M3P11

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 33

M3P11 Galois Theory

Lectured by Prof Alessio Corti


Typed by David Kurniadi Angdinata
Spring 2019

K (α) K (α0 ) K (β, γ) K (δ) K (δ 0 )

K (β) K (βγ) K (γ)

hei

hτ i σ2 τ σ2 hστ i σ3 τ

σ2 , τ hσi σ 2 , στ

Syllabus
Field extensions. Irreducible polynomials. Normal extensions. Separable extensions. Fundamental the-
orem of Galois theory. Galois theory of quadratic polynomials. Galois theory of biquadratic polynomials.
Galois theory of finite fields. Galois theory of cubic polynomials. Reduction modulo prime.

1
M3P11 Galois Theory Contents

Contents
0 What is Galois theory? 3

1 Eisenstein numbers 6

2 Elementary facts 9

3 Axiomatics 11

4 Galois correspondence 14

5 Normal extensions 17

6 Separable polynomials 18

7 Separable degree 20

8 Separable extensions 21

9 Biquadratic polynomials 22

10 Finite fields 26

11 Symmetric polynomials 27

12 Irreducible polynomials 29

13 Reduction modulo prime 31

2
M3P11 Galois Theory 0 What is Galois theory?

0 What is Galois theory?


Lecture 1
References. Thursday
• E Artin, Galois theory, 1994 10/01/19

• A Grothendieck and M Raynaud, Revêtements étales et groupe fondamental, 2002


• I N Herstein, Topics in algebra, 1975
• M Reid, Galois theory, 2014
Notation. If K is a field, or a ring, I denote

K [X] = {a0 + · · · + an X n | ai ∈ K} ,

the ring of polynomials with coefficients in K.


Example.
• Q, R, C.
• Quadratic fields
√  n √ o Q [X]
Q 2 = a + b 2 | a, b ∈ Q = .
hX 2 − 2i
It is also a field, since √
1 a−b 2
√ = 2 .
a+b 2 a − 2b2

• If p is prime, Z/pZ = Fp is a finite field. If f (X) ∈ K [X] is irreducible, K [X] / hf (X)i is a field.
For example, X 2 − 2. Both Z and K [X] have a division algorithm. For example, let [a] ∈ Z/pZ and
[a] 6= 0, that is p | a. Since p is prime, gcd (p, a) = 1, so there exist x, y ∈ Z such that ax + py = 1.
Thus [a] · [x] = 1 in Z/pZ.
• For K a field, either for all m ∈ Z, m 6= 0 in K, so K has characteristic ch (K) = 0, or there exists p
prime such that m = 0 if and only if p | m, so K has characteristic ch (K) = p.
• For K a field,
( )
f (X)
K (X) = F rac (K [X]) = φ (X) = f, g ∈ K [X] , g 6= 0 .
g (X)

is also a field, the field of rational functions with coefficients in K. For example, Fp (X, Y ) = Fp (X) (Y ).
Example. Consider algebraic equations in a field K.
• Let aX 2 + bX 2 + c = 0 for a, b, c ∈ K be a quadratic. There is a formula

−b + b2 − 4ac
X= .
2a

• For a cubic Y 3 + 3pY + 2q = 0,


q p q p
3 3
Y = −q + q + p + −q − q 2 + p3 .
2 3

• There is a formula for quartic equations.


• It is a theorem that there can be no such formula for equations of degree at least five.
Galois theory deals with these easily.

3
M3P11 Galois Theory 0 What is Galois theory?

Lecture 2
Definition 0.1. A field homomorphism is a function φ : K1 → K2 that preserves the field operations, Friday
for all a, b ∈ K1 , 11/01/19

φ (a + b) = φ (a) + φ (b) ,
φ (ab) = φ (a) φ (b) ,

and φ (0K1 ) = 0K2 and φ (1K1 ) = 1K2 .


Remark. All field homomorphisms are injective. If a ∈ K1 \ {0}, then there exists b ∈ K1 such that ab = 1,
then φ (a) φ (b) = 1, so φ (a) 6= 0. This easily implies φ is injective. If a1 6= a2 , then a1 − an 6= 0, so
0 6= φ (a1 − a2 ) = φ (a1 ) − φ (a2 ). Then φ (a1 ) 6= φ (a2 ).
We concern ourselves with field extensions k ⊂ K, and every homomorphism is an extension. Consider a
field extension k ⊂ K and α ∈ K. Then k (α) ⊂ K denotes the smallest subfield of K that contains k and
α. Not to be confused with k (X).
Example. There are two very different cases exemplified in Q ⊂ C.
√ √ 
• α = 2, so Q 2 .
• α = π, so Q (π).

Definition 0.2.
• α is algebraic over k if f (α) = 0 for some 0 6= f ∈ k [X]. Otherwise we say that α is transcendental
over k.
• The extension k ⊂ K is algebraic if for all α ∈ K, α is algebraic over k.

Definition 0.3. Consider a field k and f ∈ k [X]. We say that k ⊂ K is a splitting field for f if
Qn
• f (X) = a i=1 (X − λi ) ∈ K [X] for a ∈ k \ {0}, and
• K = k (λ1 , . . . , λn ).

Example.
√ 
• If f (X) = X 2 − 2 ∈ Q [X], then K = Q 2 is a splitting field for f . Indeed
 √  √  √ 
X2 − 2 = X + 2 X − 2 ∈ Q 2 [X] .

√ 
• If f (X) = X 2 + 2, then K = Q −2 .
• If f (X) = X 3 − 2, then √  n
3

3

3
o
Q 2 = a + b 2 + c 4 | a, b, c ∈ Q
√ √
2, ω , where ω = −1+2 3 , is a splitting field.
3

is not a splitting field. K = Q
 √  √  √ 
X 3 − 2 = X − 2 X − ω 2 X − ω2 2 .
3 3 3

4
M3P11 Galois Theory 0 What is Galois theory?

Theorem 0.4 (Fundamental theorem of Galois theory, Galois correspondence). Assume characteristic zero.
Let k ⊂ K be the splitting field of f (X) ∈ k [X]. Let

G = {σ : K → K | σ field automorphism, σ|k = idk } .

We call this group the Galois group. There is a one-to-one correspondence

{k ⊂ K1 ⊂ K | K1 subfield} ↔ {H ≤ G | H subgroup}
K1 7→ {σ ∈ G | ∀λ ∈ K1 , σ (λ) = λ} .
{λ ∈ K | ∀σ ∈ H, σ (λ) = λ} ←[ H ≤ G

Why is this cool? Fields are hard, groups are easy. We will see that there is a good formula for the roots of
f (X) if and only if G is a soluble group. Lecture 3
Tuesday
Example. Let deg (f ) = 2 and f (X) = X 2 + 2AX + B ∈ K [X]. If K already contains the roots then 15/01/19
L = K and G = {id}. Suppose K does not contain the roots. We still have quadratic formula
p
λ1,2 = −A ± A2 − B.

If ∆ = A2 − B then ∆ does not exist in K. We must have
√  n √ o
L=K ∆ = a + b ∆ | a, b ∈ K .

Then K ⊂ L and
G = {σ : L → L | σ|K = idK } = C2
is generated by √ √
σ : a + b ∆ 7→ a − b ∆.
The following is further specialisation.
• Let K = R and ∆ = −1. Then
 √
L = C = a + b −1 | a, b ∈ R ,

and G = C2 is generated by √ √
σ : a + b −1 7→ a − b −1,
complex conjugation.
• Let K = Q and ∆ = 2. Then n √ o
L = a + b 2 | a, b ∈ Q ,

and G = C2 is generated by √ √
σ : a + b 2 7→ a − b 2.

The fundamental theorem implies there does not exist


√ 
K ( K1 ( K ∆ = L.

Is this obvious? Consider x ∈ L \ K, so x = a + b ∆, and b 6= 0, and then
√ x−a
∆= ,
b
so K (x) = L.

5
M3P11 Galois Theory 1 Eisenstein numbers

1 Eisenstein numbers
√ √
2, ω , where ω = −1+i 3

Let f (X) = X 3 − 2 ∈ Q [X] and L = Q 3
2 is a solution of X 2 + X + 1 = 0. Then
√ √  n √ √ o
3 3 3

Q (ω) = Q −3 , Q 2 = a + b 2 + c 4 | a, b, c ∈ Q .

Remark. For any splitting field of f , there is always a natural inclusion group homomorphism

ρ : G ,→ S (λ1 , . . . , λn ) ,

where S (λ1 , . . . , λn ) is the group of permutations of the roots of f = X n + a1 X n−1 + · · · + an .


• If σ ∈ G, f (λ) = 0, so λn + a1 λn−1 + · · · + an = 0.
n n−1
0 = σ (0) = σ λn + a1 λn−1 + · · · + an = σ (λ) + a1 σ (λ)

+ · · · + an .

• ρ is injective. If for all i, σ (λi ) = λi , then σ = id on K (λ1 , . . . , λn ) = L.


The fundamental theorem and remark implies that G = S3 . Lecture 4
Thursday
Definition 1.1. K ⊂ L is finite if L is finite-dimensional as a vector space over K. The degree of L over 17/01/19
K is
[L : K] = dimK (L) .
Theorem 1.2 (Tower law). Let K ⊂ L ⊂ F . Then

[F : K] = [F : L] [L : K] .

Theorem 1.3. Suppose f (X) ∈ K [X] is irreducible of degree d = deg (f ) and L = K (λ) where f (λ) = 0,
then [K (λ) : K] = d.
√  √ 
K = Q 3 2 is a field, and [K : Q] = 3. Let L = Q 3 2, ω be the splitting field of X 3 − 2 over Q. The
lattice of subfields is
L
2 2
2
√  √  √  3
Q 32 Q ω32 Q ω2 3 2
.

3
3 Q (ω)
3

2
Q
Then (Exercise)
√   √   √  √ √ 
Q ω 2 2 ∩ Q ω 2 = Q,
3 3 3 3 3
Q 2 + ω = L, Q 2, ω 2 = L.
 √  √  √  √ √  √ 
What is L : Q 3 2 ? Note that L = Q 3 2 −3 . Could −3 ∈ Q 3 2 ? Consider X 2 +3 ∈ Q 3 2 [X].
By the tower law,
(
[L : Q] = [L : Q (ω)] [Q (ω) : Q] = 2 [L : Q (ω)] =⇒ 2 | [L : Q]
 √   √    √  =⇒ 6 | [L : Q] .
[L : Q] = L : Q 3 2 Q 3 2 : Q = 3 L : Q 3 2 =⇒ 3 | [L : Q]
√   √ 
• Either X 2 + 3 is irreducible over Q 3
2 , so by Theorem 1.3 L : Q 3 2 = 2 and [L : Q] = 6.
√ 
• Or X 2 + 3 is not irreducible, so Q 3 2 = L and [L : Q] = 3, a contradiction.

6
M3P11 Galois Theory 1 Eisenstein numbers

Are there any other fields? Claim that there are no other fields. Suppose Q ( K ( L is such a field. By the
tower law [K : Q] = 2 or [K : Q] = 3.
• Suppose [K : Q] = 2.
L

3
K (ω)
.
K Q (ω)

2 2
Q

– Either ω ∈ K, that is Q (ω) ⊂ K, so by the tower law Q (ω) = K.


– Or ω ∈/ K, so [K (ω) : K] = 2, so [K (ω) : Q] = 4 contradicts the tower law for Q ⊂ K (ω) ⊂ L.
• Suppose [K : Q] = 3.
L


3

2 K 2
.

K
3

Q
 √  
Claim that X 3 − 2 ∈ K [X] splits. Suppose that it were irreducible, then K 3 2 : K = 3, which
√  √ √
contradicts the tower law for K ⊂ K 3 2 ⊂ L. So it has a root in K. Either 3 2 ∈ K, ω 3 2 ∈ K, or
√ √  √  √ 
ω 2 3 2 ∈ K. Thus Q 3 2 = K, Q ω 3 2 = K, or Q ω 2 3 2 = K.
I want to prove that n o
G = AutQ (L) = σ : L → L | σ|Q = idQ = S3 .
Lecture 5
Proof of Theorem 1.2. Suppose y1 , . . . , ym ∈ F is a basis of F as a vector space over L. Suppose x1 , . . . , xn ∈ Friday
L is a basis of L as a vector space over K. Claim that {xi yj } is a basis of F over K. 18/01/19
• {xi yj } generates F . Let z ∈ F . There exist µ1 , . . . , µn ∈ L such that
z = µ1 y1 + · · · + µn yn . (1)
µj ∈ L so for all j there exists λij ∈ K such that
µj = x1 λ1j + · · · + xm λmj . (2)
Plugging in (2) into (1), X
z= λij xi yj .
i,j

• {xi yj } are linearly independent over K. Suppose there exists λij ∈ K such that
!
X X X
0= λij xi yj = λij xi yj ,
i,j j i
P
so for all j, i λij xi = 0, so for all j and all i, λij = 0.

7
M3P11 Galois Theory 1 Eisenstein numbers


Example. To show G = S3 . Let σ = 1 2 . A basis of L/Q is

3

3

3

3
1, 2, 4, ω, ω 2, ω 4.

• σ (1) = 1.
√  √
• σ 3 2 = ω 3 2.
√  √
• σ ω 3 2 = 3 2.
√  √ √  √ √ √ √ √ √
• σ 3 4 = σ 3 2 · 3 2 = ω 3 2 · ω 3 2 = ω 2 3 4 = (−ω − 1) 3 4 = −ω 3 4 − 3 4.
√ √  √  √  √ √
• σ (ω) = σ ω 3 2/ 3 2 = σ ω 3 2 /σ 3 2 = 3 2/ω 3 2 = 1/ω = −1 − ω.
√  √ √  √  √  √ √ √
• σ ω 3 4 = σ ω 3 2 · 3 2 = σ ω 3 2 · σ 3 2 = 3 2 · ω 3 2 = ω 3 4.
Thus  
1 0 −1 0 0 0
0 0 0 1 0 0
 
0 0 0 0 0 −1
σ= .
0 0
 −1 0 0  0
0 1 0 0 0 0
0 0 0 0 1 −1

A question is if there were σ ∈ G such that ρ (σ) = 1 2 then we have written the matrix of σ as a Q-linear
map of L in a basis. But how to check that this Q-linear map is a field homomorphism? We know the Galois
correspondence for extensions of degree two.
  √    √    √ 
2 , Gal L/Q ω 2 2 , Gal L/Q ω 2 ⊂ G
3 3 3
Gal L/Q

contain an element of order two, and



3
 
ρ: Gal L/Q √ 2 7→ 2 3
Gal L/Q ω 2 √
3
2 7 → 1 2
Gal L/Q ω 3 2 7 → 1 3 .

The lattice of subgroups is

hei
2 2
2
   3
2 3 1 2 1 3
.

3
3 1 2 3
3

2
G

Q (ω) /Q is the splitting field of X 2 + X + 1 and of X 2 + 3.

We can learn the following. Let k ⊂ L be a splitting field. Consider k ⊂ K ⊂ L. Then K ⊂ L is also a
splitting field. The corresponding H ≤ G is the Galois group Gal (L/K). On the other hand k ⊂ K is not
always a splitting field. It is a splitting field if and only if the corresponding H ≤ G is a normal subgroup
and in that case Gal (K/k) = G/H.

8
M3P11 Galois Theory 2 Elementary facts

2 Elementary facts
Lecture 6
Let K ⊂ L and a ∈ L. The evaluation homomorphism Tuesday
22/01/19
ea : K [X] −→ K [a] ⊂ L
f (X) 7−→ f (a)

is a surjective ring homomorphism, where K [a] is the smallest subring of L containing K and a.
Definition 2.1. f (X) = a0 X n + · · · + an ∈ K [X] is monic if a0 = 1.
Lemma 2.2.

• If a is transcendental, ea is injective and it extends to eea : K (X) → K (a), by

K (X)
e a .


f

K [X] ea L

• If a is algebraic, then Ker (ea ) = hfa i, where fa ∈ K [X] is irreducible, or prime, and unique if monic,
then called the minimal polynomial of a ∈ L/K. In this case
ea
K [X] K [a] ∼
= K (a) ⊂ L

[ea ]
.
K [X]
hfa i

Proof. There is nothing to prove.

Remark. Let g (X) ∈ K [X] and g (a) 6= 0. Claim that 1/g (a) ∈ K [a]. Indeed gcd (f, g) = 1 in K [X] and
f - g. There exists φ, ψ ∈ K [X] such that f φ + gψ = 1 and g (a) ψ (a) = 1. All of this is saying
• K [a] ∼
= K (a), and
• K [X] / hfa i ∼
= K (a).
Let
EmK (K (a) , F ) = {σ : K (a) → F | σ field homomorphism, σK = idK } ,
where
K (a)

K σ .

F
Corollary 2.3. For K ⊂ L and a ∈ L algebraic over K,
• [K (a) : K] = deg (fa ), and

• If K ⊂ F is an extension,
EmK (K (a) , F ) = {b ∈ F | fa (b) = 0} .

9
M3P11 Galois Theory 2 Elementary facts

Proof. Since K (a) = K [a], [K (a) : K] = dimK (K (a)) = dimK [K (a)]. Suppose

f (X) = X n + µ1 X n−1 + · · · + µn ∈ K [X]

is the minimal polynomial of a over K. Claim that 1, . . . , an−1 is a basis of K [a] over K.
• The set generates K [a]. Let c ∈ K [a]. There exists g ∈ K [X] such that g (a) = c. Long division
implies that
g (X) = f (X) q (X) + r (X) , m = deg (r (X)) < n.
Then r (X) = λ0 + · · · + λm X m and g (a) = r (a) = λ0 + · · · + λm am .
• The set is linearly independent, otherwise there exists

g (X) = λ0 + · · · + λn−1 X n−1 ∈ K [X] , g (a) = 0,

and f was not the minimal polynomial.


σ (a) is a root of f , since applying σ to f (a) = 0 gives
n n−1
0 = σ an + µ1 an−1 + · · · + µn = σ (a) + µ1n−1 σ (a)

+ · · · + µn = f (σ (a)) .

Vice versa, if b ∈ F is a root of f ,


[eb ] K [X] [ea ]
K (b) ←−− −−→ K (a) ,
∼ hf i ∼
−1
then σ = [eb ] [ea ] . Thus there is a one-to-one correspondence

EmK (K (a) , F ) ↔ {b ∈ F | f (b) = 0}


σ 7→ σ (a) .
−1
[eb ] [ea ] ←[ b

Corollary 2.4. Let K be a field and f ∈ K [X]. Then there exists K ⊂ L such that f has a root in L.
Proof. Take g a prime factor of f . Take L = K [X] / hgi. In here a = [X] is a root of g hence a root of f .
Lecture 7
From now on in this course, we study field extensions K ⊂ L, always assumed to be finite, so [L : K] = Thursday
dimK (L) < ∞. 24/01/19
Remark. K ⊂ L is finite if and only if
• it is algebraic, that is for all a ∈ L, a is algebraic over K, and
• it is finitely generated, that is there exist a1 , . . . , am ∈ L such that L = K (a1 , . . . , am ).
An important point of view is that we study all possible field homomorphisms

Em (K, L) = {σ : K → L | σ field homomorphism} .

Often there is a field k ⊂ K, L in the background which we want to stay fixed, so let

Emk (K, L) = {σ : K → L | σ field homomorphism, σ|k = idk } .


√  √ √ √ 
Example. Let K = Q 3 2 . The minimal polynomial of 3 2 is X 3 − 2. Let L = Q 3 2, −3 be the
splitting field of X 3 − 2. Then
n√ √ √ o
EmQ (K, L) = Em (K, L) = roots of X 3 − 2 in L = 2, ω 2, ω 2 2 .
3 3 3


Remark. Suppose k ⊂ K. Then Emk (K, K) = G = Gal (K/k). Indeed every k-homomorphism σ : K → K
is automatically invertible. We know σ is injective. σ is also surjective because σ is a k-linear endomorphism
of a finite-dimensional k-vector space.

10
M3P11 Galois Theory 3 Axiomatics

3 Axiomatics
Proposition 3.1. Fix k ⊂ K and k ⊂ L. Then

#Emk (K, L) ≤ [K : k] .

Proof.
Special case. If K = k (a), let f (X) ∈ k [X] be the minimal polynomial of a. Then Emk (k (a) , L) is the
roots of f (X) in L, so

#Emk (K, L) = # {roots} ≤ deg (f ) = [k (a) : k] ,

as proved last time.

General case. If k = K, nothing to do. Otherwise choose a ∈ K \ k.

L
⊂ y .
k ⊂ k (a) ⊂ K

Consider the restriction map

ρ : Emk (K, L) → Emk (k (a) , L) .

Fix y ∈ Emk (k (a) , L). Then


n o
ρ−1 (y) = x : K → L | x|k(a) = idk(a) .

Since [k (a) : k] > 1, by the tower law [K : k (a)] < [K : k]. By induction we may assume
#ρ−1 (y) ≤ [K : k (a)]. So
X
#Emk (K, L) ≤ #ρ−1 (y) ≤ [k (a) : k] [K : k (a)] = [K : k] ,
y∈Emk (k(a),L)

by the tower law.

Proposition 3.2. Suppose given two field extensions k ⊂ K and k ⊂ L. Then there is a non-unique bigger
common field
K
σ1 φ1

k Ω
σ2 φ2
L
that contains both.

11
M3P11 Galois Theory 3 Axiomatics

Remark.
• More formally, suppose given σ1 ∈ Em (k, K) and σ2 ∈ Em (k, L), then there exist Ω, φ1 ∈ Em (K, Ω),
and φ2 ∈ Em (L, Ω) such that φ1 ◦ σ1 = φ2 ◦ σ2 .
√  √ 
• I never said that Ω is unique. For example, let K = Q 3 2 and L = Q 3 2 . One choice is Ω = k.
√ √ 
Another choice is Ω = Q 3 2, −3 , where

3

Q 2

3 √
3
σ 27→ 2

√ √ 
Q Q 3
2, −3 .
σ √
3 √
3
27→ω 2
√ 
Q 32

• Another more precise way to state this is there exists k ⊂ Ω such that Emk (K, Ω) and Emk (L, Ω) are
both non-empty.
Lecture 8
Friday
Proof.
25/01/19
Special case. If K = k (a), let f (X) ∈ k [X] be the minimal polynomial of a over k. Let L ⊂ E be
such that f (X) ∈ L [X] has a root α ∈ E. Then there exists σ ∈ Emk (k (a) , E) such that
σ (a) = α.
k (a)
σ

.
k E

General case. By induction on [K : k]. If [K : k] = 1, take Ω = L. If [K : k] > 1, take a ∈ K \ k.

K
⊂ ⊂

k (a) Ω
⊂ ⊂
.

k E

By special case there exists E as in the diagram. By tower law [K : k (a)] < [K : k] hence
by induction find Ω as in the diagram. Ω solves the original problem.

12
M3P11 Galois Theory 3 Axiomatics

Proposition 3.3. Let L be any field and G be a finite group acting on L as automorphisms. Let
K = G∗ = F ix (G) = LG = {λ ∈ L | ∀σ ∈ G, σ (λ) = λ} .

Consider AutK (L) = K † . Then the obvious inclusion G ⊂ K † = (G∗ ) is an equality, so G is all of K † .
Remark. Contextualising, this thing is half of the Galois correspondence.
{F | k ⊂ F ⊂ Ω} ↔ {G | G ≤ Autk (Ω)}
F 7→ AutF (Ω) = F † .
F ix (G) = G∗ ←[ G
† ∗
Then to prove the Galois correspondence, we need for all G, G = (G∗ ) . We also need for all F , F = F † .
Proposition 3.3 follows from the following lemma.
Lemma 3.4. K ⊂ L is a finite extension of degree [L : K] ≤ |G|.
Proof of Proposition 3.3. From Proposition 3.1, AutK (L) = EmK (L, L) because K ⊂ L is finite, and
#EmK (L, L) ≤ [L : K]. By Lemma 3.4,
[L : K] ≤ #EmK (L, L) ≤ [L : K] ,
so |G| = #EmK (L, L). By what we said, G ⊂ EmK (L, L), so G = EmK (L, L).
Lecture 9
Lecture 9 is a problem class. Tuesday
Proof of Lemma 3.4. Write G = {σ1 , . . . , σn } for n = |G|. Want that all (n + 1)-tuples a1 , . . . , an+1 ∈ L are 29/01/19
linearly dependent over K. Let a1 , . . . , an+1 ∈ L. Consider the n + 1 vectors in Ln . Let Lecture 10
    Thursday
σ1 (a1 ) σ1 (an+1 ) 31/01/19
a1 =  ...  , . . . , an+1 =  ..
∈L .
n
   
.
σn (a1 ) σn (an+1 )
These are linearly dependent over L. There exist x1 , . . . , xn+1 ∈ L not all zero such that
x1 a1 + · · · + xn+1 an+1 = 0.
By reordering the ai , may assume
x1 a1 + · · · + xk ak = 0, (3)
for some 1 ≤ k ≤ n + 1 with
• for all i ∈ {1, . . . , k}, xi 6= 0,
• such k is the smallest, and
• x1 = 1.
Claim that all these xi ∈ K. This does it, by reading j-th row where σj = idG . We need to show for all i,
xi ∈ LG . Take σ ∈ G.
   
σ (σ1 (a1 )) σ (σ1 (ak ))
.. .. n
σ (x1 )   + · · · + σ (xk )  =0∈L .
   
. .
σ (σn (a1 )) σ (σn (ak ))
Note that
G −→ G
τ 7−→ σ◦τ
is a bijective function and {σ ◦ σ1 , . . . , σ ◦ σn } = G. Multiplying by σ reshuffles the rows. So in fact,
σ (x1 ) a1 + · · · + σ (xk ) ak = 0. (4)
Claim that for all i, σ (xi ) = xi . Otherwise (3) − (4),
(x2 − σ (x2 )) a2 + · · · + (xk − σ (xk )) ak = 0
is a shorter solution, contradicting k minimal.

13
M3P11 Galois Theory 4 Galois correspondence

4 Galois correspondence
Definition 4.1. k ⊂ K is normal if

∀k ⊂ Ω, ∀σ1 , σ2 ∈ Emk (K, Ω) , ∃σ ∈ Emk (K, K) , σ2 = σ1 ◦ σ. (5)


⊂ σ

σ1 (K) σ1 K σ2 σ2 (K) .


⊂ ⊂

k
Equivalently, k ⊂ K is normal if

∀k ⊂ Ω, ∀σ1 , σ2 ∈ Emk (K, Ω) , σ2 (K) ⊂ σ1 (K) . (6)


√  √ √ 
Example. Q ⊂ Q 3 2 is not normal. Take Ω = Q 3 2, −3 .

(5) =⇒ (6) Indeed for all λ ∈ K, σ2 (λ) = σ1 (σ (λ)) ∈ σ1 (K), so σ2 (K) ⊂ σ1 (K).
(6) =⇒ (5) Work inside Ω, so k ⊂ σ2 (K) ⊂ σ1 (K) ⊂ Ω. Tower law implies that

[K : k] = [σ1 (K) : k] = [σ1 (K) : σ2 (K)] [σ2 (K) : k] = [σ1 (K) : σ2 (K)] [K : k] .

So [σ1 (K) : σ2 (K)] = 1, so σ1 (K) = σ2 (K). Take σ = σ1−1 ◦ σ2 . σ is clearly bijective and
it is more or less obvious that σ ∈ Emk (K, K).
Lecture 11
Equivalently, k ⊂ K is normal if for all K ⊂ Ω, for all σ ∈ Emk (K, Ω), σ (K) ⊂ K. Friday
01/02/19



σ
K σ (K)

Remark. We will see that k ⊂ K is normal if and only if there exists f (X) ∈ K [X] such that K is a splitting
field of f .
Lemma 4.2. Suppose k ⊂ K is normal. Consider k ⊂ L ⊂ K. Then also L ⊂ K is normal.
Proof. If σ ∈ EmL (K, Ω), then σ ∈ Emk (K, Ω).

Warning.
• It is not true in general that k ⊂ K is normal implies that k ⊂ L is normal. For example, let
√  √ √ 
3 3
k=Q⊂Q 2 ⊂Q 2, −3 = K.

3

k ⊂ K is normal because it is a splitting field but Q ⊂ Q 2 is not normal.
• Suppose k ⊂ L is normal and L ⊂ K is normal. This does not imply k ⊂ K is normal. This will be in
an example sheet.

14
M3P11 Galois Theory 4 Galois correspondence

Definition 4.3. k ⊂ K is separable if for all k ⊂ K1 ⊂ K2 ⊂ K, if K1 6= K2 , there exist k ⊂ Ω and


embeddings x ∈ Emk (K1 , Ω) and y1 , y2 ∈ Emk (K2 , Ω) such that

K Ω


y1
K2 y1 (K2 ) y2 (K2 )
y2 .


⊂ ⊂
x
K1 x (K1 )


That is, y1 |K1 = y2 |K1 = x but y1 6= y2 .


Slogan is that embeddings separate fields. We will see that
• in characteristic zero everything is separable, and
• in characteristic p we will have good ways to decide if something is separable.
Lemma 4.4. Suppose k ⊂ K ⊂ L. Then k ⊂ L is separable if and only if k ⊂ K and K ⊂ L are separable.
Proof.
=⇒ Obvious. K ⊂ K1 ⊂ K2 ⊂ L leads to k ⊂ K1 ⊂ K2 ⊂ L.
⇐= I will do later.

Theorem 4.5 (Fundamental theorem of Galois theory, Galois correspondence). Let k ⊂ K be normal and
separable. Let G = Emk (K, K). Then there is a one-to-one correspondence

{k ⊂ L ⊂ K} ↔ {H ≤ G}
L 7→ L† = {σ ∈ G | ∀λ ∈ L, σ (λ) = λ} .

H = {λ ∈ K | ∀σ ∈ H, σ (λ) = λ} ←[ H
† ∗
Proof. We show that for all H ≤ G, (H ∗ ) = H and for all k ⊂ L ⊂ K, L† = L. We already did the
∗ We just prove the latter now. Note that L ⊂ K is normal and separable so all I need to show is
former.
k † = k, that is k = G∗ is the fixed field of G. That is, if λ ∈
/ k, there exists σ : K → K in G such that
σ (λ) 6= λ. By separability, there exists Ω and x1 6= x2 ∈ Emk (k (λ) , Ω) such that

K
x
f 1 ,f
x2

k (λ) x1 ,x2 Ω ,

so x1 (λ) 6= x2 (λ). Two steps.


• There exist x f2 : K → Ω extending x1 , x2 : k (λ) → Ω, by the following lemma.
f1 , x
• Because k ⊂ K is normal there exists σ ∈ Emk (K, K) such that x f1 ◦ σ then clearly σ (λ) 6= λ.
f2 = x

15
M3P11 Galois Theory 4 Galois correspondence

Lemma 4.6. Suppose k ⊂ K is normal. Then for all towers k ⊂ F ⊂ K ⊂ Ω, the natural restriction

ρ : Emk (K, Ω) → Emk (F, Ω)

is surjective.
Lecture 12
Lemma 4.6 says for all σ ∈ Emk (F, Ω), there exists σ
e ∈ Emk (K, Ω) such that σ
e|F = σ. Tuesday
05/02/19
K
σ
e

F σ Ω .

Proof. We know that there exists Ω


e as follows.

φ2
K Ω
e
ψ
σ
Ω .
e
F σ

There are two K ⊂ Ω,


e
ψ
φ1 : K ⊂ Ω ,−
→ Ω,
e φ2 : K ,→ Ω.
e

Because k ⊂ K is normal φ2 (K) ⊂ φ1 (K) ⊂ ψ (Ω). That proves that σ


e exists.
Corollary 4.7. Suppose k ⊂ K is normal. Then for all towers k ⊂ F ⊂ K ⊂ Ω,

Emk (F, K) → Emk (F, Ω)

is also surjective.

Corollary 4.7 states that for all σ ∈ Emk (F, Ω), σ (F ) ⊂ K.

σ
K e
σ
e (K)
.

F σ σ (F )

Proof. This clearly follows from Lemma 4.6. σ (F ) ⊂ σ


e (K) ⊂ K by definition of normal.

16
M3P11 Galois Theory 5 Normal extensions

5 Normal extensions
Theorem 5.1. For finite k ⊂ K, the following are equivalent.
1. For all f ∈ k [X] irreducible either f has no root in K or f splits completely in K.
2. There exists f ∈ k [X] not necessarily irreducible such that K is a splitting field of f .
3. k ⊂ K is normal.

Proof.
1 =⇒ 2 There are λ1 , . . . , λm ∈ K such that K = k (λ1 , . . . , λm ). For all i let fi ∈ k [X] be the minimal
polynomial of λi . fi is irreducible and by 1 it splits completely. K is the splitting field of
m
Y
f (X) = fi (X) .
i=1

2 =⇒ 3 Suppose K ⊂ Ω. Let σ : K → Ω be another embedding. For all λi , σ (λi ) is a root of f , so


σ (λi ) ⊂ K hence σ (K) ⊂ K.

3 =⇒ 1 Let f (X) ∈ k [X] be irreducible. Suppose there exists λ ∈ K such that f (λ) = 0. Let Ω be a
splitting field of f (X) ∈ K [X]. Let µ ∈ Ω be a root of f . There exists a unique σ ∈ Emk (k (λ) , Ω)
such that σ (λ) = µ.
K

σ
F = k (λ) σ (F ) ⊂ Ω 3 µ .

k
By Corollary 4.7, σ (F ) ⊂ K, so µ ∈ K.

(Exercise: prove that any two splitting fields of f ∈ k [X] are k-isomorphic, not necessarily in a unique way) Lecture 13
Thursday
Proposition 5.2. Let k ⊂ L be a field extension. Then there exists a tower k ⊂ L ⊂ K such that k ⊂ K is 07/02/19
normal.
Proof. We use normal if and only if splitting field. Pick λ1 , . . . , λn ∈ L such that L = k (λ1 , . . . , λn ). Let
fi ∈ k [X] be the minimal polynomial of λi over k. Let K be the splitting field of
n
Y
f= fi ∈ L [X] .
i=1

Claim that K is the splitting field of f over k. Key point is argue that K is generated by the roots of f over
k.

17
M3P11 Galois Theory 6 Separable polynomials

6 Separable polynomials
Definition 6.1. A polynomial f ∈ k [X] is separable if it has n = deg (f ) distinct roots in any field k ⊂ K
such that f ∈ K [X] splits completely.
Remark. It is not completely obvious that this definition is independent of K. To see this, use the fact that
any two splitting fields are isomorphic.
Example.
p p
• Let k = Fp = Z/pZ. Then X p − a = (X − a) is not separable, since in characteristic p, (a + b) =
ap + bp .
• Let k = Fp (t). Then X p − t is an irreducible polynomial. Why? Let

Fp (t) [u]
K= = Fp (u) .
hup − ti
p
In K [X], X p − t = (X − u) .

For all k, define the derivation as

D : k [X] −→ k [X]
,
X n 7−→ nX n−1

and extend linearly to all of k [X]. The following are some properties.
• D is k-linear, that is for all λ, µ ∈ k, for all f, g ∈ k [X],

D (λf + µg) = λDf + µDg.

• Leibnitz rule, that is for all f, g ∈ k [X],

D (f g) = f Dg + gDf.

Most important thing to know in characteristic p, if p | n then DX n = nX n−1 = 0. If Df = 0 that does not
mean f is constant. This just means that there exists h ∈ k [X] such that f (X) = h (X p ).
Proposition 6.2. f (X) ∈ k [X] is separable if and only if gcd (f, Df ) = 1.
In R [x], f is inseparable if and only if there exists a multiple root, a critical point, which is a root of Df . Lecture 14
Friday
Lemma 6.3. Let f, g ∈ k [X] and c = gcd (f, g) in k [X]. Let k ⊂ L be an extension. Then c = gcd (f, g) in 08/02/19
L [X].
Proof. Indeed, if c | f and c | g in k [X] then also in L [X]. We also know that there exists φ, ψ ∈ k [X] such
that
f φ + gψ = c (7)
in k [X], and hence also in L [X]. Suppose that u | f and u | g in L [X], so u | c in L [X] by (7).

18
M3P11 Galois Theory 6 Separable polynomials

Proof of Proposition 6.2. Let k ⊂ L be any field where f splits completely. We can do the proof in L [X].
That is, we may assume that f splits completely, so
Y
f (X) = (X − λi ) .
i

2
⇐= Assume for a contradiction that f is not separable then f (X) = (X − λ) g (X). Then
2
Df (X) = 2 (X − λ) g (X) + (X − λ) Dg (X) = (X − λ) (2g (X) + (X − λ) Dg (X)) .

That is, (X − λ) | f and (X − λ) | Df , so gcd (f, Df ) 6= 1.

=⇒ For all i 6= j, λi 6= λj .  
j
X Y
Df =  (X − λj ) .
i=1 j6=i

Claim that for all i, (X − λi ) - Df . I hope you see this. This shows gcd (f, Df ) = 1.

Theorem 6.4. f ∈ k [X] irreducible is inseparable if and only if


• ch (k) = p > 0, and
• there exists h ∈ k [X] such that f (X) = h (X p ).
Proof. Indeed f is inseparable if and only if gcd (f, Df ) 6= 1, if and only if Df = 0, since f is irreducible so
gcd (f, Df ) 6= 1 if and only if f | Df , and deg (Df ) < deg (f ).
Definition 6.5. A field k in ch (k) = p > 0 is perfect if for all a ∈ k there exists b ∈ k such that bp = a.
Proposition 6.6. If k is perfect then f ∈ k [X] is irreducible implies that f (X) is separable.
Proof. If f were inseparable then f (X) = h (X p ). For all i, finding bpi = ai ,

h (X) = X n + a1 X n−1 + · · · + an = X n + bp1 X n−1 + · · · + bpn .

Thus p
f (X) = h (X p ) = X n + b1 X n−1 + · · · + bn ,
so f is not irreducible.
Example. All finite fields are perfect. Suppose F is a finite field. Then ch (F ) = p > 0 so Fp ⊂ F therefore
[F : Fp ] = n < 0. dimFp (F ) = n < ∞, so F ∼
n
= (Fp ) as a vector space over Fp , so F has pn elements. The
n n
group F × = F \ {0} has pn − 1 elements. So for all a ∈ F × , ap −1 = 1. For all a ∈ F , ap = a, so
 n−1 p
ap = a,

and this shows F is perfect.


Definition 6.7. Consider k ⊂ K. An element a ∈ L is separable over k if the minimal polynomial
f (X) ∈ k [X] of a is a separable polynomial.
Lecture 15
Lecture 15 is a problem class. Tuesday
Lecture 16 is a problem class. 12/02/19
Lecture 17 is a class test. Lecture 16
Thursday
14/02/19
Lecture 17
Friday
19 15/02/19
M3P11 Galois Theory 7 Separable degree

7 Separable degree
Lecture 18
Definition 7.1. Let k ⊂ K. Choose K ⊂ Ω such that k ⊂ Ω is normal. Define the separable degree as Tuesday
19/02/19
[K : k]s = |Emk (K, Ω)| .

Remark. [K : k]s does not depend on K ⊂ Ω. Suppose k ⊂ Ω1 and k ⊂ Ω2 are normal. Then there exists a
e such that Ω1 ⊂ Ω
bigger field Ω e and Ω2 ⊂ Ω.
e Then
 
Emk (K, Ω1 ) = Emk K, Ω
e = Emk (K, Ω2 ) ,

by Corollary 4.7 a while ago,


Ω1
σ


e

K e .

σ


k
Remark. We can restate the definition of separable extension. Recall that k ⊂ K is separable if for all towers
k ⊂ K1 ⊂ K2 ⊂ K, there exist Ω, y : K1 → Ω, x1 , x2 : K2 → Ω such that x1 6= x2 and x1 |K1 = x2 |K2 = y, so

K2
x1 ,x2

K1 y Ω ,

that is [K2 : K1 ]s 6= 1. Thus k ⊂ K is separable if for all towers k ⊂ K1 ⊂ K2 ⊂ K,

[K2 : K1 ]s = 1 =⇒ K1 = K2 .

Theorem 7.2 (Tower law). For all k ⊂ K ⊂ L,

[L : k]s = [L : K]s [K : k]s .

Proof. Choose L ⊂ Ω and k ⊂ Ω normal, so

L
y

K Ω .
x= y|K

Study
ρ : Emk (L, Ω) → Emk (K, Ω) .
ρ is surjective. For all x ∈ Emk (K, Ω), there exists y ∈ Emk (L, Ω) such that y|K = x, so ρ−1 (x) =
EmK (L, Ω). Then
X X
[L : k]s = |Emk (L, Ω)| = ρ−1 (x) = [L : K]s = [L : K]s [K : k]s .
x∈Emk (K,Ω) x∈Emk (K,Ω)

20
M3P11 Galois Theory 8 Separable extensions

8 Separable extensions
Recall that for k ⊂ K, we said a ∈ K is separable over k if the minimal polynomial f (X) ∈ k [X] of a is a
separable polynomial.
Theorem 8.1. k ⊂ K is separable if and only if [K : k]s = [K : k].
Proof.

Step 1. [K : k]s = [K : k], so k ⊂ K is separable. Recall [K : k]s ≤ [K : k]. Statement follows from two
tower laws for k ⊂ K1 ⊂ K2 ⊂ K, so [K2 : K1 ]s = [K2 : K1 ]. So if [K2 : K1 ]s = 1 then [K2 : K1 ] = 1
then K1 = K2 .
Step 2. Suppose that k ⊂ k (a) is separable then a is separable. Let f (X) ∈ k [X] be the minimal polynomial.
Suppose for a contradiction that it is not a separable polynomial. f is irreducible and f | Df , so
Df ≡ 0, so ch (k) = p and there exists h (X) ∈ k [X] irreducible such that f = h (X p ). Let b = ap
and consider k ⊂ k (b) ⊂ k (a). a is a root of X p − b ∈ k (b) [X]. Then

p deg (h) = [k (a) : k] = [k (a) : k (b)] [k (b) : k] = [k (a) : k (b)] deg (h) ,
p
so [k (a) : k (b)] = p. Thus X p − b = (X − a) is the minimal polynomial of a over k (b), so
[k (a) : k (b)]s = 1 contradicts step 1 and two tower laws.
Step 3. For k ⊂ k (a), k ⊂ k (a) is separable, so [k (a) : k]s = [k (a) : k]. This is obvious from step 2. Then
[k (a) : k] is the degree of the minimal polynomial and [k (a) : k]s is the number of roots of minimal
polynomial.

Step 4. End of proof, by a familiar method. Let us do the general case by induction on [K : k]. If k = K then
there is nothing to prove. Otherwise pick a ∈ K \ k. We know that both k ⊂ k (a) and k (a) ⊂ K
are separable. Then [K : k (a)] < [K : k] by tower law, hence by induction [K : k (a)]s = [K : k (a)].
We also know [k (a) : k]s = [k (a) : k]. Two tower laws imply that [K : k]s = [K : k].

Lecture 19
Thursday
Corollary 8.2. For all towers k ⊂ K ⊂ L, if k ⊂ K and K ⊂ L are separable then k ⊂ L is separable. 21/02/19
Corollary 8.3. k ⊂ K is separable if and only if for all a ∈ K, a is separable over k.
Proof. Suppose k ⊂ K is separable. Pick a ∈ K then k ⊂ k (a) is also separable. By step 2 last time, a is
separable. Conversely, suppose for all a ∈ K, a is separable over k. Pick a ∈ K \ k. I claim k ⊂ k (a) is
separable. Then

[k (a) : k]s = |{roots of minimal polynomial f }| = deg (f ) = [k (a) : k] ,

so k ⊂ k (a) is separable. We want to show that k (a) ⊂ K is separable, by the following lemma.
Lemma 8.4. Let k ⊂ L ⊂ K. For λ ∈ K, λ is separable over k implies that λ is separable over L.

Proof. The minimal polynomial over L divides the minimal polynomial over k.

21
M3P11 Galois Theory 9 Biquadratic polynomials

9 Biquadratic polynomials
Let
√ √
q 
p p
K⊂K a± b = L, c = a2 − b, β= b∈
/ K, α= a + β ∈ L, α0 = a − β ∈ L.

We know that ±α, ±α0 are the roots of

f (X) = X 4 − 2aX 2 + c. (8)

This time we are not assuming (8) is irreducible. Let



δ = α + α0 , δ 0 = α − α0 , γ = αα0 = c.

Then
δ + δ0 δ − δ0
γ 2 = c, δ 2 = 2 (a + γ) , δ 02 = 2 (a − γ) , δδ 0 = 2β, α= , α0 = ,
2 2
and ±δ, ±δ 0 are the roots of
g (Y ) = Y 4 − 4aY 2 + 4b.
L is the splitting field of g. Assume
1. ch (K) 6= 2, and
2. b is not a square in K, that is [K (β) : K] = 2.
Claim that the extension K ⊂ L is separable. It is the splitting field of f (X). I need to check gcd (f, Df ) = 1.

Df = 4X 3 − 4aX = 4X X 2 − a .



f, Df have no common roots, since X = 0 is not a root of f and X = ± a is not a root of f , since b 6= 0.
Theorem 9.1. Assume 1 and 2.
1. Suppose bc, c are not squares. Then

[L : K] = 8, G = D8 ,

and f (X) is irreducible.


2. Suppose bc is a square, so c is not a square. Then

[L : K] = 4, G = C4 ,

and f (X) is irreducible.


3. Suppose c is a square, so bc is not a square. Then
• either 2 (a + γ) , 2 (a − γ) both not squares in K, then

[L : K] = 4, G = C2 × C2 ,

and f (X) is irreducible.


• or one of 2 (a + γ) , 2 (a − γ) is a square in K, but not the other, then

[L : K] = [K (β) : K] = 2, G = C2 ,

and f (X) is reducible.

22
M3P11 Galois Theory 9 Biquadratic polynomials

√  Lecture 20
Lemma 9.2. Let B ∈ F and A ∈ F be not square in F . If B is square in F A then either B is square Friday
in F or AB is square in F . 22/02/19
 √ 2  √
Proof. Let B = x + y A = x2 + Ay 2 + 2xy A. Then
2
• either x = 0, so B = Ay 2 , so AB = (Ay) is square in F ,
• or y = 0, so B = x2 , so B = x2 is square in F .

Proof of Theorem 9.1.


1. Strategy is [K (α) : K (β)] = [K (α0 ) : K (β)] = 2 and K (α) 6= K (α0 ).

L
2 2

K (α) K (α0 )
.
2 2
K (β)
2

K
• Key idea is that suppose α ∈ K (β) = {x + yβ | x, y ∈ K}. There exist x, y ∈ K such that
2 2
α = x + yβ. Then (x + yβ) = a + β and (x − yβ) = a − β, so
2 2
K 3 x2 − y 2 b = ((x + yβ) (x − yβ)) = (a + β) (a − β) = a2 − b = c,
so c is a square in K. Similarly, α0 ∈ K (β), so α ∈ K (β), so c is a square in K. c is not a square
therefore α ∈/ K (β) and α0 ∈
/ K (β), that is [K (α) : K (β)] = [K (α0 ) : K (β)] = 2.

• Suppose for a contradiction α0 ∈ K (α), that is a − β is square in K (α) = K (β) a + β . Apply


Lemma 9.2 with


F = K (β) , A = a + β, B = a − β.
Then either B is square in F , a contradiction, or AB is square in F , that is (a + β) (a − β) =
a2 − b = c is a square in K (β). Apply Lemma 9.2 again with
F = K, A = b, B = c.
Then either c is square in K or bc is square in K, which are contradictions. Thus K (α) 6= K (α0 ).
|G| = 8. Let σ ∈ G. Then
• either σ (β) = β, so there are four possibilities σ (α) = ±α and σ (α0 ) = ±α0 ,
• or σ (β) = −β, so there are four possibilities σ (α) = ±α0 and σ (α0 ) = ±α, since σ y 2 − a − β =


y 2 − a + β.
Because |G| = 8 all these permutations are elements of G. Thus G = D8 is the group of symmetries of
the square
α0

−α xσ α lτ .

−α0

23
M3P11 Galois Theory 9 Biquadratic polynomials

The lattice of subgroups is

hei

hτ i σ2 τ σ2 hστ i σ3 τ
.

σ2 , τ hσi σ 2 , στ

G
The lattice of subfields is
L
2 2
2 2
2

K (α) K (α0 ) K (β, γ) K (δ) K (δ 0 )


2 2 2 .
2 2 2 2
K (β) K (βγ) K (γ)
2
2 2
K
Lecture 21
2. K (βγ) = K, so K (β) = K (γ). β ∈ / K. Suppose a + β is square in K (β). There exist x, y ∈ K such Tuesday
2 2
that a + β = (x + yβ) = x2 + y 2 b + 2xyβ, so (x − yβ) = a − β, then 26/02/19
2 2
K 3 x2 − by 2 = ((x + yβ) (x − yβ)) = (a + β) (a − β) = a2 − b = c,
so c is square in K, a contradiction.

L = K (α) = K (α0 ) = K (δ) = K (δ 0 )


2

K (β) = K (γ) = K (β, γ) .


2

K = K (βγ)

Claim that G = C4 . What’s different? αα0 = γ and βγ ∈ K. Let σ ∈ G. If σ (β) = β then σ (α) = ±α.
• σ (α) = α gives σ (α0 ) = α0 , and
• σ (α) = −α gives σ (α0 ) = −α0 .
If σ (β) = −β then σ (α) = ±α0 .
• σ (α) = α0 gives σ (α0 ) = −α, and
• σ (α) = −α0 gives σ (α0 ) = α.

α0

−α xσ α .

−α0
Thus G = C4 .

24
M3P11 Galois Theory 9 Biquadratic polynomials

p   
3. L = K 2 (a ± γ) is the splitting field of g (Y ) = Y 2 − 2a − 2γ Y 2 − 2a + 2γ .

L = K (δ, δ 0 )

K (β) K (δ) K (δ 0 ) .
≤2
2 ≤2
K

If [L : K] = 4 then G = C2 × C2 . Note that [L : K] cannot be 1. Can it be [L : K] = 2? At least one


of 2 (a + γ) and 2 (a − γ)
p  in K. Suppose 2 (a − γ) is not square in K. Can it be that
is not square
2 (a + γ) is square in K 2 (a − γ) = K (δ 0 )? By Lemma 9.2

• either 2 (a + γ) is square in K, which is possible,



• or 2 (a + γ) 2 (a − γ) = 4 a2 − c = 4b is square in K, which is impossible.
Conclusion is
• either [L : K] = 4, f (X) is irreducible, and G = C2 × C2 ,
• or one of 2 (a + γ) or 2 (a − γ) is square in K but not the other, [L : K] = 2, f (X) is not
irreducible, and G = C2 .

Example. All over Q.

• Let

q 
4
f (X) = X − 2, L=Q ± 2 .

Then [L : Q] = 8 and G = D8 .
• Let

q 
4 2
f (X) = X − 4X + 2, L=Q 2+ 2 .

Then [L : Q] = 4 and G = C4 .
• Let    √ 
2πi
f (X) = X 4 − X 2 + 1, L = Q e 12 = Q i, 3 .

Then [L : Q] = 4 and G = C2 × C2 .
• Let
√ √ √  √ √ 
q 
f (X) = X 4 − 10X 2 + 1, L=Q 5+2 6 =Q 2+ 3 =Q 2, 3 .

Then [L : Q] = 4 and G = C2 × C2 .

• Let
√ √ 
q 
f (X) = X − 6X + 1 = X − 2X − 1 X 2 + 2X − 1 ,
4 2 2
 
L=Q 3+2 2 =Q 2 .

Then [L : Q] = 2 and G = C2 .

25
M3P11 Galois Theory 10 Finite fields

10 Finite fields
Lecture 22
If F is finite, then it has ch (F ) = p for some prime p. Then Fp ⊂ F . Because F is finite, it is a finite Thursday
dimensional vector space over Fp . As a vector space F ∼
m
= (Fp ) where m = dimFp (F ) = [F : Fp ], so |F | is a 28/02/19
power of p.
Theorem 10.1. Fix a prime p > 0. Then for all m ∈ Z≥1 , there exists a unique, up to non-unique
isomorphism, finite field with q = pm elements. Notation is Fq . Moreover,

Z
G = Gal (Fq /Fp ) = .
mZ
Proof. Suppose |F | = q. Then F × = F \ {0} is a group with q − 1 elements. That is, if λ ∈ F \ {0} then
λq−1 = 1. Y
Fp [X] 3 X q−1 − 1 = (X − λ) ∈ Fq [X] .
λ∈F \{0}

q−1
Every such field is a splitting field of X − 1. Any two splitting fields are isomorphic. This does the
uniqueness part. As for the existence part, let F be a splitting field over Fp of f (X) = X q−1 − 1 ∈ Fp [X].
Let us prove that F has q elements. Fp is a perfect field, so for all λ ∈ Fp there exists µ ∈ Fp such that
µp = λ. In particular f (X) has q − 1 distinct roots in F . Let us call them λ1 , . . . , λq−1 . Claim that

F 0 = {0, λ1 , . . . , λq−1 }

is a field, then clearly F 0 = F . We need to show that


• F is closed under addition,

• F is closed under multiplication, and


• things in F \ {0} have inverses.
F is closed under multiplication and inverses since for all n, {λ | λn = 1} is a group. F is closed under
q
addition since for all a, b ∈ F , (a + b) = aq + bq , for example
     
p p p p−1 p p
(a + b) = a + a b + ··· + abp−1 + bp , ∀1 ≤ k ≤ p − 1, p .
1 p−1 k

Claim that the function


F : Fq −→ Fq
a 7−→ ap
is a field automorphism, that is F ∈ G, of order exactly m. It is a field automorphism, since

p
a  a p ap F (a)
F (ab) = (ab) = ap bp = F (a) F (b) , F = = p
= ,
b b b F (b)
p
F (a + b) = (a + b) = ap + bp = F (a) + F (b) , F (1) = 1, F (0) = 0.
Certainly
F m = F ◦ · · · ◦ F = id,
k k
since for all λ ∈ Fq , λq = λ. Otherwise if order is k < m then for all λ ∈ Fq , λp = λ, so X p − X has q > pk
roots, a contradiction.

26
M3P11 Galois Theory 11 Symmetric polynomials

11 Symmetric polynomials
Lecture 23
Consider Friday
f (X) = (X − x1 ) . . . (X − xn ) = X n − σ1 X n−1 + · · · ± σn ∈ K (x1 , . . . , xn ) [X] , 01/03/19
where X X
σ1 = σ1 (x1 , . . . , xn ) = xi , σ2 = σ2 (x1 , . . . , xn ) = xi xj , ....
i≤i≤n i≤i≤j≤n

Here σ1 ∈ K [x1 , . . . , xn ] are the elementary symmetric polynomials. Let


Y Y 2
δ= (xi − xj ) , ∆ = δ2 = (xi − xj ) .
roots of f roots of f

Definition 11.1. σ ∈ K [x1 , . . . , xn ] is symmetric if and only if for all g ∈ Sn



σ xg(1) , . . . , xg(n) = σ (x1 , . . . , xn ) .

Example. Consider a degree two polynomial

(X − x1 ) (X − x2 ) = X 2 − σ1 X + σ2 .

• δ = x1 − x2 is not symmetric, for g = 1 2 ,

δ xg(1) , xg(2) = δ (x2 , x1 ) = x2 − x1 = −δ (x1 , x2 ) .

• But
2 2
∆ = δ 2 = (x1 − x2 ) = (x1 + x2 ) − 4x1 x2 = σ12 − 4σ2
is symmetric.
Example. Let
f (X) = X 3 − σ1 X 2 + σ2 X − σ3 .
The plan is to write an invariant telling us when a cubic has repeated roots.

δ = (x1 − x2 ) (x1 − x3 ) (x2 − x3 )


∼ C2 . Can I write δ 2 = ∆ as a

is not symmetric under S3 , but it is invariant under A3 = 1 2 3 =
polynomial in
σ1 = x1 + x2 + x3 , σ2 = x1 x2 + x1 x3 + x2 x3 , σ3 = x1 x2 x3 ?
Yes,
∆ = σ12 σ22 − 4σ13 σ3 − 4σ23 + 18σ1 σ2 σ3 − 27σ32 .
For X 3 + 3pX + 2q,
∆ = −22 33 p3 + q 2 .


The exact expression is totally relevant.


Can we find a formula for discriminant of a degree n polynomial? It is a general fact that all symmetric
polynomials are polynomials in the elementary symmetric polynomials, so
Sn
K [x1 , . . . , xn ] = K [σ1 , . . . , σn ] ⊂ K (σ1 , . . . , σn ) .

27
M3P11 Galois Theory 11 Symmetric polynomials

Theorem 11.2. Consider a degree n separable polynomial

f (X) = X n + a1 X n−1 + · · · + an ∈ k [X] .

Let k ⊂ L be the splitting field of f . Then G ⊂ An if and only if ∆ is a square in k.

By Galois theory ∆ ∈ k, because ∆ is symmetric, that is Sn -invariant, and hence G-invariant.


Proof. G ⊂ An if and only if δ is G-invariant, if and only if δ ∈ k.
Remark.
• We know K ⊂ L is a normal and separable splitting field of f ∈ K [X] implies that G ⊂ Sn .

• If in addition f ∈ k [X] is irreducible then G is transitive, that is for all λ and µ roots of f there exists
σ ∈ G such that σ (λ) = µ.
Theorem 11.3. Consider an irreducible cubic polynomial

X 3 − σ1 X 2 + σ2 X − σ3 ,

and k ⊂ L be the splitting field then G = S3 iff ∆ is not square in k, and G = A3 = C3 iff ∆ is square in k.
Example. For K = Q,
f (X) ∆ G
X3 − X − 1 −23 S3
X 3 − 2X − 1 5 S3
X 3 − 3X − 1 81 A3 .
X 3 − 4X − 1 229 S3
X 3 − 5X − 1 473 S3
X 3 − 6X − 1 837 S3

28
M3P11 Galois Theory 12 Irreducible polynomials

12 Irreducible polynomials
Lecture 24
Proposition 12.1. Suppose Tuesday
f (X) = a0 + · · · + ad X d ∈ Z [X] 05/03/19
has a root p/q ∈ Q with gcd (p, q) = 1, then p | a0 and q | ad .
Example.
• X 5 − 5 has no rational roots. Note that this does not show X 5 − 5 is irreducible over Q.
• X 3 − 2 is irreducible over Q.

Proof. Let
   d
p p
f = a0 + · · · + ad = 0.
q q
Multiplying by q d ,
a0 q d + · · · + ad pd = 0.
Then
q | a0 q d + · · · + ad−1 qpd−1 ,

so q | ad pd . Note that if c | ab and gcd (c, a) = 1 then c | b. Then gcd q, pd = 1, so q | ad . Similarly
p | a0 .
Remark. If K is a field then K [X] is a Euclidean domain, in particular unique factorisation holds, in
particular K [X] is an integral domain, that is for all a, b ∈ K [X] if ab = 0, then either a = 0 or b = 0.

Suppose that you want to show n ∈ Z is prime. Try to factor by all primes p < n.

Example. 97 is prime because 2 - 97, 3 - 97, 5 - 97, 7 - 97.


A question is can such a method work with polynomials f (X) ∈ Q [X]? Yes but we will not go there because
it is not very practical. This method is ok in Fp [X], where p is prime, and this leads to a useful strategy.
Example. Is X 5 − 5 ∈ Q [X] irreducible?

• Is it irreducible in F2 [X]? X 5 − 5 ≡ X 5 + 1 mod 2 and X = 1 is a root, so not irreducible.


• Is it irreducible in F3 [X]? X 5 − 5 ≡ X 5 + 1 mod 3 and X = −1 is a root, so not irreducible.
• It is not irreducible in F5 [X] since X 5 − 5 ≡ X 5 mod 5.

• Is it irreducible in F7 [X]? (Exercise)

29
M3P11 Galois Theory 12 Irreducible polynomials

Lemma 12.2 (Gauss’ lemma). Suppose

f (X) = a0 + · · · + ad X d ∈ Z [X] , gcd (a0 , . . . , ad ) = 1

factorises non-trivially in Q [X]. Then it factors non-trivially in Z [X].

Corollary 12.3. If f (X) is prime in Fp [X], for some p, then it is prime in Q [X].
Proof. Otherwise f (X) factors in Fp [X].
Proof of Lemma 12.2. Suppose f (X) = g (X) h (X) in Q [X] for g (X) , h (X) ∈ Q [X]. There is a c ∈ Z
such that

cf (X) = g 0 (X) h0 (X) , g 0 (X) , h0 (X) ∈ Z [X] , g 0 = λg, h0 = µh, λ, µ ∈ Q. (9)

There is a smallest such c. I claim c = 1. Otherwise there exists p prime such that p | c, so (9) is

0 = g 0 (X) h0 (X) ∈ Fp [X] .

Either p | g 0 (X), that is p divides all coefficients of g 0 , or p | h0 (X), a contradiction.


Corollary 12.4 (Eisenstein).
f (X) = a0 + · · · + ad X d ∈ Z [X]
is irreducible in Q [X] if there exists p prime such that p - ad but p | ai for i < d and p2 - a0 .
Proof. Work in Fp [X]. Then f (X) ≡ ad X d mod p. If f (X) = h (X) g (X) in Z [X], then

h (X) ≡ bk X k mod p, g (X) ≡ cd−k X d−k mod p,

and that means that


h (X) = b0 + · · · + bk X k , p | bi , i < k,
and
g (X) = c0 + · · · + cd−k X d−k , p | ci , i < d − k.
2
Thus p | a0 = b0 c0 , a contradiction.
Example. X 5 − 5 is irreducible by Eisenstein and p = 5.
Lecture 25
Lecture 25 is a problem class. Thursday
Lecture 26 is a problem class. 07/03/19
Lecture 26
Friday
08/03/19

30
M3P11 Galois Theory 13 Reduction modulo prime

13 Reduction modulo prime


Lecture 27
Theorem 13.1. Let f (X) ∈ Z [X] be monic of degree n, Q ⊂ K be the splitting field of f , and G = Tuesday
Gal (K/Q) ⊂ Sn . For p prime, denote by f as f viewed in Fp [X]. If there exists p such that f ∈ Fp [X] has 12/03/19
n distinct roots in a splitting field and
k
Y
f= fi (X) ∈ Fp [X] ,
i=1

with fi ∈ Fp [X] irreducible of degree ni , then there exists σ ∈ G ⊂ Sn of cycle decomposition type

(n1 ) . . . (nk ) .

The plan is to understand the statement and prove it, following Jacobson Basic Algebra I page 301. I want
to use Theorem 13.1 to write down an explicit degree five polynomial f ∈ Z [X] such that G = S5 .
Proposition 13.2. Suppose that r is prime and let G ⊂ Sr be a subgroup. If G contains an r-cycle and
one transposition, then G = Sr .

Proof. Say σ = (1 2 3 4 5) ∈ G and 1 2 ∈ G, by relabelling. Then

σ −i 1 2 σi = 1 − i
 
2−i

implies that    
1 2 , 2 3 , 3 4 , 4 5 ∈ G.
A general fact is that for all n,  
1 2 , ..., n−1 n
generate Sn , since a < b implies that
   
a b = a a+1 a+1 b a a+1 .

The following is the plan.

• Find irreducible monic degree five φ (X) ∈ F2 [X].


• Find irreducible monic degree two ψ (X) ∈ F3 [X].
• Find f ∈ Z [X] such that f ≡ φ in F2 [X] and f ≡ X (X − 1) (X + 1) ψ in F3 [X].
Theorem 13.1 implies that G = S5 .

• The irreducible degree two polynomial in F2 [X] is X 2 + X + 1.


• The irreducible degree two polynomial in F3 [X] are X 2 + 1, and two more.
Claim that
f ≡ φ (X) = X 5 + X 3 + 1 ∈ F2 [X]
is irreducible. Need to check that φ has no root in F2 and φ is not divisible by X 2 + X + 1. Then

f ≡ X (X − 1) (X + 1) X 2 + 1 = X 5 − X ∈ F3 [X] .


Thus
f (X) = X 5 + 3X 3 + 2X + 3.

31
M3P11 Galois Theory 13 Reduction modulo prime

Lecture 28
Definition 13.3. The character of a monoid to K is χ : P → K such that Thursday
14/03/19
• χ (0) = 1, and
• for all p1 , p2 ∈ P , χ (p1 + p2 ) = χ (p1 ) χ (p2 ).
Remark. If K is a field and A is a set then {f : A → K} is a K-vector space.
Theorem 13.4 (Linear independence of characters, Dedekind independence theorem). Let K be a field and
P be a monoid, such as P = N. Any set of distinct non-zero characters

χ1 : P → K, ..., χn : P → K, ...

is linearly independent in the vector space {f : P → K}.


Proof. Assume for a contradiction that

λ1 χ1 + · · · + λn χn = 0. (10)

We may assume (10) to be the shortest. We may assume for all i, λi 6= 0. n ≥ 2, since all are not zero.
There exists p such that χ1 (p) 6= χ2 (p), so

λ1 χ1 (p) χ1 + · · · + λn χn (p) χn = 0. (11)

Because (10) is the shortest then (10) and (11) are multiples of each other, so χ1 (p) = χ2 (p), a contradiction.

Theorem 13.5. Let f (X) ∈ Z [X] be degree n monic, Q ⊂ K be the splitting field of f , G = Gal (K/Q) ⊂
Sn , and λ1 , . . . , λn ∈ K be the roots of f (X). Let p be a prime. Denote by f image of f mod p. Assume f
is separable. Let Fp ⊂ F be a splitting field for f , so f has n distinct roots in F . Let R ⊂ K be the subring
generated by the roots of f , so R = Z [λ1 , . . . , λn ]. Then
1. there exists a ring homomorphism ψ : R → F ,
2. if ψ 0 : R → F is a ring homomorphism then ψ 0 induces a bijection

φ0 : {roots of f (X) in R} → roots of f (X) in F ,




3. ψ 0 : R → F is a ring homomorphism if and only if there exists σ ∈ G such that ψ 0 = ψ ◦ σ.


Lecture 29
Lecture 29 is a class test. Friday
15/03/19
Proof.
Lecture 30
Step 1. R is a finitely generated free Z-module, since R is generated as a Z-module by λe11 , . . . , λenn where Tuesday
0 ≤ ei < n. 19/03/19
Step 2. Let u1 , . . . , ud be a basis of R as Z-module. This is a basis of K as a Q-vector space, so d = [K : Q].
u1 , . . . , ud are clearly linearly dependent over Q. Next let Q ⊂ QR ⊂ K. Then QR is a subring
containing Q, so QR is a field. (Exercise: if K ⊂ L is finite and K ⊂ R ⊂ L then R is a ring implies
that R is a field) QR contains all roots of f , so QR = K, that is u1 , . . . , ud generate K over Q.

32
M3P11 Galois Theory 13 Reduction modulo prime

Step 3. Proof of 1. Let m ⊃ hpi be a maximal ideal in R then Fp ⊂ R/m is a finite field. π : R → R/m gives
n
Y n
Y
f (X) = (X − λi ) 7→ f (X) = (X − π (λi )) ,
i=1 i=1

that is f (X) splits in R/m [X]. R is generated by λi implies that R/m is generated by π (λi ), so
R/m is a splitting field for f ∈ Fp [X], so R/m ∼
= F . Thus

R
π ψ
.
R
∼ F
m

Step 4. Proof of 2. Easy. ψ 0 : R → F gives


n
Y n
Y
f (X) = (X − λi ) 7→ f (X) = (X − π (λi )) ,
i=1 i=1

so {λi } 7→ {π (λi )}.

Step 5. Proof of 3. Converse is obvious. Let σ ∈ G and G = {σ1 , . . . , σN } for rkZ (R) = N = [K : Q].
Consider ψi = ψ ◦ σi : P → F where P = (R \ {0} , ×) is a semigroup. Suppose ψN +1 : P → F is
another character. If for all i, ψN +1 6= ψi , we will derive a contradiction. Let r1 , . . . , rN be a basis
of R as a Z-module. Solve for xi ∈ F , for i = 1, . . . , N , in
(N +1 )
X
xi ψi (rj ) = 0 1 ≤ j ≤ N ,
i=1

which has N equations in (N + 1) variables in F . Since rj is a Z-basis this implies


N
X +1
xi ψj = 0,
i=1

and this contradicts Dedekind.

Proof of Theorem 13.1. Let R and ψ : R → F be as above. Consider F r ∈ Gal (F/Fp ) then ψ 0 = F r ◦ ψ :
R → F is a ring homomorphism. By Theorem 13.5.3 there exists σ ∈ G such that F r ◦ ψ = ψ ◦ σ. Thus

Fr
σ

ψ 
{roots of f in R} roots of f in F .

33

You might also like