Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 1

Search Wikipedia Search Create account Log in

Belief 75 languages

Contents hide Article Talk Read Edit View history Tools

(Top) From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Conceptions
This article is about the general concept. For other uses, see Belief (disambiguation).
Types
A belief is a subjective attitude that a proposition is true or a state of affairs is the case. A subjective
Part of a series on
Contents attitude is a mental state of having some stance, take, or opinion about something.[1] In epistemology,
Epistemology
Epistemology philosophers use the term "belief" to refer to attitudes about the world which can be either true or false.[2]
To believe something is to take it to be true; for instance, to believe that snow is white is comparable to Outline · Category · Index
Religion
accepting the truth of the proposition "snow is white". However, holding a belief does not require active [show]
Schools
Psychology introspection. For example, few individuals carefully consider whether or not the sun will rise tomorrow,
[show]
See also simply assuming that it will. Moreover, beliefs need not be occurrent (e.g. a person actively thinking "snow Concepts
is white"), but can instead be dispositional (e.g. a person who if asked about the color of snow would assert [show]
References Domains
"snow is white").[2]
[show]
Further reading Epistemologists
There are various ways that contemporary philosophers have tried to describe beliefs, including as [show]
External links Related fields
representations of ways that the world could be (Jerry Fodor), as dispositions to act as if certain things are
· ·
true (Roderick Chisholm), as interpretive schemes for making sense of someone's actions (Daniel Dennett
and Donald Davidson), or as mental states that fill a particular function (Hilary Putnam).[2] Some have also
attempted to offer significant revisions to our notion of belief, including eliminativists about belief who argue that there is no phenomenon in the natural
world which corresponds to our folk psychological concept of belief (Paul Churchland) and formal epistemologists who aim to replace our bivalent notion
of belief ("either we have a belief or we don't have a belief") with the more permissive, probabilistic notion of credence ("there is an entire spectrum of
degrees of belief, not a simple dichotomy between belief and non-belief").[2][3]

Beliefs are the subject of various important philosophical debates. Notable examples include: "What is the rational way to revise one's beliefs when
presented with various sorts of evidence?", "Is the content of our beliefs entirely determined by our mental states, or do the relevant facts have any
bearing on our beliefs (e.g. if I believe that I'm holding a glass of water, is the non-mental fact that water is H2O part of the content of that belief)?", "How
fine-grained or coarse-grained are our beliefs?", and "Must it be possible for a belief to be expressible in language, or are there non-linguistic beliefs?"[2]

Conceptions [ edit ]

Various conceptions of the essential features of beliefs have been proposed, but there is no consensus as to which is the right one. Representationalism
is the traditionally dominant position. Its most popular version maintains that attitudes toward representations, which are typically associated with
propositions, are mental attitudes that constitute beliefs.These attitudes are part of the internal constitution of the mind holding the attitude. This view
contrasts with functionalism, which defines beliefs not in terms of the internal constitution of the mind but in terms of the function or the causal role played
by beliefs. According to dispositionalism, beliefs are identified with dispositions to behave in certain ways. This view can be seen as a form of
functionalism, defining beliefs in terms of the behavior they tend to cause. Interpretationism constitutes another conception, which has gained popularity
in contemporary philosophy. It holds that the beliefs of an entity are in some sense dependent on or relative to someone's interpretation of this entity.
Representationalism tends to be associated with a mind-body-dualism. Naturalist considerations against this dualism are among the motivations for
choosing one of the alternative conceptions.[4]

Representationalism [ edit ]

Representationalism characterizes beliefs in terms of mental representations. Representations are usually defined as objects with semantic properties—
like having a content, referring to something, or being true or false.[4][5] Beliefs form a special class of mental representations since they do not involve
sensory qualities in order to represent something, unlike perceptions or episodic memories.[6] Because of this, it seems natural to construe beliefs as
attitudes towards propositions, which also constitute non-sensory representations, i.e. as propositional attitudes. As mental attitudes, beliefs are
characterized by both their content and their mode.[6] The content of an attitude is what this attitude is directed at: its object. Propositional attitudes are
directed at propositions.[7][8][5] Beliefs are usually distinguished from other propositional attitudes, like desires, by their mode or the way in which they are
directed at propositions. The mode of beliefs has a mind-to-world direction of fit: beliefs try to represent the world as it is; they do not, unlike desires,
involve an intention to change it.[4][6] For example, if Rahul believes that it will be sunny today, then he has a mental attitude towards the proposition "It
will be sunny today" which affirms that this proposition is true. This is different from Sofía's desire that it will be sunny today, despite the fact that both
Rahul and Sofía have attitudes toward the same proposition. The mind-to-world direction of fit of beliefs is sometimes expressed by saying that beliefs
aim at truth.[9] This aim is also reflected in the tendency to revise one's belief upon receiving new evidence that an existing belief is false.[4] Upon hearing
a forecast of bad weather, Rahul is likely to change his mental attitude but Sofía is not.

There are different ways of conceiving how mental representations are realized in the mind. One form of this is the language of thought hypothesis,
which claims that mental representations have a language-like structure, sometimes referred to as "mentalese".[10][11] Just like regular language, this
involves simple elements that are combined in various ways according to syntactic rules to form more complex elements that act as bearers of
meaning.[4][11] On this conception, holding a belief would involve storing such a complex element in one's mind. Different beliefs are separated from each
other in that they correspond to different elements stored in the mind. A more holistic alternative to the "language of thought hypothesis" is the map-
conception, which uses an analogy of maps to elucidate the nature of beliefs.[4][11] According to this view, the belief-system of a mind should be
conceived of not as a set of many individual sentences but as a map encoding the information contained in these sentences.[4][11] For example, the fact
that Brussels is halfway between Paris and Amsterdam can be expressed both linguistically as a sentence and in a map through its internal geometrical
relations.

Functionalism [ edit ]

Functionalism contrasts with representationalism in that it defines beliefs not in terms of the internal constitution of the mind but in terms of the function or
the causal role played by them.[12][13] This view is often combined with the idea that the same belief can be realized in various ways and that it does not
matter how it is realized as long as it plays the causal role characteristic to it.[4][14] As an analogy, a hard drive is defined in a functionalist manner: it
performs the function of storing and retrieving digital data. This function can be realized in many different ways: being made of plastic or steel, or using
magnetism or laser.[4] Functionalists hold that something similar is true for beliefs (or mental states in general).[12][13] Among the roles relevant for beliefs
is their relation to perceptions and to actions: perceptions usually cause beliefs and beliefs cause actions.[4] For example, seeing that a traffic light has
switched to red is usually associated with a belief that the light is red, which in turn causes the driver to bring the car to a halt. Functionalists use such
characteristics to define beliefs: whatever is caused by perceptions in a certain way and also causes behavior in a certain way is called a belief. This is
not just true for humans but may include animals, hypothetical aliens or even computers.[4][12] From this perspective, it would make sense to ascribe the
belief that a traffic light is red to a self-driving car behaving just like a human driver.

Dispositionalism is sometimes seen as a specific form of functionalism.[4] It defines beliefs only concerning their role as causes of behavior or as
dispositions to behave in a certain way.[15][16] For example, a belief that there is a pie in the pantry is associated with the disposition to affirm this when
asked and to go to the pantry when hungry.[6] While it is uncontroversial that beliefs shape our behavior, the thesis that beliefs can be defined exclusively
through their role in producing behavior has been contested.[4][15] The problem arises because the mechanisms shaping our behavior seem to be too
complex to single out the general contribution of one particular belief for any possible situation.[6] For example, one may decide not to affirm that there is
a pie in the pantry when asked, because one wants to keep it secret. Or one might not eat the pie despite being hungry, because one also believes that it
is poisoned.[6] Due to this complexity, we are unable to define even a belief as simple as this one in terms of the behavioral dispositions for which it could
be responsible.[4]

Interpretationism [ edit ]

According to interpretationism, the beliefs of an entity are in some sense dependent on, or relative to, someone's interpretation of this entity.[4][17] Daniel
Dennett is an important defender of such a position. He holds that we ascribe beliefs to entities in order to predict how they will behave. Entities with
simple behavioral patterns can be described using physical laws or in terms of their function. Dennett refers to these forms of explanation as the
"physical stance" and the "design stance". These stances are contrasted with the intentional stance, which is applied to entities with a more complex
behavior by ascribing beliefs and desires to these entities.[18][19] For example, we can predict that a chess player will move her queen to f7 if we ascribe
to her the desire to win the game and the belief that this move will achieve that. The same procedure can also be applied to predicting how a chess
computer will behave. The entity has the belief in question if this belief can be used to predict its behavior.[4] Having a belief is relative to an interpretation
since there may be different equally good ways of ascribing beliefs to predict behavior.[4] So there may be another interpretation that predicts the move of
the queen to f7 that does not involve the belief that this move will win the game. Another version of interpretationism is due to Donald Davidson,[17] who
uses the thought experiment of radical interpretation, in which the goal is to make sense of the behavior and language of another person from scratch
without any knowledge of this person's language.[4] This process involves ascribing beliefs and desires to the speaker. The speaker really has these
beliefs if this project can be successful in principle.[4]

Interpretationism can be combined with eliminativism and instrumentalism about beliefs. Eliminativists hold that, strictly speaking, there are no beliefs.
Instrumentalists agree with eliminativists but add that belief-ascriptions are useful nonetheless.[4] This usefulness can be explained in terms of
interpretationism: belief-ascriptions help us in predicting how entities will behave. It has been argued that interpretationism can also be understood in a
more realistic sense: that entities really have the beliefs ascribed to them and that these beliefs participate in the causal network.[20] But, for this to be
possible, it may be necessary to define interpretationism as a methodology and not as an ontological outlook on beliefs.[17]

Origins [ edit ]

Biologist Lewis Wolpert discusses the importance of causal beliefs and associates the making and use of tools with the origin of human beliefs.[21]

Historical [ edit ]

In the context of Ancient Greek thought, three related concepts were identified regarding the concept of belief: pistis, doxa, and dogma. Simplified, pistis
refers to "trust" and "confidence," doxa refers to "opinion" and "acceptance," and dogma refers to the positions of a philosopher or of a philosophical
school such as Stoicism.

Types [ edit ]

Beliefs can be categorized into various types depending on their ontological status, their degree, their object or their semantic properties.

Occurrent and dispositional [ edit ]

Having an occurrent belief that the Grand Canyon is in Arizona involves entertaining the representation associated with this belief—for example, by
actively thinking about it. But the great majority of our beliefs are not active most of the time: they are merely dispositional.[4] They usually become
activated or occurrent when needed or relevant in some way and then fall back into their dispositional state afterward.[4] For example, the belief that 57 is
greater than 14 was probably dispositional to the reader before reading this sentence, has become occurrent while reading it and may soon become
dispositional again as the mind focuses elsewhere. The distinction between occurrent and dispositional beliefs is sometimes identified with the distinction
between conscious and unconscious beliefs.[22][23] But it has been argued that, despite overlapping, the two distinctions do not match. The reason for
this is that beliefs can shape one's behavior and be involved in one's reasoning even if the subject is not conscious of them. Such beliefs are cases of
unconscious occurrent mental states.[22] On this view, being occurrent corresponds to being active, either consciously or unconsciously.[23]

A dispositional belief is not the same as a disposition to believe.[16] We have various dispositions to believe given the right perceptions; for example, to
believe that it is raining given a perception of rain. Without this perception, there is still a disposition to believe but no actual dispositional belief.[16] On a
dispositionalist conception of belief, there are no occurrent beliefs, since all beliefs are defined in terms of dispositions.[4]

Full and partial [ edit ]

An important dispute in formal epistemology concerns the question of whether beliefs should be conceptualized as full beliefs or as partial beliefs.[24] Full
beliefs are all-or-nothing attitudes: either one has a belief in a proposition or one does not. This conception is sufficient to understand many belief
ascriptions found in everyday language: for example, Pedro's belief that the Earth is bigger than the Moon. But some cases involving comparisons
between beliefs are not easily captured through full beliefs alone: for example, that Pedro's belief that the Earth is bigger than the Moon is more certain
than his belief that the Earth is bigger than Venus. Such cases are most naturally analyzed in terms of partial beliefs involving degrees of belief, so-called
credences.[24][25] The higher the degree of a belief, the more certain the believer is that the believed proposition is true.[26] This is usually formalized by
numbers between 0 and 1: a degree of 1 represents an absolutely certain belief, a belief of 0 corresponds to an absolutely certain disbelief and all the
numbers in between correspond to intermediate degrees of certainty. In the Bayesian approach, these degrees are interpreted as subjective
probabilities:[27][28] e.g. a belief of degree 0.9 that it will rain tomorrow means that the agent thinks that the probability of rain tomorrow is 90%.
Bayesianism uses this relation between beliefs and probability to define the norms of rationality in terms of the laws of probability.[26] This includes both
synchronic laws about what one should believe at any moment and diachronic laws about how one should revise one's beliefs upon receiving new
evidence.[25][26]

The central question in the dispute between full and partial beliefs is whether these two types are really distinct types or whether one type can be
explained in terms of the other.[24] One answer to this question is called the Lockean thesis. It states that partial beliefs are basic and that full beliefs are
to be conceived as partial beliefs above a certain threshold: for example, that every belief above 0.9 is a full belief.[24][29][30] Defenders of a primitive
notion of full belief, on the other hand, have tried to explain partial beliefs as full beliefs about probabilities.[24] On this view, having a partial belief of
degree 0.9 that it will rain tomorrow is the same as having a full belief that the probability of rain tomorrow is 90%. Another approach circumvents the
notion of probability altogether and replaces degrees of belief with degrees of disposition to revise one's full belief.[24] From this perspective, both a belief
of degree 0.6 and a belief of degree 0.9 may be seen as full beliefs. The difference between them is that the former belief can readily be changed upon
receiving new evidence while the latter is more stable.[24]

Belief-in and belief-that [ edit ]

Traditionally, philosophers have mainly focused in their inquiries concerning belief on the notion of belief-that.[31] Belief-that can be characterized as a
propositional attitude to a claim which is either true or false. Belief-in, on the other hand, is more closely related to notions like trust or faith in that it refers
usually to an attitude to persons.[31] Belief-in plays a central role in many religious traditions in which belief in God is one of the central virtues of their
followers.[32] The difference between belief-in and belief-that is sometimes blurry since various expressions using the term "belief in" seem to be
translatable into corresponding expressions using the term "belief that" instead.[33] For example, a belief in fairies may be said to be a belief that fairies
exist.[32] In this sense, belief-in is often used when the entity is not real, or its existence is in doubt. Typical examples would include: "he believes in
witches and ghosts" or "many children believe in Santa Claus" or "I believe in a deity".[34] Not all usages of belief-in concern the existence of something:
some are commendatory in that they express a positive attitude towards their object.[34][31] It has been suggested that these cases can also be
accounted for in terms of belief-that. For example, a belief in marriage could be translated as a belief that marriage is good.[32] Belief-in is used in a
similar sense when expressing self-confidence or faith in one's self or one's abilities.

Defenders of a reductive account of belief-in have used this line of thought to argue that belief in God can be analyzed in a similar way: e.g. that it
amounts to a belief that God exists with his characteristic attributes, like omniscience and omnipotence.[32] Opponents of this account often concede that
belief-in may entail various forms of belief-that, but that there are additional aspects to belief-in that are not reducible to belief-that.[33] For example, a
belief in an ideal may involve the belief that this ideal is something good, but it additionally involves a positive evaluative attitude toward this ideal that
goes beyond a mere propositional attitude.[32] Applied to the belief in God, opponents of the reductive approach may hold that a belief that God exists
may be a necessary pre-condition for belief in God, but that it is not sufficient.[32][33]

De dicto and de re [ edit ]

See also: De dicto and de re

The difference between de dicto and de re beliefs or the corresponding ascriptions concerns the contributions singular terms like names and other
referential devices make to the semantic properties of the belief or its ascription.[4][35] In regular contexts, the truth-value of a sentence does not change
upon substitution of co-referring terms.[36] For example, since the names "Superman" and "Clark Kent" refer to the same person, we can replace one
with the other in the sentence "Superman is strong" without changing its truth-value; this issue is more complicated in case of belief ascriptions.[36] For
example, Lois believes that Superman is strong but she does not believe that Clark Kent is strong.[4] This difficulty arises due to the fact that she does
not know that the two names refer to the same entity. Beliefs or belief ascriptions for which this substitution does not generally work are de dicto,
otherwise, they are de re.[4][36][35] In a de re sense, Lois does believe that Clark Kent is strong, while in a de dicto sense she does not. The contexts
corresponding to de dicto ascriptions are known as referentially opaque contexts while de re ascriptions are referentially transparent.[4][36]

Collective belief [ edit ]

A collective belief is referred to when people speak of what "we" believe when this is not simply elliptical for what "we all" believe.[37] Sociologist Émile
Durkheim wrote of collective beliefs and proposed that they, like all "social facts", "inhered in" social groups as opposed to individual persons. Jonathan
Dancy states that "Durkheim's discussion of collective belief, though suggestive, is relatively obscure".[38] Margaret Gilbert has offered a related account
in terms of the joint commitment of a number of persons as a body to accept a certain belief. According to this account, individuals who together
collectively believe something need not personally believe it individually. Gilbert's work on the topic has stimulated a developing literature among
philosophers.[39] One question that has arisen is whether and how philosophical accounts of belief in general need to be sensitive to the possibility of
collective belief.

Collective belief can play a role in social control[40] and serve as a touchstone for identifying and combatting/purging heresies,[41] deviancy[42] or political
deviationism.

Contents [ edit ]

As mental representations, beliefs have contents, which is what the belief is about or what it represents. Within philosophy, there are various disputes
about how the contents of beliefs are to be understood. Holists and molecularists hold that the content of one particular belief depends on or is
determined by other beliefs belonging to the same subject, which is denied by atomists. The question of dependence or determination also plays a
central role in the internalism-externalism- debate. Internalism states that the contents of someone's beliefs depend only on what is internal to that
person and are determined entirely by things going on inside this person's head. Externalism, on the other hand, holds that the relations to one's
environment also have a role to play in this.

Atomism, molecularism and holism [ edit ]

The disagreement between atomism, molecularism and holism concerns the question of how the content of one belief depends on the contents of other
beliefs held by the same subject.[43] Atomists deny such dependence relations, molecularists restrict them to only a few closely related beliefs while
holists hold that they may obtain between any two beliefs, however unrelated they seem.[4][5][43] For example, assume that Mei and Benjamin both affirm
that Jupiter is a planet. The most straightforward explanation, given by the atomists, would be that they have the same belief, i.e. that they hold the same
content to be true. But now assume that Mei also believes that Pluto is a planet, which is denied by Benjamin. This indicates that they have different
concepts of planet, which would mean that they were affirming different contents when they both agreed that Jupiter is a planet. This reasoning leads to
molecularism or holism because the content of the Jupiter-belief depends on the Pluto-belief in this example.[4][43]

An important motivation for this position comes from W. V. Quine's confirmational holism, which holds that, because of this interconnectedness, we
cannot confirm or disconfirm individual hypotheses, that confirmation happens on the level of the theory as a whole.[43][44] Another motivation is due to
considerations of the nature of learning: it is often not possible to understand one concept, like force in Newtonian physics, without understanding other
concepts, like mass or kinetic energy.[43] One problem for holism is that genuine disagreements seem to be impossible or very rare: disputants would
usually talk past each other since they never share exactly the same web of beliefs needed to determine the content of the source of the
disagreement.[4][43]

Internalism and externalism [ edit ]

Internalism and externalism disagree about whether the contents of our beliefs are determined only by what's happening in our head or also by other
factors.[4][5][45][46] Internalists deny such a dependence on external factors. They hold that a person and a molecule-by-molecule copy would have
exactly the same beliefs. Hilary Putnam objects to this position by way of his twin Earth thought experiment. He imagines a twin Earth in another part of
the universe that is exactly like ours, except that their water has a different chemical composition despite behaving just like ours.[4][45][46] According to
Putnam, the reader's thought that water is wet is about our water while the reader's twin's thought on twin Earth that water is wet is about their water.
This is the case despite the fact that the two readers have the same molecular composition. So it seems necessary to include external factors in order to
explain the difference. One problem with this position is that this difference in content does not bring any causal difference with it: the two readers act in
exactly the same way. This casts doubt on the thesis that there is any genuine difference in need of explanation between the contents of the two
beliefs.[4][45][46]

Epistemology [ edit ]

Main article: Epistemology

Epistemology is concerned with delineating the boundary between justified belief and opinion,[47] and involved
generally with a theoretical philosophical study of knowledge. The primary problem in epistemology is to
understand what is needed to have knowledge. In a notion derived from Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, where
the epistemology of Socrates most clearly departs from that of the sophists, who appear to have defined
knowledge as "justified true belief". The tendency to base knowledge (episteme) on common opinion (doxa)
Socrates dismisses, results from failing to distinguish a dispositive belief (doxa) from knowledge (episteme)
when the opinion is regarded correct (n.b., orthé not alethia), in terms of right, and juristically so (according to
the premises of the dialogue), which was the task of the rhetors to prove. Plato dismisses this possibility of an
affirmative relation between opinion and knowledge even when the one who opines grounds his belief on the A Venn diagram illustrating the
traditional definition of knowledge as
rule, and is able to add justification (logos: reasonable and necessarily plausible
justified true belief (represented by the
assertions/evidence/guidance) to it.[citation needed] A belief can be based fully or partially on intuition.[48] yellow circle). The Gettier problem gives
us reason to think that not all justified true
Plato has been credited for the justified true belief theory of knowledge, even though Plato in the Theaetetus beliefs constitute knowledge.
elegantly dismisses it, and even posits this argument of Socrates as a cause for his death penalty. The
epistemologists, Gettier[49] and Goldman,[50] have questioned the "justified true belief" definition.

Justified true belief [ edit ]

See also: Definitions of knowledge § Justified true belief

Justified true belief is a definition of knowledge that gained approval during the Enlightenment, "justified" standing in contrast to "revealed". There have
been attempts to trace it back to Plato and his dialogues, more specifically in the Theaetetus,[51] and the Meno. The concept of justified true belief states
that in order to know that a given proposition is true, one must not only believe the relevant true proposition, but also have justification for doing so. In
more formal terms, an agent knows that a proposition is true if and only if:

is true
believes that is true, and
is justified in believing that is true

That theory of knowledge suffered a significant setback with the discovery of Gettier problems, situations in which the above conditions were seemingly
met but where many philosophers deny that anything is known.[52] Robert Nozick suggested a clarification of "justification" which he believed eliminates
the problem: the justification has to be such that were the justification false, the knowledge would be false.[53] Bernecker and Dretske (2000) argue that
"no epistemologist since Gettier has seriously and successfully defended the traditional view."[54]: 3 On the other hand, Paul Boghossian argues that the
justified true belief account is the "standard, widely accepted" definition of knowledge.[55]

Belief systems [ edit ]

A belief system comprises a set of mutually supportive beliefs. The beliefs of any such system can be religious, philosophical, political, ideological, or a
combination of these.[56]

Glover's view [ edit ]

The British philosopher Jonathan Glover, following Meadows (2008), says that beliefs are always part of a belief system, and that tenanted belief
systems are difficult for the tenants to completely revise or reject.[57][58] He suggests that beliefs have to be considered holistically, and that no belief
exists in isolation in the mind of the believer. Each belief always implicates and relates to other beliefs.[57] Glover provides the example of a patient with
an illness who returns to a doctor, but the doctor says that the prescribed medicine is not working. At that point, the patient has a great deal of flexibility in
choosing what beliefs to keep or reject: the patient could believe that the doctor is incompetent, that the doctor's assistants made a mistake, that the
patient's own body is unique in some unexpected way, that Western medicine is ineffective, or even that Western science is entirely unable to discover
truths about ailments.[57]

This insight has relevance for inquisitors, missionaries, agitprop groups and thought-police. The British philosopher Stephen Law has described some
belief systems (including belief in homeopathy, psychic powers, and alien abduction) as "claptrap" and says that such belief-systems can "draw people in
and hold them captive so they become willing slaves of claptrap ... if you get sucked in, it can be extremely difficult to think your way clear again".[59]

Religion [ edit ]

This section uses texts from within a religion or faith system without referring to secondary sources that
critically analyze them. Please help improve this article. (August 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this
template message)

This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding
citations to reliable sources in this section. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Belief" – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (May 2021) (Learn how and when to remove this
template message)

Main article: Faith

Religion is a personal set or institutionalized system of religious attitudes, beliefs, and practices; the service or
worship of God or the supernatural.[60] Religious belief is distinct from religious practice and from religious
behaviours—with some believers not practicing religion and some practitioners not believing religion. Belief is no
less of a theoretical term than is religion.[61] Religious beliefs often relate to the existence, characteristics and
worship of a deity or deities, to the idea of divine intervention in the universe and in human life, or to the
deontological explanations for the values and practices centered on the teachings of a spiritual leader or
community.[62] In contrast to other belief systems, religious beliefs are usually codified.[63]

Forms [ edit ]

A popular view holds that different religions each have identifiable and exclusive sets of beliefs or creeds, but surveys of religious belief have often found
that the official doctrine and descriptions of the beliefs offered by religious authorities do not always agree with the privately held beliefs of those who
identify as members of a particular religion.[64] For a broad classification of the kinds of religious belief, see below.

Fundamentalism [ edit ]
Main article: Religious fundamentalism

First self-applied as a term to the conservative doctrine outlined by anti-modernist Protestants in the United States,[65] "fundamentalism" in religious
terms denotes strict adherence to an interpretation of scriptures that are generally associated with theologically conservative positions or traditional
understandings of the text and are distrustful of innovative readings, new revelation, or alternative interpretations.[66] Religious fundamentalism has been
identified[by whom?] in the media as being associated with fanatical or zealous political movements around the world that have used a strict adherence to a
particular religious doctrine as a means to establish political identity and to enforce societal norms.[67]

Orthodoxy [ edit ]
Main article: Orthodoxy

First used in the context of Early Christianity, the term "orthodoxy" relates to religious belief that closely follows the edicts, apologies, and hermeneutics
of a prevailing religious authority. In the case of Early Christianity, this authority was the communion of bishops, and is often referred to by the term
"Magisterium". The term orthodox was applied[when?] almost as an epithet to a group of Jewish believers who held to pre-Enlightenment understanding of
Judaism—now known as Orthodox Judaism. The Eastern Orthodox Church of Christianity and the Catholic Church each consider themselves to be the
true heir to Early Christian belief and practice. The antonym of "orthodox" is "heterodox", and those adhering to orthodoxy often accuse the heterodox of
apostasy, schism, or heresy.

Modernism/reform [ edit ]

The Renaissance and later the Enlightenment in Europe exhibited varying degrees of religious tolerance and intolerance towards new and old religious
ideas. The philosophes took particular exception to many of the more fantastical claims of religions and directly challenged religious authority and the
prevailing beliefs associated with the established churches. In response to the liberalizing political and social movements, some religious groups
attempted to integrate Enlightenment ideals of rationality, equality, and individual liberty into their belief systems, especially in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries. Reform Judaism[68][69] and Liberal Christianity offer two examples of such religious associations.

Attitudes to other religions [ edit ]

Adherents of particular religions deal with the differing doctrines and practices espoused by other religions or by other religious denominations in a
variety of ways.

Exclusivism [ edit ]
See also: Religious exclusivism

People with exclusivist beliefs typically explain other beliefs either as in error, or as corruptions or counterfeits of the true faith. This approach is a fairly
consistent feature among smaller new religious movements that often rely on doctrine that claims a unique revelation by the founders or leaders, and
considers it a matter of faith that the "correct" religion has a monopoly on truth. All three major Abrahamic monotheistic religions have passages in their
holy scriptures that attest to the primacy of the scriptural testimony, and indeed monotheism itself is often[quantify] vouched[by whom?] as an innovation
characterized specifically by its explicit rejection of earlier polytheistic faiths.

Some exclusivist faiths incorporate a specific element of proselytization. This is a strongly-held belief in the Christian tradition which follows the doctrine
of the Great Commission, and is less emphasized by the Islamic faith where the Quranic edict "There shall be no compulsion in religion" (2:256) is often
quoted as a justification for toleration of alternative beliefs. The Jewish tradition does not actively seek out converts.

Exclusivism correlates with conservative, fundamentalist, and orthodox approaches of many religions, while pluralistic and syncretist approaches either
explicitly downplay or reject the exclusivist tendencies within a religion.[citation needed][70]

Inclusivism [ edit ]

People with inclusivist beliefs recognize some truth in all faith systems, highlighting agreements and minimizing differences. This attitude is sometimes
associated[by whom?] with Interfaith dialogue or with the Christian Ecumenical movement, though in principle such attempts at pluralism are not
necessarily inclusivist and many actors in such interactions (for example, the Roman Catholic Church) still hold to exclusivist dogma while participating in
inter-religious organizations. Explicitly inclusivist religions include many that are associated with the New Age movement, as well as modern
reinterpretations of Hinduism and Buddhism. The Baháʼí Faith considers it doctrine that there is truth in all faith-systems.

Pluralism and syncretism are two closely related concepts. People with pluralist beliefs make no distinction between faith systems, viewing each one as
valid within a particular culture. People with syncretic views blend the views of a variety of different religions or traditional beliefs into a unique fusion
which suits their particular experiences and contexts (eclecticism). Unitarian Universalism exemplifies a syncretic faith.

Adherence [ edit ]

See also: Existence of God

Typical reasons for adherence to religion include the following:

Some see belief in a deity as necessary for moral behavior.[71]


Some regard religious practices as serene, beautiful, and conducive to religious experiences, which in turn support religious beliefs.[72]
Organized religions promote a sense of community among their followers, and the moral and cultural common ground of these communities makes
them attractive to people with similar values.[73] Indeed, while religious beliefs and practices are usually connected, some individuals with
substantially secular beliefs still participate in religious practices for cultural reasons.[74]
Each religion asserts that it is a means by which its adherents may come into closer contact with the Divine, with Truth, and with spiritual power. They
all promise to free adherents from spiritual bondage, and to bring them into spiritual freedom. It naturally follows that a religion which can free its
adherents from deception, sin, and spiritual death will have significant mental-health benefits. Abraham Maslow's research after World War II showed
that Holocaust survivors tended to be those who held strong religious beliefs (not necessarily temple attendance, etc.), suggesting that belief helped
people cope in extreme circumstances. Humanistic psychology went on to investigate how religious or spiritual identity may have correlations with
longer lifespan and better health. The study found that humans may particularly need religious ideas to serve various emotional needs such as the
need to feel loved, the need to belong to homogeneous groups, the need for understandable explanations and the need for a guarantee of ultimate
justice. Other factors may involve sense of purpose, sense of identity, or a sense of contact with the divine. See also Man's Search for Meaning, by
Viktor Frankl, detailing his experience with the importance of religion in surviving the Holocaust. Critics assert that the very fact that religion was the
primary selector for research subjects may have introduced a bias, and that the fact that all subjects were Holocaust survivors may also have had an
effect. According to Larson et al. (2000), "[m]ore longitudinal research with better multidimensional measures will help further clarify the roles of these
[religious] factors and whether they are beneficial or harmful."[75]

Psychologist James Alcock also summarizes a number of apparent benefits which reinforce religious belief. These include prayer appearing to account
for successful resolution of problems, "a bulwark against existential anxiety and fear of annihilation," an increased sense of control, companionship with
one's deity, a source of self-significance, and group identity.[76]

Apostasy [ edit ]

Main article: Apostasy


See also: Existence of God § Arguments against the existence of God or gods

Typical reasons for rejection of religion include:

Some people regard certain fundamental doctrines of some religions as illogical, contrary to experience, or unsupported by sufficient evidence; such
people may reject one or more religions for those reasons.[77] Even some believers may have difficulty accepting particular religious assertions or
doctrines. Some people believe the body of evidence available to humans to be insufficient to justify certain religious beliefs. They may thus disagree
with religious interpretations of ethics and human purpose, or with various creation myths. This reason has perhaps[original research?] been aggravated
by the protestations and emphases of some fundamentalist Christians.
Some religions include beliefs that certain groups of people are inferior or sinful and deserve contempt, persecution, or even death, and that non-
believers will be punished for their unbelief in an after-life.[78] Adherents to a religion may feel antipathy to unbelievers. Numerous examples exist of
people of one religion or sect using religion as an excuse to murder people with different religious beliefs. To mention just a few examples:
the slaughter of the Huguenots by French Catholics in the sixteenth century
Hindus and Muslims killing each other when Pakistan separated from India in 1947
the persecution and killing of Shiite Muslims by Sunni Muslims in Iraq
the murder of Protestants by Catholics and vice versa in Ireland (both of these examples in the late twentieth century)
the Israeli–Palestinian conflict that continues as of 2018 – According to some critics of religion, such beliefs can encourage completely
unnecessary conflicts and in some cases even wars. Many atheists believe that, because of this, religion is incompatible with world peace,
freedom, civil rights, equality, and good government. On the other hand, most religions perceive atheism as a threat and will vigorously and even
violently[79] defend themselves against religious sterilization, making the attempt to remove public religious practices a source of strife.[79]
Some people may be unable to accept the values that a specific religion promotes and will therefore not join that religion. They may also be unable to
accept the proposition that those who do not believe will go to hell or be damned, especially if said nonbelievers are close to the person.
The maintenance of life and the achievement of self-esteem require of a person the fullest exercise of reason[citation needed]—but morality (people are
taught[by whom?]) rests on and requires faith.[80][page needed]

Psychology [ edit ]

This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding
citations to reliable sources in this section. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.
Find sources: "Belief" – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (May 2021) (Learn how and when to remove this
template message)

Mainstream psychology and related disciplines have traditionally treated belief as if it were the simplest form of mental representation and therefore one
of the building blocks of conscious thought.[81] Philosophers have tended to be more abstract in their analysis, and much of the work examining the
viability of the belief concept stems from philosophical analysis.[82]

The concept of belief presumes a subject (the believer) and an object of belief (the proposition). Like other propositional attitudes, belief implies the
existence of mental states and intentionality, both of which are hotly debated topics in the philosophy of mind, whose foundations and relation to brain
states are still controversial.

Beliefs are sometimes divided into core beliefs (that are actively thought about) and dispositional beliefs (that may be ascribed to someone who has not
thought about the issue). For example, if asked "do you believe tigers wear pink pajamas?" a person might answer that they do not, despite the fact they
may never have thought about this situation before.[83]

Philosopher Lynne Rudder Baker has outlined four main contemporary approaches to belief in her book Saving Belief:[84]

Our common-sense understanding of belief is correct – Sometimes called the "mental sentence theory," in this conception, beliefs exist as coherent
entities, and the way we talk about them in everyday life is a valid basis for scientific endeavor. Jerry Fodor was one of the principal defenders of this
point of view.
Our common-sense understanding of belief may not be entirely correct, but it is close enough to make some useful predictions – This view argues
that we will eventually reject the idea of belief as we know it now, but that there may be a correlation between what we take to be a belief when
someone says "I believe that snow is white" and how a future theory of psychology will explain this behavior. Philosopher Stephen Stich has argued
for this particular understanding of belief.
Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong and will be completely superseded by a radically different theory that will have no use for
the concept of belief as we know it – Known as eliminativism, this view (most notably proposed by Paul and Patricia Churchland) argues that the
concept of belief is like obsolete theories of times past such as the four humours theory of medicine, or the phlogiston theory of combustion. In these
cases science has not provided us with a more detailed account of these theories, but completely rejected them as valid scientific concepts to be
replaced by entirely different accounts. The Churchland argue that our common-sense concept of belief is similar in that as we discover more about
neuroscience and the brain, the inevitable conclusion will be to reject the belief hypothesis in its entirety.
Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong; however, treating people, animals, and even computers as if they had beliefs is often a
successful strategy – The major proponents of this view, Daniel Dennett and Lynne Rudder Baker, are both eliminativists in that they hold that beliefs
are not a scientifically valid concept, but they do not go as far as rejecting the concept of belief as a predictive device. Dennett gives the example of
playing a computer at chess. While few people would agree that the computer held beliefs, treating the computer as if it did (e.g. that the computer
believes that taking the opposition's queen will give it a considerable advantage) is likely to be a successful and predictive strategy. In this
understanding of belief, named by Dennett the intentional stance, belief-based explanations of mind and behaviour are at a different level of
explanation and are not reducible to those based on fundamental neuroscience, although both may be explanatory at their own level.

Strategic approaches make a distinction between rules, norms and beliefs as follows:

Rules. Explicit regulative processes such as policies, laws, inspection routines, or incentives. Rules function as a coercive regulator of behavior and
are dependent upon the imposing entity's ability to enforce them.
Norms. Regulative mechanisms accepted by the social collective. Norms are enforced by normative mechanisms within the organization and are not
strictly dependent upon law or regulation.
Beliefs. The collective perception of fundamental truths governing behavior. The adherence to accepted and shared beliefs by members of a social
system will likely persist and be difficult to change over time. Strong beliefs about determinant factors (i.e., security, survival, or honor) are likely to
cause a social entity or group to accept rules and norms.[85]

Belief formation and revision [ edit ]

See also: Belief revision

Belief revision is a term commonly used to refer to the modification of beliefs. An extensive amount of scientific research and philosophical discussion
exists around belief revision. Generally speaking, the process of belief revision entails the believer weighing the set of truths and/or evidence, and the
dominance of a set of truths or evidence on an alternative to a held belief can lead to revision. One process of belief revision is Bayesian updating (or
Bayesian inference) and is often referenced for its mathematical basis and conceptual simplicity.[86] However, such a process may not be representative
for individuals whose beliefs are not easily characterized as probabilistic.

There are several techniques for individuals or groups to change the beliefs of others; these methods generally fall under the umbrella of persuasion.
Persuasion can take on more specific forms such as consciousness raising when considered in an activist or political context. Belief modification may
also occur as a result of the experience of outcomes. Because goals are based, in part on beliefs, the success or failure at a particular goal may
contribute to modification of beliefs that supported the original goal.

Whether or not belief modification actually occurs is dependent not only on the extent of truths or evidence for the alternative belief, but also
characteristics outside the specific truths or evidence. This includes, but is not limited to: the source characteristics of the message, such as credibility;
social pressures; the anticipated consequences of a modification; or the ability of the individual or group to act on the modification. Therefore, individuals
seeking to achieve belief modification in themselves or others need to consider all possible forms of resistance to belief revision.

Glover maintains that any person can continue to hold any belief if they would really like to[57] (for example, with help from ad hoc hypotheses). One
belief can be held fixed, and other beliefs will be altered around it. Glover warns that some beliefs may not be entirely explicitly believed (for example,
some people may not realize they have racist belief-systems adopted from their environment as a child). Glover believes that people tend to first realize
that beliefs can change, and may be contingent on their upbringing, around age 12 or 15.[57]

Glover emphasizes that beliefs are difficult to change. He says that one may try to rebuild one's beliefs on
more secure foundations (axioms), like building a new house, but warns that this may not be possible. Glover
offers the example of René Descartes, saying: "[Descartes] starts off with the characteristic beliefs of a 17th-
century Frenchman; he then junks the lot, he rebuilds the system, and somehow it looks a lot like the beliefs
of a 17th-century Frenchman." To Glover, belief systems are not like houses but are instead like boats. As
Glover puts it: "Maybe the whole thing needs rebuilding, but inevitably at any point you have to keep enough
of it intact to keep floating."[57]

Models of belief formation [ edit ]


Philosopher Jonathan Glover warns
Psychologists study belief formation and the relationship between beliefs and actions. Three types of models that belief systems are like whole boats in
of belief formation and change have been proposed: conditional inference process models, linear models and the water; it is extremely difficult to alter
them all at once (for example, it may be
information processing models.
too stressful, or people may maintain their
biases without realizing it).[57]
Conditional inference process models emphasize the role of inference for belief formation. When asked to
estimate the likelihood that a statement is true, people allegedly search their memory for information that has
implications for the validity of this statement. Once this information has been identified, they estimate the
likelihood that the statement would be true if the information were true, and the likelihood that the statement
would be true if the information were false. If their estimates for these two probabilities differ, people average
them, weighting each by the likelihood that the information is true and false. Thus, information bears directly on
beliefs of another, related statement.[87]

Unlike the previous model, linear models take into consideration the possibility of multiple factors influencing
belief formation. Using regression procedures, these models predict belief formation on the basis of several We are influenced by many factors
different pieces of information, with weights assigned to each piece on the basis of their relative importance.[87] that ripple through our minds as our
beliefs form, evolve, and may
Information processing models address the fact that the responses people have to belief-relevant information eventually change.
is unlikely to be predicted from the objective basis of the information that they can recall at the time their beliefs
are reported. Instead, these responses reflect the number and meaning of the thoughts that people have about
the message at the time that they encounter it.[87]

Some influences on people's belief formation include:

Internalization of beliefs during childhood, which can form and shape humans' beliefs in different domains. Albert Einstein is often quoted as having
said that "Common sense is the collection of prejudices acquired by age eighteen." Political beliefs depend most strongly on the political beliefs most
common in the community where one lives.[88] Most individuals believe the religion they were taught in childhood.[89]
Charismatic leaders can form or modify beliefs (even if those beliefs fly in the face of all previous beliefs).[90] Rational individuals need to reconcile
their direct reality with any said belief; therefore, if belief is not present or possible, it reflects the fact that contradictions were necessarily overcome
using cognitive dissonance.
Advertising can form or change beliefs through repetition, shock, or association with images of sex, love, beauty, and other strong positive
emotions.[91] Contrary to intuition, a delay, known as the sleeper effect, instead of immediate succession may increase an advertisement's ability to
persuade viewer's beliefs if a discounting cue is present.[92]
Physical trauma, especially to the head, can radically alter a person's beliefs.[93]

However, even educated people, well aware of the process by which beliefs form, still strongly cling to their beliefs, and act on those beliefs even against
their own self-interest. In her book Leadership Therapy, Anna Rowley states: "You want your beliefs to change. It's proof that you are keeping your eyes
open, living fully, and welcoming everything that the world and people around you can teach you." This view implies that peoples' beliefs may evolve as
they gain new experiences.[94]

Prediction [ edit ]

Different psychological models have tried to predict people's beliefs and some of them try to estimate the exact probabilities of beliefs. For example,
Robert Wyer developed a model of subjective probabilities.[95][96] When people rate the likelihood of a certain statement (e.g., "It will rain tomorrow"), this
rating can be seen as a subjective probability value. The subjective probability model posits that these subjective probabilities follow the same rules as
objective probabilities. For example, the law of total probability might be applied to predict a subjective probability value. Wyer found that this model
produces relatively accurate predictions for probabilities of single events and for changes in these probabilities, but that the probabilities of several beliefs
linked by "and" or "or" do not follow the model as well.[95][96]

Delusion [ edit ]

In the DSM-5, delusions are defined as fixed false beliefs that are not changed even when confronted with conflicting evidence.

Belief studies [ edit ]

There is research investigating specific beliefs, types of beliefs and patterns of beliefs. For example, a study
estimated contemporary prevalence and associations with belief in witchcraft around the world, which (in its
data) varied between 9% and 90% between nations and is still a widespread element in worldviews globally. It
also shows associations such as with lower "innovative activity", higher levels of anxiety, lower life expectancy,
and higher religiosity.[98][97] Other research is investigating beliefs in misinformation and their resistance to
correction, including with respect to misinformation countermeasures. It describes cognitive, social and affective
processes that leave people vulnerable to the formation of false beliefs.[99] A study introduced the concept of
false social reality which refers to widespread perceptions of public opinion that are shown to be false, such as
underestimated general public support in the U.S. for climate change mitigation policies.[100][101] Studies also
suggested some uses of psychedelics can shift beliefs in some humans in certain ways, such as increasing Socio-demographic correlates of
witchcraft beliefs[97]
attribution of consciousness to various entities (including plants and inanimate objects) and towards
panpsychism and fatalism.[102][103]

Emotion and beliefs [ edit ]

This section needs expansion.


You can help by adding to it.
(January 2020)

Research has indicated that emotion and cognition act in conjunction to produce beliefs, and more specifically emotion plays a vital role in the formation
and maintenance of beliefs.[104][105][106]

See also [ edit ]

Alief Moore's paradox Theory of justification


Philosophy portal
Bayesian epistemology Observer-expectancy effect Thomas theorem
Psychology portal
Culture-specific syndrome Opinion Tinkerbell effect
Doxastic attitudes Propositional knowledge Trust Society portal
Doxastic logic Self-deception Unintended consequence
Doxastic voluntarism Subject-expectancy effect Validity
Expectation (epistemic) Subjective validation Value (personal and cultural)
Idea Suggestibility World view
Magical thinking Suggestion

References [ edit ]

1. ^ Primmer, Justin (2018), "Belief", in Primmer, Justin (ed.), The Stanford 51. ^ The received view holds it that Plato's theory presents knowledge as
Encyclopedia of Philosophy , Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research remembering eternal truths and justification reawakens memory, see Fine,
Lab, archived from the original on 15 November 2019, retrieved G. (2003). "Introduction". Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays.
19 September 2008 New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 5–7. ISBN 978-0199245581.
2. ^ a b c d e "Belief" . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from 52. ^ Chisholm, Roderick (1982). "Knowledge as Justified True Belief". The
the original on 15 November 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020. Foundations of Knowing. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
3. ^ "Formal Representations of Belief" . Stanford Encyclopedia of ISBN 978-0816611034.
Philosophy. Archived from the original on 11 July 2020. Retrieved 22 June 53. ^ Nozick, Robert. (1981). Philosophical explanations . Cambridge, Mass.:
2020. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0674664485. OCLC 7283862 .
4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag Schwitzgebel, 54. ^ Bernecker, Sven; Dretske, Fred (2000). Knowledge. Readings in
Eric (2019). "Belief" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. contemporary epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 3.
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original ISBN 978-0198752615.
on 15 November 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020. 55. ^ Paul Boghossian (2007), Fear of Knowledge: Against relativism and
5. ^ a b c d Pitt, David (2020). "Mental Representation" . The Stanford constructivism , Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, ISBN 978-0199230419,
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford archived from the original on 7 October 2017, retrieved 20 April 2017,
University. Archived from the original on 6 August 2019. Retrieved 2 April Chapter 2, p. 15.
2021. 56. ^ "A system is an interconnected set of elements that is coherently
6. ^ a b c d e f Borchert, Donald (2006). "Belief". Macmillan Encyclopedia of organized in a way that achieves something." —Donella Meadows (2008)
Philosophy, 2nd Edition . Macmillan. Archived from the original on 12 Thinking in Systems: A Primer Archived 2 May 2021 at the Wayback
January 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. Machine p.11, as quoted by Tim Rettig (2017) Belief Systems: what they are
7. ^ "Philosophy of mind – Propositional attitudes" . Encyclopedia Britannica. and how they affect you Archived 16 May 2021 at the Wayback Machine
Archived from the original on 19 July 2020. Retrieved 2 April 2021. 57. ^ a b c d e f g " "Jonathan Glover on systems of belief", Philosophy Bites
8. ^ Oppy, Graham. "Propositional attitudes" . www.rep.routledge.com. Podcast, Oct 9 2011" . Archived from the original on 14 October 2011.
Archived from the original on 4 March 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. Retrieved 5 July 2014.
9. ^ Fassio, Davide. "Aim of Belief" . Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 58. ^ Elizabeth A. Minton, Lynn R. Khale (2014). Belief Systems, Religion, and
Archived from the original on 11 February 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. Behavioral Economics . New York: Business Expert Press LLC. ISBN 978-
10. ^ Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis" . Internet 1606497043. Archived from the original on 22 December 2019. Retrieved
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 February 30 April 2019.
2021. Retrieved 31 March 2021. 59. ^ New Scientist (magazine), 11 June 2011 A field guide to bullshit | New
11. ^ a b c d Craig, Edward (1996). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Scientist Archived 16 June 2015 at the Wayback Machine - "Intellectual
Routledge. Archived from the original on 16 January 2021. Retrieved black holes are belief systems that draw people in and hold them captive so
2 April 2021. they become willing slaves of claptrap. Belief in homeopathy, psychic
12. ^ a b c Levin, Janet (2018). "Functionalism" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of powers, alien abductions—these are examples of intellectual black holes. As
Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived you approach them, you need to be on your guard because if you get
from the original on 18 April 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. sucked in, it can be extremely difficult to think your way clear again."
13. ^ a b Polger, Thomas W. "Functionalism" . Internet Encyclopedia of 60. ^ "Definition of RELIGION" . Merriam-Webster. Retrieved 5 May 2023.
Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 May 2019. Retrieved 2 April 61. ^ Iii, Thomas J. Coleman; Jong, Jonathan; Mulukom, Valerie van (31 August
2021. 2018). "Introduction to the Special Issue: What are Religious Beliefs?" .
14. ^ Bickle, John (2020). "Multiple Realizability" . The Stanford Encyclopedia Contemporary Pragmatism. 15 (3): 279–283. doi:10.1163/18758185-
of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived 01503001 . ISSN 1572-3429 . S2CID 171838557 .
from the original on 16 March 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. 62. ^ Nye, Malory (2008). Religion: The Basics. Routledge. ISBN 978-
15. ^ a b Quilty-Dunn, Jake; Mandelbaum, Eric (1 September 2018). "Against 1134059478.
dispositionalism: belief in cognitive science" . Philosophical Studies. 175 63. ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (2007). Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics,
(9): 2353–2372. doi:10.1007/s11098-017-0962-x . ISSN 1573-0883 . Psychology and Religious Belief. University of California Press. p. 53.
16. ^ a b c Audi, Robert (1999). "Belief". The Cambridge Dictionary of ISBN 978-0520251816.
Philosophy . Cambridge University Press. Archived from the original on 64. ^ Braithwaite, R.B. (1975). An empiricist's view of the nature of religious
14 April 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. belief. Norwood Editions (Norwood, Pa.). ISBN 978-0883059555.
17. ^ a b c Child, William (1994). "1. Interpretationism". Causality, Interpretation, 65. ^ "The Fundamentals: A Testimony to the Truth" . 27 November 2012.
and the Mind . Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Archived from the Archived from the original on 3 December 2012. Retrieved 28 November
original on 5 May 2016. Retrieved 2 April 2021. 2012.
18. ^ Dennett, Daniel (1989). The Intentional Stance . The MIT Press. 66. ^ Bruce, Steve (2008). Fundamentalism . Polity. ISBN 978-0745640754.
ISBN 978-0262040938. Archived from the original on 15 April 2021. OCLC 1001942770 .
Retrieved 2 April 2021. 67. ^ Fox, Jonathan (13 February 2018). An Introduction to Religion and
19. ^ Dennett, Daniel C. (1988). "Précis of The Intentional Stance". Behavioral Politics . doi:10.4324/9781315183787 . ISBN 978-1315183787.
and Brain Sciences. 11 (3): 495–505. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.1026.2283 . 68. ^ "What is Reform Judaism?" . Reform Judaism. Retrieved 27 March
doi:10.1017/S0140525X00058611 . S2CID 145750868 . 2022.
20. ^ Child, William (1994). "4. Causalism and Interpretationism: The Problem of 69. ^ "Reform Judaism | Britannica" . Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved
Compatibility". Causality, Interpretation, and the Mind . Oxford, UK: Oxford 27 March 2022.
University Press. Archived from the original on 5 May 2016. Retrieved 70. ^ Meister, Chad (2011). The Oxford Handbook of Religious Diversity. OUP
2 April 2021. US. ISBN 978-0195340136.
21. ^ Wolpert, Lewis (3 February 2011) [2006]. "Belief". Six Impossible Things 71. ^ Compare: "Roy Moore: 'We Have No Morality Without an Acknowledgment
Before Breakfast: The Evolutionary Origins of Belief (reprint ed.). London: of God' " . Christianity Today. 7 March 2005. Archived from the original
Faber & Faber. ISBN 9780571266722. Retrieved 22 December 2023. on 8 January 2009. Retrieved 19 May 2006.
"Causal beliefs are a fundamental characteristic of humans; animals, by 72. ^ Miller, David Ian (15 February 2005). "Finding My Religion: Steve
contrast, [...] have very few causal beliefs. Beliefs come from a wide variety Georgiou on his faith and mentor, minimalist poet Robert Lax" . SFGate.
of sources that include the individual's experiences, the influence of Archived from the original on 16 May 2012. Retrieved 19 May 2006.
authority, and the interpretation of events. At their core, beliefs establish a 73. ^ Repa, J. Theodore (18 October 1998). "Building Community: The Marriage
cause and effect relationship between events [...] From an evolutionary point of Religion and Education" . Archived from the original on 7 September
of view, beliefs should help the individual survive, and I will argue that they 2006. Retrieved 19 May 2006.
had their origin in tool making and use." 74. ^ Note for example the concept of a cultural Christian.
22. ^ a b Bartlett, Gary (2018). "Occurrent States" . Canadian Journal of 75. ^ Larson, David B.; Susan S. Larson; Harold G. Koenig (October 2000).
Philosophy. 48 (1): 1–17. doi:10.1080/00455091.2017.1323531 . "Research Findings on Religious Commitment and Mental Health" .
S2CID 220316213 . Archived from the original on 4 May 2021. Retrieved Psychiatric Times. 17 (10). Archived from the original on 8 January 2009.
3 April 2021. Retrieved 19 May 2006.
23. ^ a b Frise, Matthew (2018). "Eliminating the Problem of Stored Beliefs" . 76. ^ Alcock, James (2018). "The God Engine". Skeptical Inquirer. 42 (5): 32–
American Philosophical Quarterly. 55 (1): 63–79. doi:10.2307/45128599 . 38.
JSTOR 45128599 . S2CID 149057271 . Archived from the original on 1 77. ^ For example: Russell, Bertrand (1927). "Why I am Not a Christian" .
June 2021. Retrieved 3 April 2021. Archived from the original on 19 November 2006. Retrieved 19 May 2006.
24. ^ a b c d e f g Genin, Konstantin; Huber, Franz (2021). "Formal 78. ^ For example, some Muslims believe that women are inferior to men. Some
Representations of Belief" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Christians share this belief. At the time of the American Civil War of 1861–
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original 1865, many Southerners used passages from the Bible to justify race-based
on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 1 April 2021. slavery. Certain campaigners have used the Christian religion as a reason to
25. ^ a b Olsson, Erik J. (2018). "Bayesian Epistemology". Introduction to Formal persecute and to deny the rights of homosexuals, on the basis that the
Philosophy . Springer. pp. 431–442. Archived from the original on 16 Christian biblical God disapproves of homosexuality, and by implication of
May 2021. Retrieved 3 April 2021. homosexuals. Compare http://www.godhatesfags.com Archived 7 March
26. ^ a b c Hartmann, Stephan; Sprenger, Jan (2010). "Bayesian Epistemology". 2021 at the Wayback Machine
The Routledge Companion to Epistemology . London: Routledge. pp. 609– 79. ^ a b Beauchamp, Philip (pseudonym of Jeremy Bentham) Analysis of the
620. Archived from the original on 16 May 2021. Retrieved 3 April 2021. Influence of Natural Religion on the Temporal Happiness of Mankind
27. ^ Hájek, Alan (2019). "Interpretations of Probability: 3.3 The Subjective Archived 4 February 2020 at the Wayback Machine, 1822, R. Carlile,
Interpretation" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics London, at page 76: "Of all human antipathies, that which the believer in a
Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 17 God bears to the unbeliever is the fullest, the most unqualified, and the most
February 2021. Retrieved 6 March 2021. universal"
28. ^ Pettigrew, Richard (2018). "Précis of Accuracy and the Laws of 80. ^ Waldau, Paul (2001). The Specter of Speciesism: Buddhist and Christian
Credence" . Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 96 (3): 749– Views of Animals (American Academy of Religion Books) . Oxford
754. doi:10.1111/phpr.12501 . hdl:1983/d9f3e1c4-1bc9-4e04-b74c- University Press, US. ISBN 978-0195145717.
dba4eb795393 . Archived from the original on 1 June 2021. Retrieved 81. ^ Bering, Jesse (2006). "The Cognitive Psychology of Belief in the
3 April 2021. Supernatural" . American Scientist. 94 (2): 142.
29. ^ Dorst, Kevin (2019). "Lockeans Maximize Expected Accuracy" . Mind. doi:10.1511/2006.58.142 . ISSN 0003-0996 .
128 (509): 175–211. doi:10.1093/mind/fzx028 . Archived from the 82. ^ Barnett, Zach (1 January 2019). "Philosophy Without Belief" . Mind. 128
original on 20 October 2020. Retrieved 3 April 2021. (509): 109–138. doi:10.1093/mind/fzw076 . ISSN 0026-4423 .
30. ^ Locke, Dustin Troy (2014). "The Decision-Theoretic Lockean Thesis" . 83. ^ Bell, V.; Halligan, P.W.; Ellis, H.D. (2006). "A Cognitive Neuroscience of
Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 57 (1): 28–54. Belief". In Halligan, Peter W.; Aylward, Mansel (eds.). The Power of Belief:
doi:10.1080/0020174x.2013.858421 . S2CID 85521556 . Archived Psychological Influence on Illness, Disability, and Medicine. Oxford: Oxford
from the original on 5 July 2016. Retrieved 3 April 2021. University Press. ISBN 978-0198530107.
31. ^ abc Price, H. H. (1965). "Belief 'In' and Belief 'That' " . Religious Studies. 84. ^ Baker, Lynne Rudder (1989). Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism.
1 (1): 5–27. doi:10.1017/S0034412500002304 . S2CID 170731716 . Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0691073200.
Archived from the original on 1 June 2021. Retrieved 2 March 2021. 85. ^ Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff, U.S. Army (2012). Information
32. ^ abcdef Williams, John N. (1992). "Belief-in and Belief in God" . Operations. Joint Publication 3–13. Joint Doctrine Support Division, Suffolk,
Religious Studies. 28 (3): 401–406. doi:10.1017/s0034412500021740 . VA. p. 22.
S2CID 170864816 . Archived from the original on 19 May 2021. 86. ^ Parr, Thomas; Rees, Geraint; Friston, Karl J. (2018). "Computational
Retrieved 2 March 2021. Neuropsychology and Bayesian Inference" . Frontiers in Human
33. ^ a b c Macintosh, J. J. (1994). "Belief-in Revisited: A Reply to Williams" . Neuroscience. 12: 61. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2018.00061 . ISSN 1662-
Religious Studies. 30 (4): 487–503. doi:10.1017/S0034412500023131 . 5161 . PMC 5829460 . PMID 29527157 .
S2CID 170786861 . Archived from the original on 29 September 2020. 87. ^ a b c Wyer, R.S., & Albarracin, D. (2005). "Belief formation, organization,
Retrieved 2 March 2021. and change: Cognitive and motivational influences". In D. Albarracin, B.T.
34. ^ a b Macintosh, Jack (2005). "Belief-in". The Oxford Companion to Johnson, & M.P. Zanna, The Handbook of Attitudes (273–322). New York:
Philosophy . Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 29 Psychology Press.
January 2021. Retrieved 2 March 2021. 88. ^ Gelman, Andrew; Park, David; Shor, Boris; Bafumi, Joseph; Cortina,
35. ^ a b Broackes, Justin (1986). "Belief de Re and de Dicto" . Philosophical Jeronimo (2008). Red State, Blue State, Rich State, Poor State: Why
Quarterly. 36 (144): 374–383. doi:10.2307/2220191 . JSTOR 2220191 . Americans Vote the Way They Do . Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-
Archived from the original on 17 November 2016. Retrieved 3 April 2021. 0691139272.
36. ^ a b c d Nelson, Michael. "Propositional Attitude Reports: The De Re/De 89. ^ Argyle, Michael (1997). The Psychology of Religious Behaviour, Belief and
Dicto Distinction" . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from Experience. London: Routledge. p. 25. ISBN 978-0415123303. "Religion, in
the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. most cultures, is ascribed, not chosen."
37. ^ Dancy, Jonathan (2014). A Companion to Epistemology . Just the 90. ^ Hoffer, Eric (2002). The True Believer. New York: Harper Perennial
Facts101 (2 ed.). Content Technologies Inc. ISBN 978-1478400028. Modern Classics. ISBN 978-0060505912.
Retrieved 30 April 2019. "A collective belief is referred to when people speak 91. ^ Kilbourne, Jane; Pipher, Mary (2000). Can't Buy My Love: How Advertising
of what 'we' believe when this is not simply elliptical for what 'we all' believe." Changes the Way We Think and Feel . Free Press. ISBN 978-
38. ^ Dancy, Jonathan (2014). A Companion to Epistemology . Just the 0684866000.
Facts101 (2 ed.). Content Technologies Inc. (published 2016). ISBN 978- 92. ^ See Kumkale & Albarracin, 2004.
1478400028. Retrieved 30 April 2019. "Sociologist Émile Durkheim wrote of 93. ^ Rothschild, Babette (2000). The Body Remembers: The Psychophysiology
collective beliefs and proposed that they, like all 'social facts', 'inhered in'
of Trauma and Trauma Treatment. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
social groups as opposed to individual persons. Durkheim's discussion of
ISBN 978-0393703276.
collective belief, though suggestive, is relatively obscure."
94. ^ Rowley, Anna (2007). Leadership Therapy: Inside the Mind of Microsoft .
39. ^ Gilbert, Margaret (1987). "Modelling collective belief" . Synthese. 73 (1):
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. p. 69 . ISBN 978-1403984036.
185–204. doi:10.1007/bf00485446 . ISSN 0039-7857 .
95. ^ a b Wyer, R.S. (1970). "Quantitative prediction of belief and opinion
S2CID 46976878 .
change: A further test of a subjective probability model". Journal of
40. ^ Innes, Martin (16 December 2003). "A history of the idea of social control".
Personality and Social Psychology. 16 (4): 559–570.
Understanding Social Control: Deviance, crime and social order . UK
doi:10.1037/h0030064 .
Higher Education OUP Humanities & Social Sciences Criminology.
96. ^ a b Wyer, R.S.; Goldberg, L. (1970). "A probabilistic analysis of the
Maidenhead, Berkshire: McGraw-Hill Education (UK). p. 22.
relationships among beliefs and attitudes". Psychological Review. 77 (2):
ISBN 9780335225880. Retrieved 30 October 2023. "[...] all states and all
100–120. doi:10.1037/h0028769 .
collectives draw upon shared remembrances of the past to establish or
97. ^ a b Gershman, Boris (23 November 2022). "Witchcraft beliefs around the
preserve a sense of shared identity and a collective belief system. A
world: An exploratory analysis" . PLOS ONE. 17 (11): e0276872.
coherent approach to understanding the functions of social control for
Bibcode:2022PLoSO..1776872G . doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0276872 .
collective life is to be found in Erikson's (1966) discussion of the social
PMC 9683553 . PMID 36417350 .
control of witchcraft in seventeenth-century New England."
98. ^ "Witchcraft beliefs are widespread, highly variable around the world" .
41. ^ Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (23 December 2011). "Critique of Representation:
Public Library of Science via phys.org. Retrieved 17 December 2022.
Cultures of Knowledge - Humanly Speaking". In Abel, Günter; Conant,
99. ^ Ecker, Ullrich K. H.; Lewandowsky, Stephan; Cook, John; Schmid, Philipp;
James (eds.). Rethinking Epistemology . Berlin Studies in Knowledge
Fazio, Lisa K.; Brashier, Nadia; Kendeou, Panayiota; Vraga, Emily K.;
Research, volume 1. Vol. 1. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. p. 185.
Amazeen, Michelle A. (January 2022). "The psychological drivers of
ISBN 9783110253573. Retrieved 30 October 2023. "Collective belief
misinformation belief and its resistance to correction" . Nature Reviews
systems are characterized by the belief of knowing what counts as proper
Psychology. 1 (1): 13–29. doi:10.1038/s44159-021-00006-y .
beliefs; divergence is condemned as heresy, betrayal, apostasy, etc."
hdl:1983/889ddb0f-0d44-44f4-a54f-57c260ae4917 . ISSN 2731-0574 .
42. ^ Visano, L. A. (1998). Crime and Culture: Refining the Traditions .
S2CID 245916820 .
Toronto: Canadian Scholars Press. p. 51. ISBN 9781551301273. Retrieved
100. ^ Clifford, Catherine. "Americans don't think other Americans care about
30 October 2023. "[...] deviance cannot be studied in isolation nor
climate change as much as they do" . CNBC. Retrieved 15 September
understood apart from [...] overwhelmingly binding collective belief systems."
abcdef
2022.
43. ^ Block, Ned (1996). "Holism, Mental and Semantic". Routledge
101. ^ Sparkman, Gregg; Geiger, Nathan; Weber, Elke U. (23 August 2022).
Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Routledge. Archived from the original on
"Americans experience a false social reality by underestimating popular
15 August 2016. Retrieved 5 April 2021.
climate policy support by nearly half" . Nature Communications. 13 (1):
44. ^ Wagner, Steven J. (1986). "Quine's Holism" . Analysis. 46 (1): 1–6.
4779. Bibcode:2022NatCo..13.4779S . doi:10.1038/s41467-022-32412-
doi:10.2307/3328733 . ISSN 0003-2638 . JSTOR 3328733 . Archived
y . ISSN 2041-1723 . PMC 9399177 . PMID 35999211 .
from the original on 1 June 2021. Retrieved 5 April 2021.
abc
102. ^ Nayak, Sandeep M.; Griffiths, Roland R. (28 March 2022). "A Single
45. ^ Rowlands, Mark; Lau, Joe; Deutsch, Max (2020). "Externalism About
Belief-Changing Psychedelic Experience Is Associated With Increased
the Mind" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics
Attribution of Consciousness to Living and Non-living Entities" . Frontiers in
Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 April
Psychology. 13: 852248. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2022.852248 . ISSN 1664-
2021. Retrieved 4 April 2021.
1078 . PMC 8995647 . PMID 35418909 .
46. ^ abc Smith, Basil. "Internalism and Externalism in the Philosophy of Mind
103. ^ Timmermann, Christopher; Kettner, Hannes; Letheby, Chris; Roseman,
and Language" . Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the
Leor; Rosas, Fernando E.; Carhart-Harris, Robin L. (23 November 2021).
original on 6 May 2021. Retrieved 4 April 2021.
"Psychedelics alter metaphysical beliefs" . Scientific Reports. 11 (1):
47. ^ Oxford Dictionaries – definition Archived 6 September 2016 at the
22166. Bibcode:2021NatSR..1122166T . doi:10.1038/s41598-021-01209-
Wayback Machine published by OUP [Retrieved 2015-08-09]
2 . ISSN 2045-2322 . PMC 8611059 . PMID 34815421 .
48. ^ Pust, Joel (2019), "Intuition" , in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford
104. ^ Frijda, Nico H (2010). Emotions and Beliefs. Cambridge University Press.
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research
ISBN 978-0511659904.
Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 27 September 2022
105. ^ Mercer, Jonathan (January 2010). "Emotional Beliefs". International
49. ^ Gettier, E.L. (1963). "Is justified true belief knowledge?" (PDF).
Organization. 65: 1–31. doi:10.1017/S0020818309990221 .
Analysis. 23 (6): 121–123. doi:10.1093/analys/23.6.121 .
S2CID 232251086 .
JSTOR 3326922 . Archived (PDF) from the original on 2 September
106. ^ Harlé, Katia M.; Shenoy, Pradeep; Paulus, Martin P. (19 September 2013).
2019. Retrieved 24 September 2019.
"The influence of emotions on cognitive control: feelings and beliefs—where
50. ^ Goldman, A.I. (1967). "A causal theory of knowing". The Journal of
do they meet?" . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 7: 508.
Philosophy. 64 (12): 357–372. doi:10.2307/2024268 . JSTOR 2024268 .
doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00508 . ISSN 1662-5161 . PMC 3776943 .
S2CID 53049561 .
PMID 24065901 .

Further reading [ edit ]

Robert Audi (Dec. 1994). "Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe" , Noûs, Vol. 28, No. 4, pp. 419–434. OCLC 481484099 .
Coleman, T. III, Jong, J., & van Mulukom, V. (2018). Introduction to the Special Issue: What are Religious Beliefs? . Contemporary Pragmatism,
15(3), 279–283. doi:10.1163/18758185-01503001
Järnefelt, Elisa, Created by Some Being: Theoretical and Empirical Exploration of Adults' Automatic and Reflective Beliefs about the Origin of Natural
Phenomena. Diss. University of Helsinki, 2013. ISBN 978-9521094163.
Leicester, J. "What beliefs are made from". Sharjah, UAE: Bentham Science Publishers, 2016.

External links [ edit ]

Schwitzgebel, Eric. "Belief" . In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.


Wikimedia Commons has
"The Aim of Belief" . Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. media related to Belief.

Wikiquote has quotations


related to Belief.

Wikiversity has learning


resources about Knowing
How You Know

Wikiversity has learning


resources about Seeking
True Beliefs

Look up belief in Wiktionary,


the free dictionary.

Look up belief system in


Wiktionary, the free
dictionary.

Links to related articles [show]

Authority control databases [show]

Categories: Belief Religious belief and doctrine Concepts in epistemology Propositional attitudes Psychological attitude
Psychological concepts Truth

This page was last edited on 10 February 2024, at 09:21 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit
organization.

Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers Contact Wikipedia Code of Conduct Developers Statistics Cookie statement Mobile view

You might also like