone pitch and voice melody, mien
and stereotyped gestures. Here, as where more overt punitive sanctions are mobilized,
sources of friction, of tension, and of cleavage in the social system tend to erupt in
increasing degree as overt controls become weakened. The efficiency of traditional
relationships is impaired and ego controls fail to inhibit expressions of conflict about
normative means for achieving agreed-upon goals.
It is precisely in such groups, especially when they are confronted with stresses
having the attributes of fairly long duration, covertness, complexity, curtailment, and
selectivity that pervasive factionalism occurs with striking regularity. Factionalism
appears to go hand in hand with the existence of an authority system supported by
strong overt punitive sanctions where the centralized authority is susceptible to the
threat of new allegiance (see also Firth I949, pp. I68-88).
On the other hand, as long as the normal range of alternatives appropriate to the
various life situations is not challenged by unusual circumstances, conventional ways of
handling strain will tend to suffice. Even though traditional techniques for solving
problems should prove inadequate for coping with stress, it is still possible that imported
or specially invented techniques can be applied in such a way that strains and cleavages
will not be accentuated. This appears to be true of the situations described by Hohenthal
& McCorkle (I955) of the many cases of formal substitution of cultural elements
without change in meaning such as the spread of Christian religious concepts or of
antagonistic acculturation (Loeb & Devereux I943).
When stress-induced exacerbations of strain are not resolved, other less adaptive
reactions tend to occur. In many cases these, occurring singly or together, may delay
or prevent the development of factionalism. For example, cumulative frustrations or
lack of consensus on decisions may lead certain individuals to leave the group. While
this may bring about change in the direction of involuting or reinforcing traditional
standards and patterns of control, it does not seriously disturb the cohesion or the
cultural orientations of those who remain. A related response may be a tendency to-
ward apathy and withdrawal from group affairs. Inability to act within the group may

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CONFLICT AND FACTIONALIST DISPUTE II5

be evidenced by anomie, suicide, infanticide, a lowering of the birth rate, or an increase


in crime. In some cases older habits may be expressed at a much lower level of efficiency.
Strain and stress will be ignored by decreasing the intensity of interaction. Picuris
pueblo seems to be a case in point. Here the existence of strains is concealed through a
conspiracy of silence although it is apparent that deterioration in ability to handle
situations will increase unless the sources of strain are rooted out.
Individuals and groups unable to make realistic adaptations to environmental
threats and dangers may have recourse to fantasy. This can take the form of prophetic
or messianic cults or religious revitalization movements. There are numerous examples
of such tendencies. In all of these cases the social arrangements linked to actual or
perceived survival involve rigorous ritualistic or quasi-ritualistic submission to external
controls over behaviour.
Another type of reaction which may occur is what might be called malevolentaccusa-
tion. This may include such behaviours as vicious gossip, chronic sorcery and witch-
craft, and the various kinds of scapegoat practices. It should be noted that these
behaviours can occur when overt controls have not been known to be strong (Eskimo,
Navaho), as well as in situations where once effective controls have been weakened as
in Zuni, Latin American mestizo or Eastern Pueblo communities. In general malevolent
accusation can be thought of as a device for justifying the failure of the group by placing
the blame on a small minority.
It is to be noted that all the maladaptive reactions to stress situations mentioned
above represent strains in the social system. Hence, although a stable social system can
be built (and most are) round such deferred solutions to internal strains or external
stresses, the presence of the artifacts of such deferred solutions render the group
increasingly likely to develop factionalism. For example, revitalistic movements with
their strong controls and tendency to encourage submissiveness often encounter severe
organizational difficulties when promised supernatural assistance is not provided.
Again, use of the technique of malevolent accusation leads to increasing social stratifica-
tion and the threat that the group accused of being at fault may ultimately reject the
goals of the group. The only maladaptive adjustment which would seem to preclude
factionalism would appear to be withdrawal leading to the dissolution of the group and
the abandonment of its goals. Ultimately it appears probable that factionalism will be
found to be a precursor of dissolution although factionalism is not necessarilyfollowed by
dissolution.
Whether viewed as a step towards the dissolution of a group or as the end point
of a certain kind of interaction between stress and strain, factionalism appears to be
one of the more common maladaptive reactions to stress. When factionalism occurs,
potential antagonisms inherent in strains are magnified to a point where they become
publicly divisive and potential cleavages become sources of unregulated conflict. The
form that factionalism takes is dependent upon the particular nature of the social struc-
ture and its built-in strains and cleavages.

CONCLUSION

In this paper we have tried to explicate the dynamics of factionalist dispute and its
relationship to other forms of conflict resolution. Without attempting to develop a

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
I I6 BERNARD J. SIEGEL & ALAN R. BEALS

satisfactory theory of conflict, it is nevertheless possible to make the assumption from


available cross-cultural literature that dispute will originate round configurations of
rights and duties which define structural features of a society. Furthermore, as the
environmental context in which a social system functions is altered, behavioural
adaptations may take several forms as discussed above. It is argued that the particular
form taken will be a function of special relationships between stress (alterations in
pressures external to the system) and strain (sensitive points of potential disruption
within the system). Factionalist dispute is simply one of these, but it is a widespread
phenomenon-whether it occurs in an Indian village, an American Indian pueblo, an
African community, a labour Union, or a political party. We might expect, therefore,
that systematic comparative study of this process would provide a good opportunity
for securing insight into the nature of social systems.

NOTES
1 The argument for this paper was derived originally from an analysis of field work observations in
Mysore State in southern India by A. Beals between March I952 and August I953, supported by the
Social Science Research Council; from field work by B. Siegel in Taos and Picuris pueblos during the
summers of I947 and I957; and from a project on the Codification of Acculturation Phenomena con-
ducted at Stanford University with an initial grant by the Wenner-Gren Foundation and the Stanford
Committee for Research in the Social Sciences.
2 Observations of this sort, when our knowledge is more adequate, may bear upon newer approaches
to the nature of evolution. Simpson, for example, points out that many parts of the world which have
changed little over great time spans are filled with very ancient forms of life, and that newer, more
complex forms do not tend to displace them unless clearly more adaptive to such life-spaces. Similarly
it is probable that certain forms of society and culture are viable within given environmental limits
(both human and physical), but may be displaced by more adaptive forms under environmental change.
See G. G. Simpson, The Meaningof Evolution,chapter 9; Julian Huxley, 'Evolution Cultural and Biolo-
gical', in W. L. ThomasJr. (ed.), rearbookof Anthropology(I955); also B.J. Siegel (I955).
3 Factionalism has been reported and described variously in India. Lewis's study (I954) appears to
deal with schismatic factionalism. Firth (I957) has drawn together a symposium of papers which de-
scribe adequately the operation of pervasive factionalism as it occurs in various Indian and overseas
societies. They do not provide, however, any explanatory analysis. The writers have also examined
relative case materials from the Marshall Islands (Tobin I953); Isleta Pueblo (French I948); the Skagit
of north-western North America (Collins I952); and Jamaica (Kerr I952) which describe variously
schismatic and pervasive factionalism without actually identifying the phenomena.

REFERENCES

ADAMS, JOHN B. I 957. Culture and Conflict in an Egyptian Village. Amer.Anthrop.,59, pp. 225-35.
BATESON, GREGORY I 935. Culture Contact and Schismogenesis.MAN I 935, I 99.
-BEALS, ALAN R. I954.- CultureChangeand Social Conflictin a South Indian Village. Unpublished
Ph.D.
dissertation. Berkeley, University of California.
COLLINS, JUNE McC. I952. An Interpretation of Skagit Intergroup Conflict during Acculturation.
Amer. Anthrop., 54, pp. 347-55-
DuBois, CORA I 944. ThePeopleof Alor. Minneapolis.
FIRTH, RAYMOND I948. Authority and Public Opinion in Tikopia, in SocialStructure:StudiesPresented
to
A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, Meyer Fortes (ed.). Oxford.
FIRTH, RAYMOND, et al. I957. Factions in India and Overseas Dependencies. Brit. Sociol.,8.

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CONFLICT AND FACTIONALIST DISPUTE I 17

FORTES, MEYER I949. Time and Social Structure: An Ashanti Case Study, in Social Structure:Studies
toA. R. Radcliffe-Brown,
Presented Meyer Fortes (ed.). Oxford.
FORTES, MEYER & EVANS-PRITCHARD, E. E. (eds.) I940. AfricanPoliticalSystems.
London.
FORTUNE, REOF. I932. Sorcerersof Dobu.London.
FRENCH, DAVID I938. Factionalism in Isleta Pueblo.Monographs of the American Ethnological Society,
14. New York.
HENRY,JULES I 94 I. JunglePeople,a KaingangTribeof theHighlandsof Brazil. New York.
HOHENTHAL, W. D. & MCCORKLE, THOMAS I955. The Problem of Aboriginal Persistence. Sthwest. j.
Anthrop.,
xI, pp. 288-300.
HUXLEY, JULIAN I955. Evolution, Cultural and Biological, in rearbookof Anthropology,
W. L. Thomas,
Jr. (ed.). Chicago.
KERR, MADELINE I952.PersonalityandConflictinJamaica.Liverpool.
LEWIS, OSCAR & HARVANT SINGH DHILLON I954. GroupDynamicsin a North-IndianVillage, a Study of
Factions.New Delhi.
LOEB, EDWIN M. & DEVEREUX, GEORGE 1943. Antagonistic Acculturation. Amer.Sociol.Rev., 8, pp.
I33-47.
MANDELBAUM, DAVID G. I94I. Social Trends and Personal Pressures,in Language,CultureandPersonality,
Leslie Spier et al. (eds.). Menasha, Wisconsin.
SIEGEL, BERNARD J. I955. High Anxiety Levels and Cultural Integration: Notes on a Psycho-Cultural
Hypothesis. SocialForces,34, pp. 42-8.
SIMPSON, GEORGE G. I949. Themeaning of Evolution.New Haven.
TOBIN, J. E. I 953. An Investigation of theSocio-PoliticalSchismonMajuroAtoll. Mimeographed.

This content downloaded from 146.201.208.22 on Tue, 03 Nov 2015 14:54:23 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like