Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

UTILITARIANISM AND VEGETARIANISM

Roger Crisp

Thl セ author is at present Lecturer in Philosophy at St Anne's The Compromise Requirement Wew (CR): One
Co, lege, Oxford. He has taken the degrees of BA., MA. and is morally required both to abstain from the flesh
B.l 'hiJ. at Oxford, and is eurrendy working on a D.PhiJ. thesis of intensively reared animals and to eat the flesh
on ideal utilitarianism. Previously he has been Lecturer in
of certain non-intensively-reared animals.
Ph 1osophy at Magdalen College, Oxford. He has had a
nu. nber ofartieles published, ineluding three in applied ethies: The Raymond Frey Wew (RF): One is morally
'TJ re argument trom marginal ・。ウセ Journal of Applied
permitted to eat all kinds of meat, but required
Ph ilosophy 2, 1985; セ good death: who best to bring it?:
Bioethics 1, 1987; 'Persuasive advertising, autonomy, and the to campaign against intensive fanning, by means
Cf',( セ。エゥッョ of desire: Journal of Business Ethics 6, 1987. such as political lobbying.
The Full Meat-eating Requirement Wew (FR):
One is morally required to eat all kinds ofmeat.
T he condition ofnon-human animals--especially
tl.ose consumed as food by human beings-has
「Lセ・ョ a major concern ofmany recent thinkers in 1 THE ARGUMENT FROM KILLING
tlle utilitarian tradition. Two main lines ofthought
have been taken on the ethics of eating meat. It 1. The widespread practice of Meat-eating re-
ゥセ claimed either that utilitarianism requires Veg- quires killing sentient beings.
e tarianism (V) 1, or that it does not, but permits 2. Killing sentient beings is wrong.
one to eat meat. 2 In this paper, I shall develop a 3. Therefore, the widespread practice of Meat-
t lird line: that utilitarianism does not permit V, eating is wrong.
requiring a form of non-V. This view I shall call The first premise ofthis argument is undeniable.
the Compromise Requirement view (CR). I shall Therefore, it can only be vulnerable as regards its
(:laim that one is morally required both to abstain second premise. The premise can be supported,
f rom the flesh of intensively reared animals and in turn, by three subsidiary utilitarian arguments
t 0 eat the flesh of certain non-intensively-reared intended to demonstrate the wrongness ofkilling.
clnimals. Replies to each will show that these arguments
The paper will proceed primarily in a negative do not apply to the case of killing animals for
'Nay, through consideration and refutation ofthe food, and thus that the Argument from Killing
nain utilitarian arguments for V. But a positive fails.
:ase for CR will emerge, particularly in the discus-
sion of the Argument from Suffering.
Before proceeding to the first argument, it might l(a) THE ARGUMENT FROM DlRECT
be helpful to outline the utilitarian positions under DIMINUTION OF UTILITY
consideration:
1. Killing a sentient being for food directly re-
Vegetarianism (V): One is morally required to abs- duces the amount of utility in the world by
tain from meat. removing that being from the world.
The Compromise Permission Wew (CP): One is 2. Reducing the amount of utility is wrong.
morally required to abstain from the flesh ofinten- 3. Therefore, killing a sentient being for food is
sively reared animals, but permitted to eat the wrong.
flesh of certain non-intensively-reared animals. The second premise here is correct by definition in

-41-
utilitarian terms. Thus, we must focus on the first. counter-balanced by the bringing into existence
It is not clear that this is correct. of a new animal.
The reason for this is that utilitarianism is com- . The fulfillment of future-related desires, how-
mitted to replaceability. The replacing of one ever, does not differ from mental states, as far as
being by another at a similar level of utility is, replaceability is concerned. 6 Utilitarian theories
other things being equal, morally neutral. are neutral as to when or where utility is located.
It may be objected that if the utility levels of Thus, .the surrogate animal will also have future-
both the animal to be killed and that intended as related desires, and if these desires are fulfilled,
a surrogate are above zero, then it would be better replaceability once again ensures the moral neut-
that both live. There are two replies to this. The rality of the killing. 7
first is that we are concerned with Meat-eating In the context ofa widespread practice ofMeat-
as a widespread practice. And an inherent feature eating, of course, the surrogate animal is highly
of this practice is that over time some animals unlikely to go on living for very long. It too will
will be killed for food, and others will take their be killed and eaten. It might be thought that to
places. If animals were not killed, the practice ensure the moral neutrality ofthe process one has
could not exist. The second is that the objection only to stipulate that the final animal in the pro-
is not anyway to the point. All that needs to be cess will be allowed to survive. Given that the
shown is that killing an animal need not be wrong, process of rearing animals for food is nowhere
not that failing to increase the overall level of near its end, this is a worry that need not afHict
utility is not wrong. Replaceability makes morally us at present.
neutral killing a possibility. 3 But this claim misses the same point as the
In what does an animal's utility consist? original Vegetarian argument based on desires.
Primarily it must be sheer pleasurable experience, Desire-fulfillment, and hence frustration, like
land the fulfillment of desires for those experi- pleasure and pain is cumulative. As the process
ences. 4 And the pleasures of even the more intel- continues, more and more future-related desires
ligent domestic animals, such as pigs, will tend will be frustrated, and these are not counter-bal-
to be ofthe 'low' variety.5 Indeed, one would not anced by the fulfillment of one such set of desires
have to be a Socrates dissatisfied to have a life at the end of the process.
preferable to that of a contented pig. Not all the To solve the problem, one has to be aware of
desires ofanimals are for pleasurable experiences, another mistaken assumption underlying the orig·-
however. For example, they also have desires con- inal Vegetarian argument. This is the view that
nected with their relations with other animals. If there is something special about these particuiar
a cow sees her calf being mistreated, she will future-related desires. The utilitarian must accept
show signs ofacute distress, and perhaps attempt that the value of their fulfillment can be out-
to protect her offspring. It would be more plaus- weighed by the value of the fulfillment of other
ible to explain her actions by ascribing to her the desires (and, depending on the type of
desire that her otfspring not sutfer, than the desire utilitarianism in question, other values, such as
that she not experience the sight of her otfspring pleasure or aesthetic appreciation).
sutfering. No cow is so stupid as not to realize Thus, the frustration of the future-related de-
that a more effective way of fulfilling the latter sires of the animal killed is counter-balanced by:
desire would be to turn tail and head for the other i) the utility of the life of the surrogate anima];
end of the field. ii) the utility of the desire-satisfaction, ーャ・。ウオイセL
The Vegetarian may use the notion of the or aesthetic appreciation in eating the animal; andl
sophistication of animal desires in the following (which surely tips the balance in favour ッヲm・。エセ
way. She may accept that merely replacing one eating here) iii) the utility ofthe life ofthe anima]
pleasurable experience with another is morally killed, given that, in the context of a widespread
neutral. But, she may continue, desires are not practice ofMeat-eating, it would not have existed
llike this. An animal may have desires for the fu- had it not been intended for slaughter. (It is impor-
It ure. The frustration of these desires is not tant to bear in mind that i) and iii) will not apply

-42-
in tlle case ofintensively reared animals, who live equal, violates its autonomy and deprives it of
at iヲセカ・ャウ ofnegative utility. But these animals are liberty.
bet:er off not existing, so killing them is not 2. Autonomy and liberty are productive ofutility.
wrc1ng.) 3. Thus, killing a sentient being reduces the
amount of utility in the world.
4. Reducing the amount of utility is wrong.
I I,b) THE ARGUMENT FROM INDlRECT
5. Therefore, killing a sentient being is wrong.
DIMINUTION OF UTILITY
1. Killing a sentient being causes grief: anxiety, Some utilitarians have appealed to respect for
and thereby suffering in other sentient beings. autonomyas a moral principle. 8 And a Vegetarian
2. Thus, killing a sentient being indirectly reduces might think that an ideal utilitarian theory, which
the amount of utility in the world. included the claim that autonomy is itself part of
3. Reducing the amount of utility is wrong. utiJity, would also support her case.
4. Therefore, killing a sentient being is wrong. She will be disappointed, however: For animals
do not possess セッョエオ。 9
They do have desires,
l Pr セュゥウ・ 3 is correct by definition, and premise 2 and they do make choices. But their choices are
is ':rue if premise 1 is true. Thus, we must attend not about how their lives should go. They are about
to premise 1. immediate things, such as whether to walle in this
Now it cannot be denied that killing certain or that direction, to lie in the shade or under the
se:ltient beings, in particular humans and other sun, to flee or ウエ。セ Autonomy requires at least some
ィゥ[ セ ・イ primates, almost always causes grief and degree of a global conception ofone's life, and this
ar xiety among other such beings. But this does it seems clear animals do not have. 10
ne tt seem to be the case with domestic animals. Animals can, however, be free. Indeed, the basis
\\ 'e are not unduly perturbed at the killing of ofthe ethical criticism ofour treatment ofanimals
aIlimals, especially if we do not see it happen. for many people is that we deprive them ofliberty.
And those who kill them are similarly unaffected. But by killing an animal we do not deprive it of
It may be said that animals become distressed liberty alone. We deprive it of everything. And, if
\\ 'hen members of their group are killed in their my critique ofthe Argument from Direct Diminu-
p resence. In the case of domestic animals, this tion of Utility is correct, depriving a being of ev-
o Juld only occur at the slaughter-house. But there erything including liberty can be justified by re-
ゥセ no argument for not killing, if it is possible to
placeability. Thus, even if animals possess liberty,
alter the circumstances of the death. And surely it is not always wrong to deprive them of it.
,i1. is possible to do this, bychanging the methods
() f slaughtering. Animals could be killed in sepa-
rate pens, for example. 2 THE ARGUMENT FROM SUFFERING
Animals can also be distressed at the death of 1. The widespread practice of Meat-eating
a mate. Pair-bonding, however, is not found causes suffering.
etIllong the animals we eat. And finally there is 2. The causing of suffering is wrong.
the problem of distress caused by the death of a 3. Therefore, Meat-eating is wrong.
parent or offspring. This again is not an argument
tor not killing. The problem can be dealt with The second premise of this argument requires
either by slaughtering both parent and offspring attention. Utilitarians do, of course, claim that
at the same time or by slaughtering neither parent suffering is bad, and that causing suffering is in
nor offspring at times when the offspring is young itselfa bad thing to do. But causing suffering can
enough to experience distress at the loss or to be a good thing to do when it is not considered
cause the parent distress at the loss of the off- in itselt: It may lead to better consequences occur-
spring. ing than ifsutfering had not been caused (e.g. the
action of a dentist filling a cavity), or it may be
part of aseries of actions which, taken overall,
l(c) THE ARGUMENT FROM AUTONOMY are productive of utility (e.g. the punishing of a
1. Killing a sentient being, other things being child). Thus, as I noted in the discussion of re-

-43-
placeability, doing something that causes a drop reared meat, given the vast scale of modem meat-
in the level of utility can be counter-balanced by production, will be irrelevant as to whether any
doing something else which causes an increase. good effects arise from a widespread practice of
In the case of rearing animals for food, it may abstaining from intensively reared meat.
weIl be that the suffering they will inevitably en- One response to this .problem might be that it
dure is analogous to that experienced by a child is unfair to take advantage ofothers. Ifwe assurne
who is punished in the normal run of things. I I that intensive rearing will decrease in scale if a
Most non-intensively-reared animals lead worth- certain number of people give up eating meat
while lives l2 , and we enjoy eating them. The reared in that way, and that one accepts that this
worthwhileness of their lives, and the pleasure is a good thing, then when others are boycotting
we gain from eating them, justify the practice of such meat, it is unfair not to join them.
rearing them, although it inevitably involves caus- This claim, however, is counter to the con-
ing suffering. And if we were not to eat them, sequentialism at the heart ofutilitarianism. Ifthe
both of these sources of utility would disappear. consequences alone determine the moral standing
Thus, there is here the beginning ofa case for CR of an act, and the only consequences relevant to
Intensively-reared animals, however, fall into a this determination are benefits and harms, then
different category. Their lives are frustrating, pain- to claim that an act is wrong, although it does no
ful, stunted, and devoid of anything but the harm and indeed produces a benefit (the plea:sure
slightest pleasure. IJ It would have been better for of eating meat), seems not only churlish, but also
such animals ifthey had not been born. The only contradictory.15
consideration counter-balancing the severe suf- A more promising response might be to claim
fering endured by intensively reared animals is that characterizing the problem in this way makes
our pleasure in eating them. When we consider what Partit calls the 'fifth mistake in moral
the fact that alternative meals are available, it mathematics'.16 One makes this mistake if one
seems patently clear that this consideration will thinks that:
not justify factory-farming.
If some act has effects on other people that
Thus far, I have ruled out V as an option, and
are imperceptible, this act cannot be moral-
suggested that there is a requirement on us to eat
ly wrong because it has these effects. An aet
non-intensively-reared meat. This gives prima
cannot be wrong because of its effects on
facie support to CR, RF, and FR I have also
other people if none of these people could
suggested that intensively rearing animals cannot
ever notice any difference. Similarly, ifsome
be justified in utilitarian terms. This narrows the
act would have imperceptible effects on
field to CR and RF.
other people, these effects cannot make this
RF is still in play for the reason that from the
act what someone ought to do.
claim that the practice of intensively rearing ani-
mals is wrong, in that it causes more suffering
than pleasure overall, one cannot conclude that Developing Partit's analysis, one might clainl
an individual is therefore required to desist from that in order to avoid the paradox that, if imper··
eating the products of factory-farms. For it may ceptible acts are never wrong, many people who
be that an individual's actions will have no effect increase the suffering ofa person until it is severe,
on the practice. each by an imperceptible amount, are doing no
This problem is similar to the Problem of Col- wrong, we should attend to the consequences Hセヲ
lective Action in Marxism l4 : just as it is not in what we together do.
the interest of individual workers to struggle for This response also fails, however, in that it still
socialism, even ifthey see socialism as a desirable provides no reason for the individual to join the
goal, since what an ordinary individual does boycott The group will go on doing the good
makes no difference to what others do, and so whether or not any one individual partakes in the
whether socialism comes about or not does not boycott
depend on the actions of that individual; so The following response to the Problem of Col-
whether or not I abstain from intensively lective Action is more successful. There are three

-44-
ーッセNウゥ「ャ・ effects of an individual boycotting in- 3 THE ARGUMENT FROM CALLOUSNESS
ten sively reared meat. It will either have no effect,
bei ng below the threshold required to make a 1. The practice of rearing animals and killing
、ゥヲセ・イョ」[ or a great effect, 'tipping the balance' them for food engenders a callous attitude in
ovヲセイ a threshold; or a small effect, if thresholds human beings towards other human beings.
do not exist and the effect on intensive farming 2. This attitude will be expressed in callous act-
is jirect. ions towards other human beings, which cause
suffering.
(f thresholds do exist, the action will have one
3. Causing suffering is wrong.
or other ofthe first two effects. It might be thought
4. Therefore, the practice is wrong.
th 1t this gives the individual a reason not to join
th セ boycott, in the same way that the fact that One way to criticize this old argument would be
there is a very small probability ofhaving an effect to point out that, once again, only the bad conse-
in a general election might be thought to supply quences are being taken into account. The
a good reason for any one individual not to vote. number ofpeople actually involved in the practice
T"lis, however, is to make Partit's third mistake, is small, relative to the number of people who
th at of ignoring small chances. 17 According to benefit trom it (the Meat-eaters). Thus, even if
ulilitarianism, we should act so as to maximize animal-farmers and employees of slaughter-
・セアj 」エ 、 utility. Thus, a small chance ofbringing houses do cause more suffering to other human
al )out a great good does give me a reason to act. beings than they might otherwise have done if
employed in a different area, it is still possible
It is also possible that boycotting intensively
that the benefits gained by those who enjoy their
、・イ。セョ meat will have an effect on intensive farm-
products will more than suffice to counter-bal-
it 19, regardless of the effects of the acts of others.
ance that suffering.
111 fact, it seems likely that this will sometimes be
t:le case. Imagine that lama Meat-eating indi- But it seems questionable whether the first
\idual, who, like most people, enjoys the taste of premise is anyway correct. If those involved in
(hicken. In a year, I might buy, say, five chickens. 'the practice are made aware of the justifications
キッセイ information-transfer in a corporate market for it, there need be no presumption that they
e=:conomy is not perfect. Ifl chose to boycott Ber- will become callous in their attitude towards other
llard Matthews' chickens, he would not be able animals or humans. And even ifnot only are they
,10 find out that I had done so. But neither is it
not aware ofthe justifications, but also (as is often
Tセョエゥイ・ャケ inefficient. If I buy my chickens from the claimed) they must think of animals as in some
セN。ュ・ store, and then stop buyingthem, the figures sense inanimate if they are to do their job, there
lor chicken sales for the next year will be less by is no reason to think that this is the first step on
'lve than if I had not joined the boycott. The store a slippery slope leading to callous actions towards
mayorder fewer chickens over the next year, and human beings. For this attitude to animals would
the farmer produce fewer chickens. For farmers be based on the notion that they are even more
surely will supply fewer chickens if demand unlike humans than they in fact are.
drops. If this scenario appears unlikely, however, The truth of the matter is that there is a place
the argument based around thresholds still suf- for compassion in the rearing ofanimals for food,
fices to solve the Collective Action Problem. and that even where callousness takes the place
of compassion, there is no reason to think that
It is also the case that an individual's boycott this will spill over into callousness towards human
can be a symbolic gesture, and thus have indirect beings.
effects on intensive farming through influencing
others to reflect upon the reasons for the boycott
and to join it. 4 THE ARGUMENT FROM PATERNALISM
On the basis ofthe discussion so far, then, CR
emerges as the most plausible utilitarian view on 1. There is strong evidence that Meat-eating is
Meat-eating. not conducive to the health of a population.

-45-
2. It is the utilitarian duty of a government to be starving? It is true that utilitarianism does otfer
minimize hann. a strong rationale for the institution of prope:rty.18
3. Therefore, Meat-eating ought to be forbidden. .But, given that goods diminish marginally in
カ。ャセ・L any utilitarian theory of property which
The first premise is loosely worded. There is
would permit the present inequality of wealth,
strong evidence that the eating of red meat-and
and hence control over resources, between north-
fatty foods in general-in large quantities is linked
ern and southern hemispheres must be entirely
with conditions such as heart-disease. But there
unconvincing. 19
is little, if any, evidence that eating meat, in par-
The problem with this argument is the simplis-
ticular white meat or fish, in moderation is hann-
tic conception of economics on which its main
ful.
assumption rests. This is that practices of Meat-
The proponent of the argument may then at-
eating use protein which would otheIWise have
tempt to weaken the conclusion to the claim that
been available for the starving. But famines are
eating red meat ought to be forbidden. But this
not usually caused by shortages offood, but rather
ignores the direct and indirect hanns of pater-
more complex events such as sudden changes in
nalism. Paternalism, by definition, violates a per-
entitlement relations. 2o What those who are starv-
son's autonomy, and infringes upon his or her
ing need is wealth, to buy food and long-term
liberty. And banning red meat would also have
productive capacity, not our ceasing to eat meat.
obvious bad side-etfects, similar to those which
This would be likely to disturb the world grain-
occurred during the era of Prohibition of alcohol
market to such an extent that very bad conse-
in the United States. Indeed, it is likely that any
quences could occur. For example, countries re-
such measure would have to be repealed. The
lying on grain-export would become poorer, with
conclusion, then, must be weakened still further.
adverse etfects on their population. And a further
The argument can only require a government to
likely consequence would be that there would be
disseminate information concerning the dangers
less grain available to those who are starving. This
to the individual of consuming large amounts of
was suggested by a number of economists, イセ。」エᆳ
food with a high fat content.
ing to the statement in the nineteen-seventies by
the American senator Earl Butt that each Amer-
ican citizen ought to eat one less hamburger a
5 THE ARGUMENT FROM STARVATION
week, with a view to easing starvation in the Third
World. 21 Third World grain supplies fluctuate ac-
1. The widespread practice of Meat-eating re-
セッイ、ゥョァ .to surpluses in the First World. Suppty
quires the feeding of large amounts of protein
In the First World in turn fluctuates according to
to animals.
demand. And the greater the demand, the greater
2. This protein could be used to feed those
the likely surplus. Thus, as it tumed out, Butt
human beings who are starving.
should have urged Americans to eat one more
3. By eating meat, we are causing the deaths of
hamburger a week!
these human beings.
If the proponent of the argument then clainls
4. Causing the death ofhuman beings is wrong.
to be aware ofthese problems, and to be otfering
5. Therefore, we ought to cease to eat meat.
a purely tactical or protreptic thesis, designed to
Utilitarians cannot accept that there is a moral bring about a change in people's diets, there is a
distinction between acts and omissions. Thus, the requirement that V be shown to be justified on
obvious common-sense reply to the argument, grounds other than those allegedly supplied by
that we are not killing those who starve to death the Argument from Starvation. 22 And thOSt:
but merely allowing them to die, is not open エセ grounds we have yet to find. The Argument frorn
me in a dispute with a utilitarian. Starvation is valid and true if re-interpreted as a
Could I claim that we have property-rights over demand that an individual give money to a charity
this protein, in that it is purchased on the open concerned with aid to the Third World. But be-
market trom its legal owners, either at horne or coming a Vegetarian will not aid those who are
in other countries, where people may or may セッエ starving.

-46-
6 THE ARGUMENT FROM long-term. And consider the etfects of two
FUTURE GENERATIONS policies: Depletion of resources, through increas-
ing the population; and Conservation, through
1. Extra sentient beings in the world would raise maintaining present levels of population. Deple-
the level of utility. tion will benefit the short-term generations, but
2. Human beings are the most efficient producers at the expense ofthe medium-term. Conservation
of utility. will benefit the medium-term, but at the expense
3. Therefore, it is wrong to rear animals for food, of the short term. There are two relevant consid-
since the protein consumed by these animals erations, here. Keeping the population steady will
would produce more utility if used to feed (i) give us more time to develop substitutes for
extra human beings, until an optimum popu- these resources, and (ii) enable us to contrive more
lation is reached. efficient ways of using resources that remain. If
we fail to develop substitutes, there could be a
This argument relies on Total, as opposed to Av-
global disaster. Conservation gives us more time
er age, utilitarianism. 23 According to the Total
for research, and thus is less likely to result in
vi セキL we are required to maximize the level of
disaster for medium- and long-term generations.
total utility overtime, not, say, average utility (total
And any amount of resources used in the
u1ility divided by the number of beings living).
medium-term will almost certainly provide more
One important objection to the argument is of utility, because of increased efficiency.
c()urse that most people do not believe in the Meanwhile, renewable resources, such as pro-
Total view, including most members ofmost gov- tein, should be put to their most efficient use.
eJnments. Thus, even if more protein becomes And the most efficient use of protein will involve
a ,ailable, it is unlikely to be used to support pro- feeding both human beings and domestic animals.
ァセ。ュウ of population-growth. It is not only the I conclude, then, that none of the main utili-
e :onomics, but also the politics of this argument tarian arguments for V succeeds. The suffering
\' rhich are simplistic. endured by intensively reared animals mIes out
A more trenchant point, however, is that the eating them. Thus RF, FP, and FR are incorrect.
1'otal view does not support increasing popula- The practice of rearing animals non-intensively
tlon in our world. Unless there is some disaster, is productive of utility. Thus, CP is incorrect, and
i: will be many millions of years before life on CR is the most plausible utilitarian view on Meat-
t his planet dies out through the sun's being extin- eating. 24
! ;uished. Thus, our conception of'the future' ought
10 be far broader than that implied by the Argu-
lnent from Future Generations. ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
Human beings at present are heavy users of
rinite resources, such as fossil-fuels and metals. I am indebted to Raymond Frey, James Griffin,
I fhese resources are being used very inefficiently. Richard Hare, Michael Lockwood, Peter Singer,
Imagine future generations classified into three and Eldon Soifer for their comments on previous
セイッオーウZ the short-term, the medium-term, and the drafts of this paper.

-47-
FOOTNOTES

1. See e.g. R Singer, Animal Libemtion, London: is supported by e.g. T. Regan, The Gase for
Jonathan Cape, 1976; PracticaJ Ethics, AnimaJ Rights, London: Routledge & Kegan
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Paul, chap. 2.
1979. In 'Killing animals and killing humans',
InquiJy 22, 1979, and 'Utilitarianism and 5. J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, repr. in (ed.) M.
vegetarianism', Philosophy and Public Warnock, Utilitarianism, London: Fontana,
Affairs 7, 1979-80, Singer's position be- 1962,chap.2.
comes more sympathetic to what I call
the Compromise Pennission view (CP).
Singer, does, however, appear to qualif}1 6. See M. Lockwood, 'Singer on killing and the
his adherence to CP: i) it may only be suited preferenceforlife', Inqui1)' 22, 1979,p.161.
to a society of 'sophisticated philosophers';
ii) it may be the first step onto a slippery 7. Singer appears to believe that aDesire theo [)'
slope leading us back to Full Meat-eating can supply special reasons for not killing
in a factory-farming society. Singer's arg- 'self-conscious' beings (those with the desire
uments will be discussed further below. to go on living). See PracticaJ Ethics, 80r.;
ch.5; 'Killing humans and killing animals'.
2. See e.g. R. Frey, Rights, Killing, and Sutfer- Hesays:
ing, Oxford: Basil Blackwell' 1983. Frey The replaceability principle applies:I
does not advocate the Full Meat-eating regardless of species, to beings who
Pennission view (FP) (according to which have never had the capacity to desire
one can eat all kinds of meat without continüed life. ['Killing humans and
qualms), but is sympathetic to the motiva- killing animals', 154f.]
tion behind the Compromise views. One is He also seems to believe that domestic ani-
morally permitted to eat any kind of animal mals lack self-consciousness, and do not
flesh, but also morally required to cam- therefore have the desire to go on living. The
paign for the end of intensive fanning, by latter claim seems to me false, and I suspect
means such as political lobbying. I shall call that the former is either false or confused.
this the R Freyview (RF). But as the main text shows the point is not
relevant here, and so does not deserve filr-·
3. This incidentally is why one should take ther discussion.
care in interpreting Singer's claim about re-
placeability: 8. E.g. Singer, Practical Ethics, 83ft:; J. Glo-
. . . that even if it is valid when the ver, Gausing Death and Saving Lives,
animals in question have a pleasant Hannondsworth: Penguin, 1977, chap. 5;
life, it would not justi1}r ァョセ。・ the flesh J. Griffin, Well-Being, Oxford: Clarendon
of animals reared in modem 'factory Press, 1986, p. 67.
farms', where the animals are so
crowded together and restricted in
their movements that their lives seem 9. For the opposing view, see Regan, The Gase
to be more of a burden than a benefit forAnimaJRights, eh. 3.
to them. [Practical Ethics, p. 100]
10. Again, I am concemed with domestic anj..·
4. It has been argued in Frey, Interests and mals here. Ifsomeone were to claim that cer·.'
Rights, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980 and tain chimpanzees or gorillas are autonolnous
elsewhere that animals cannot have desires. to some degree, I should be less inclined to
Common sense suggests that this is false, and dismiss her.

-48-
1. Singer sometimes seems to pass by this 17. Reasons and Persons, NWRセ See also Singer,
point. Forexample: 'Utilitarianism and vegetarianism', p. 336.
. . .the important question is not
whether animal flesh could be pro- 18. See A. Ryan, Property and Political Theory,
duced without suffering, but whether Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984, Chap. 4.
the fIesh that we are considering buy-
ing was produced without suffering. 19. See Singer, 'Famine, affiuence, and morality',
Unless we can be confident that it was, Philosophyand PublicAffairs 1,1972.
the principle of equal consideration of
interests implies that it was wrong to 20. See A. Sen, Poverty and Famines, Oxford:
sacrifice important interests of the Clarendon Press, 1981.
animal to satisfY less important in-
terests of our own; consequently we 21. Butt's claim was brought to my attention by
should boycott the end result of this Lockwood.
process. [Practical Ethics, p.56f:]
22. I discuss another tactical argument concem-
I!. Although they do of course often experience ing animals in 'The argument from marginal
severe suffering. See Singer, Animal cases', Joumal of Applied Philosophy 2,
Liberation, 15 2ff 1985. Ifthe utilitarian offers this as an argu-
ment for V-on the ground that we would
13. See Singer, Animal Liberation, Chap. 3; and think it wrong to eat mentally defective
J. Mason and Singer, Animal Factories, New people-it will fail on grounds similar to
York: Crown PubIishers, 1980. those on which the Argument from Indirect
Diminution of UtiIity (lb)failed. The side-
14. See M. Olson, The Logic ofCol1ective Act- effects in each case are markedly different.
ion, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University
Press, 1965. 23. See H. Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics,
London: Macmillan, 1907, p. 415t:
15. For a different view, see Griffin, 'Some prob-
lems offairness', Ethics 96, 1985. 24. It should be noted that CR requires only the
consumption ofartificially-reared meat. Wild
] 6. D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: animals, including fish, will not be replaced,
Clarendon Press, 1984, §§28-9. and so should not be eaten.

-49-

You might also like