Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Ecological Economics 22 (1997) 261 – 266

FORUM
Georgescu-Roegen versus Solow/Stiglitz

Herman E. Daly
School of Public Affairs, Uni!ersity of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742 -1821, USA

Received 23 September 1996; accepted 25 February 1997

In his Richard T. Ely Lecture to the American What evidence does Solow offer for this re-
Economics Association, Robert Solow (Solow, markable affirmation about the way the world
1974, 11) stated that ‘‘If it is very easy to substi- works? In the next paragraph he says, ‘‘Fortu-
tute other factors for natural resources, then there nately, what little evidence there is suggests that
is in principle no ‘problem’. The world can, in there is quite a lot of substitutability between
effect, get along without natural resources…’’ As exhaustible resources and renewable or repro-
an ‘if-then’ statement, this is no less true than ducible resources…’’ True enough, but irrelevant.
saying, ‘If wishes were horses then beggars would The issue is not substitution between two types of
ride’. But the facts are that wishes are not horses, natural resource, rather it is one of substitution of
and that natural resources and capital are gener- capital for resources, an entirely different matter.
ally not substitutes, but complements. While it is
Easy substitution between two types of natural
no doubt useful to state this conditional possibil-
resource will not help the world to get along
ity for the sake of logical completeness in catalog-
without natural resources!
ing alternatives, one would expect that the
Since the production function is often explained
production-without-resources case, once recog-
nized, would be quickly set aside as unrealistic as a technical recipe, we might say that Solow’s
and unworthy of further analysis. However, recipe calls for making a cake with only the cook
Solow does not set it aside, but retains it as a real and his kitchen. We do not need flour, eggs,
possibility. In fact, it is precisely this ‘real possibil- sugar, etc., nor electricity or natural gas, nor even
ity’ that has provided the foundation for a signifi- firewood. If we want a bigger cake, the cook
cant part of his previous work. His well-known simply stirs faster in a bigger bowl and cooks the
work in growth theory is based on an aggregate empty bowl in a bigger oven that somehow heats
production function in which resources do not itself. Nor does the cook have any cleaning up to
appear at all, and which takes production to be a do, because the production recipe produces no
function only of capital and labor. That produc- wastes. There are no rinds, peelings, husks, shells,
tion function is a mathematically clear way of or residues, nor is there any waste heat from the
saying that ‘the world can, in effect, get along oven to be vented. Furthermore, we can make not
without natural resources’. only a cake, but any kind of dish—a gumbo, fried

0921-8009/97/$17.00 © 1997 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.


PII S 0 9 2 1 - 8 0 0 9 ( 9 7 ) 0 0 0 8 0 - 3
262 H.E. Daly / Ecological Economics 22 (1997) 261–266

chicken, a paella, bananas foster, cherries ju- This shows that R may be as small as we wish,
bilee —all without worrying about the qualita- provided K is sufficiently large. Ergo, we can
tively different ingredients, or even about the obtain a constant annual product indefinitely
quantity of any ingredient at all! Real recipes in even from a very small stock of resources R!
real cookbooks, by contrast, begin with a list of 0, if we decompose R into an infinite series
specific ingredients and amounts. R =!Ri, with Ri " 0, use Ri in year i, and
A technical production recipe that contradicts increase the stock of capital each year as re-
both the first and second laws of thermodynamics, quired by (2). But this ‘ergo’ is not valid in
as well as best practice in cooking, is more than a actuality. In actuality, the increase of capital
little troubling. It led Georgescu-Roegen to the implies an additional depletion of resources.
following verdict on Solow: And if K" #, then R will rapidly be exhausted
by the production of capital. Solow and Stiglitz
One must have a very erroneous view of the could not have come out with their conjuring
economic process as a whole not to see that trick had they borne in mind, first, that any
there are no material factors other than natural material process consists in the transformation
resources. To maintain further that ‘the world of some materials into others (the flow ele-
can, in effect, get along without natural re- ments) by some agents (the fund elements), and
sources’ is to ignore the difference between the second, that natural resources are the very sap
actual world and the Garden of Eden of the economic process. They are not just like
(Georgescu-Roegen, 1975, 361). any other production factor. A change in capi-
tal or labor can only diminish the amount of
Perhaps as an unacknowledged concession to waste in the production of a commodity: no
Georgescu-Roegen’s criticism, we find some years agent can create the material on which it works.
later a new version of the production function in Nor can capital create the stuff out of which it
which resources appear along with labor and cap- is made. In some cases it may also be that the
ital, all multiplied together in a Cobb – Douglas same service can be provided by a design that
function. Georgescu-Roegen labeled this the requires less matter or energy. But even in this
‘Solow–Stiglitz variant’, and showed that includ- direction there exists a limit, unless we believe
ing R (resources) in this type of production func- that the ultimate fate of the economic process is
tion simply sweeps the contradiction under the an earthly Garden of Eden. The question that
rug, without removing it. confronts us today is whether we are going to
Georgescu-Roegen deserves to be quoted at discover new sources of energy that can be
length on this point. He writes the ‘Solow – Stiglitz safely used. No elasticities of some Cobb–Dou-
variant’ of the Cobb – Douglas function as: glas function can help us to answer it
(Georgescu-Roegen, 1979, 98) (See also Stiglitz,
Q = K a1R a2L a3 (1) 1979, 41, fn 5).

where Q is output, K is the stock of capital, R To my knowledge neither Solow nor Stiglitz has
is the flow of natural resources used in produc- ever replied to Georgescu-Roegen’s critique. What
tion, L is the labor supply, and a1 +a2 +a3 = 1 reply could they make? Let us consider a few
and of course, ai !0. From this formula it possibilities that others have put forward in simi-
follows that with a constant labor power, L0, lar contexts.
one could obtain any Q0, if the flow of natural First, it might be argued that resources can be
resources satisfies the condition left out of the production function because they
are not really scarce. Air is usually necessary for
production, but we do not explicitly enter it in the
Q0 function because it is considered a free good. This
R a2 = (2)
K L a03
a1
argument loses plausibility as soon as we remem-
H.E. Daly / Ecological Economics 22 (1997) 261–266 263

ber that most resources are not free goods. Fur- animus of neoclassical theory, which is to deny
thermore, we cannot logically use price, even a any important role to nature.2
zero price, as a coefficient of factors in the pro- The Solow-Stiglitz variant includes resources
duction function. The production function is a explicitly, but implicitly makes a similar assump-
technical recipe with all terms in physical units, tion about near perfect substitution of capital for
not value units.1 The fact that aggregate produc- resources—what Georgescu-Roegen aptly dis-
tion functions must use prices as weights in calcu- missed as a ‘conjuring trick’. In the Solow-Stiglitz
lating an aggregate quantity index (dollar’s worth) variant, to make a cake we need not only the
of capital (or labor or resources) is a fundamental cook and his kitchen, but also some non-zero
problem that limits the usefulness of aggregate amount of flour, sugar, eggs, etc. This seems a
production functions, not an answer to the great step forward until we realize that we could
difficulty just raised. Also, expressing the quanti- make our cake a thousand times bigger with no
ties of different factors in units of the same nu- extra ingredients, if we simply would stir faster
meraire reflects an assumption, not a and use bigger bowls and ovens. The conjuring
demonstration, that the factors are substitutes. trick is to give the appearance of respecting the
Second, it is sometimes argued that leaving first law of thermodynamics (material balance)
resources out of the production function is without really doing so.
justified by the implicit assumption that resources Another argument for the unimportance of re-
can be perfectly substituted by reproducible capi- sources was offered in the influential book
tal. Nordhaus and Tobin (1972) are quite explicit: Scarcity and Growth, (Barnett and Morse, 1963,
‘‘The prevailing standard model of growth as- 11) where it was argued that ‘‘Advances in funda-
sumes that there are no limits on the feasibility of mental science have made it possible to take
expanding the supplies of nonhuman agents of advantage of the uniformity of matter/energy, a
production. It is basically a two-factor model in uniformity that makes it feasible without pre-
which production depends only on labor and assignable limit, to escape the quantitative con-
reproducible capital. Land and resources, the straints imposed by the character of the earth’s
third member of the classical triad, have generally crust… Nature imposes particular scarcities, not
been dropped… the tacit justification has been an inescapable general scarcity.’’ Just below the
that reproducible capital is a near perfect substi- surface lies the alchemist’s dream of converting
tute for land and other exhaustible resources.’’ If lead into gold. All we need from nature are
that were the case then we could equally well uniform, indestructible building blocks—the al-
leave out capital and include natural resources chemical ‘quintessence’ or ‘fifth essence’ to which
(substitution is reversible), yet no one suggests the traditional four essences (earth, air, fire, and
doing that (for related discussion, see Victor, water) are thought to be reducible, and through
1991). To do that would run counter to the whole which they become convertible one into the other.

1 2
To see why this must be so, recall the following chain of Acceptance of the dogma that nature makes no contribu-
derivations. From the production function we derive the cost tion to production allows some neoclassical economists to
function by introducing factor prices, and from the cost func- assume that any increase in production not explained by
tion we derive the supply curve by introducing a schedule of increases in labor or capital must be the result of some other
product prices. From the utility function we derive the demand humanly created factor, namely technology. Such economists
curve with the aid of an introduced schedule of product prices. do not flinch from claiming that a 50% unexplained residual
The interaction of supply and demand simultaneously deter- must really be a measure of technological progress (human
mines equilibrium prices and quantities. If we already have ingenuity). In fact the residual is a measure of everything that
those prices included in either the production or utility func- is not labor and capital, including, of course, natural re-
tions then we are assuming from the beginning that which sources. To make matters worse, as Georgescu-Roegen
ultimately is to be explained. Simultaneous determination by pointed out, capital and labor themselves have a necessary and
supply and demand is one thing, but circular reasoning is significant resource content from which neoclassical produc-
something else. tion functions totally abstract.
264 H.E. Daly / Ecological Economics 22 (1997) 261–266

Given the building blocks, all the rest is trans- tem need not produce significant amounts of
mutation—value added by capital and labor material goods at all.’’ Further down the same
(and perhaps a few magic words or symbols). page he implicitly conflates the production func-
Technical improvement enables labor and capital tion with the utility function to make the claim
to add more value to the inert building blocks, that, ‘‘nobody can define a finite absolute mini-
but nature remains unnecessary beyond the ini- mum material input required to produce a unit
tial provision of those blocks. This view at least of economic welfare.’’ Maybe not, but we were
respects the first law of thermodynamics, but un- talking about physical output, not welfare. Even
fortunately crashes headlong into the second production functions that yield services are pro-
law. While it may be technically possible to con- ducing a physical output—the use of something
vert lead into gold thereby eliminating the par- or somebody for some period of time. That is
ticular scarcity of gold, we do not thereby different from utility or welfare. The service of
remove general scarcity, because the potential my physician may not increase my welfare at all,
for making such conversions is itself scarce. and could even reduce it, but it remains a mea-
That potential must be continually used up by surable service for which I am charged. But even
the economy and resupplied by nature in the without this clarification Ayres found it neces-
form of low-entropy natural resorces. sary to immediately condition his statement,
Another possible reply would be to take off questioning the existence of a minimum material
from Georgescu-Roegen’s qualification that in input, by adding ‘‘with the obvious exception of
some cases ‘‘the same service may be provided food and drink.’’ Are there not other obvious
by a design that requires less matter or energy.’’
exceptions, e.g. clothing and shelter?
This implicitly introduces a distinction between
Maybe there are other replies to Georgescu-
substitution among factors within a given set of
Roegen’s criticism that are less unconvincing
technologies (existing state of the art), and sub-
than those considered above, but if so then
stitution among factors made possible by a new
Solow or Stiglitz should break their silence and
technology (improved state of the art). Even the
finally reply to Georgescu-Roegen’s criticism of
latter case is limited. Future technologies must
long standing. Of course Georgescu-Roegen is
also conform to the laws of thermodynamics,
Georgescu-Roegen insists, but he leaves it at now deceased, but his critique did not die with
that. Just how far new technology can ease the him. Serious criticism and serious replies are
burden of scarcity, within the constraint of phys- both essential parts of science. When a funda-
ical laws, remains an open question. But that mental critique from a very prominent
really is another subject from the one at hand, economist goes for 20 years without a reply, we
since in constructing their aggregate production should worry about the health of our discipline!
function Solow/Stiglitz aim to represent actual Consider a further major difficulty resulting
production processes of today and the recent from the conjuring trick of just plugging R into a
past —not unknown future possibilities. It is as production function along with K and L. An
an empirically-based representation of actual immediate consequence is that the marginal phys-
production processes that their production func- ical products of K and L would have to be zero
tion is intended, and it is as such that it fails. once R is included in the function. This is because
That it would also fail to depict future technolo- the definition of marginal product of one factor
gies is an a fortiori criticism. requires that the amounts of all other factors be
In an article otherwise critical of neoclassical held constant as one more unit of the variable
theory, Ayres (Ayres, 1996, 12) offers a last- factor is added. But when resources are held
ditch defense of Solow – Stiglitz, in the absence constant then there can be no extra unit of output
of which he considers Georgescu-Roegen’s cri- as labor or capital is increased because there is no
tique ‘devastating’. Ayres’ too-generous defense extra physical substance for the extra output to be
is that, ‘‘in the distant future the economic sys- made from. It would have to be produced out of
H.E. Daly / Ecological Economics 22 (1997) 261–266 265

nothing, again fracturing the first law of thermody- causes). We can often substitute one efficient cause
namics.3 The point of course is not limited to for another, or one material cause for another, but
Cobb–Douglas functions — any production func- the relation between efficient and material cause is
tion that obeys the first law of thermodynamics fundamentally one of complementarity, not substi-
cannot avoid a strict complementarity between tutability.
resources on the one hand and capital or labor on If we wish to retain the neoclassical production
the other hand.4 function then we must at least include natural
Zero marginal physical products of labor and resource inputs and waste outputs, and must adopt
capital, a necessary consequence of including R in mathematical representations that, unlike the cus-
any production function that obeys the most basic tomary multiplicative forms, do not assume that
laws of nature, would destroy neoclassical distribu- agents of transformation (funds) can substitute for
tion theory—perhaps too heavy a price to pay for the resources undergoing transformation (flows).
admission that the world, in effect, cannot get along Accuracy of analytical representation of reality
without natural resources! And once we admit that must replace mathematical tractability as the main
natural processes, as well as labor and capital, add criterion of a good model. Once we recognize the
value to the indestructible building blocks, then we reality of inputs from nature then we must inquire
must ask who has the right to appropriate nature’s about their scarcity and about the ecological pro-
contribution? These are not trivial issues! Of cesses that regenerate them. Once we recognize the
course, we can continue to write mathematical necessity of returning waste outputs to nature then
functions that contradict physical laws, call them we must inquire about the capacities of ecosystems
‘production’ functions, take the partial derivatives to absorb those wastes. We will no longer be able
of L and K, and still label them marginal products to avoid the ecological economist’s vision of the
of labor and capital. But then, as Georgescu-Roe- economy as an open subsystem of a complex
gen put it, this becomes a ‘‘mere paper-and-pencil ecosystem that is finite, nongrowing, and materially
operation’’ (PAP was his acronym). closed. In effect, neoclassical economists will be-
Georgescu’s fund-flow model of the production come ecological economists!
process is superior to the neoclassical production Toward that happy end it is appropriate to
function. It emphasizes that physically what we call reissue Georgescu-Roegen’s invitation to Solow/
‘production’ is really transformation — of resources Stiglitz, and the whole community of neoclassical
into useful products and waste products. Labor and economists for whom they are distinguished
capital are agents of transformation (efficient spokesmen, to put an end to ‘conjuring tricks’—to
causes), while resources, low-entropy matter/en- mathematical fun and games with infinity in the
ergy, are ‘that which is being transformed’ (material Garden of Eden—and to devote their impressive
analytical powers to helping develop serious eco-
3
The aggregate production function is taken to be in physical logical economics for the real world.5
units, as in microeconomics. The aggregate production functions
of macroeconomics may seem to be in value units because prices 5
A perceptive reviewer suggested that the best way to get an
are used to aggregate the variables, but fundamentally a ‘dollar’s answer to Georgescu-Roegen’s critique is probably not to raise
worth’ of capital, labor, or resources is a physical quantity. The it again with the same people that have ignored it for twenty
relationship expressed by the function is a relationship among years, but rather to somehow get 10 000 students to ask their
physical quantities, not values. By expressing physical quantities economics professors the following questions in class: (1) Do you
as ‘dollar’s worth’ we do not escape the physical laws of mass believe that economic activities must satisfy mass balance? (2)
balance and entropy! Why is it that neoclassical production functions do not satisfy
4
It is unavailing to appeal to the alternative definition of the condition of mass balance? (3) Do you believe that Georgescu-
marginal product as the decline in total product resulting from Roegen’s interpretation of production as physical transformation
using one less unit of the variable factor, because R still has to is correct? (4) Do you agree that the economic system is embedded
be constant, and if we use one unit less of capital or labor then in the larger environmental system, and totally dependent on it
we will have some R left unneeded. But to keep R constant we as both source and sink for the matter/energy transformed by
must use the unneeded amount anyway, i.e. use it wastefully. economic activity? (5) Do you believe that the matter/energy
That means the function is not a technically efficient recipe and transformations required by economic activity are constrained
therefore does not qualify as a relevant production function. by the entropy law? Ten thousand students, please take note!
266 H.E. Daly / Ecological Economics 22 (1997) 261–266

Acknowledgements Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas, 1975. Energy and economic


myths. South. Econ. J. 347 – 381.
Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas, 1979. Comments on the papers
For helpful comments on earlier drafts I am by Daly and Stiglitz. In: Smith, V. Kerry (Ed.), Scarcity
grateful to R. Ayres, S. El Serafy, J. Gowdy, B. and Growth Reconsidered. RFF and Johns Hopkins Press,
Hannon, G. Lozada, R. Nelson, T. Page and P. Baltimore, MD.
Victor. Of course, remaining shortcomings are Nordhaus, William, Tobin, James, 1972. Economic Growth.
mine alone. National Bureau of Economic Research, Columbia Uni-
versity Press, New York.
Solow, Robert, 1974. The economics of resources or the
resources of economics. Am. Econ. Rev. 1 – 14.
References Stiglitz, J.E., 1979. A Neoclassical Analysis of the Economics
of Natural Resources. In: Smith, V. Kerry (Ed.), Scarcity
Ayres, R.U., 1996. Theories of Economic Growth. INSEAD, and Growth Reconsidered. RFF and Johns Hopkins Press,
September 1996, Fontainebleau, France. Baltimore, MD.
Barnett, Harold, Chandler, Morse, 1963. Scarcity and Growth. Victor, P.A., 1991. Indicators of sustainable development:
RFF and Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD. Some lessons from capital theory. Ecol. Econ. 4, 191 – 213.

. .

You might also like