Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 17

SOURCE: https://iep.utm.

edu/legalpos/#:~:text=Legal
%20positivism%20does%20not%20base,on%20the
%20content%20of%20law.
SEPARATION THESIS
For Garnder - Gardner claims, and rightly so in my mind, that the separation thesis pertains to
one, and only one, aspect of law: the conditions of legal validity. (Application, the hour rules of the
House or Congress conform with our 1987 Constitution, but it does not mean that the house rules of
Congress is part of our constitution.)

Example given in the material - Consider, for example, the norms governing the conduct of members of
Oxford University. They are legally valid norms, presumably enforceable in UK courts, but it would be
rather strange to say that Oxford University’s rules and regulations are part of UK law. Similarly, a
collective bargaining agreement between General Motors and its employees, is legally valid but not part
of US law

And it is this social, institutional aspect of law that creates a gap between legal validity and moral
validity.

A valid promise cannot be anything else but a morally valid promise; a legally valid norm or directive can
be morally invalid. In other words, promising is entirely a moral practice, whereas law is a social practice
with moral aspects.

Gardner clearly thinks that the only commitment legal positivists share or, at least, the only commitment
embodied in the separation thesis, is the idea that whatever makes it the case that something counts as
law is not merit-based.

When curators pick an object to exhibit in an art gallery they pick it because they think that it is a work of
art; they would not think that it becomes art because they have exhibited it in the gallery. But this is
precisely the point at which the analogy between law and art breaks down. In the legal case, institutional
recognition is constitutive of what is a legal norm. Legislatures do not enact something because they
think that it is law already; they make it law by enacting it.

But, as we have assumed here all along, the separation thesis is not about law’s normativity; it is only
about the conditions of legal validity.

The second way in which merit based consideration may bear on legal validity, which is much more
familiar to lawyers, is by way of explicit legal instruction. The clear cases are typically constitutional,
whereby the constitution renders unconstitutional, and thus not legally valid, certain norms that violate
moral-political principles, such as respect for freedom of speech or, human dignity, and such. In other
words, it seems that the law can incorporate, explicitly and perhaps sometimes implicitly, merit based
considerations as conditions on the legal validly of norms.29

”. It would seem that this constitutional provision makes the legal validity of certain norms depend on
the question of whether their content is such that they violate the moral-political right to free speech. If
an act of Congress violates freedom of speech it is not legally valid in the US. Or so it seems that the
Constitution prescribes. And of course, whether an act of Congress violates freedom of speech or not, is
a matter of moral-political argument, it depends on the law’s merit, as it were. But this portrayal of the
constitutional provision is misleading. What such constitutional provisions do, legally speaking, is grant
legal power to the courts, the legal power to strike down acts of the legislature if the court finds them in
violation of the 29 Cf Raz, Between Authority and Interpretation, ch 7. 20 rights to freedom of speech. To
see the difference, just bear in mind that an act of Congress that violates the freedom of speech is not
legally void unless, and until, a court with a final authority on the matter holds that it is.

Legal Positivism
Legal positivism is a philosophy of law that emphasizes the conventional nature of law—
that it is socially constructed. According to legal positivism, law is synonymous with
positive norms, that is, norms made by the legislator or considered as common law or
case law. Formal criteria of law’s origin, law enforcement and legal effectiveness are all
sufficient for social norms to be considered law. Legal positivism does not base law on
divine commandments, reason, or human rights. As an historical matter, positivism
arose in opposition to classical natural law theory, according to which there are necessary
moral constraints on the content of law.
Legal positivism does not imply an ethical justification for the content of the law, nor a
decision for or against the obedience to law. Positivists do not judge laws by questions of
justice or humanity, but merely by the ways in which the laws have been created. This
includes the view that judges make new law in deciding cases not falling clearly under a
legal rule. Practicing, deciding or tolerating certain practices of law can each be
considered a way of creating law.

Within legal doctrine, legal positivism would be opposed to sociological jurisprudence


and hermeneutics of law, which study the concrete prevailing circumstances of
statutory interpretation in society.
The word “positivism” was probably first used to draw attention to the idea that law is
“positive” or “posited,” as opposed to being “natural” in the sense of being derived from
natural law or morality.

Table of Contents
1. The Pedigree Thesis
2. The Separability Thesis
a. Inclusive vs. Exclusive Positivism
3. The Discretion Thesis
4. Classic Criticisms of Positivism
a. Fuller’s Internal Morality of Law
a. Positivism and Legal Principles
a. The Semantic Sting
5. References and Further Reading
1. The Pedigree Thesis
The pedigree thesis asserts that legal validity is a function of certain social facts.
Borrowing heavily from Jeremy Bentham, John Austin argues that the principal
distinguishing feature of a legal system is the presence of a sovereign who is habitually
obeyed by most people in the society, but not in the habit of obeying any determinate
human superior (Austin 1995, p. 166). On Austin’s view, a rule R is legally valid (that is,
is a law) in a society S if and only if R is commanded by the sovereign in S and is backed
up with the threat of a sanction. The severity of the threatened sanction is irrelevant;
any general sovereign imperative supported by a threat of even the smallest harm is a
law.
Austin’s command theory of law is vulnerable to a number of criticisms. One problem is
that there appears to be no identifiable sovereign in democratic societies. In the United
States, for example, the ultimate political power seems to belong to the people, who elect
lawmakers to represent their interests. Elected lawmakers have the power to coerce
behavior but are regarded as servants of the people and not as repositories of sovereign
power. The voting population, on the other hand, seems to be the repository of ultimate
political authority yet lacks the immediate power to coerce behavior. Thus, in
democracies like that of the United States, the ultimate political authority and the power
to coerce behavior seem to reside in different entities.

A second problem has to do with Austin’s view that the sovereign lawmaking authority is
incapable of legal limitation. On Austin’s view, a sovereign cannot be legally constrained
because no person (or body of persons) can coerce herself (or itself). Since constitutional
provisions limit the authority of the legislative body to make laws, Austin is forced to
argue that what we refer to as constitutional law is really not law at all; rather, it is
principally a matter of “positive morality” (Austin 1977, p. 107).

Austin’s view is difficult to reconcile with constitutional law in the United States. Courts
regard the procedural and substantive provisions of the constitution as constraints on
legal validity. The Supreme Court has held, for example, that “an unconstitutional act is
not a law; it confers no rights; it imposes no duties; it is, in legal contemplation, as
inoperative as though it had never been passed.” (Norton v. Shelby County, 118 U.S. 425
(1886)). Moreover, these constraints purport to be legal constraints: the Supremacy
Clause of Article VI of the Constitution states that “[t]his Constitution … shall be the
supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby.”
The most influential criticisms of Austin’s version of the pedigree thesis, however, owe
to H. L. A. Hart’s seminal work, The Concept of Law. Hart points out that Austin’s theory
provides, at best, a partial account of legal validity because it focuses on one kind of rule,
namely that which requires citizens “to do or abstain from certain actions, whether they
wish to or not” (Hart 1994, p. 81). While every legal system must contain so-called
primary rules that regulate citizen behavior, Hart believes a system consisting entirely of
the kind of liberty restrictions found in the criminal law is, at best, a rudimentary or
primitive legal system.
On Hart’s view, Austin’s emphasis on coercive force leads him to overlook the presence
of a second kind of primary rule that confers upon citizens the power to create, modify,
and extinguish rights and obligations in other persons. As Hart points out, the rules
governing the creation of contracts and wills cannot plausibly be characterized as
restrictions on freedom that are backed by the threat of a sanction. These rules empower
persons to structure their legal relations within the coercive framework of the law-a
feature that Hart correctly regards as one of “law’s greatest contributions to social life.”
The operation of power-conferring primary rules, according to Hart, indicates the
presence of a more sophisticated system for regulating behavior.

But what ultimately distinguishes societies with full-blown systems of law from those
with only rudimentary or primitive forms of law is that the former have, in addition to
first-order primary rules, secondary meta-rules that have as their subject matter the
primary rules themselves:

[Secondary rules] may all be said to be on a different level from the primary rules, for
they are all about such rules; in the sense that while primary rules are concerned with
the actions that individuals must or must not do, these secondary rules are all concerned
with the primary rules themselves. They specify the way in which the primary rules may
be conclusively ascertained, introduced, eliminated, varied, and the fact of their
violation conclusively determined (Hart 1994, p. 92).
Hart distinguishes three types of secondary rules that mark the transition from
primitive forms of law to full-blown legal systems: (1) the rule of recognition, which
“specif[ies] some feature or features possession of which by a suggested rule is taken as
a conclusive affirmative indication that it is a rule of the group to be supported by the
social pressure it exerts” (Hart 1994, p. 92); (2) the rule of change, which enables a
society to add, remove, and modify valid rules; and (3) the rule of adjudication, which
provides a mechanism for determining whether a valid rule has been violated. On Hart’s
view, then, every society with a full-blown legal system necessarily has a rule of
recognition that articulates criteria for legal validity that include provisions for making,
changing and adjudicating law. Law is, to use Hart’s famous phrase, “the union of
primary and secondary rules” (Hart 1994, p. 107). Austin theory fails, on Hart’s view,
because it fails to acknowledge the importance of secondary rules in manufacturing legal
validity.

Hart also finds fault with Austin’s view that legal obligation is essentially coercive.
According to Hart, there is no difference between the Austinian sovereign who governs
by coercing behavior and the gunman who orders someone to hand over her money. In
both cases, the subject can plausibly be characterized as being “obliged” to comply with
the commands, but not as being “duty-bound” or “obligated” to do so (Hart 1994, p. 80).
On Hart’s view, the application of coercive force alone can never give rise to an
obligation-legal or otherwise.

Legal rules are obligatory, according to Hart, because people accept them as standards
that justify criticism and, in extreme cases, punishment of deviations:

What is necessary is that there should be a critical reflective attitude to certain patterns
of behavior as a common standard, and that this should display itself in criticism
(including self-criticism), demands for conformity, and in acknowledgements that such
criticism and demands are justified, all of which find their characteristic expression in
the normative terminology of ‘ought’, ‘must’, and ‘should’, and ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ (Hart
1994, p. 56).
The subject who reflectively accepts the rule as providing a standard that justifies
criticism of deviations is said to take “the internal point of view” towards it.

On Hart’s view, it would be too much to require that the bulk of the population accept
the rule of recognition as the ultimate criteria for legal validity: “the reality of the
situation is that a great proportion of ordinary citizens-perhaps a majority-have no
general conception of the legal structure or its criteria of validity” (Hart 1994, p. 111).
Instead, Hart argues that what is necessary to the existence of a legal system is that the
majority of officials take the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition and
its criteria of validity. All that is required of citizens is that they generally obey the
primary rules that are legally valid according to the rule of recognition.

Thus, on Hart’s view, there are two minimum conditions sufficient and necessary for the
existence of a legal system: “On the one hand those rules of behavior which are valid
according to the system’s ultimate criteria of validity must be generally obeyed, and, on
the other hand, its rules of recognition specifying the criteria of legal validity and its
rules of change and adjudication must be effectively accepted as common public
standards of official behavior by its officials” (Hart 1994, p. 113).

Hart’s view is vulnerable to the same criticism that he levels against Austin. Hart rejects
Austin’s view because the institutional application of coercive force can no more give
rise to an obligation than can the application of coercive force by a gunman. But the
situation is no different if the gunman takes the internal point of view towards his
authority to make such a threat. Despite the gunman’s belief that he is entitled to make
the threat, the victim is obliged, but not obligated, to comply with the gunman’s orders.
The gunman’s behavior is no less coercive because he believes he is entitled to make the
threat.

Similarly, in the minimal legal system, only the officials of the legal system take the
internal point of view towards the rule of recognition that endows them with authority
to make, execute, adjudicate, and enforce the rules. The mere presence of a belief in the
officials that they are entitled to make law cannot give rise to an obligation in other
people to comply with their enactments any more than the presence of a belief on the
part of a gunman that he is entitled to issue orders gives rise to an obligation in the
victim to comply with those orders. Hart’s minimal legal system is no less coercive than
Austin’s legal system.

2. The Separability Thesis


The second thesis comprising the foundation of legal positivism is the separability
thesis. In its most general form, the separability thesis asserts that law and morality are
conceptually distinct. This abstract formulation can be interpreted in a number of ways.
For example, Klaus Faber (1996) interprets it as making a meta-level claim that the
definition of law must be entirely free of moral notions. This interpretation implies that
any reference to moral considerations in defining the related notions of law, legal
validity, and legal system is inconsistent with the separability thesis.

More commonly, the separability thesis is interpreted as making only an object-level


claim about the existence conditions for legal validity. As H.L.A. Hart describes it, the
separability thesis is no more than the “simple contention that it is in no sense a
necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality, though in
fact they have often done so” (Hart 1994, pp. 181-82). Insofar as the object-level
interpretation of the separability thesis denies it is a necessary truth that there are moral
constraints on legal validity, it implies the existence of a possible legal system in which
there are no moral constraints on legal validity.

a. Inclusive vs. Exclusive Positivism


Though all positivists agree there are possible legal systems without moral constraints
on legal validity, there are conflicting views on whether there are possible legal systems
with such constraints. According to inclusive positivism (also known as
incorporationism and soft positivism), it is possible for a society’s rule of recognition to
incorporate moral constraints on the content of law. Prominent inclusive positivists
include Jules Coleman and H.L.A. Hart, who maintains that “the rule of recognition may
incorporate as criteria of legal validity conformity with moral principles or substantive
values … such as the Sixteenth or Nineteenth Amendments to the United States
Constitution respecting the establishment of religion or abridgements of the right to
vote” (Hart 1994, p. 250).

In contrast, exclusive positivism (also called hard positivism) denies that a legal system
can incorporate moral constraints on legal validity. Exclusive positivists like Joseph Raz
(1979, p. 47) subscribe to the source thesis, according to which the existence and content
of law can always be determined by reference to its sources without recourse to moral
argument. On this view, the sources of law include both the circumstances of its
promulgation and relevant interpretative materials, such as court cases involving its
application.

At first glance, exclusive positivism may seem difficult to reconcile with what appear to
be moral criteria of legal validity in legal systems like that of the United States. For
example, the Fourth Amendment provides that “[t]he right of the people to be secure in
their persons, houses, papers, and effects against unreasonable searches and seizures,
shall not be violated.” Likewise, the First Amendment prohibits laws abridging the right
of free speech. Taken at face value, these amendments seem to make moral standards
part of the conditions for legal validity.

Exclusive positivists argue that such amendments can require judges to consider moral
standards in certain circumstances, but cannot incorporate those standards into the law.
When a judge makes reference to moral considerations in deciding a case, she
necessarily creates new law on an issue-and this is so even when the law directs her to
consider moral considerations, as the Bill of Rights does in certain circumstances. On
this view, all law is settled law and questions of settled law can be resolved without
recourse to moral arguments:

The law on a question is settled when legally binding sources provide its solution. In
such cases judges are typically said to apply the law, and since it is source-based, its
application involves technical, legal skills in reasoning from those sources and does not
call for moral acumen. If a legal question is not answered by standards deriving from
legal sources then it lacks a legal answer-the law on such questions is unsettled. In
deciding such cases courts inevitably break new (legal) ground and their decision
develops the law…. Naturally, their decisions in such cases rely at least partly on moral
and other extra-legal considerations (Raz 1979, pp. 49-50).
If the judge can resolve an issue involving the First Amendment merely by applying past
court decisions, then the issue is settled by the law; if not, then the issue is unsettled.
Insofar as the judge looks to controversial moral standards to resolve the issue, she is
going beyond the law because the mere presence of controversy about the law implies
that it is indeterminate. Thus, on Raz’s view, references to moral language in the law, at
most, direct judges to consider moral requirements in resolving certain unsettled
questions of law. They cannot incorporate moral requirements into the law.

3. The Discretion Thesis


Third thesis commonly associated with positivism is the discretion thesis, according to
which judges decide difficult cases by making new law in the exercise of discretion.
Ronald Dworkin describes this thesis as follows:

The set of these valid legal rules is exhaustive of ‘the law’, so that if someone’s case is not
clearly covered by such a rule . . . then that case cannot be decided by ‘applying the law.’
It must be decided by some official, like a judge, ‘exercising his discretion,’ which means
reaching beyond the law for some other sort of standard to guide him in manufacturing
a fresh legal rule or supplementing an old one (Dworkin 1977, p. 17).
On this view, a judge cannot decide a case that does not fall clearly under a valid rule by
interpreting or applying the law; she must decide the case by creating or promulgating a
law that did not exist prior to the adjudication. Thus, the discretion thesis implies that
judges are empowered with a quasi-legislative lawmaking authority in cases that cannot
be decided merely by applying law.

Though often associated with positivism, the discretion thesis does not belong to
positivism’s theoretical core. The pedigree and separability theses purport to be
conceptual claims that are true of every possible legal system. These two claims jointly
assert that, in every possible legal system, propositions of law are valid in virtue of
having been manufactured according to some set of social conventions. On this view,
there are no moral constraints on the content of law that hold in every possible legal
system.
But many positivists regard the discretion thesis as a contingent claim that is true of
some, but not all, possible legal systems. Hart, for example, believes there will inevitably
arise cases that do not fall clearly under a rule, but concedes a rule of recognition could
deny judges discretion to make law in such cases by requiring judges “to disclaim
jurisdiction or to refer the points not regulated by the existing law to the legislature to
decide” (Hart 1994, p. 272). Indeed, Hart’s inclusive positivism allows him to hold that a
rule of recognition could require judges to decide cases in precisely the manner that
Dworkin advocates (Hart 1994, p. 263; and see Section IV-2, infra). Thus, at least for
inclusive positivists like Hart, the discretion thesis makes a different kind of claim than
the conceptual claims that form positivism’s theoretical core (Himma 1999).
Moreover, the discretion thesis is consistent with some forms of natural law theory.
According to Blackstone’s classical naturalism, conformity with the natural law is a
necessary condition for legal validity in every possible legal system. But insofar as the
natural law is incomplete, there will inevitably arise issues that have multiple outcomes
consistent with the natural law. Since none of the relevant outcomes in such cases
offend the natural law, there is nothing in the assumption of necessary moral
constraints on the content of law, in and of itself, that precludes Blackstone from
endorsing the discretion thesis in such cases. Of course, if Blackstone believes the
natural law contains a principle denying discretion to judges, then that commitment is
inconsistent with the discretion thesis. But the assertion there are necessary constraints
on the content of law, in and of itself, is consistent with the discretion thesis, even
construed as a conceptual claim, as long as there are cases to which the natural law is
indifferent.
In any event, Dworkin distinguishes three different senses in which a judge might be
said to have discretion: (1) a judge has discretion when she exercises judgment in
applying a legal standard to a particular case; (2) a judge has discretion when her
decision is not subject to reversal by any other authority; and (3) a judge has discretion
when her decision is not bound by any legal standards.

According to Dworkin, positivism’s discretion thesis is committed to the third sense of


discretion, which he refers to as strong discretion. On Dworkin’s view, the thesis that
judges have discretion only in the sense that they exercise judgment is trivially true,
while the thesis that judges have discretion in the sense that their decisions are not
subject to being reversed by a higher authority is false. Even the Supreme Court can be
reversed by Congress or by constitutional amendment. Thus, on Dworkin’s view, the
discretion thesis implies that judges have discretion to decide hard cases by what
amounts to an act of legislation because the judge is not bound by any legal standards.

Thus construed, the discretion thesis is inconsistent with ordinary legal practice. Even
in the most difficult of cases where there is no clearly applicable law, lawyers do not ask
that the judge decide the relevant issue by making new law. Each lawyer cites cases
favorable to her client’s position and argues that the judge is bound by those cases to
decide in her client’s favor. As a practical matter, lawyers rarely, if ever, concede there
are no legal standards governing a case and ask the judge to legislate in the exercise of
discretion.
Nevertheless, the problem with Dworkin’s analysis is that it falsely presupposes an
official cannot make new law unless there are no legal standards constraining the
official’s decision. Indeed, lawmaking authorities in legal systems like the U.S. never
have what Dworkin describes as strong discretion. Even the legislative decisions of
Congress, the highest legislative authority in the nation, are always constrained by
constitutional standards. For example, under the Fourteenth Amendment, Congress
cannot enact a law that sets one speed limit for male drivers on interstate highways and
another for female drivers.

For his part, Hart concedes that judicial lawmaking authority is limited in two respects:
“not only are the judge’s powers subject to many constraints narrowing his choice from
which a legislature may be quite free, but since the judge’s powers are exercised only to
dispose of particular instant cases he cannot use these to introduce large-scale reforms
or new codes” (Hart 1994, p. 273). What explains the judge’s discretion to make new law
in a given case, on Hart’s view, is not the absence of legal standards constraining her
decision; rather it is the absence of legal standards that dictate a uniquely correct
answer to the case. The judge cannot decide such a case merely by applying existing law
because there is more than one available outcome that coheres with existing law. In such
instances, it is impossible to render a substantive decision (as opposed to simply
referring the matter back to the legislature) without creating new law.
The discretion thesis is vulnerable to one powerful objection. Insofar as a judge decides
a difficult case by making new law in the exercise of discretion, the case is being decided
on the basis of a law that did not exist at the time the dispute arose. If, for example, a
judge awards damages to a plaintiff by making new law in the exercise of discretion, it
follows that she has held the defendant liable under a law that did not exist at the time
the dispute arose. And, as Dworkin points out, it seems patently unfair to deprive a
defendant of property for behavior that did not give rise to liability at the time the
behavior occurred.

Nevertheless, Dworkin’s view fares no better on this count. While Dworkin


acknowledges the existence of difficult cases that do not fall clearly under a rule, he
believes they are not resolved by an exercise of judicial discretion. On Dworkin’s view,
there is always a right answer to such cases implicit in the pre-existing law. Of course, it
sometimes takes a judge of Herculean intellectual ability to discern what the right
answer is, but it is always there to be found in pre-existing law. Since the right answer to
even hard legal disputes is always part of pre-existing law, Dworkin believes that a judge
can take property from a defendant in a hard case without unfairness (Dworkin 1977,
pp. 87-130).

But if fairness precludes taking property from a defendant under a law that did not exist
at the time of the relevant behavior, it also precludes taking property from a defendant
under a law that did not give reasonable notice that the relevant behavior gives rise to
liability. Due process and fundamental fairness require reasonable notice of which
behaviors give rise to liability. As long as Dworkin acknowledges the existence of cases
so difficult that only the best of judges can solve them, his theory is vulnerable to the
same charge of unfairness that he levels at the discretion thesis.
4. Classic Criticisms of Positivism
a. Fuller’s Internal Morality of Law
In The Morality of Law, Lon L. Fuller argues that law is subject to an internal morality
consisting of eight principles: (P1) the rules must be expressed in general terms; (P2)
the rules must be publicly promulgated; (P3) the rules must be (for the most part)
prospective in effect; (P4) the rules must be expressed in understandable terms; (P5) the
rules must be consistent with one another; (P6) the rules must not require conduct
beyond the powers of the affected parties; (P7) the rules must not be changed so
frequently that the subject cannot rely on them; and (P8) the rules must be
administered in a manner consistent with their wording (Fuller 1964, p. 39).
On Fuller’s view, no system of rules that fails minimally to satisfy these principles of
legality can achieve law’s essential purpose of achieving social order through the use of
rules that guide behavior. A system of rules that fails to satisfy (P2) or (P4), for example,
cannot guide behavior because people will not be able to determine what the rules
require. Accordingly, Fuller concludes that his eight principles are “internal” to law in
the sense that they are built into the existence conditions for law: “A total failure in any
one of these eight directions does not simply result in a bad system of law; it results in
something that is not properly called a legal system at all” (Fuller 1964, p. 39).

These internal principles constitute a morality, according to Fuller, because law


necessarily has positive moral value in two respects: (1) law conduces to a state of social
order and (2) does so by respecting human autonomy because rules guide behavior.
Since no system of rules can achieve these morally valuable objectives without
minimally complying with the principles of legality, it follows, on Fuller’s view, that they
constitute a morality. Since these moral principles are built into the existence conditions
for law, they are internal and hence represent a conceptual connection between law and
morality that is inconsistent with the separability thesis.
Hart responds by denying Fuller’s claim that the principles of legality constitute an
internal morality; on Hart’s view, Fuller confuses the notions of morality and efficacy:

[T]he author’s insistence on classifying these principles of legality as a “morality” is a


source of confusion both for him and his readers…. [T]he crucial objection to the
designation of these principles of good legal craftsmanship as morality, in spite of the
qualification “inner,” is that it perpetrates a confusion between two notions that it is
vital to hold apart: the notions of purposive activity and morality. Poisoning is no doubt
a purposive activity, and reflections on its purpose may show that it has its internal
principles. (“Avoid poisons however lethal if they cause the victim to vomit”….) But to
call these principles of the poisoner’s art “the morality of poisoning” would simply blur
the distinction between the notion of efficiency for a purpose and those final judgments
about activities and purposes with which morality in its various forms is concerned
(Hart 1965, pp. 1285-86).
On Hart’s view, all actions, including virtuous acts like lawmaking and impermissible
acts like poisoning, have their own internal standards of efficacy. But insofar as such
standards of efficacy conflict with morality, as they do in the case of poisoning, it follows
that they are distinct from moral standards. Thus, while Hart concedes that something
like Fuller’s eight principles are built into the existence conditions for law, he concludes
that they do not constitute a conceptual connection between law and morality.

Unfortunately, Hart’s response overlooks the fact that most of Fuller’s eight principles
double as moral ideals of fairness. For example, public promulgation in understandable
terms may be a necessary condition for efficacy, but it is also a moral ideal; it is morally
objectionable for a state to enforce rules that have not been publicly promulgated in
terms reasonably calculated to give notice of what is required. Similarly, we take it for
granted that it is wrong for a state to enact retroactive rules, inconsistent rules, and
rules that require what is impossible. Poisoning may have its internal standards of
efficacy, but such standards are distinguishable from the principles of legality in that
they conflict with moral ideals.

Nevertheless, Fuller’s principles operate internally, not as moral ideals, but merely as
principles of efficacy. As Fuller would likely acknowledge, the existence of a legal system
is consistent with considerable divergence from the principles of legality. Legal
standards, for example, are necessarily promulgated in general terms that inevitably
give rise to problems of vagueness. And officials all too often fail to administer the laws
in a fair and even-handed manner-even in the best of legal systems. These divergences
may always be prima facie objectionable, but they are inconsistent with a legal system
only when they render a legal system incapable of performing its essential function of
guiding behavior. Insofar as these principles are built into the existence conditions for
law, it is because they operate as efficacy conditions-and not because they function as
moral ideals.
Fuller’s jurisprudential legacy, however, should not be underestimated. While positivists
have long acknowledged that law’s essential purpose is to guide behavior through rules
(e.g., John Austin writes that “[a] law .. may be defined as a rule laid down for the
guidance of an intelligent being by an intelligent being having power over him” Austin
1977, p. 5), they have not always appreciated the implications of this purpose. Fuller’s
lasting contribution to the theory of law was to flesh out these implications in the form
of his principles of legality.

b. Positivism and Legal Principles


Dworkin argues that, in deciding hard cases, judges often invoke legal principles that do
not derive their authority from an official act of promulgation (Dworkin 1977, p. 40).
These principles, Dworkin believes, must be characterized as law because judges are
bound to consider them when relevant. But if unpromulgated legal principles constitute
law, then it is false, contra the pedigree thesis, that a proposition of law is valid only in
virtue of having been formally promulgated.
According to Dworkin, principles and rules differ in the kind of guidance they provide to
judges:

Rules are applicable in an all-or-nothing fashion. If the facts a rule stipulates are given,
then either the rule is valid, in which case the answer it supplies must be accepted, or it
is not, in which case it contributes nothing to the decision…. But this is not the way
principles operate…. [A principle] states a reason that argues in one direction, but does
not necessitate a particular decision (Dworkin 1977, pp. 24-25).
On Dworkin’s view, conflicting principles provide competing reasons that must be
weighed according to the importance of the respective values they express. Thus, rules
are distinguishable from principles in two related respects: (1) rules necessitate, where
principles only suggest, a particular outcome; and (2) principles have, where rules lack,
the dimension of weight.

Dworkin cites the case of Riggs v. Palmer as representative of how judges use principles
to decide hard cases. In Riggs, the court considered the question of whether a murderer
could take under the will of his victim. At the time the case was decided, neither the
statutes nor the case law governing wills expressly prohibited a murderer from taking
under his victim’s will. Despite this, the court declined to award the defendant his gift
under the will on the ground that it would be wrong to allow him to profit from such a
grievous wrong. On Dworkin’s view, the court decided the case by citing “the principle
that no man may profit from his own wrong as a background standard against which to
read the statute of wills and in this way justified a new interpretation of that statute”
(Dworkin 1977, p. 29).
The positivist might respond that when the Riggs court considered this principle, it was
reaching beyond the law to extralegal standards in the exercise of judicial discretion. But
Dworkin points out that the Riggs judges would “rightfully” have been criticized had they
failed to consider this principle; if it were merely an extralegal standard, there would be
no rightful grounds to criticize a failure to consider it (Dworkin 1977, p. 35).
Accordingly, Dworkin concludes that the best explanation for the propriety of such
criticism is that principles are part of the law.
Further, Dworkin maintains that the legal authority of standards like the Riggs principle
cannot derive from promulgation in accordance with purely formal requirements:
“[e]ven though principles draw support from the official acts of legal institutions, they
do not have a simple or direct enough connection with these acts to frame that
connection in terms of criteria specified by some ultimate master rule of recognition”
(Dworkin 1977, p. 41). Unlike legal rules, legal principles lack a canonical form and
hence cannot be explained by formal promulgation.
On Dworkin’s view, the legal authority of a binding principle derives from the
contribution it makes to the best moral justification for a society’s legal practices
considered as a whole. According to Dworkin, a legal principle maximally contributes to
such a justification if and only if it satisfies two conditions: (1) the principle coheres with
existing legal materials; and (2) the principle is the most morally attractive standard
that satisfies (1). The correct legal principle is the one that makes the law the moral best
it can be. Thus, Dworkin concludes, “if we treat principles as law we must reject the
positivists’ first tenet, that the law of a community is distinguished from other social
standards by some test in the form of a master rule” (Dworkin 1977, p. 44).

In response, positivists concede that there are legal principles, but argue that their
authority as law can be explained in terms of the conventions contained in the rule of
recognition:
Legal principles, like other laws, can be enacted or repealed by legislatures and
administrative authorities. They can also become legally binding through establishment
by the courts. Many legal systems recognize that both rules and principles can be made
into law or lose their status as law through precedent (Raz 1972, p. 848).
According to this view, legal principles are like legal rules in that both derive their
authority under the rule of recognition from the official acts of courts and legislatures. If
the Riggs principle that no person shall profit from her own wrong has legal authority, it
is because that principle was either declared by a court in the course of adjudicating a
dispute or formally promulgated by the appropriate legislative body.
Further, inclusive positivists argue that Dworkin’s account of principles is itself
consistent with the pedigree thesis. As Hart puts it, “this interpretative test seems not to
be an alternative to a criterion provided by a rule of recognition, but … only a complex
‘soft-positivist’ form of such a criterion identifying principles by their content not by
their pedigree” (Hart 1994, p. 263). The idea, familiar from Section II, is that a rule of
recognition can incorporate content-based constraints on legal validity, even those
rooted ultimately in morality.

c. The Semantic Sting


In Law’s Empire, Dworkin distinguishes two kinds of disagreement legal practitioners
can have about the law. Lawyers can agree on the criteria a rule must satisfy to be legally
valid, but disagree on whether those criteria are satisfied by a particular rule. For
example, two lawyers might agree that a rule is valid if enacted by the state legislature,
but disagree on whether the rule at issue was actually enacted by the state legislature.
Such disagreements are empirical in nature and hence pose no theoretical difficulties for
positivism.
There is, however, a second kind of disagreement that Dworkin believes is inconsistent
with positivism. Lawyers often agree on the facts about a rule’s creation, but disagree on
whether those facts are sufficient to endow the rule with legal authority. Such
disagreement is considerably deeper than empirical disagreement as it concerns the
criteria for legal validity-which, according to positivism, are exhausted by the rule of
recognition. Dworkin calls this second kind of disagreement theoretical disagreement
about the law.

Theoretical disagreement, on Dworkin’s view, is inconsistent with the pedigree thesis


because the pedigree thesis explains the concept of law in terms of shared criteria for
creating, changing and adjudicating law:

If legal argument is mainly or even partly about [the properties that make a proposition
legally valid], then lawyers cannot all be using the same factual criteria for deciding
when propositions of law are true and false. Their arguments would be mainly or partly
about which criteria they should use. So the project of the semantic theories, the project
of digging out shared rules from a careful study of what lawyers say and do, would be
doomed to fail (Dworkin 1986, p. 43).
If lawyers disagree about the criteria of legal validity, then the grounds of legal validity
cannot be exhausted by the shared criteria contained in a rule of recognition. The
semantic sting, then, implies that there must be more to the concept of legal validity
than can be explained by promulgation in accordance with shared criteria embodied in a
rule of recognition.

The semantic sting resembles one of Dworkin’s earlier criticisms of Hart’s pedigree
thesis. Hart believes that the rule of recognition is a social rule and is hence constituted
by the conforming behavior of people who also accept the rule as a ground for criticizing
deviations. Like all social rules, then, the rule of recognition has an external and internal
aspect. The external aspect of the rule of recognition consists in general obedience to
those rules satisfying its criteria of validity; the internal aspect is constituted by its
acceptance as a public standard of official behavior. Hart believes it is this double aspect
of the rule of recognition that accounts for its normativity and enables him to
distinguish his theory from Austin’s view of law as a system of coercive commands. For,
as Hart points out, a purely coercive command can oblige, but never obligate, a person
to comply (see Section I, supra).
Dworkin argues that this feature of Hart’s theory commits him to the claim that there
cannot be any disagreement about the content of rule of recognition:

Hart’s qualification … that the rule of recognition may be uncertain at particular points
… undermines [his theory]…. If judges are in fact divided about what they must do if a
subsequent Parliament tries to repeal an entrenched rule, then it is not uncertain
whether any social rule [of recognition] governs that decision; on the contrary, it is
certain that none does (Dworkin 1977, pp. 61-62).
On Dworkin’s view, the requirements of a social rule cannot be uncertain since a social
rule is constituted by acceptance and conforming behavior by most people in the
relevant group: “two people whose rules differ … cannot be appealing to the same social
rule, and at least one of them cannot be appealing to any social rule at all” (Dworkin
1977, p. 55).

Jules Coleman responds that if the rule of recognition is a social rule, then Hart’s view
implies there must be general agreement among the officials of a legal system about
what standards constitute the rule of recognition, but it does not imply there cannot be
disagreement as to what those standards require in any given instance:

The controversy among judges does not arise over the content of the rule of recognition
itself. It arises over which norms satisfy the standards set forth in it. The divergence in
behavior among officials as exemplified in their identifying different standards as legal
ones does not establish their failure to accept the same rule of recognition. On the
contrary, judges accept the same truth conditions for propositions of law…. They
disagree about which propositions satisfy those conditions (Coleman 1982, p. 156).
Coleman, then, distinguishes two kinds of disagreement practitioners can have about
the rule of recognition: (1) disagreement about what standards constitute the rule of
recognition; and (2) disagreement about what propositions satisfy those standards. On
Coleman’s view, Hart’s analysis of social rules implies only that (1) is impossible.

Under the U.S. rule of recognition, for example, a federal statute is legally valid if and
only if it has been enacted in accordance with the procedural requirements described in
the body of the Constitution and is consistent with the first fourteen amendments.
Since, on Hart’s view, the U.S. rule of recognition is a social rule, U.S. officials must
agree on the procedures the federal government must follow in enacting law, the set of
sentences constituting the first fourteen amendments, and the requirement that federal
enactments be consistent with those amendments.

But Hart’s view of social rules does not imply there cannot be any disagreement about
whether a given enactment is consistent with the first fourteen amendments. Legal
practitioners can and do disagree on what Hart calls penumbral (or borderline) issues
regarding the various amendments. While every competent practitioner in the U.S.
would agree, for example, that torturing a person to induce a confession violates the
fifth amendment right against self-incrimination, there is considerable disagreement
about whether compelling a defendant to undergo a psychiatric examination for the
purpose of increasing her sentence also violates that right. On Coleman’s view, there is
nothing in Hart’s analysis of social rules that precludes such borderline disagreements
about whether a practice is consistent with the Fifth Amendment.

Despite its resemblance to this earlier criticism, Dworkin’s semantic sting argument
takes aim at a deeper target. The semantic sting targets all so-called semantic theories of
law that articulate the concept of law in terms of “shared rules … that set out criteria that
supply the word’s meaning” (Dworkin 1986, p. 31). Thus, while the earlier criticism is
directed at Hart’s extraneous account of social rules, the semantic sting is directed at
what Dworkin takes to be the very heart of positivism’s theoretical core, namely, the
claim that there are shared criteria that exhaust the conditions for the correct
application of the concept of law.

At the root of the problem with semantic theories, on Dworkin’s view, is a flawed theory
of what makes disagreement possible. According to Dworkin, semantic theories
mistakenly assume that meaningful disagreement is impossible unless “we all accept
and follow the same criteria for deciding when our claims are sound, even if we cannot
state exactly, as a philosopher might hope to do, what these criteria are” (Dworkin 1986,
p. 45). On this flawed assumption, two people whose concepts of law differ cannot be
disagreeing about the same thing.

Perhaps with Coleman’s response to his earlier criticism in mind, Dworkin concedes
that semantic theories are consistent with theoretical disagreements about borderline or
penumbral cases: “people do sometimes speak at cross-purposes in the way the
borderline defense describes” (Dworkin 1986, p. 41). But Dworkin denies semantic
theories are consistent with theoretical disagreement about pivotal (or core) cases.
According to semantic theories, he says,
[Y]ou and I can sensibly discuss how many books I have on my shelf, for example, only if
we both agree, at least roughly, about what a book is. We can disagree over borderline
cases: I may call something a slim book that you would call a pamphlet. But we cannot
disagree over what I called pivotal cases. If you do not count my copy of Moby-Dick as a
book because in your view novels are not books, any disagreement is bound to be
senseless (Dworkin 1986, p. 45).
The problem, on Dworkin’s view, is that many difficult appellate cases like Riggs involve
theoretical disagreement about pivotal cases:
The various judges who argued about our sample cases did not think they were
defending marginal or borderline claims. Their disagreements about legislation and
precedent were fundamental; their arguments showed that they disagreed not only
about whether Elmer should have his inheritance, but about why any legislative act,
even traffic codes and rates of taxation, impose the rights and obligations everyone
agrees they do…. They disagreed about what makes a proposition of law true not just at
the margin but in the core as well (Dworkin 1986, pp. 42-43).
On Dworkin’s view, the judges in Riggs were not having a borderline dispute about some
accepted criterion for the application of the concept of law. Rather, they were having a
disagreement about the status of some putatively fundamental criterion itself: the
majority believed, while the dissent denied, that courts have power to modify
unambiguous legislative enactments.
Accordingly, theoretical disagreement about pivotal cases like Riggs is inconsistent with
semantic theories of law, on Dworkin’s view, because it shows that shared criteria do not
exhaust the proper conditions for the application of the concept of law. For the majority
and dissenting judges in Riggs were having a sensible disagreement about law even
though it centered on a pivotal case involving the criteria of legal validity. Thus,
Dworkin concludes, the concept of law cannot be explained by so-called criterial
semantics.
In response, Hart denies both that his theory is a semantic theory and that it assumes
such an account of what makes disagreement possible:

[N]othing in my book or in anything else I have written supports [a semantic account] of


my theory. Thus, my doctrine that developed municipal legal systems contain a rule of
recognition specifying the criteria for the identification of the laws which courts have to
apply may be mistaken, but I nowhere base this doctrine on the mistaken idea that it is
part of the meaning of the word ‘law’ that there should be such a rule of recognition in
all legal systems, or on the even more mistaken idea that if the criteria for the
identification of the grounds of law were not uncontroversially fixed, ‘law’ would mean
different things to different people (Hart 1994, p. 246).
Instead, Hart argues that his theory of law is “a descriptive account of the distinctive
features of law in general as a complex social phenomenon” (Hart 1994, p. 246). Hart
presents his theory, not as an account of how people apply the concept of law, but rather
as an account of what distinguishes systems of law from other systems of social rules.
On Hart’s view, it is the presence of a rule of recognition establishing criteria of validity
that distinguishes law from other systems of social rules. Thus, according to Hart,
Dworkin’s criticism fails because it mischaracterizes positivism as providing a criterial
explanation of the concept of law.

5. References and Further Reading


 Austin, John, Lectures on Jurisprudence and the Philosophy of Positive Law (St. Clair Shores, MI:
Scholarly Press, 1977)
 Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1995)
 Bentham, Jeremy, Of Laws In General (London: Athlone Press, 1970)
 Blackstone, William, Commentaries on the Law of England (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1979)Dworkin, Ronald M., Law’s Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986)
 Dworkin, Ronald M., Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977)
 Finnis, John, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)
 Fuller, Lon L., The Morality of Law, Revised Edition (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1969)
 Fuller, Lon L., “Positivism and Fidelity to Law–A Reply to Professor Hart,” 71 Harvard Law
Review 630 (1958)
 Faber, Klaus, “Farewell to ‘Legal Positivism’: The Separation Thesis Unraveling,” in George, Robert
P., The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 119-162
 George, Robert P., “Natural Law and Positive Law,” in George, Robert P., The Autonomy of Law:
Essays on Legal Positivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 321-334
 Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law, Second Edition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)
 Hart, H.L.A., “American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream,”
reprinted in Hart, H.L.A., Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983),
123-144.
 Hart, H.L.A., “Book Review of The Morality of Law” 78 Harvard Law Review 1281 (1965)
 Hart, H.L.A., Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982)
 Hart, H.L.A., “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” 71 Harvard Law Review 593
(1958)
 Himma, Kenneth E., “Judicial Discretion and the Concept of Law,” forthcoming in Oxford Journal of
Legal Studies vol. 18, no. 1 (1999)
 Mackie, J.L., “The Third Theory of Law,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, vol. 7, no. 1 (Fall 1977)
 Moore, Michael, “Law as a Functional Kind,” in George, Robert P. (ed.), Natural Law Theory:
Contemporary Essays (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 188-242
 Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979)
 Raz, Joseph, “Authority, Law and Morality,” The Monist, vol. 68, 295-324
 Raz, Joseph, “Legal Principles and the Limits of Law,” 81 Yale Law Review 823 (1972)
 Raz, Joseph, “Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison,” Legal Theory,
vol. 4, no. 3 (September 1998), 249-282
 Waluchow, W.J., Inclusive Legal Positivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)

You might also like