Christian Religious Education and The Development of Moral Virtues - A Neo-Thomistic Approach

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

British Journal of Religious Education

ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cbre20

Christian religious education and the development


of moral virtues: a neo-Thomistic approach

Jarosław Horowski

To cite this article: Jarosław Horowski (2020) Christian religious education and the
development of moral virtues: a neo-Thomistic approach, British Journal of Religious
Education, 42:4, 447-458, DOI: 10.1080/01416200.2020.1752618

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/01416200.2020.1752618

© 2020 The Author(s). Published by Informa


UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group.

Published online: 14 Apr 2020.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 7505

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Citing articles: 5 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cbre20
BRITISH JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS EDUCATION
2020, VOL. 42, NO. 4, 447–458
https://doi.org/10.1080/01416200.2020.1752618

Christian religious education and the development of moral


virtues: a neo-Thomistic approach
Jarosław Horowski
Faculty of Philosophy and Social Sciences, Nicolaus Copernicus University in Toruń, Toruń, Poland

ABSTRACT KEYWORDS
This article explores the implications for Christian religious education of Moral virtues; cardinal
the theory of moral virtues formulated by Thomas Aquinas and developed virtues; Christian religious
by the contemporary Neo-Thomists. The analysis is divided into two parts. education; neo-Thomistic
theory; Poland
The first part introduces Thomistic virtue theory and presents cardinal
virtues crucial for Thomistic ethics: prudence, justice, temperance and
fortitude, as the reference points for moral education. This part also
includes analysis of the relationship between cardinal and theological
virtues, leading to the conclusion that Christian religious education also
requires the development of theological virtues. The second part explores,
through Thomistic theory, what factors condition the development of
a person’s moral character (i.e. his/her moral virtues) and what those
factors mean for supporting moral education within Christian religious
education, initially within the context of Polish schooling. Particular atten-
tion is given to three issues: introducing the concept of responsibility for
community members, introducing knowledge of moral virtues, and build-
ing a relationship with God.

Introduction
The analysis undertaken in the present article aims at answering the question of the potential of
Christian religious education within the scope of supporting young people’s moral virtue develop-
ment. This relates to significant issues concerning – firstly – the process of supporting young
people’s moral character development and – secondly – the role played by (Christian) religious
education in that process. Education includes students gaining knowledge of the surrounding world,
moral aspects of their actions and their religious conditions. Religious education generally provides
knowledge regarding different religions, paying particular attention to the dominant denominations
in a given society, and shows the relationship between religion and morality. Secularisation and the
principle of tolerance for people of different religions, denominations and non-believers participat-
ing in religious classes (Franken and Loobuyck 2017) mean that there is a reluctance for religious
education to induct children into a particular religion. In Poland, despite the fact that religious
education is taught by representatives of a given religious community, it does not in practice include
initiation into religious life, for example into prayer or liturgy, but typically involves a transmission of
information alone (Tomasik 1998; Chałupniak 2012). The specificity of the Polish context includes the
tendency of many parents to leave religious development of their children to the school, rather than
the home or church. Considering the significant connections between religion and morals, namely
between persons’ faith and their moral choices, the question arises as to how well Christian religious
education that is implemented in such a way can support the moral development of the individuals.

CONTACT Jarosław Horowski jarohor@umk.pl


© 2020 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives License http://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the
original work is properly cited, and is not altered, transformed, or built upon in any way.
448 J. HOROWSKI

On the one hand, it is easy to maintain that a privileged place for supporting the development of
moral character is the family or religious community, for example a parish, rather than the school, so
in school there is no need for moral education based on the faith of the individuals. On the other
hand, school is where maturing people first encounter persons not belonging to their families or the
local communities who are befriended by the families. In school, children have to cooperate with
people from different cultural and religious backgrounds. The period of school education conse-
quently becomes the time in which moral virtues, crucial for further functioning in public space and
occupational roles, are developed in maturing persons. The relationships with schoolmates are often
where the germ of moral virtues and vices begins to take shape. May (Christian) religious education
support an individual in this area of development, and to what extent? Does the school, caring about
maintaining worldview neutrality, lose the chance to support the moral development of individuals
by preferring a particular form of Christian religious education that ignores the connection between
the moral development and individual’s faith?
For this analysis, the key category is ‘virtue’ and its associated theory, as formulated within neo-
Thomistic philosophy. The practice of using the category of virtue to conduct an ethical reflection,
examine moral development from the perspective of theory, and formulate concepts of moral
education has a rich history, since its roots can be traced back to ancient philosophy and to the
works of Plato and Aristotle (Wren 2014). Unlike other ethical traditions, such as deontology and
utilitarianism, in which attention is given to the target of particular individuals’ decision, in virtue
ethics an account is made from the target to agents (Hursthouse and Pettigrove 2018) and to
character traits which, in a moral dimension, adjust themselves in relation to other people – positive
traits being diligence, charity, understanding and patience, and negative ones being laziness, self-
ishness, arrogance or cowardice. Consequently, virtue theory offers a great opportunity to analyse
specific dispositions and moral decisions, as well as to observe moral development and its socialisa-
tion and educational conditions. It also facilitates an understanding of the dissonance between
individuals’ theoretical recognition of what is morally good or bad, and the decisions made by them,
which indicates that moral decisions are influenced not only by the ability to assess what is good or
bad, what should be done and what should be avoided, but also by the ability to refrain from small or
big indulgences for the sake of the greater good, as well as patience in confronting hardships that
individuals may encounter in the pursuit of good.
In philosophical reflection in the 17th and 18th centuries, the category of virtue was somewhat
marginalised, but since the end of the 19th century, it has experienced a renaissance in philosophical
thought. This is associated with the intensive development of empirical sciences, psychology and
sociology, in which it is frequently asked what stable feature do the attitudes of individuals towards
other people and the external world have. In this context, the theory of virtues as moral traits
gradually became a bridge between the fields of ethics and empirical sciences (Carr 1991; Steutel
and Carr 1999; Curren 2015; Szutta 2015a; Snow 2016). The representatives of neo-Thomistic
philosophy were the first to refer to the category of virtue. This school in the field of philosophy
has been developed intensively since the end of the 19th century in Catholic circles, not least
because it was seen within it as a channel for dialogue between natural science and matters of faith
(Gilson 1971). As an integral part of philosophy, the category of virtue became fundamental not only
to ethics but also to pedagogy (Kunowski 1966). Through the perspective of virtue, efforts were
made to build a Catholic theory of moral education. One can trace the level of progress of these
efforts in the works of Joseph Mausbach (1920, 1925), a professor at the University of Münster in
Germany, or of Jacek Woroniecki, one of the founders of the Catholic University of Lublin in Poland
(Woroniecki 1922; Horowski 2015, 78–82). In the Anglo-Saxon philosophical tradition, the revival of
reflection on virtue is associated with Elizabeth Anscombe and her 1958 text entitled Modern Moral
Philosophy, in which she criticised the prevailing ethical theories of the 20th century and explored
their weaknesses and deficiencies; what is more, she made a plea for a return to Aristotelian ethical
thought (Anscombe 1958; Szutta 2015b, 14). One of the best-known projects concerning virtue
ethics, which is based on Aristotle’s own reflections, was proposed by Alasdair MacIntyre in his book
BRITISH JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS EDUCATION 449

After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory (2007). Also within this trend, virtue theory finds application in
pedagogical thought (Arthur et al. 2016; Carr 1991, 1996, 2017; Eaude 2016; Kristjánsson 2015;
Kaźmierczak 2019).
The reference to neo-Thomistic philosophy is related to the emphasis that it places on the real
conditions of humans actions (Krąpiec 1999). It draws attention to how real people ― amongst
whom individuals live and whom the individuals try to care for ― condition the decisions made by
them and, consequently, the development of their character traits. Neo-Thomistic thought also
examines the reality of the subjects who, when making decisions about dealing with another person,
take into account their abilities and the impact of various decisions on themselves. The use of other
philosophical positions for analyses, such as phenomenology or hermeneutics, means shifting the
point of interest from actual reality to the subjects’ consciousness, i.e. a subjective image of reality. By
transferring this specificity to the pedagogical field, one can argue that Thomistic thought refers to
and tries to analyse the significance of real conditionings of individuals’ experiences for their moral
development, while the domain of other philosophical concepts within the philosophy of education
is the reflection on subjective aspects of experience and building the image of the world (including
knowledge of what is morally right or wrong) of individuals. The specificity of Thomism is reflected in
its potential but also in its weaknesses in analysing and explaining educational reality. On the one
hand, within its scope it is possible to show the importance of external reality, as perceived by the
senses, to the process of development of individuals; on the other hand, since Thomism does not
penetrate into consciousness conditionings, this school does not analyse or explain all the develop-
ment conditions of the individuals. Bernard Lonergan attempted to overcome this weakness of
Thomistic thought in the field of pedagogy by developing a philosophy of education that was built
on the Thomistic theory of knowledge and included processes of judging that are strongly con-
nected with sensory experience and reasoning ― a specifically intellectual activity. The specificity of
his approach in relation to Jacques Maritain’s philosophy was highlighted by Mario D’Souza (2016).
However, it does not change the fact that the specificity of Thomistic thought in the field of
pedagogy is based on referring mainly to the real conditionings of human development and
building an education concept that uses those conditionings as a basis.
The approach to the research problem outlined above means that in this case Thomism is treated
as an interpretative key and an analytical philosophy that builds the basis for understanding reality of
Christian religious education, but does not claim the right to build comprehensive visions of the
world (Bocheński 1962), and even less so to justify or support any model of social relations (i.e. to act
in favour of a specific civilisation ― Christian, liberal or dialogical) (Luby 2019). These analyses are
only an attempt to use neo-Thomistic philosophy, and especially the theory of moral virtues
formulated within it, to ascertain what conditionings the moral development of an individual and
what that means for moral education provided within religious, especially Christian, education. An
attempt to answer these questions will be made in the second part of the text. The first part will
present a brief description of the Thomistic theory of moral virtues, which also incorporates the issue
of special challenges that are faced by Christians.

Christian morality from the perspective of the Thomistic theory of virtues


The selection of character traits which, from the moral dimension, improve people and thereby
improve their relationships with other persons, after a deeper reflection always raises some doubts.
Diligence – so appreciated in working life – might be accompanied by neglecting duties which
should be fulfilled by individuals towards their close relatives: spouse, children, parents. Repeatedly,
the public sphere raises the subject of courage shown by mountain climbers who strive to reach the
highest peaks on Earth. At the same time, regarding the fact that they ignore the risk of losing their
lives and that they might leave their children with a single parent, it is difficult to perceive their
courage as a virtue. Alasdair MacIntyre noticed this ambivalence and consequently acknowledged
that one could speak of a particular trait as a virtue or vice only with regard to the contexts of one’s
450 J. HOROWSKI

life: social and individual (MacIntyre 2007). The first context is created by culture which prevails in
a given moment. The second one, depends on the aims and ways of life chosen by a person. Doctors
need certain virtues, while teachers need different ones and fire-fighters different ones again. His
theory might be regarded as the one which relativises virtues (Carr 2017).
The point of reference for these analyses is the standpoint taken by Thomas Aquinas and the
20th-century neo-Thomists. Thomas Aquinas built his virtue theory on the foundation of four virtues,
outlined in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (1990) as the essential ones: prudence, justice, temperance
and fortitude (Aquinas Thomas, 1485 [1947]; Pieper 1966; Mróz 2001; Keenan 2016). Therefore,
Thomas Aquinas initially formulated the theory of basic, cardinal virtues, whereas MacIntyre’s
reflection moved the analyses immediately to the level of detailed virtues. Essential, cardinal virtues
are related to four powers distinguished in Thomistic anthropology and the theory of human activity.
It would be a good idea to take a closer look at this theory so as to understand the concept of virtues
as capabilities which improve human activity. Thomas Aquinas regards man as an intelligent being.
He therefore considers that each action starts with a decision taken by spiritual powers: the intellect
and the will. The intellect recognises the truth, while the will desires the good. According to him, it is
impossible that a good action is the result of merely one of the powers (STh I–II, q. 14, a. 1, ad 1). In
order to do good, it is not enough to learn the truth about it. There are people who know what is
good and what should be done in a particular situation and yet, they do not do so, since it is of no
importance for them or they are not able to resist the temptation of some pleasures. On the other
hand, the desire for good which is not navigated by the intellect is blind. An action of a person who
seeks good but has recognised the way to its achievement improperly, will end in failure. In order to
do good, a perfection of the intellect recognising the truth (prudence – STh I–II, q. 57, a. 4; II–II, q. 47)
and a perfection of the will seeking good (justice – STh II, q. 58) are needed simultaneously. Likewise,
Thomistic belief does not depreciate emotions, being the agitations of sensual powers, which are
generated either by pleasant goods or by things that might cause unpleasant feeling (STh I–II, q. 59).
A necessary condition for doing good is the capacity for reasonable management of emotions so
that, on the one hand, a person (in particular situations) does not succumb to the desire of sensual
pleasures (temperance – STh II, q. 141) and on the other hand, does not refrain from difficult
challenges, especially when the journey towards the good involves suffering (fortitude – STh II–II,
q. 123). Cardinal virtues are, in other words, the perfections of the intellect, the will and the sensual
powers, thanks to which a specific person discovers the path of good in the complicated circum-
stances of daily life more efficiently, quickly, easily and finally, follows this path.
In Thomistic theory, any other ability might be called a virtue as long as it is built on the
foundation of four cardinal virtues. Referring to an example of diligence, this affair will be discussed
more deeply. This virtue may be regarded as an excellence of an activity oscillating between the
extremities of indolence and workaholism. In any event, the boundary between these very extre-
mities will run somewhere else. Persons who do not have their own family might devote consider-
ably more time to work than persons responsible for a spouse, bringing up children or taking care of
sick parents. The virtue of diligence could take a different form when people are able to easily earn
their own keep and that of their families, and another form, when food acquisition for themselves
and their children would be feasible merely as a result of hard and time-consuming work. In order to
define properly the amount of time and strength that should be devoted to work, the virtue of
prudence is needed. In turn, the virtue of justice is a condition for proper division of time and
strength, which means that agents do not scorn anyone’s good: their own, their families’, their
employers’ and those who make use of the effects of their work. This virtue does not consist so much
in the ability of the assessment of whom to devote time and strength and how much (it is a virtue of
prudence), but in the desire for giving everyone as much as they should get. Temperance is
a condition for diligence as well; nevertheless, it might take a different form. It might involve the
renunciation of goods which would be achievable provided that individuals worked a lot (forgoing
the time devoted to the families) or it may involve renouncing pleasures that might be enjoyed if
they did not go to work. The last cardinal virtue is fortitude. It is not solely a matter of accepting
BRITISH JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS EDUCATION 451

tough challenges. The manifestation of fortitude is also a daily struggle against hardships, oppres-
sion, fatigue, and the awareness of the effects a particular work exerts on specific organisms.
The example provided above leads to two conclusions. First of all, it shows that in Thomistic
theory, the virtue is not a kind of trait that sets a regular tone for one’s action (it is not an automatic
habit), but an ability that makes a reasonable management of one’s own action easier (Austin 2017).
The second conclusion is associated with the unity of cardinal virtues. Despite the fact that they are
distinguished, they essentially form a single unit (Szutta 2010). In other words, either they develop
evenly or a given agent does not have anyone. For example, persons cannot be assessed as prudent
when, instead of aiming at doing good for themselves and their families, they indulges themselves
due to lack of temperance (Horowski 2019a).
When speaking of Christian morality, it should be noted that it is inspired by specific challenges,
like the call to love thine enemy (Mt 5:44) or a call to forgive up to seventy-seven times (Mt 18:22). At
first glance, accepting these challenges is acting in defiance of cardinal virtues and is not feasible.
Referring to the Parable of the Prodigal Son (Lk 15:11–32), one could either notice that being virtuous
means taking into account not only the well-being of themselves, but considering third party’s well-
being as well. The forgiveness by the older brother is prudent and just because of the good of the
father who could receive what belongs to him by right, that is, the son. Furthermore the Parable
shows that major challenges, like forgiving someone (in particular a stranger) for injustice or giving
enemies help, need a particular point of reference since morality is of purposeful character (Maritain
1990). If the older son is to forgive his brother, only love for the father who loves the prodigal son
might persuade him to do so. Therefore, forgiving harm or concern for an enemy is possible if an
agent sees those people from God’s perspective (Horowski 2017). As a consequence, moral virtues
could reach a level that make it possible to accept specific challenges for a Christian only when
a man, facing moral dilemmas, has a relationship with God. The relationship is, in turn, reinforced
with theological virtues: faith as a perfection of the intellect knowing God as well as hope and charity
as perfections of the will desiring God (Mróz 2001; Conrad 2017). At this point, one arrives at the
significant change that was introduced to Aristotle’s virtue theory by Thomas Aquinas. Not only did
he make God the point of reference for virtues, but he also considered theological virtues – faith,
hope and charity – as pivotal ones for morality (Pinsent 2015; Roberts 2017).
In summary, it might be stated that, following the suggestions of Thomas Aquinas and contem-
porary neo-Thomists, both cardinal and theological virtues are the key virtues for Christian morality.
The achievement of excellence in prudence, justice, temperance and fortitude is the condition for
a deliberate action with the purpose of the well-being of the people who will see the effects of this
action. On the other hand, theological virtues of faith, hope and charity are, in a certain sense, given
as a condition for regarding God as a person who constitutes a point of reference for accepting
specifically Christian challenges and that may, thereby, prompt such difficult decisions (STh I–II, q. 63;
Maritain 1967, 131; Keenan 2016, 198–199; Conrad 2017) as forgiveness or concern for enemies.

Christian religious education and development of moral virtues in school


The introduction to the neo-Thomistic theory of virtue makes it possible to ask the question about
potential, and limitations, of school (Christian) religious education to support the development of
moral virtues. The answer to the question raised above will be divided into three stages. In the first,
the issue of the development of moral virtues will be presented, as well as the school as a space for
building moral character. In the second stage, the problem of introducing to understanding of
virtues will be addressed. The third stage directly concerns the tasks of Christian religious education
in the process of supporting the development of moral virtues. This argument is initially made as
appropriate for Christian religious education, and it could be applied to the religious education
found in Polish schools – where all religious education is denominational and provided by religious
communities. It could be extended to other contexts internationally where religious education is
denominational in this way. The theories of virtue development are of relevance to all considering
452 J. HOROWSKI

moral education as an element of religious education, as religious education of all kinds should
consider the moral development of young people learning about religion.

Supporting virtue development as an introduction to being responsible for community


members
This brief introduction to virtue theory creates an awareness that moral education is more than just
following standards or preparing people so that they can analyse and solve moral dilemmas. It is also
about supporting human development in such a way that maturing persons consistently follows
solutions regarded by them as good ones, keeps being moderate in relation to pleasures or even
gives them up when the situation so requires, and bravely endures adversity when good is hard to
achieve. Is it possible ― in the context of school education ― to support moral development that is
understood more broadly than merely developing moral reasoning? Before attempting to answer
this question, let us try to examine briefly the problem of developing virtues.
Thomas Aquinas, talking about virtues’ development, stated that they are improved by an
exercise, a practice (STh I–II, q. 51, a. 2; q. 52; Keenan 2016, 198–201). Jacek Woroniecki also
suggested that respective powers improve and achieve harmony in pursing one’s good only if an
agent attempts to act morally. Each subsequent minor act in pursuit of well-being makes the act of
doing good easier. The same applies to the vices. Each subsequent act of succumbing to the
temptation of pleasure and devotion to greater good in exchange for the achievement of this
pleasure makes it increasingly easier for an agent to abdicate from difficult and demanding
challenges (Woroniecki 2000, 359–360; Horowski 2015, 175–180). Therefore, the privileged place
for moral virtues’ development is a community in which an agent is able to interact with others in
achieving a common good, and where a particular person is entrusted with responsibility for the
realisation of specific tasks.
Speaking about community as a place of moral virtues’ development, it is worth noting that
maturing persons are encountered with specific real problems that have to be solved. What does it
mean for moral development? Konstanty Michalski, one of the rectors of the Jagellonian University in
Cracow in the inter-war period, distinguished two phenomena: ‘perfectionism’ and “perfectiorism”.
He stated that perfectionism is striving for perfection and is self-centred in character (perfection
becomes the objective of the action); perfectiorism, on the other hand, is achieving perfection by the
way of an action that heads towards the good of another person (Michalski 1937). If moral perfection
becomes a purpose in itself, it will actually never be realised since it is not another’s well-being at the
centre of attention, but the agents themselves (egocentrism). In order for agents to develop in the
moral dimension, they have to secure the well-being of another people. In this case, moral devel-
opment (moral virtues’ development) will be gradually accomplished almost incidentally (Wojtyła
1993).
School is a place where young people not only ponder how to treat other people, but also meet
defined, real individuals who do not belong to their family circle. Each person encountered in this
community experiences a variety of issues and difficulties, and in many situations needs support
from people who, on an everyday basis, are close to him/her. These issues can be due to learning
difficulties, financial problems of the family, or difficulties in building relationships with peers. When
meeting schoolmates, maturing persons must decide whether to be caring towards them, to ignore
their problems, or even to humiliate them by taking advantage of their weakness. When deciding to
help schoolmates learn, they must demonstrate the cardinal virtues of prudence in managing their
time; justice, i.e. readiness to fulfil their obligations towards that person and other people (e.g. family
members), or towards the school; and temperance, when helping the schoolmates requires, for
example, giving up the pleasure of playing with friends. A school is also a place where young people
brought up in different cultures and religions meet, especially nowadays, in the age of migration.
Consequently, a school becomes a space where people with stereotypical views and fears of the
unknown meet. Maturing persons in this situation are forced to deal with the dilemma of whether to
BRITISH JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS EDUCATION 453

establish relationships with cultural/religious strangers, invite them to play, or alternatively ignore
them and deepen their isolation/rejection. The decision to overcome stereotypes is always accom-
panied by the danger of being misunderstood by friends, and consequently experiencing isolation.
Therefore, the virtue of courage is needed to establish a relationship with someone who is margin-
alised. Repeating similar decisions on a daily basis leads to the formation of specific character traits:
justice, temperance and courage, or alternatively injustice, the pursuit of pleasure without heeding
the welfare of others, and fearful conformism. Therefore, not only is a learning community created at
school, but also a community that constitutes the context of moral development. A school creates
a space for the germination and development of traits that in the future will determine the
individual’s adoption of specific attitudes in public life. One might say that the time of school
education always leads a person to the development of some character traits. However, it does
not mean that each trait can always be called a virtue. At times, this functioning leads to the
development of vice in the moral character of a student.
It can be concluded from the above reflection that school education in its moral aspect should be
understood more broadly than information transfer. Teachers must also look at their roles more
broadly and deeply. If school education is to lead to virtue development, form teachers’ challenge at
school is a deliberate incorporation of maturing people into a school community life (Horowski
2019b, 106) in such a way as to face moral dilemmas, seek solutions which would be – in their
opinion – just, and learn to forgo simple pleasures, by taking actions with the objective aimed at the
goodness of other community members. One may say, following Aristotle, that education is a kind of
certain policy whose art should be seized by teachers (Vogler 2017).
Teachers may also ― sometimes unconsciously ― not take advantage of opportunities to
support moral virtue development, or may contribute through their actions to the development of
moral vices. If school become an exemplification of contemporary individualistic and consumer
societies, where everyone cares about their own good, and relationships are established primarily in
order to attain goods that are impossible to acquire otherwise, students strive to acquire knowledge
and competences that increase the chances of success in later life, and often collaborate with their
schoolmates because it suits their own interests. Teachers can take advantage of these mechanisms
and motivate students to learn by allowing competition between them. Students thus achieve better
results, but at the expense of them ― developing moral vices, such as egoism, craftiness or
selfishness. This mechanism could be used in many schools, regardless of whether they declare
a Christian or secular character. Can a teacher direct school community life in such a way that it
promotes a sense of responsibility for a classmate, the importance of supporting a classmate in his/
her weakness, and the ability to give up certain pleasures to help another person? Students should
learn prudence, justice, temperance and courage in relation to their schoolmates every day (van der
Zee 2012; Kozubek 2015). Special opportunities to support moral development are critical moments
in the lives of individual students, particularly if, for instance, one of the students falls seriously ill,
undergoes a crisis in his/her family or his/her family experiences a traumatic event (e.g. the death of
a family member).

Supporting virtue development by introducing an understanding of virtue


The reflection on moral virtues and their development conditions leads to the conclusion that the
very didactic classes implemented at school contribute to virtues development to a small extent.
Jacques Maritain, speaking of school education, ascertained that it conducts ‘premoral’ education: ‘a
point which deals not with morality strictly speaking, but with the preparation and first tilling of the
soil thereof’ (Maritain 1943, 27). In other words, within didactics students might be provided with
knowledge about the moral rightness and wrongness, they may acquire skills of analysing moral
problems from various perspectives and of identifying the consequences of particular acts and
finally, they might understand what moral virtues are for. Notwithstanding, didactic activities
themselves are not able to motivate students in such a sufficient way that, when finding themselves
454 J. HOROWSKI

in a situation requiring decision, they are able to take a morally difficult decision. Following the
reflection of Thomas Aquinas on the virtues, it may be stated that students, within didactic classes,
may develop the virtues of deliberation well and judiciousness (good sense), which are related to
a situation analysis and have a characteristically intellectual nature, but within these classes, they will
not be able to obtain the virtue of prudence which is expressed in firm decision making.
The above statements do not depreciate the value of knowledge transferred within school
education. Thomas Aquinas himself is the author of a well-known statement: ‘God’s greatest gift
to human beings is reason’. Through the life, human beings are not only guided by reason, but they
can be changed only when their way of understanding reality is changed. Maritain in his famous
work Education at the Crossroads (1943) ascertained that education of man is always an appeal for his
reason. Intellectual development is important and constitutes a condition for moral development,
including virtues development. If maturing persons, at some point of their life, are to seize control of
their moral development, starting thereby the process of self-education, it is vital for them to be
previously introduced to the understanding of moral virtue.
As regards the area that we are interested in, the key lies not only in supporting positive attitudes
towards moral virtue and encouraging students to take actions that develop such virtues (Smith and
Smith 2013), but also in explaining what concrete virtues are about. Unfortunately, virtue ― as
a moral proficiency ― is not distinguished from habit in contemporary culture. Virtue is proficiency
in adapting activities to goals and circumstances, so it is reason-based. Habits are revealed in
automatic, thoughtless actions. In modern cultures, these two phenomena are not distinguished
from each other, since the term ‘habitus’ ― used by Thomas Aquinas to mean such a formation of
man that manifests itself in reason-based actions ― has been utilised in psychological and socio-
logical theories to define an automatic, mechanical action (an example of this is the theory of Pierre
Bourdieu, Austin 2017). Consequently, students do not perceive that the same virtue can manifest
itself in different decisions when those decisions are taken in different contexts, or the action can be
a manifestation of either virtue or vice, depending on the context. They do not perceive, for example,
that taking actions that threaten health and life can, in certain circumstances, be a manifestation of
the virtue of courage, and in other circumstances a manifestation of thoughtless bravado (which is in
fact a vice), or that transferring money to a stranger may in some circumstances be an expression of
the virtue of generosity, while in other circumstances it may indicate the vice of prodigality. School
education should therefore introduce an understanding of virtue that can help to properly identify
examples of it and distinguish those examples from similar but non-virtuous features.
In this context, introducing an understanding of virtue is connected with showing its relationship with
the cardinal virtues. This of course assumes a prior understanding of the cardinal virtues by the students.
Defining a given feature as a virtue or vice implies indicating whether that feature leads to prudent and
just actions in specific situations, or alternatively to hasty and unreasonable actions that are unjust to the
people who directly or indirectly experience the effects of specific decisions brought about by that
features. Consequently, a virtue or vice can be identified when, in an individual’s given action, the role
that moderation/immoderation and courage/cowardice played when the decision was made is indicated.
Finally, it is important for students to learn the understanding of virtue through examples that are
close to their life, and consequently to analyse the decisions they have made, in which they have
dealt with moral dilemmas, while identifying their own virtues or vices. The narration about virtues,
as well as the examples cited to characterise specific virtues, often do not relate to students’ daily
decisions. Students learn virtues through the example of heroic deeds, in which individuals risk their
health or life for the good of others. Consequently, knowledge of virtue is not directly related to their
own lives. If it is true that in order to make heroic decisions one has to mature for years by making
good decisions on seemingly unimportant matters on a daily basis, then students must discover
virtues and vices in their own relationships with family, schoolmates and neighbours, so that this
knowledge can accentuate their diligence, kindness, punctuality, exactitude, modesty, patience and
forbearance.
BRITISH JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS EDUCATION 455

Supporting the development of moral virtues by development of theological virtues


The last issue raised in these analyses directly concerns the potential of Christian religious education
in supporting the moral development of students. It aims at answering the question of what
Christian religious education can bring to moral education in school. It is not the question about
the involvement of a religious teacher in activities that can be taken by other teachers, but about the
specific factor of moral development that could be provided by religious education.
As outlined in the introduction, Neo-Thomistic thought claims that students’ moral choices are
conditioned by their moral beliefs, but are not a simple consequence of those outlooks. According to
representatives of neo-Thomism, who pay attention to the external, objective conditions of the
human act, the will plays a key role in making moral decisions, and specifically the good that is
desired by the will. Referring to this thesis, it can be said that for moral choices the most important is
whether students want their personal good, do they care about the good of their friends, do they
want a friendly atmosphere in the classroom, etc. Religious education can support moral education
by adding a motivation that could be significant if the student is a believer. Religious education can
show concern for another person (stranger or even hostile) as concern for someone loved by God.
If Christian religious education is to contribute to moral education, understood as supporting the
development of moral virtues, the religion teacher should observe the relationships between
students belonging to different peer, social, sometimes religious groups, and encourage them to
cooperate and sometimes solve conflicts, drawing strength from religious faith. To integrate moral
development and religious development in maturing persons, students should treat schoolmates,
whether they profess the same faith, whether they are unbelievers or belonging to another religious
community, as the subject of their calling. For young Christians, the differences, difficulties, or
weaknesses of peers may be seen as opportunities for virtuous action. Christian religious education,
if it is to support moral development, cannot be limited to information, but should also lead to
initiation in undertaking moral challenges adequate to the students’ faith. It is necessary to learn
moral virtues in everyday situations by performing minor morally good deeds.
The understanding of virtues is evidently also important. Just as in moral education, it is possible
to analyse actions in terms of the moral virtues manifesting in them; thus, in religious education, it is
possible to search for the causes of specific attitudes in the strength of theological virtues. The
purpose of this analysis should not be to value someone’s faith, hope or love, but to see how
theological virtues could change moral attitudes. This reflection may be particularly important in the
specific challenges that maturing persons face such as the love of their enemies or the forgiveness of
the perpetrator of evil. Difficulties in meeting these challenges can sometimes lead young people to
faith and moral crises and to blame themselves for an inability to meet specific and very difficult
norms (Grün 2015). Reflecting on the relationship between morality and faith can help people
understand that faith, hope and love of God are a source of additional strength to meet difficult
standards.
Reflection on the potential of religious education to support moral development also leads to
a question about the nature of religious education, or, more specifically, to the issue of confessional
religious education, and to the problem of initiation in religious education (Bagrowicz 2006; Valk
2007; Court 2013). If religious education is to contribute to supporting the moral development of
maturing people, and the thesis that the potential of religious education is primarily associated with
the integration of faith and morality is correct, then the greatest contribution to moral development
can be made by religious education by supporting the development of theological virtues in which
strength to face the moral dilemmas can be obtained. However, fulfiling the function of supporting
the development of theological virtues is currently difficult. On the one hand, as was mentioned in
the introduction, due to social, cultural, legal and political conditions, religious school education is
limited to the transfer of knowledge, and religious education broadly understood is limited to
religious school education – it means that maturing persons do not receive other religious educa-
tion, as part of which they would be introduced to prayer, liturgy, and meditation. Consequently, it
456 J. HOROWSKI

must be stated that the potential of Christian religious education in relation to supporting moral
development which is understood as the development of moral virtues is limited. Referring to
Maritain’s thesis, it can be said that Christian religious education conducted within its contemporary
socio-cultural and legal conditions is rather a ‘premoral’ than moral education; it more creates the
foundation for Christian moral development than supports the development of Christian moral
character.

Conclusion
The analysis conducted in the article was made on the basis of the theory of moral virtue formulated
by Thomas Aquinas, and developed in works of contemporary neo-Thomists. Their purpose was to
determine the extent of the potential of Christian religious education to support students’ moral
development. The analysis was accompanied by an assumption that each school is not only provided
with certain content, including an introduction to the understanding of moral problems and possible
ways to solve them, but it also develops specific character traits among students. Depending on how
students’ community life is, their cooperation and care for each other is organised by teachers who,
by means of their ideas, can either support the development of students’ moral virtues or support
the development of students’ moral vices. In extreme cases, a student might be taught about moral
good and at the same time, the mode of school functioning could stimulate the development of
moral vices.
Reflection on the theory of moral virtues leads to the conclusion that virtue education should be
accompanied by such an organisation of school life that students could build communities in which
they take responsibility for one another and work together towards the achievement of morally
acceptable goals. The only condition for virtues’ development, including cardinal virtues – prudence,
justice, temperance and fortitude, is the pursuit of the realisation of a common good. Transferring
knowledge about virtues and caring for their proper understanding by students are crucial, but as
such they cannot make students be more patient, understanding or inclined to forgo simple
pleasures.
Reflection on school education from the perspective of the Thomistic theory of moral virtues also
allowed us to ascertain what the specificity of moral education implemented within religious
education is. This is related to the development of theological virtues that can support students’
motivation to care for the good of their classmates, even if they have suffered harm from them or
perceive a hostile attitude from the individual in concern. The reflection taken in the article also leads
to the conclusion that religious education can play an important role in moral education understood
as supporting the development of moral virtues, when it is not limited only to the implementation of
informational functions.

Disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.

Notes on contributor
Dr Jarosław Horowski is an associate professor in Faculty of Philosophy and Social Sciences of Nicolaus Copernicus
University in Toruń, Institute of Education Sciences, Chair of History and Theory of Education, editor-in-chief of the
scientific journal “Paedagogia Christiana”. Author of Moral Education According to neo-Thomistic Pedagogy (WN UMK,
2015). Intrested in Philosophy of education, moral and religious education, neo-Thomistic notion in pedagogy,
education for moral virtues, and education for forgiveness.
BRITISH JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS EDUCATION 457

ORCID
Jarosław Horowski http://orcid.org/0000-0002-6412-1544

References
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1958. “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy 33 (142): 1–19. doi:10.1017/S0031819100037943.
Aristotle. 1990. The Nicomachean Ethics. London, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Arthur, J., K. Kristjánsson, T. Harrison, W. Sanderse, and D. Wright. 2016. Teaching Character and Virtue in Schools. London:
Routledge.
Austin, N. 2017. Aquinas on Virtue: A Causal Reading. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Bagrowicz, J. 2006. Towarzyszyć wzrastaniu. Z dyskusji o metodach i środkach edukacji religijnej młodzieży. Toruń: UMK.
Bocheński, J. M. 1962. Philosophy: An Introduction. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.
Carr, D. 1991. Educating the Virtues. An Essay on the Philosophical Psychology of Moral Development and Education.
London and New York: Routledge.
Carr, D. 1996. “After Kohlberg: Some Implications of an Ethics of Virtue for the Theory and Practice of Moral Education.”
Studies in Philosophy and Education 15: 353–370. doi:10.1007/BF00368492.
Carr, D. 2017. “Educating for the Wisdom of Virtue.” In Varieties of Virtue Ethics, edited by D. Carr, et al., 319–335.
doi:10.1057/978-1-137-59177-7_19.
Chałupniak, R. 2012. “Katecheza w szkole czy poza szkołą?” Paedagogia Christiana 1/29: 163–178. doi:10.12775/
PCh.2012.009.
Conrad, R. 2017. “Human Practice and God’s Making-Good in Aquinas’ Virtue Ethics.” In Varieties of Virtue Ethics, edited
by D. Carr, et al., 319–335. doi:10.1057/978-1-137-59177-7_10.
Court, D. 2013. “Religious Experience as an Aim of Religious Education.” British Journal of Religious Education 35 (3):
251–263. doi:10.1080/01416200.2012.750596.
Curren, R. 2015. “Virtue Ethics and Moral Education.” In The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics, edited by L. Besser-
Jones and M. Slote, 459–470. London and New York: Routledge.
D’Souza, M. O. 2016. A Catholic Philosophy of Education. Montreal&Kingston, London, Chicago: McGill-Queen’s University
Press.
Eaude, T. 2016. New Perspectives on Young Children’s Moral Education: Developing Character through a Virtue Ethics
Approach. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Franken, L., and P. Loobuyck. 2017. “Neutrality and Impartiality in RE: An Impossible Aim?” British Journal of Religious
Education 1: 1–6. doi:10.1080/01416200.2016.1218219.
Gilson, E. 1971. Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas. Freeport, N.Y: Books for Libraries Press.
Grün, A. 2015. Vergib dir selbst. Münsterschwarzach: Vier-Türme-Verlag.
Horowski, J. 2015. Wychowanie moralne według pedagogiki neotomistycznej. Toruń: Wydawnictwo Naukowe UMK.
Horowski, J. 2017. “Wychowanie do przebaczenia a edukacja religijna.” In Septuaginta pedagogiczno-katechetyczna,
edited by A. Walulik and J. Mółka, 401–411. Kraków: Akademia Ignatianum.
Horowski, J. 2019a. “Education for Forgiveness in the Context of Developing Prudence.” Ethics and Education 14 (3):
314–332. doi:10.1080/17449642.2019.1624483.
Horowski, J. 2019b. “Wspólnota a Wychowanie Moralne – O Metodach Wychowania Moralnego Według Pedagogiki
Neotomistycznej.” Seminare 40 (1): 105–117. doi:10.21852/sem.2019.1.08.
Hursthouse, R., and G. Pettigrove. 2018. “Virtue Ethics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by E. N. Zalta.
Accessed 26 June 2019. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/ethics-virtue/
Kaźmierczak, P. 2019. Neoarystotelesowska filozofia edukacji w ujęciu Alasdaira MacIntyre’a. Kraków: Wydawnictwo
Naukowe Akademii Ignatianum.
Keenan, J. F. 2016. “Virtues.” In The Cambridge Companion to the Summa Theologiae, edited by P. McCosker and
D. Turner, 194–205. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kozubek, M. T. 2015. “Wspólnota i jedność w wybranych obszarach życia społecznego – doświadczenie Ruchu Focolari.”
Paedagogia Christiana 2/36: 79–108. doi:10.12775/PCh.2015.027.
Krąpiec, M. A. 1999. Odzyskać świat realny. Lublin: RW KUL.
Kristjánsson, K. 2015. Aristotelian Character Education. London: Routledge.
Kunowski, S. 1966. “Tomistyczne studia w dziedzinie pedagogiki.” In Pastori et Magistro, edited by A. Krupa, 469–488.
Lublin: Katolicki Uniwersytet Lubelski.
Luby, A. 2019. “A Culture of Dialogue. Vision, Pedagogy and Dialogic Skills for the RE Classroom.” British Journal of
Religious Education. doi:10.1080/01416200.2019.1628006.
MacIntyre, A. 2007. After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.
Maritain, J. 1943. Education at the Crossroads. New Haven & London: Yale University Press.
Maritain, J. 1967. The Education of Man. ed. D. Gallagher, I. Gallagher. Noter Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Maritain, J. 1990. An Introduction to the Basic Problems of Moral Philosophy. New York: Magi.
458 J. HOROWSKI

Mausbach, J. 1920. Grundlage und Ausbildung des Charakters nach dem hl. Thomas von Aquin. Freiburg im Breisgau:
Herder.
Mausbach, J. 1925. Thomas von Aquin als Meister christlichen Sittenlehre. München-Rom: Verlag.
Michalski, K. 1937. “Katolicka idea wychowania.” In Katolicka myśl wychowawcza. Pamiętnik II. Studium Katolickiego
w Wilnie w dn. 28 VIII–1 IX 1936 r, edited by S. Bross, 23–45. Poznań: Naczelny Instytut Akcji Katolickiej.
Mróz, M. 2001. Człowiek w dynamizmie cnoty. Aktualność aretologii św. Tomasza z Akwinu w świetle pytania o podstawy
moralności chrześcijańskiej. Toruń: Wyższe Seminarium Duchowne.
Pieper, J. 1966. The Four Cardinal Virtues: Prudence, Justice, Fortitude, Temperance. Chicago: University of Notre Dame
Press.
Pinsent, A. 2015. “Aquinas: Infused Virtues.” In The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics, edited by L. Besser-Jones and
M. Slote, 141–153. London and New York: Routledge.
Roberts, R. C. 2017. “Varieties of Virtue Ethics.” In Varieties of Virtue Ethics, edited by D. Carr, et al., 319–335. doi:10.1057/
978-1-137-59177-7_2.
Smith, G., and S. Smith. 2013. “From Values to Virtues: An Investigation into the Ethical Content of English Primary
School Assemblies.” British Journal of Religious Education 35 (1): 5–19. doi:10.1080/01416200.2011.649344.
Snow, N. E. 2016. “How Habits Make Us Virtuous.” In Developing the Virtues. Integrating Perspectives, edited by J. Annas,
D. Narvaez, and N. E. Snow, 135–156. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Steutel, J., and D. Carr. 1999. “Virtue Ethics and the Virtue Approach to Moral Education.” In Virtue Ethics and Moral
Education, edited by D. Carr and J. Steutel, 3–18. London and New York: Routledge.
Szutta, N. 2010. “Jedność cnót jako warunek normatywności cnoty. W obronie doktryny jedności cnót.” Ethos 92: 78–93.
Szutta, N. 2015a. “Wychowanie moralne z perspektywy etyki cnót.” Diametros 46: 111–133. doi:10.13153/
diam.46.2015.839.
Szutta, N. 2015b. “Wprowadzenie, czyli o co chodzi w dyskusji nad moralnym charakterem.” In W: W poszukiwaniu
moralnego charakteru, edited by N. Szutta, 13–34. Lublin: Academicon.
Thomas Aquinas. “1485[1947].Summa Theologica (Sth).” http://www.summatheologica.info/
Tomasik, P. 1998. Nauczanie religii w publicznym liceum ogólnokształcącym wobec założeń programowych polskiej szkoły.
Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Salezjańskie.
Valk, J. 2007. “Plural Public Schooling: Religion, Worldviews and Moral Education.” British Journal of Religious Education
29 (3): 273–285. doi:10.1080/01416200701479661.
van der Zee, T. 2012. “Inspiration: A Thought-provoking Concept for RE Teachers.” British Journal of Religious Education
34 (1): 21–34. doi:10.1080/01416200.2011.601908.
Vogler, C. 2017. “Virtue, the Common Good and Self-Transcendence.” In Varieties of Virtue Ethics, edited by D. Carr, et al.,
217–229. doi:10.1057/978-1-137-59177-7_13.
Wojtyła, K. 1993. “In Search of the Basis of Perfectionism in Ethics.” In Person and Community. Selected Essays, edited by
K. Wojtyła, 45–56. New York: Peter Lang.
Woroniecki, J. 1922. Metoda i program nauczania teologii moralnej. Lublin: Uniwersytet Lubelski.
Woroniecki, J. 2000. Katolicka etyka wychowawcza. Vol. I. Lublin: RW KUL.
Wren, T. 2014. “Philosophical Moorings.” In Handbook of Moral and Character Education, edited by L. Nucci, D. Narvaez,
and T. Krettenauer, 11–29. London and New York: Routledge.

You might also like