Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

B

Brahman that a priest would use in a ritual, through which


the gods would be strengthened, or otherwise help
Aleksandar Uskokov would be derived for achieving a purpose, such as
Department of South Asian Languages and getting rid of one’s enemies, of evil spirits, or of
Civilizations, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, danger in general. Bráhman was, further, com-
USA monly and explicitly identified with speech
(vāc), and the poet or priest that utters such speech
was called brahmán (with the acute accent on the
Definition last syllable) through association ([1], pp. 1–10).
Brahman was, thus, a complex of related ideas of
The first principle; the cause of creation, mainte- inspired speech that had creative power and was
nance, and destruction of beings. associated with men who utter it.
The early scholarship on Brahman has recog-
nized this complex and has focused on what
Introduction Bráhman meant in the various early Vedic texts
and how it developed to stand for the great ground
Brahman is one of the most common ideas in of Being and origin of everything: the investiga-
Hinduism, persistent throughout its history, and tion of Brahman the origin commonly proceeded
it may generally be defined as the first cause in the through searching after the origin of Brahman and
creation of the world. Its canonical definition is through negotiating the space between Bráhman
given in the Brahma-Sūtra 1.1.2 (derived from the the holy speech and Brahman the universal prin-
Taittirī ya Upaniṣad 3.1.1 and repeated in the ciple. In many cases, the arena of such polemics
Bhāgavata 1.1.1) as that from which proceed the was comparative Indo-European linguistics.
creation, sustenance, and destruction of beings. It Without going into the details, we may point out
is, thus, the most general ontological principle, two views that were at the extreme not only con-
and in theistic Vedānta it is also identified with ceptually but methodologically as well. Paul
personal divinity such as Viṣṇu or Kṛṣṇa. Thieme claimed that the original import of
The earliest uses of Brahman, however, are not Bráhman was a “formulation” that was created
as straightforward as our initial paragraph sug- specifically for ritual use. In other words,
gests. In the early Vedic corpus, Bráhman (with Bráhman was a poetic creation. By implication,
the acute accent on the first syllable) was solely brahmán was a “formulator” in the sense of Brah-
associated with a hymn that an inspired poet man that creates [2]. Jan Gonda, on the other hand,
would fashion, or a charm or a sacrificial formula was much more willing to side with the native
# Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2018
P. Jain et al. (eds.), Hinduism and Tribal Religions, Encyclopedia of Indian Religions,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1036-5_341-1
2 Brahman

tradition that always interpreted Brahman as the external things are its apparent transformations.
power that makes things grow: “To my mind, This is another śabda-brahman that is, further,
brahman is a more or less definite power . . . commonly identified with the Vedic praṇava, the
which often, and especially in the more ancient holy sound Om.
texts, manifests itself as word, as ritual . . . sacred
or magical word” ([3], p. 70).
As hinted above, the native tradition had con- Brahman in the Upanisads and the
sistently related Brahman to a principle which is Brahma-Sūtra ˙
itself great and makes other things grow, and its
etymology was associated with the root √bṛṁh, It was in the Upaniṣads, however, that the notion
meaning “to grow” or “to make things grow” ([3], of Brahman became the central object of reflec-
p. 20). This etymology is found, for instance, in tion. In the Upaniṣadic corpus, as the Brahma-
the Viṣṇu Purāṇa 3.3.31: “It is called Brahman Sūtra (BS) had systematized it, Brahman in the
because it is great and because it makes things most general sense is the first principle from
grow” ([3], p. 19). Śaṅkara likewise says in his which individual beings are born. The locus
commentary on the Taittirī ya Upaniṣad (2.1.1) classicus of this canonical determination of Brah-
[12]: “It is Brahman because it is the greatest.” man was Taittirī ya Upaniṣad (TU) 3.1.1: “That
The association of Brahman with speech as a from which these beings are born, on which, being
creative principle, however, was not lost on the born, they live, and into which they return at
native tradition, and Brahman is occasionally death, try to know that distinctly: it is Brahman.”
identified with the Veda, with the performance of This passage provided the definition of Brahman
ritual, and through that with growth. In such con- in the tradition of Vedānta because it was the
texts, it is explicitly called śabda-brahman or the topical text for the Brahma-Sūtra statement that
verbal Brahman. One such case is in the third Brahman is that from which proceed creation,
chapter of the Bhagavad-Gī tā [10], which delin- maintenance, and destruction of beings
eates a primordial social contract between the (BS 1.1.2).
gods and the humans, forged by the highest Creation passages with different degrees of
Vedic divinity Prajāpati, in which men are obliged elaboration and a significant variety of detail are,
to offer sacrifices for the gods and the gods to otherwise, found throughout the Upaniṣads, and
reward men by pouring rain. Verses 14–15 say this principle from which creation proceeds is
that beings grow from grain, grain grows from variously called “the great being” (mahān bhūta,
rain, rain is produced through sacrifice, sacrifice Bṛhad-Āraṇyaka Upaniṣad [BĀU] 2.4.10;
is rooted in action, and action is rooted in “Brah- 4.5.11), “the imperishable” (akṣara, Muṇḍaka
man.” Brahman on its part is rooted in the “imper- Upaniṣad [MU] 1.1.7), “Being” (sat, satyam,
ishable.” Śaṅkara and most other commentators Chāndogya Upaniṣad [ChU] 6, TU 2.6), and
identify “Brahman” with the Veda and the “imper- “the Self” (ātman, TU 2.1.1) and is implicitly or
ishable” with Brahman itself. The speech that is explicitly identified with Brahman. The beings
Brahman, thus, makes things grow through laying that are created from Brahman include further
out ritual performances that cause rain, and creation principles that are associated with colors,
through that food, but is itself an effect of Brah- the combination of which produces all the details
man the first principle. of the world (ChU 6: heat, water, and food,
In the philosophy of the grammarians and of corresponding to red, white, and black), the five
the Vedāntin Maṇḍana Miśra, however, Brahman elements (TU 2.1.1: space, air, fire, water, and
the first principle itself was speech in nature. earth), the four Vedas and other items of scriptural
Bhartṛhari’s Vākyapadī ya famously opens with and ritual significance (BĀU 2.4.10; 4.5.11), the
the statement that Brahman which has no origin social classes and Vedic deities (BĀU 1.4.9–15),
and end and which itself is the origin of the world or simply “the whole” or “everything” (sarvam,
is essentially verbal (śabda-tattvam), whereas the BĀU 1.4.10).
Brahman 3

The Taittirī ya definition of Brahman as the described this akṣara as the origin from which
cause was itself found in a wider context, how- beings are born and through that identified the
ever, and it was commonly taken by Vedāntins as imperishable with Brahman: “As a spider spins
not informative enough. It was the positing of the out threads, then draws them into itself; As plants
category – Brahman is the great cause of things – sprout out from the earth; As head and body hair
but not a distinguishing definition or a determinate grows from a living man; So from the imperish-
description, such that it would be sufficiently clear able all things here spring” ([4], p. 437). The
just how that great cause was different from other Bhagavad-Gī tā likewise identified the imperish-
possible causes. Four characteristics are further able with the highest Brahman (8.3: akṣaraṁ
predicated of Brahman in the TU that define Brah- brahma paramam). The intention of describing
man in its peculiar character. TU 2.1.1 contains Brahman in such negative terms was to commu-
the famous statement satyaṁ jñānam anantam nicate that Brahman was essentially different from
brahma, which says that Brahman is Being, con- the beings that it creates.
sciousness, and limitless. Further, the whole third These two textual loci were the most important
chapter of the Upaniṣad is an identification of for the Brahma-Sūtra notion, which intended to
Brahman the cause of beings with ānanda, bliss. define Brahman essentially through the means of
These four characteristics provided the positive analogy with its creation, by combining such pos-
definition of Brahman for Vedānta in general: itive and negative characteristics. Two sūtras in
Brahman the cause was conscious, blissful, and the BS were key to this: 3.3.11 and 3.3.33 [9].
a unique, single cause. While Vedāntins have dif- Without going into the technical details, these two
fered widely on what precise relation obtains sūtras say that whenever Brahman is mentioned in
between Brahman and the four characteristics the various Upaniṣadic texts that serve as props
and on what kind of a thing this Brahman is, as for meditation, the proper characteristics of Brah-
we shall see later, the definition itself was com- man are to be “read in” these texts because they
mon to all Vedāntins since it provided the para- form the general or essential notion of Brahman.
digmatic positive determination of Brahman. Sūtra 3.3.11 states the positive characteristics,
From this derived the popular characterization of “bliss and the rest,” whereas sūtra 3.3.33 refers
Brahman as sac-cid-ānanda, Being, conscious- to the “imperishable.” They, thus, point to the
ness, and bliss. Taittirī ya and the Bṛhad-Āraṇyaka positive and
Another Upaniṣadic text of central importance negative characterizations of Brahman as equally
for the Brahma-Sūtra notion of Brahman was determinative of the notion.
Yājñavalkya’s dialogue with Gārgī Vācaknavī in Yājñavalkya’s theological contest at the sacri-
BĀU 3.8. There, Gārgī challenges Yājñavalkya to fice of Janaka provided two more related main-
tell her about that on which all things above the stays which were influential in different ways in
sky, below the earth, and in between are woven the schools of Vedānta but concerned specifically
warp and woof. Yājñavalkya says that it is the Brahman’s relation to the individual Selves. One
imperishable, akṣara, and proceeds to describe it was the identification of Brahman with the cogni-
in thoroughly negative terms: “That, Gārgī, is the tive agent within each individual, the inner Self or
imperishable, and Brahmins refer to it like this – it antarātman, most explicitly stated in BĀU 3.4.
is neither coarse nor fine; it is neither short nor There, on the insistence of Uṣasta Cākrāyaṇa to
long; it has neither blood nor fat; it is without tell him about that Brahman which is known
shadow or darkness; it is without air or space; it immediately (sākṣād aparokṣāt brahma) as the
is without contact; it has no taste or smell; it is Self within all, Yājñavalkya describes this Brah-
without sight or hearing; it is without speech or man as the principle that accommodates seeing,
mind; it is without energy, breath, or mouth; it is hearing, thinking, and knowing in general but that
beyond measure; it has nothing within it or out- cannot itself become an object of these cognitive
side of it; it does not eat anything; and no one eats processes.
it” ([4], p. 91). The MU (1.1.7) explicitly
4 Brahman

The second is in BĀU 3.7, where Yājñavalkya that promotes some form of unity between the
responds to the question of Uddālaka Āruṇi about individual Self and Brahman that does not abolish
the string (sūtra) that keeps the world and all the separate existence of the first, such as that of
beings together, as well as the inner controller an attribute to a substratum.
(antaryāmin) that guides them from within. The Upaniṣads themselves were far from unan-
Yājñavalkya identifies the inner controller with imous in this regard. While Yājñavalkya’s teach-
the Self within Uddālaka, which is also present ings in the BĀU easily lend themselves to
in the elements of creation, in the heavenly bodies monistic interpretations, there are Upaniṣadic pas-
such as the sun, the moon, and the stars, in natural sages that explicitly promote a form of dualism.
phenomena such as light and darkness, in the Some of them crucially concern Brahman and the
functions of life such as respiration, and in the Self in the state of liberation from embodiment.
cognitive faculties: it is this Self that controls all of An often-quoted passage from the MU (3.1.1-3,
them from within, unbeknownst to them. Then the first two verses also in Śvetāśvatara Upaniṣad
Yājñavalkya proceeds to describe this inner con- [ŚU] 4.6-7 and the very first taken from the
troller as the inner Self that is the principle that Ṛgveda 1.164.20) says that two friendly birds
accommodates cognition but is itself not known: reside on the same tree, and the one eats its
“He sees, but he can’t be seen; he hears, but he sweet fig fruits, while the other just observes.
can’t be heard; he thinks, but he can’t be thought The analogy is clearly between the individual
of; he perceives, but he can’t be perceived. Self and Brahman, who is called here a golden-
Besides him, there is no one who sees, no one colored Person, the creator, the Lord, and Brah-
who hears, no one who thinks, and no one who man the source; the tree represents the body and
perceives. It is this self of yours who is the inner the sweet figs – karma. The Upaniṣad proceeds to
controller, the immortal” ([4], p. 89). The notions say that the bird that represents the individual Self
of antarātman and antaryāmin are clearly suffers, being ignorant of the Lord, but when it
identified. sees him, its suffering disappears, it becomes
This theme of the inner Self and the inner freed from the good and bad karma and attains
controller became one of the key problems in the paramaṁ sāmyam, the highest sameness or
schools of Vedānta, which were divided into similarity.
monistic and pluralistic theologies. The question A triangulation of passages from some of the
about Brahman being the inner Self was whether oldest Upaniṣads indicates that the qualitative
Brahman was the only Self, there being no indi- rather than the quantitative identity between Brah-
vidual Selves ultimately distinct from Brahman, man and the individual Self was the norm. TU
or whether Brahman was the inner Self and con- 2.1.1 that provided the definition of Brahman as
troller of the individual Selves that kept their Being, knowledge, and limitless proceeds to
separate existence. While Vedāntins have gener- claiming how he who knows these characteristics
ally recognized that the Upaniṣads affirmed the as present both in the cavity of one’s own heart
identity between Brahman and the Self, several and in the highest heaven “enjoys all desires with
schools of Vedānta understood this identity as the wise Brahman.” This text was the topical
qualitative rather than quantitative, and they passage for the Brahma-Sūtra understanding of
interpreted the identity statements as promoting liberation as a state where one had become equal
assimilative identification through meditation. An to Brahman in all respect, primarily in the power
all-important sūtra in this regard is BS 4.1.3, of enjoyment, but excluding the ability to interfere
which points to Upaniṣadic texts that understand in the functioning of the world (BS 4.4.21). The
and teach Brahman or the Supreme Self idea of liberation as a state of enjoying all desires
(paramātman, parama-puruṣa) as one’s own was most thoroughly elaborated in the last chapter
Self. The theistic commentators such as of the ChU. There, the claim is that he who had
Nimbārka, Rāmānuja, and Śrīnivāsa have discovered the Self “that is free from evil, free
interpreted this sūtra as a statement of meditation from old age and death, free from sorrow, free
Brahman 5

from hunger and thirst; the Self whose desires and whole world as life breath, prāṇa (BS 4.3.6-10).
intentions are real” (ChU 8.7.1) – taken by Śaṅkara’s Advaita Vedānta had endorsed this
Vedāntins to refer to Brahman – becomes simi- interpretation, but Bādarāyaṇa himself had
larly one “whose desires and intentions are real,” rejected it (BS 4.3.14), and in the theistic schools
satya-kāma and satya-saṅkalpa, that is, wins the of Vedānta Brahman was in any case identified
ability to fulfill one’s desires and intentions by the with a personal divinity, such as Viṣṇu, and
mere thought. This was further specified as the brahma-loka with a sphere beyond the created
ability to have one’s ancestors appear before one- world.
self at one’s will, the ability to enjoy things such as In the later Upaniṣads, there are several pas-
perfumes and garlands, food and drink, music, sages based on which two other characteristics are
and women through sheer intention, as well as commonly predicated to Brahman in Vedānta:
unimpeded motion through the Vedic heavens omnipotence (sarvaśakti) and omniscience
(ChU 8.2.1-10, 8.3.4, 8.12.2). More specifically, (sarvajña). The first is in the ŚU 6.8, which says
liberation was a state of non-return to the human that the Supreme has various innate capacities (ś
world of performing sacrifices for the gods, on the akti) and proceeds to list three: knowledge, power,
account of attaining the world of Brahman, and action (jñāna, bala, kriyā). The Upaniṣad
brahma-loka, where one remains in some form directly presents such capacities as the means
of an unembodied state but not quite shapeless, through which the divinity creates the world in
like “the wind is without a body, and so are the its various details: “Who alone, himself without
rain-cloud, lightning and thunder” (ChU 8.12.2). color, wielding his power [śakti] creates variously
This world of Brahman is graphically countless colors, and in whom the universe comes
described in the first chapter of the Kauṣītaki together at the beginning and dissolves in the
Upaniṣad (KU), and for our purposes it is impor- end – may he furnish us with lucid intelligence”
tant to note that Brahman itself is presented as (ŚU 4.1, [4], p. 423). That Brahman possesses ś
personified. Brahman sits on a couch called aktis of various kinds through which it vicariously
amitaujas, “of limitless might,” which is identi- transforms itself into the world became an impor-
fied with life breath and is made of various Vedic tant determination of Brahman in several schools
chants. The liberated Self approaches this Brah- of Vedānta, and even Śaṅkara commonly
man, sits on its couch, and on Brahman’s question describes Brahman as omnipotent.
“Who are you?” concludes its reply with “You The ŚU also describes the divinity which
yourself are the Self of every being, and I am through its greatness creates the world, explicitly
who you are.” After some more discussion, Brah- called the wheel of Brahman, as omniscient,
man concludes, “You have truly attained my sarvavid (6.1-2). The commonplace reference for
world, it is yours.” Despite the explicit identifica- Brahman’s omniscience in later Vedānta texts,
tion of the individual with Brahman, this is clearly however, came from verse 1.1.9 of the MU. That
a case of qualitative identity, “the highest similar- verse is also situated in a creation passage, and it
ity,” which is further confirmed by the description describes the imperishable Brahman (akṣara)
of the attained state: “When one comes to know from which the creation proceeds as sarvajña
this, he wins the same victory and success that and sarvavid, omniscient.
Brahman has” (KU 1.7).
In the Brahma-Sūtra, already, Bādari had
rejected such personal Brahman as the first prin- Brahman in Vedānta
ciple, for several reasons, the main being that it
makes no sense for the omnipresent Brahman to In systematic thought, Brahman was the specific
be localized in brahma-loka. The Brahman in domain of the schools of Vedānta that developed
brahma-loka was, rather, the so-called kārya- through the medium of commentaries on the
brahman, Brahman as the effect or the universal Upaniṣads and the Brahma-Sūtra. Although all
soul called Hiraṇyagarbha that animates the the schools of Vedānta drew on the same
6 Brahman

Upaniṣadic data, and addressed the same question of consciousness” that makes cognition possible
about Brahman in its relation to the individual yet does not admit of the subject-object distinction
Selves on the one hand and the world on the on which cognitive content depended. Finally,
other, their ideas about Brahman differed widely. Brahman’s being bliss did not involve any expe-
Here we will look briefly at the founders of the riential bliss, and to Śaṅkara’s mind this bliss was
three most prominent schools of Vedānta: the but synonymous with freedom from transmigra-
Advaitin Śaṅkara, the Viśiṣṭādvaitin Rāmānuja, tion (BĀUBh 3.9.28.7) [11].
and the Dvaitin Madhva. The second and the third set were the negative
Śaṅkara’s (ca. 700–750) theology identified characteristics of Brahman, such as “unborn,
Brahman with the cause from which all beings are deathless, beyond hunger and thirst” etc., whose
created, according to the standard Taittirī ya defi- purpose were to deny any change in Brahman on
nition. Such determination of Brahman, however, the one hand and to present it as thoroughly dif-
was not informative enough in Śaṅkara’s eyes to ferent from its creation on the other. These nega-
distinguish Brahman the first cause from compet- tive characteristics of Brahman were related to the
ing candidates, such as the atoms of Vaiśeṣika or positive as their determinants – the Being and
the prakṛti of Sāṅkhya (TUBh 2.1.1). In fact, in consciousness that is Brahman is not liable to
later Advaita Vedānta, causality is commonly change – and through that had a massive herme-
described as a taṭastha-lakṣaṇa or an accidental neutic significance in Śaṅkara’s system. Since
characteristic of Brahman. Śaṅkara, therefore, Brahman was a permanently changeless thing,
claimed that Brahman in its specific nature was the Upaniṣadic descriptions of creation where
defined in three sets of characteristics stated in Brahman was that from which real things proceed
Upaniṣadic texts (BSBh 4.1.2) [13]. The first could not be read as statements that have full truth
were characteristics that present Brahman as “the value, since Brahman’s transformation into such
light of consciousness,” and these are the positive things would be contradictory to Brahman’s being
qualities from the Brahma-Sūtra systematization: permanently changeless. The Upaniṣadic descrip-
Being, consciousness, bliss, and limitless. tions of creation, then, had to be read not as
Brahman, however, did not belong to the genus accounts of real creation but as illustrations of
of causes, and Śaṅkara’s theology did not take causality that should intimate not that Brahman
these qualities as characteristics the collocation transforms into everything but that everything just
of which would make a determinate description was Brahman. It was such kind of cause that
of Brahman, a particular of a genus, but as defin- Brahman was, and the talk of transformation into
ing features whose purpose was to jointly delimit beings in the Upaniṣads was just the closest
Brahman as a thing sui generis. For that to be the approximation of causality that one could com-
case, Brahman’s qualities could not be character- prehend (BSBh 2.1.14).
istics such as common things have, for instance, The negative characteristics were similarly
color, but features that are identical with Brahman related to Brahman’s feature of consciousness,
as constitutive of its nature. This was the idea specifically through the Self of every individual
behind Śaṅkara’s habitual descriptions of Brah- being. The Upaniṣadic accounts of creation say
man as nirviśeṣa, having no distinguishing char- that Brahman, having created the world, entered
acteristics (TUBh 2.1.1). into it as the cognitive agent, that is, as the Self of
Brahman’s Being, for instance, was not like the every individual being. The negative characteris-
being of any object, such as a clay pot, an object to tics of Brahman applied to the feature of con-
which being was predicated as a characteristic so sciousness were meant to prevent cognitive
long as the object was existent: Brahman was agency from obtaining as an essential characteris-
Being that is predicated to everything, the Being tic of the cognitive agent. To put it differently,
that never ceases to be. Likewise, Brahman’s con- Brahman in its feature of consciousness was
sciousness was not any content of awareness that each and every individual Self, not, however, as
can be predicated of a subject, but it was the “light individual nor as the Self that cognizes content of
Brahman 7

awareness but as the pure awareness that makes The first, svarūpa-nirūpaṇa-dharma, is five in
cognition possible (TUBh 2.1.1). number and is the canonical characteristics from
The two essential features of Brahman, how- the BS: Being, consciousness, limitless, bliss, and
ever, had some internal uneasiness. As Being, purity. The last of these, purity or amalatva, may
Brahman was essentially causal, that great plenti- be understood as a collective noun that includes
tude that is coordinated with everything as the the full set of the negative characteristics of Brah-
only real thing, and through that it was external. man from the BS, and it seems to be equivalent to
As consciousness, Brahman was inner, to which the freedom from imperfections in the first classi-
the great external Brahman seemed like a second fication ([5], pp. 88–113). Purity and infinity dis-
entity. This external Brahman is commonly tinguish Brahman from the individual selves and
described by Śaṅkara as Īśvara, with omnipotence the world, and thus Brahman essentially or sub-
and omniscience as the important characteristics. stantively is Being that is unlimited and uncondi-
It was, therefore, in the identity statements of the tional consciousness and bliss in nature.
Upaniṣads, such as the tat tvam asi, “You are Consciousness and bliss are also constitutive of
that,” in ChU 6.8.7ff, and ahaṁ brahmāsmi, “I the essential nature of the individual selves, and
am Brahman,” in BĀU 1.4.10, that Brahman was matter is Being – Rāmānuja is a realist, unlike
most directly defined. Brahman’s being the inner Śaṅkara – but they are not essential in the same
Self of the cognitive agent prevented Brahman way as in Brahman’s case. Brahman’s Being is
from being causal and external, and Brahman’s changeless, unlike that of matter, and the con-
being great prevented there being a second entity sciousness of the individual selves is liable to
to the inner Self. This was, then, the only abso- contraction occasioned by embodiment. The two
lutely true statement about Brahman, “I myself am are, also, entities essentially dependent on Brah-
Brahman,” the light of consciousness, eternal, man, unlike Brahman that is essentially
pure, and bliss in the sense of being ever free. independent.
Brahman’s being the cause, its entering the crea- The group of “natural” (svabhāva) characteris-
tion as the Self, etc. was just a way of facilitating tics seems to include relational characteristics
the subject’s understanding that the Being, con- which Brahman has “naturally” but which he
sciousness and bliss that is Brahman is nothing can exhibit only in relation to other beings. We
but myself (BSBh 2.1.22). (Here we will not go may illustrate these with the characteristic of
into the details of Śaṅkara’s cosmology where the saulabhya or accessibility, which became one
question of Brahman’s relation to ignorance or the most important divine attributes in post-
avidyā becomes important, and the reader should Rāmānuja Śrīvaiṣṇava theology: Brahman is
look at the entry on Śaṅkara.) accessible naturally, but the manifestation of his
Rāmānuja’s (ca. 1077–1157) theology of accessibility is contingent on there being other
Brahman was radically different from that of living beings that intend to approach him ([5],
Śaṅkara. For Rāmānuja, Brahman was a personal pp. 96–97). This rubric, the “natural” characteris-
divinity, identical with Viṣṇu: he refers to him tics of Brahman, is equivalent to what Rāmānuja
predominantly as Puruṣottama, the supreme per- calls the “superlative auspicious qualities” and
son. The most common way for Rāmānuja to includes two sets of characteristics that the later
describe Brahman was through the so-called tradition has subsumed under the notions of
ubhaya-liṅgatva or the fact that Brahman pos- supremacy (paratva) or lordship (ī śitṛtva) and
sesses two kinds of characteristics: “superlative accessibility (saulabhya) ([5], pp. 77–87). The
auspicious qualities” (niratiśaya-kalyāṇa-guṇa) first consists of six characteristics that made their
and “freedom from imperfections” or “opposition entrance into Vedānta from the Pañcarātra system
to everything defiling” (nikhila-heya-pratyanī ka) as the defining features of the category of
([5], pp. 65–76). Another classification that Bhagavān or God: knowledge (jñāna), power
Rāmānuja occasionally makes divides the charac- (bala), majesty (aiśvarya), capacity (śakti), valor
teristics of Brahman into essential and natural. (vī rya), and splendor (tejas). Commentators
8 Brahman

interpret this knowledge as omniscience to distin- Madhva (1238–1317) was another famed
guish it from the essential jñāna or consciousness. Vedāntin, an uncompromising pluralist and a real-
The second set consists of characteristics such as ist. He was the only founder of a school of
compassion and generosity. The classification that Vedānta who claimed that Brahman could not
involves a limited number of characteristics not- possibly be the material cause of the world:
withstanding, however, Rāmānuja was in the Brahman’s essential nature was consciousness
habit of describing the auspicious qualities as and bliss, and it was unthinkable that the insen-
“infinite.” tient world that is the locus of suffering could be a
Rāmānuja was, like Śaṅkara, a monist but of a transformation of a cause so different from it. For
very different kind. The world and the individual Madhva, then, Brahman was just the efficient
Selves in this ontology were real entities, consti- cause of the world, and there obtained absolute
tuting “the body” of Brahman. By a “body,” difference between Brahman and the two other
Rāmānuja meant any dependent reality that a con- principles of reality, the insentient matter and the
scious being can use for its own purpose, as its sentient individual Selves. Madhva’s doctrine is
extension of a sort. The body and the embodied known as prapañca-bheda, a fivefold absolute
formed a unit of entities that kept their separate difference between Brahman and the individual
being yet constituted an organic whole. Thus, Self, Brahman and insentient matter, the various
central to Rāmānuja’s theology of Brahman’s rela- individual Selves, insentient matter and the indi-
tionship to the world and the individual Selves vidual Selves, and the various material entities
was Yājñavalkya’s teaching about the inner ([6], p. 73).
dweller, the antaryāmin, that controls everything What distinguishes Brahman as one among the
from within. Brahman was the universal Self to several coeval reals is its independence. Brahman
which everything else was a body. Rāmānuja is an independent principle, svatantra, omniscient
referred to other similar kinds of relations to illus- and omnipotent, whereas the insentient matter and
trate this notion of organic whole, such as modes the individual sentient Selves are dependent on
and mode-possessor (prakāra-prakārin), parts Brahman ([7], pp. 36–41). Although insentient
and part-possessor (aṁśa-aṁśin), subordinate matter is the stuff of creation and is coeval with
and principal (guṇa-guṇin), supported and sup- Brahman, unlike the Sāṅkhyan prakṛti, it is not in
port (ādheya-ādhāra), ruled and ruler (niyamya- itself able to evolve the world, and it requires the
niyantṛ), etc. His system is commonly called guidance and control of Brahman. Likewise,
viśiṣṭādvaita or “non-duality of the qualified,” although the individual Selves are essentially
through one of these relations, namely, the knowledge in nature and possess agency, these
substantive-adjective or viśeṣya-viśeṣaṇa-bhāva. are obscured by ignorance, a feature of matter
Rāmānuja also accepted the BS doctrine of Brah- that is an “inscrutable power of Brahman,” such
man as the material cause of the world, but Brah- that without the intervention of Brahman the indi-
man was such a cause through having matter as its vidual Self remains in bondage. Since matter is
mode, in virtue of which the shortcomings of the itself insentient, though, even this feature of
world did not affect Brahman’s essential nature obscuring the knowledge of the individual Selves
([5], pp. 114–157). depends on the will of Brahman. Thus, both the
Finally, Brahman for Rāmānuja was most spe- individual Selves and matter are dependent prin-
cifically Nārāyaṇa, the personal divinity that has ciples, asvatantra, incapable of independent
his own body in the direct sense, a body that is a action without the sanction of Brahman ([8],
permanent divine form characterized by beauty, p. 100). Brahman is, therefore, immanent in the
grace, and similar superlative features and dwells world in a sense that is much more direct than in
in a celestial abode with consorts, retinue, etc., the any other brand of Vedānta.
“supreme place,” paramam padam, of Viṣṇu ([5], Madhva further argued that Brahman is an
pp. 167–175). entity that essentially possesses diverse positive
characteristics. Even if one were to assume that
Brahman 9

Brahman is without positive characteristics, Cross-References


nirviśeṣa, that would still be a positive determina-
tion insofar as Brahman would be characterized as ▶ Advaita Vedānta
different from everything else. “Having no ▶ Aum
distinguishing features” was a distinguishing fea- ▶ Bhagavad Gītā
ture, and such being the case, there is no reason ▶ Bhāgavata Purāṇa
why Brahman would not have other kinds of ▶ Bhāskara
characteristics that are positive in a more straight- ▶ Bhedābheda
forward manner ([8], pp. 115–121). ▶ Brahmā
Madhva’s realist ontology, in fact, required ▶ Brahma Sūtras (Vedānta Sūtras)
that Brahman be a qualified entity, saviśeṣa, and ▶ Dvaita Vedānta
have characteristics of various kinds. As the effi- ▶ God, Overview
cient cause, Brahman must be both omniscient ▶ Madhva
and omnipotent, as well as possessed of a will to ▶ Nimbārka
create. The negative descriptions of Brahman ▶ Rāmānuja
throughout the Upaniṣads were denials that Brah- ▶ Śaṅkara (Śaṁkara)
man has characteristics that are products of the ▶ Upaniṣads
material cause of the world, prakṛti. For instance, ▶ Vāc
the statements that Brahman is formless are ▶ Vedānta, Overview
denials that Brahman possesses a form composed
of the five elements of creation, but not a denial
that Brahman may have his own form that pos- References
sesses hands, feet, a face, etc., made of Brahman’s
own trans-material nature. This trans-material 1. Griswold HDW (1900) Brahman: a study in the his-
nature was constituted, in fact, by the classical tory of indian philosophy. The Macmillan Company,
New York
positive characteristic of Brahman: Being, con-
2. Brereton J (2004) Bráhman, Brahmán, and Sacrificer.
sciousness, and bliss. “Viṣṇu’s eternal and innate In: Griffiths A, Houben JEM (eds) The vedas: text,
body is faultless consciousness and bliss,” said language & ritual. Egbert Forsten, Groningen,
Madhva ([6], pp. 94–95). Like Rāmānuja, pp 325–344
3. Gonda J (1950) Notes on Brahman. J.L. Beyers,
Madhva was also a Vaiṣṇava and Brahman for
Utrecht
him was simply Viṣṇu. 4. Olivelle P (1998) The early Upaniṣads. Oxford Uni-
In an important sense, however, Madhva was a versity Press, Oxford/New York
non-dualist. He argued that the characteristics of 5. Carman JB (1974) The theology of Rāmānuja: an
essay in interreligious understanding. Yale Publica-
Brahman were not qualities different from Brah-
tions in Religion 18. Yale University Press, New
man and standing in some sort of a relationship to Haven/London
it. Rather, Brahman was a single substance that is 6. Raghavachar SS (1959) Śrīmad-Viṣṇu-Tattva-
for practical purposes described through the attri- Vinirṇaya of Śrī Madhvācārya. Sri Ramakrishna
Ashrama, Mangalore
bution of diverse characteristics. These character-
7. Sharma BNK (1962) Philosophy of Śrī Madhvācārya.
istics are explicative, but not constitutive of Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, Bombay
Brahman, much after the fashion of attribution of 8. Sharma BNK (1997) Madhva’s teachings in his own
omnipresence to space. Central in this regard was words. Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, Mumbai
9. Bose R (2004) Vedānta-Pārijāta-Saurabha of
the notion of viśeṣa or specific difference, which
Nimbārka and Vedānta-Kaustubha of Śrīnivāsa:
for Madhva was an intrinsic capacity of a thing to English translation. Munshiram Manoharlal, Delhi
be a homogenous whole yet be described as a 10. van Buitenen JAB (1981) The Bhagavad-Gītā in the
substance that has various attributes ([6], Mahābhārata. University of Chicago Press,
Chicago/London
pp. 95–97).
11. Mādhavānanda S (1950) The Bṛhadāraṇyaka
Upaniṣad with the commentary of Śaṅkarācārya
[BAUBh]. Advaita Ashrama, Mayavati
10 Brahman

12. Swami G (1937) Eight Upaniṣads: volume one (Īśā, 13. Swami G (1965) Brahma-Sūtra-Bhāṣya of Śrī
Kena, Kaṭha, Taittirīya [TUBh]). With the commen- Śaṅkarācārya [BSBh]. Advaita Ashrama, Calcutta
tary of Śaṅkarācārya. Advaita Ashrama, Calcutta

You might also like