Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/235930763

A Realist Approach to Qualitative Research

Book · October 2011

CITATIONS READS

844 24,108

1 author:

Joseph Alex Maxwell


George Mason University
49 PUBLICATIONS 20,126 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Joseph Alex Maxwell on 22 June 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


6
REALISM AS A STANCE FOR
MIXED METHODS RESEARCH

 Joseph A. Maxwell and Kavita Mittapalli

Objectives

Upon finishing this chapter you should be able to:

• understand the main characteristics of critical realism, as the term


is used in this chapter;

• identify some of the important differences between realism, posi-


tivism, constructivism, and pragmatism that are relevant to mixed
methods research;

• understand why the view of paradigms as logically unified sets of


premises that are shared by members of a research community is
problematic; and

• identify some of the aspects of mixed methods research for which


realism can provide a useful perspective.

◆ 145
146–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

P hilosophical realism, a currently pro-


minent approach in the philosophy of
science, is gaining increased attention as an
(Archer, Bhaskar, Collier, Lawson, &
Norrie, 1998; Bhaskar, 1989), experiential
realism (Lakoff, 1987), subtle realism
alternative to both positivism/empiricism and (Hammersley, 1992), emergent realism
constructivism as a stance for research and (Henry, Julnes, & Mark, 1998; Mark et al.,
evaluation in the social sciences (Campbell, 2000), natural realism (Putnam, 1999),
1988; House, 1991; Mark, Henry, & Julnes, innocent realism (Haack, 1998, 2003), and
2000; Maxwell, 1990, 1992, 2004a, 2008; agential realism (Barad, 2007). We will use
Pawson, 2006; Pawson & Tilley, 1997; the term critical realism in a broad sense to
Sayer, 1992, 2000). Contemporary versions include all of these versions of realism. (We
of realism have presented sophisticated provide a more detailed description of real-
approaches to some of the contentious philo- ism later in this chapter.)
sophical issues involved in the paradigm wars There is a widespread view within mixed
over qualitative and quantitative research. methods research that the appropriate philo-
Although there are now a considerable sophical partner for qualitative research is
number of substantive mixed methods stud- constructivism and for quantitative research,
ies that have employed a realist perspective, postpositivist empiricism (Johnson & Gray,
realism has received relatively little notice in 2010 [this volume]). This view would seem
discussions of mixed methodology (excep- to make mixed methods research a philo-
tions include Greene, 2007; Greene & Hall, sophical oxymoron, or at least a problem-
2010 [this volume]; Lipscomb, 2008; atic union. Postpositivism and constructivism
McEvoy & Richards, 2006). We argue that, disagree on major issues concerning the
as a philosophical perspective that validates nature of the objects of research and our
and supports key aspects of both qualitative knowledge of these (Guba & Lincoln,
and quantitative approaches while identify- 1989), and these disagreements played a
ing some specific limitations of each, realism major role in what have been called the par-
can constitute a productive stance for mixed adigm wars between qualitative and quan-
methods research and can facilitate a more titative approaches.
effective collaboration between qualitative In response, methodological pragmatists
and quantitative researchers. (e.g., Patton, 2001; Reichardt & Cook,
There are many diverse versions of real- 1979; Tashakkori & Teddlie, 1998) have
ism across the philosophical landscape, but claimed that these philosophical disagree-
a common feature of the realist positions ments are not fundamental and that
that we discuss here is an integration of a research methods are not intrinsically
realist ontology (there is a real world that linked to specific philosophical positions.
exists independently of our perceptions, the- They have argued that methods can be
ories, and constructions) with a construc- combined on the basis of their practical
tivist epistemology (our understanding of utility and that paradigmatic conflicts can
this world is inevitably a construction from be ignored. This view has gained substan-
our own perspectives and standpoint, and tial acceptance within the mixed methods
there is no possibility of attaining a “God’s research community, and pragmatism has
eye point of view” that is independent of been promoted as the appropriate philo-
any particular viewpoint). In addition, these sophical stance for mixed methods research
versions of realism acknowledge the reality (Biesta, 2010 [this volume]; Johnson &
of mental phenomena and the value of an Gray, 2010 [this volume]; Maxcy, 2003;
interpretive perspective for studying these Tashakkori & Teddlie, 2003).
(Putnam, 1990, 1999; Sayer, 1992, 2000). We agree with pragmatists that research
Different terms have been used for such practices are not determined by, or depen-
versions of realism, including critical realism dent on, philosophical paradigms. A research
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––147

strategy or method is not necessarily linked to counterproductive. Paradigmatic assump-


a single philosophical stance, and any tions function not simply as constraints on
approach may be informed by one or more of methods but as lenses for viewing the world,
a number of paradigms (Greene, 2000; revealing phenomena and generating insights
Pitman & Maxwell, 1992). However, we that would be difficult to obtain with other
believe that the pragmatist position underes- lenses. This idea is at the heart of Greene’s
timates the actual influence of philosophical (2007, pp. 79–80; Greene & Hall, 2010 [this
assumptions on research methods, an influ- volume]) dialectic stance for doing mixed
ence that is particularly significant for methods research, in which the goal is to cre-
combining qualitative and quantitative ate a dialogue between diverse perspectives
approaches. Ontological, epistemological, on the phenomena being studied, so as to
and axiological assumptions are real proper- deepen, rather than simply broaden or trian-
ties of researchers and evaluators, part of gulate the understanding gained. Greene
what Henry et al. (1998; Mark et al., 2000) considers it the most valuable stance for
call values. These assumptions inevitably mixed methods research because the juxta-
influence researchers’ purposes and actions to position of different lenses or “mental mod-
some degree and are often implicit and not els” that it requires is the most likely to
easily abandoned or changed. produce generative insights and depth of
For example, mainstream quantitative understanding and also because it promotes
research has traditionally presupposed a a meaningful engagement with difference
Humean, regularity view of causation and a dialogue across paradigm boundaries.
(Mohr, 1996; cf. Johnson & Gray, 2010), In this chapter, we argue that realism—in
although this is rarely explicit. This philo- particular, what we call critical realism—can
sophical assumption leads to, and supports, contribute to such a dialogue and can help
a variable-oriented approach to research, an resolve some of the problems created by
emphasis on replicability and general laws, other perspectives. Realism provides a philo-
and a validity strategy based on experimen- sophical stance that is compatible with the
tal or statistical controls. These characteris- essential methodological characteristics of
tics, and the philosophical position that both qualitative and quantitative research,
informs them, inherently relegate qualitative and it can facilitate communication and
research to a secondary role in investigating cooperation between the two (Greene, 2000;
causality. This restricts the range of ques- Mark et al., 2000 ;). However, we also argue
tions for which qualitative methods are seen that realism has some specific implications
as appropriate and makes mixed methods that challenge certain practices in both qual-
research both more difficult and less produc- itative and quantitative research and that
tive (Maxwell, 2004a). On the other hand, point to new ways of addressing some
qualitative researchers who accept a “strong” important issues in mixed methods research.
constructivist philosophy reject quantitative We are not arguing for realism as an alter-
researchers’ characteristic assumption that nate paradigm (Greene, 2007, pp. 82–86) that
objective, verifiable knowledge about the is the preferred stance for mixed methods
world is possible (Schwandt, 1997, p. 20) research. In fact, we are skeptical of the entire
and the view of the world as analyzable in concept of unified paradigms in research, a
terms of causes (Guba & Lincoln, 1989). concept that has dominated the discussion
This prevents these qualitative researchers of the relationship between philosophical
from accepting (let alone using) some cen- assumptions and research methods. So before
tral features of quantitative design, data we discuss what we see as the potential con-
collection, and analysis. tributions of a realist perspective, we want to
Urging researchers to simply set aside address the larger issue of paradigms in mixed
these assumptions is not just unrealistic, but methods research.
148–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

♦ Paradigms in Mixed degree related to “delineating and preserv-


Methods Research ing identities and ideologies rather than to
describe possibilities and limits of a rather
heterogeneous group of data collection and
The main argument for combining qualita- analysis techniques” (p. 29).
tive and quantitative paradigmatic posi- In addition to the critiques by Bergman,
tions, as well as methods, in mixed methods Hammersley, and others of the view that
research has traditionally been their paradigms constitute a set of logically con-
complementarity—that they have different sistent assumptions that have necessary
strengths and limitations and that using connections to methods, the view that para-
them together allows the researcher to draw digms are generally shared by members of a
conclusions that would not be possible community of researchers is problematic.
using either method alone. However, this While prominent advocates of this view
argument usually assumes that the quanti- (e.g., Denzin & Lincoln, 2005) now concede
tative and qualitative traditions embody that qualitative researchers don’t all share
different paradigms—ontological, episte- the same epistemological assumptions, they
mological, and value assumptions, as well still assume, or at least write as if, qualitative
as methodological differences—that are, researchers can be divided into distinct
even if compatible, distinctly different from “camps” or “moments,” including postpos-
one another and that these differences are itivist, constructivist, and postmodern, that
straightforward and easily categorized. do share a particular paradigm.
Most textbooks or other general presenta- This view is supported by the assumption
tions of mixed methods research list the rel- that all communities are united by shared
ative strengths and limitations of qualitative beliefs, values, and practices, a theory exem-
and quantitative research and use these to plified in the anthropological concept of cul-
develop strategies for combining the two. ture. However, this assumption has frequently
These lists of strengths are typically been challenged in anthropology by authors
dichotomous, and the characteristics of who argue that it denies or ignores the exis-
each approach are presented as uniform, tence of substantial intracultural diversity in
polar, and complementary. communities and misrepresents the actual
This dichotomous and polar view of the processes that generate and maintain social
two approaches has been challenged by solidarity (Hannerz, 1992; Maxwell, 1999;
Hammersley (1992) and Howe (2003), and Wallace, 1970). It has also been challenged
more recently by Bergman (2008a), Biesta by postmodern scholars, who generally
(2010 [this volume]), Hammersley (2008), consider diversity—within individual identi-
and Fielding (2008), who argue for a more ties, as well as within social communities—to
complex and contextualized understanding be fundamental rather than superficial
of the potential contributions of each (e.g., Bernstein, 1992; Rosenau, 1992).
approach. Many of the contributors to the Studies have demonstrated substantial and
volume edited by Bergman (2008b) have often unrecognized diversity in the suppos-
serious reservations about the way mixed edly paradigmatic assumptions held by
methods research has been conceptualized linguists (McCawley, 1982) and qualitative
and see the qualitative/quantitative distinc- evaluators (Pitman & Maxwell, 1992). This
tion as much more problematic than has issue will be addressed in more general terms
traditionally been assumed. Bergman (2008a) below, in considering the importance of
claims that the assumption of generic diversity as a real phenomenon.
“strengths” of each approach, based on A perspective that makes little mention of
paradigm differences, is fallacious and that postmodernism (and is critical of specific
the conventional divide between qualitative aspects of postmodern theory when it does
and quantitative methods is to a considerable so), but that is strikingly compatible with
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––149

postmodernism’s overall insistence on the realist versus constructivist assumptions, and


pervasive significance of diversity, as well as the debates often employ both realist and
with a dialectic stance for mixed methods constructivist theoretical “moves” by partic-
research, has been presented by Abbott ular scholars within that community.
(2001, 2004). Abbott argued that ontologi- One of the many examples that Abbott
cal and epistemological positions, rather analyzed was Chambliss’s study of compet-
than being unified, foundational sets of itive swimming (Chambliss, 1989; see
premises that strongly shape the practices of Example 1). Abbott argued that the debate
particular communities of scholars, function over Chambliss’s work shows the power of
instead as heuristics, conceptual tools that making a realist or constructivist move,
are used to solve specific problems in theory even within a largely constructivist field,
and research. He stated that if we take any of creating new leads for research. He stated
a large number of debates between polar that “the idea of heuristics is to open up
positions, such as positivism versus interpre- new topics, to find new things. To do that,
tivism, analysis versus narrative, realism ver- sometimes we need to invoke construc-
sus constructivism, and so on, we find that tivism, as have the students of occupational
these issues can play out at many different prestige. Sometimes we need a little real-
levels, even within communities of scholars ism” (Abbott, 2004, p. 191). This position
that have adopted one or the other of these is quite compatible with Hacking’s (1999)
positions as characterizing their field at a detailed and incisive analysis of construc-
broader level. Thus, within the community tivism, uncovering the ways in which par-
of sociologists of science, which is generally ticular phenomena (mental illness, child
seen as constructivist in orientation, there are abuse, nuclear weapons, rocks) can be use-
internal debates that can be seen as involving fully seen as both real and social constructs.

Example 1

On the basis of 5 years of ethnographic research, including coaching swimming teams at dif-
ferent levels and observing and interviewing swimmers, Chambliss argued that there is no such
thing as talent as an explanation of high performance; it is a myth that romanticizes and mys-
tifies what he called “the mundanity of excellence.” He supported this claim with detailed evi-
dence from his observations and interviews, showing that high performance is simply the result
of dozens of specific skills, learned or stumbled upon, that are repeatedly practiced and syn-
thesized into a coherent whole. Abbott saw this as a constructivist move in the debate over
sports performance; it asserted that talent is a social construction that does not refer to any
real causal factor but is simply a vacuous explanation for high performance.
This move was consistent with the field of sociology of sport, which was generally seen as
constructionist in orientation. However, underlying Chambliss’s argument for a constructivist
interpretation of talent was a realist move, identifying actual skills and practices and excel-
lence as the outcome of these, as real phenomena rather than simply constructions. As a result,
his work was attacked by others in this field for not treating winning, and the skills that led to
this, as themselves social constructions. Chambliss’s reply was that while selecting winners on
the basis of elapsed times, rather than the beauty or precision of their strokes, was certainly a
social construction, once that construction was made, the factors that lead to success in terms
of that standard, and the outcomes of races, have a real existence independent of how they
are construed by participants and judges.
150–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

From this perspective, epistemological independently of our theories about them”


positions look less like the traditional view (p. 205). More specifically, Lakoff (1987)
of paradigms and more like tools in a lists the following characteristics of what he
toolkit. Logical consistency is the wrong terms experiential realism:
standard to apply to a toolkit. You don’t
care if the tools are all consistent with some (a) a commitment to the existence of a
axiomatic principle; you care if, among real world, (b) a recognition that reality
them, they enable you to do the job, to cre- places constraints on concepts, (c) a con-
ate something that can meet your needs or ception of truth that goes beyond mere
accomplish your goals. In the same way, internal coherence, and (d) a commit-
consistency is the wrong standard to apply ment to the existence of stable knowl-
to an individual’s or a community’s onto- edge of the world. (p. xv)
logical and epistemological views. These
views, seen as heuristics, are resources for In the social sciences, the most important
getting your work done. This approach is manifestation of realism is the critical real-
similar to Greene’s dialectic stance but puts ist tradition most closely associated with
more emphasis on the dialectic use of dis- the work of Bhaskar (1978, 1989) and
crete conceptual tools, rather than para- others in this tradition (Archer et al., 1998).
digms in a more global sense. However, we also draw substantially from
The rest of this chapter explores some of other versions of realism that we see as
the specific uses of realist conceptual tools compatible with the key ideas of this tradi-
in social research. First, however, we need tion, in particular those of the philosophers
to describe realism in more detail as a gen- Haack (1998, 2003), Manicas (2006), and
eral approach in both the natural and social Putnam (1990, 1999), the physicist and his-
sciences. torian of science Barad (2007), the linguist
Lakoff (1987; Lakoff & Johnson, 1999),
and the evaluation researchers Pawson and
♦ What Is Realism? Tilley (1997).
The distinctive feature of these forms of
realism is that they deny that we have any
In the philosophy of science, including the objective or certain knowledge of the world,
philosophy of the social sciences, realism and accept the possibility of alternative valid
has been an important, if not the dominant accounts of any phenomenon. All theories
approach for more than 30 years (Baert, about the world are grounded in a particular
1998, pp. 189–190); realism has been a perspective and worldview, and all knowl-
prominent position in other areas of philos- edge is partial, incomplete, and fallible.
ophy as well (Kulp, 1997). The prolifera- Lakoff (1987) states this distinction between
tion of realist positions has led one realist objectivist and realist views as follows:
philosopher to claim that “scientific realism
is a majority position whose advocates are Scientific objectivism claims that there
so divided as to appear a minority” (Leplin, is only one fully correct way in which
1984, p. 1). The idea that there is a real reality can be divided up into objects,
world with which we interact, and to which properties, and relations. . . . Scientific
our concepts and theories refer, has proved realism, on the other hand, assumes
to be a resilient and powerful one that has that “the world is the way it is,” while
attracted increased philosophical attention acknowledging that there can be more
following the demise of positivism. than one scientifically correct way of
Philosophic realism in general is defined understanding reality in terms of con-
by Phillips (1987) as “the view that entities ceptual schemes with different objects
exist independently of being perceived, or and categories of objects. (p. 265)
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––151

In taking this position, critical realism structures, people, meanings, and so


retains an ontological realism while accept- forth in the environment as indepen-
ing a form of epistemological relativism or dent in some way from their experience
constructivism. This position has achieved with them. (p. 134)
widespread, if often implicit acceptance as
an alternative both to naïve realism and to Schwandt (1997) also noted that most
radical constructivist views that deny the social constructivists in the sociology of
existence of any reality apart from our con- science “do not conclude that there is no
structions. Shadish, Cook, and Campbell material reality ‘out there’” (p. 20; see also
(2002) argued that “all scientists are episte- Shadish et al., 2002, pp. 28–31). Ezzy
mological constructivists and relativists” in (2002, pp. 15–18) argued similarly that
the sense that they believe that both the while some postmodernists deny that real-
ontological world and the worlds of ideol- ity exists, others simply want to problema-
ogy, values, and so forth play a role in the tize our assumptions about reality in light
construction of scientific knowledge (p. 29). of the complexity of our process of under-
Conversely, Schwandt (1997) stated that standing it. He cites Kvale’s (1995) claim
that while moderate postmodernism rejects
many (if not most, I suspect) qualita- the idea of universal truth, it “accepts the
tive researchers have a common-sense possibility of specific, local, personal, and
realist ontology, that is, they take seri- community forms of truth with a focus on
ously the existence of things, events, daily life and local narrative” (p. 21).

Example 2

A particularly detailed and sophisticated statement of the sort of realism we adopt here was
presented by the physicist and historian of science Evelyn Fox Keller (1992), with the assump-
tion that this viewpoint is so widely shared that it needs no explicit defense. She stated,
“I begin with a few philosophical platitudes about the nature of scientific knowledge upon which
I think we can agree, but which, in any case, will serve to define my own point of departure”:

Scientific theories neither mirror nor correspond to reality.


Like all theories, they are models, in Geertz’s (1973) terms, both models of and models
for, but especially, they are models for; scientific theories represent in order to intervene,
if only in search of confirmation. And the world in which they aim to intervene is, first and
foremost, the world of material (that is, physical) reality. For this reason, I prefer to call
them tools. From the first experiment to the latest technology, they facilitate our actions
in and on that world, enabling us not to mirror, but to bump against, to perturb, to trans-
form that material reality. In this sense scientific theories are tools for changing the world.
Such theories, or stories, are invented, crafted, or constructed by human subjects, inter-
acting both with other human subjects and with nonhuman subjects/objects.
But even granted that they are constructed, and even abandoning the hope for a one-to-one
correspondence with the real, the effectiveness of these tools in changing the world has
something to do with the relation between theory and reality. To the extent that scientific
(Continued)
152–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

(Continued)
theories do in fact “work”—that is, lead to action on things and people that, in extreme
cases (for example, nuclear weaponry), appear to be independent of any belief system—
they must be said to possess a kind of “adequacy” in relation to a world that is not itself
constituted symbolically—a world we might designate as “residual reality.”
I take this world of “residual reality” to be vastly larger than any possible representation
we might construct. Accordingly, different perspective, different languages will lead to
theories that not only attach to the real in different ways (that is, carve the world at
different joints), but they will attach to different parts of the real—and perhaps even
differently to the same parts. (pp. 73–74)

Such versions of realism share many reality independent of our theories can
characteristics with philosophical pragma- serve no useful function because there is no
tism. It is worth noting, therefore, that way to employ this that will avoid the con-
some of the major figures in pragmatism straints of a relativist epistemology. They
were also ontological realists (Maxcy, concluded that “Maxwell is unable to show
2003, p. 56; see also Biesta, 2010). Buchler us how to get reality to do some serious
(1940) said of Peirce, the founder of work” (p. 883). In what follows, therefore,
American pragmatism, that we attempt to show how a realist ontology
can do useful work in the methodology and
Underlying every phase of Peirce’s practice of mixed methods research, if it is
thought is his realism. The supposition taken seriously and its implications system-
that there are real things—the real is atically developed. We do so by describing
“that whose characters are independent some specific implications of critical realism
of what anybody may think them to for quantitative, qualitative, and mixed
be”—he regards as the “fundamental methods research, showing how a realist
hypothesis” of science, for it alone perspective can provide new and useful
explains the manner in which minds are ways of approaching problems and impor-
compelled to agreement. (p. xiv). tant insights into social phenomena.
Given the prominence of realist views in
Contemporary philosophers who inte- philosophy, it is puzzling that realism has
grate pragmatism and realism include not had a greater influence on research
Haack (2006) and Putnam (1990; Conant methodology. Despite the contributions to
& Zeglen, 2002); Putnam once commented a realist approach to social research by
that he should have called his version of Campbell (1988), Huberman and Miles
realism pragmatic realism. (1985), Sayer (1992, 2000), Hammersley
Despite the widespread commonsense (1992), House (1991), and others, philo-
acceptance of combining ontological real- sophic realism seems still to be largely
ism and epistemological constructivism, the unnoticed by most researchers (one excep-
application of this perspective to qualitative tion is the field of program evaluation,
research, as advocated by Hammersley where realist approaches developed by
(1992) and Maxwell (1992), was chal- Pawson and Tilley (1997) and Henry et al.
lenged by Smith and Deemer (2000), who (1998; Mark et al., 2000) have had a sig-
asserted that the ontological concept of a nificant impact). Even when realism is
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––153

noticed, it tends to be seen by quantitative ontology—a commitment to the existence


researchers as a commonsense truism with of a real, although not an objectively know-
no important implications and dismissed by able, world—and its emphasis on causal
qualitative researchers as simply positivism explanation (although a fundamentally dif-
in another guise (Mark et al., 2000, p. 166). ferent concept of causal explanation than
However, realism is strikingly different that of the positivists) as intrinsic to social
from positivism in many of its premises and science.
implications (Baert, 1998, pp. 192–193). Such an ecumenical approach is so char-
One of the most significant of these is the acteristic of realism that Baert (1998, p.
realist understanding of causality. Realists 194) accuses realists of ruling out almost
have been among the strongest critics of the nothing but extreme positivism. It is true
“regularity” view of causation, which was that realism is pragmatic in that it does not
typical of positivism and is still dominant in discard a priori those approaches that have
quantitative research (Maxwell, 2004a). In shown some ability to increase our under-
addition, most critical realists accept the standing of the world. However, the value
reality of mental states and attributes and of realism does not derive simply from its
the importance of these for causal explana- compatibility with different approaches to
tion in the social sciences, positions rejected research or from its pragmatic orientation
by both traditional positivism and con- to methods. Realism has important impli-
structivism. Both of these aspects of realism cations for the conduct of research. In the
are discussed in more detail below and con- remainder of this chapter, therefore, we
stitute two areas in which critical realism want to take seriously a realist ontology
can make an important contribution to and to outline some of its most important
mixed methods research. implications for mixed methods research.
Although some realists have been critical
of quantitative and experimental research
(e.g., Pawson & Tilley, 1997; Sayer, 1992), ♦ Potential Contributions
we believe that realism is a productive of Realism to Mixed
stance for both quantitative and qualitative Methods Research
research (cf. Mark et al., 2000). Donald
Campbell, a major figure in the develop-
ment of experimental methods in social There are many aspects of mixed methods
research and an important influence on research for which realism provides a valu-
quantitative methodology in general, was able perspective. For example, it is useful to
an explicit critical realist in the broad sense view research designs as real entities—not
we use here (Campbell, 1988; cf. Maxwell, simply as models for research but also as the
1990), and his realist perspective was actual conceptualizations and practices
acknowledged by Weisner (2005, p. 6) as employed in a specific study. The latter
an influence on the mixed methods studies approach helps a reader of a research publi-
in which he was involved. cation to understand the real design of a
Realism is also compatible with some study, its “logic-in-use,” which may differ
of the assumptions and implications of substantially from its “reconstructed logic”
constructivism and postmodernism, includ- (Kaplan, 1964, p. 8) presented in publica-
ing the idea that difference is fundamen- tions (Maxwell, 2005; Maxwell & Loomis,
tal rather than superficial, a skepticism 2003). This conception of design as a model
toward “general laws,” an antifoundation- of, as well as for, research is exemplified in
alist stance, and a relativist epistemology a classic qualitative study of medical
(Maxwell, 1995, 1999). It differs from students (Becker, Geer, Hughes, & Strauss,
these approaches primarily in its realist 1961/1977; see Example 3).
154–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

Example 3

Becker et al. (1961/1977) begin their chapter on the “Design of the Study” by stating:

In one sense, our study had no design. That is, we had no well-worked-out set of
hypotheses to be tested, no data-gathering instruments purposely designed to secure
information relevant to these hypotheses, no set of analytic procedures specified in
advance. Insofar as the term “design” implies these features of elaborate prior planning,
our study had none.
If we take the idea of design in a larger and looser sense, using it to identify those ele-
ments of order, system, and consistency our procedures did exhibit, our study had a
design. We can say what this was by describing our original view of the problem, our the-
oretical and methodological commitments, and the way these affected our research and
were affected by it as we proceeded. (p. 17)

A second example of the application of a entities and mechanisms. This view treats
realist perspective to research design is to the actual process of causality as unob-
view the relationships that a researcher servable, a “black box,” and focuses
establishes with participants and other simply on discovering whether there is a
stakeholders in a study as a real component systematic relationship between inputs
of the “design-in-use” of a study, one that and outputs. This conception of causality
is rarely addressed in discussions of is “the basis of ordinary quantitative research
research design and that often is critical to and of the stricture that we need compar-
the actual functioning of a study (Maxwell, ison in order to establish causality”
2002, 2005). (Mohr, 1996, p. 99).
In what follows, we focus on four issues In quantitative research, the regularity
for which we feel realism can make a par- theory of causation is intrinsic to an
ticularly important contribution to mixed approach to explanation that Mohr (1982)
methods research: causal explanation, mind called variance theory. Variance theory
and reality, validity, and diversity. deals with variables and the correlations
among them; it is based on an analysis of
the contribution of differences in measured
A PROCESS APPROACH values of particular variables to differences
TO CAUSALITY in values of other variables. The compari-
son of conditions or groups in which the
For most of the 20th century, the dom- presumed causal factor takes different val-
inant conception of causality in the phi- ues, while other factors are held constant or
losophy of science was based on David statistically controlled, is central to this
Hume’s analysis, generally known as the approach to causation. Thus, variance
regularity theory of causation (House, theory tends to be associated with research
1991; Salmon, 1989). Hume argued that that employs experimental or correlational
we can’t directly perceive causal relation- designs, quantitative measurement, and sta-
ships, only the observed regularities in tistical analysis. As Mohr (1982) noted,
associations of events, and he rejected “the variance-theory model of explana-
any reference to hypothesized or inferred tion in social science has a close affinity to
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––155

statistics. The archetypal rendering of this independently of them. In view of this,


idea of causality is the linear or nonlinear less weight is put on quantitative methods
regression model” (p. 42). for discovering and assessing regularities
In philosophy, the most widely accepted and more on methods of establishing the
alternative to the regularity approach to qualitative nature of social objects and
causality is a realist approach that sees relations on which causal mechanisms
causality as fundamentally referring to the depend. (pp. 2–3)
actual causal mechanisms and processes
that are involved in particular events and This approach is quite different from
situations. For the philosophy of science in variance theory. Pawson and Tilley (1997),
general, this approach was most systemati- in their realist approach to program evalu-
cally developed by Salmon (1984, 1989, ation, stated:
1998), who referred to it as the causal/
mechanical view. This approach When realists say that the constant
conjunction view of one event produc-
makes explanatory knowledge into ing another is inadequate, they are not
knowledge of the . . . mechanisms by attempting to bring further “interven-
which nature works. . . . It exhibits the ing” variables into the picture . . . The
ways in which the things we want to idea is that the mechanism is responsi-
explain come about. (Salmon, 1989, ble for the relationship itself. A mecha-
pp. 182–183) nism is . . . not a variable but an account
of the makeup, behaviour and inter-
For the social sciences, this approach to relationship of those processes which
explanation closely resembles what Mohr are responsible for the regularity.
(1982) called process theory. Process theory (pp. 67–68)
deals with events and the processes that
connect them; it is based on an analysis of Similar distinctions to that between
the causal processes by which some events variance and process theory have been
influence others. It is fundamentally differ- presented by many other writers, including
ent from variance theory as a way of think- the distinctions between variable-oriented
ing about scientific explanation. Sayer and case-oriented approaches (Ragin,
(1992) argued: 1987), propositional knowledge and case
knowledge (Shulman, 1986), and factor
Much that has been written on methods theories and explanatory theories (Yin,
of explanation assumes that causation is 1993, pp. 15–21). Sayer (1992, pp. 241–251)
a matter of regularities in relationships similarly distinguished between extensive
between events, and that without models and intensive research designs; extensive
of regularities we are left with allegedly designs address regularities, common
inferior, “ad hoc” narratives. But social patterns, and distributions of features of
science has been singularly unsuccessful populations, whereas intensive designs
in discovering law-like regularities. One focus on how processes work in particu-
of the main achievements of recent real- lar cases.
ist philosophy has been to show that this These arguments suggests that realist,
is an inevitable consequence of an erro- process-oriented qualitative investigations
neous view of causation. Realism replaces deserve a more prominent place in social
the regularity model with one in which research, including experimental research,
objects and social relations have causal where they complement regularity-based
powers which may or may not produce quantitative research. Shadish et al. (2002),
regularities, and which can be explained in what is arguably the most detailed and
156–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

sophisticated presentation of the case for polarized confrontation between qualita-


experimental research, stated: tive and quantitative researchers on this
issue of causal investigation (Maxwell,
The unique strength of experimentation 2004a, 2004b, 2008). It recognizes the
is in describing the consequences attrib- explanatory importance of the context of
utable to deliberately varying a treat- the phenomena studied and does so in a
ment. We call this causal description. In way that does not simply reduce this con-
contrast, experiments do less well in text to a set of “extraneous variables.” It
clarifying the mechanisms through relies fundamentally on an understand-
which and the conditions under which ing of the processes by which an event or
that causal relationship holds—what we situation occurs, rather than simply a
call causal explanation. (p. 9) comparison of situations involving the
presence and absence of the presumed
Referring to a “delicate balance” cause. Finally, it legitimates a concern with
between causal descriptions and causal understanding particular situations and
explanations, they assert that “most exper- events, rather than addressing only general
iments can be designed to provide better patterns. A process theory of causation
explanations than is the case today” (p. 12) does not require abandoning quantitative,
and describe several studies in which quali- variance-based methods for investigating
tative methods were used to substantially causality; it simply requires recognition
strengthen the understanding of causal that process-based approaches are as legit-
mechanisms in experimental investigations imate as, and often complementary to
(pp. 390–392). variance-based ones.
Realist social researchers also place con-
siderable emphasis on the context dependence
of causal explanation (e.g., Huberman & MIND AS PART OF REALITY
Miles, 1985, p. 354; Sayer, 1992, pp. 60–61).
Pawson and Tilley (1997) sum up this posi- The neglect of mental phenomena, or the
tion in their formula “mechanism + context = attempt to deal with these solely within a
outcome” (p. xv). They maintain that “the behavioral, variable-oriented framework, is
relationship between causal mechanisms one of the main problems that qualitative
and their effects is not fixed, but contingent” researchers attribute to quantitative research,
(p. 69); it depends on the context within and one of the main arguments that qualita-
which the mechanism operates. This is not tive researchers make for adopting a con-
simply a claim that causal relationships vary structivist or interpretivist stance for research
across contexts; it is a more fundamental is that these approaches inherently recognize
claim, that the context within which a the important of the mental realm. However,
causal process occurs is, to a greater or the types of realism that we discuss here treat
lesser extent, intrinsically involved in that mental entities as equally real to physical ones
process, and often cannot be “controlled and as relevant to causal explanations of indi-
for” in a variance-theory sense without mis- vidual and social phenomena. Sayer (1992)
representing the causal mechanism (Sayer, stated that “social phenomena are concept-
2000, pp. 114–118). For the social sciences, dependent . . . What the practices, institu-
the social and cultural contexts of the phe- tions, rules, roles, or relationships are depends
nomenon studied are crucial for understand- on what they mean in society to its members”
ing the operation of causal mechanisms. (p. 30). Emotions, beliefs, values, and so on
We argue that a realist alternative to the are part of reality; they are not simply abstrac-
dominant regularity model of causality tions from behavior or constructions of the
can provide a way out of the somewhat observer. Realism in this sense, therefore, does
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––157

not entail materialism, nor is it simply a cover thus their role as essential components of
for a reductionist agenda that would attempt any full explanation of human action.
to eliminate mental concepts from scientific Realism can deal with the apparent dissimi-
discourse (Putnam, 1999, p. 74 ff.). larity of reason explanations and cause
However, realists are not dualists, postu- explanations by showing that reasons can
lating two different realms of reality, the plausibly be seen as real events in a causal
physical and the mental. In our view, the nexus leading to the action.
clearest and most credible analysis of this Realism also supports the idea that indi-
issue has been that of Putnam (1990, viduals’ social and physical contexts have a
1999), who argued for the legitimacy of causal influence on their beliefs and per-
both mental and physical ways of making spectives. While this proposition is widely
sense of the world. He advocated a distinc- accepted in everyday life, constructivists
tion between mental and physical perspec- have tended to deny the reality of such influ-
tives or languages, both referring to reality, ences, while positivism and some forms of
but from different conceptual standpoints. postpositivist empiricism tend to simply dis-
He argued that “the metaphysical realign- miss the reality or importance of individuals’
ment we propose involves an acquiescence perspectives, or to “operationalize” these to
in a plurality of conceptual resources, of behavioral variables. From a realist perspec-
different and mutually irreducible vocabu- tive, not only are individuals’ perspectives
laries . . . coupled with a return not to dual- and their situations both real phenomena,
ism but to the ‘naturalism of the common but they are separate phenomena that
man.’” (1999, p. 38) causally interact with one another.
Thus, while realism rejects the idea of Thus, a realist perspective can provide a
“multiple realities” in the sense of indepen- framework for better understanding the
dent and incommensurable worlds in which relationship between individuals’ perspec-
different individuals or societies live, it is tives and their actual situations. This issue
quite compatible with the idea that there has been a prominent concern in the philos-
are different valid perspectives on the ophy of social science for many years
world. However, it holds that these per- (e.g., MacIntyre, 1967/1970; Menzel, 1978),
spectives, as held by the people we study as and is central to “critical” approaches to
well as ourselves, are part of the world that qualitative research. Critical realism treats
we want to understand, and that our under- both individuals’ perspectives and their sit-
standing of these perspectives can be more uations as real phenomena that causally
or less correct (Phillips, 1987). interact with one another. In this, realism
A realist approach thus recognizes the real- supports the emphasis that critical theory
ity and importance of meaning, as well as of places on the influence that social and eco-
physical and behavioral phenomena, as hav- nomic conditions have on beliefs and ide-
ing explanatory significance, and the essen- ologies. Sayer (1992, pp. 222–223) stated
tially interpretive nature of our understanding that the objects of “interpretive” under-
of the former (Sayer, 2000, pp. 17–18). standing (meanings, beliefs, motives, and so
Combining this view with a process-oriented on) are influenced both by the material cir-
approach to causality can resolve the long- cumstances in which they exist and by the
standing perceived contradiction between cultural resources that provide individuals
“reason” explanations and “cause” explana- with ways of making sense of their situa-
tions and integrate both in explanatory theo- tions. However, critical realism approaches
ries. Weber’s (1905/1949) sharp distinction the understanding of this interaction with-
between causal explanation and interpretive out assuming any specific theory of the rela-
understanding obscured the importance of tionship between material and ideational
reasons as causal influences on actions, and phenomena, such as Marxism.
158–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

A realist perspective also legitimates validity. Both focus largely on the proce-
and clarifies the concept of “ideological dures used in collecting data and drawing
distortion”—that cultural forms may obscure inferences from these data. This is particu-
or misrepresent aspects of the economic or larly obvious in the movement for evidence-
social system or the physical environment— based research, which relies almost entirely
while affirming the causal interaction on the type of research design as the basis
between the physical and social environ- for assessing the validity of the results, with
ment and cultural forms. In particular, real- randomized experiments as the gold stan-
ism is compatible with what have been dard for design quality. However, it also
called ideological or non-reflectionist characterizes prominent approaches to
approaches to culture, in which cultural validity (or its analogues) in qualitative
forms that contradict aspects of social research.
structure may serve ideological functions A realist concept of validity is quite
that act to sustain the social system or con- different from these procedure-based
stitute adaptive responses to the physical or approaches. Validity, from a realist per-
social environment (e.g., Maxwell, 1978). spective, is not a matter of procedures,
An emphasis on causal processes rather but of the relationship between the claim
than regularities or laws in explaining and the phenomena that the claim is
sociocultural phenomena also allows expla- about (Hammersley, 1992; House, 1991;
nations to be tailored to single cases and Maxwell, 1992; Norris, 1983). Shadish
unique circumstances, so that different indi- et al. (2002) in what is currently the
viduals or social groups may have different definitive work on experimental and quasi-
responses to similar situations, depending experimental research, state:
on differences in specific personal or cul-
tural characteristics that are causally rele- Validity is a property of inferences. It is
vant to the outcome. not a property of designs or methods, for
the same designs may contribute to more
or less valid inferences under different
VALIDITY AND circumstances. . . . No method guaran-
INFERENCE QUALITY tees the validity of an inference. (p. 34;
italics in original)
Validity and quality are issues about which
qualitative and quantitative researchers Also, as argued by Keller in the passage
have had substantial disagreements. The types quoted in Example 2, a realist approach to
of validity (many qualitative researchers validity does not entail that concepts, theo-
don’t even use this term) employed in each ries, or claims “reflect” or “correspond to”
tradition have little overlap (Teddlie & reality, only that whether these claims
Tashakkori, 2003), and the basic assump- “work” depends on their relationship to a
tions involved in the two approaches are reality independent of our constructions
radically different. Teddlie and Tashakkori (cf. Barad, 2007). While critical realism
went so far as to recommend abandoning denies that we can have any objective per-
the term validity entirely in mixed methods ception of these phenomena to which we
research, arguing that the term has taken can compare our claims, it does not aban-
on such diverse meanings that it is losing don the possibility of testing these claims
its ability to communicate anything against evidence about the nature of the
(pp. 12, 36–37). phenomena.
Despite these differences, there is an We see this process of testing claims
important similarity between the typical against the evidence that is relevant to the
quantitative and qualitative approaches to claims as fundamental to a scientific
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––159

approach in general. However, the types of DIVERSITY AS A


evidence that are relevant to a claim depend REAL PHENOMENON
on the nature of the claim. A claim about
a person’s beliefs requires a different sort Finally, realism implies that diversity is
of evidence from a claim about the out- itself a real phenomenon. This fact is most
come of a randomized trial of a new drug. obvious in evolutionary biology, where vari-
Specifically, claims about meanings and per- ation among organisms is the precondition
spectives, which fall under the general cate- of evolutionary change. Lewontin (1973)
gory of interpretive claims, require quite argued that the Darwinian revolution
different sorts of evidence from claims about replaced a Platonic, idealist view of varia-
behavior, let alone claims about the rela- tion (that variations were simply imperfect
tionships between variables. A realist approximations to the ideal or type of a
approach to validity also entails that a valid species) with a realist view that saw actual
description, explanation, or interpretation variation as the fundamental fact of biology
not only must not be supported by evidence, and the cornerstone of evolutionary theory.
but must address plausible alternative Mayr (1982), arguing against the prevailing
descriptions, explanations, or interpreta- view that the most important characteristic
tions of the phenomenon about which the of a species is the normal type of the organ-
claim is made. ism, stated that “the most interesting para-
For these reasons, the main approach meter in the statistics of natural populations
to validity in experimental research is the actual variation, its amount, and its
(e.g., Shadish et al., 2002) is grounded in nature” (p. 47).
the concept of a validity threat—a possible Similar arguments about diversity have
way that a conclusion might be wrong— been made for the social sciences, as described
and ways to address these threats. However, above in discussing paradigms. However,
the emphasis has largely been on the designs both qualitative and quantitative research
and methods used to deal with these have tendencies, theoretical as well as
threats. This has been facilitated by the fact methodological, to ignore or suppress diver-
that this literature has, consistently with a sity in their goal of seeking general accounts,
regularity view of causality as inherently although in different ways (Maxwell, 1995).
general, dealt mainly with types of validity Quantitative research often aggregates data
threats, rather than emphasizing the actual across individuals and settings and ignores
ways a specific conclusion might be wrong individual and group diversity that cannot be
in a given study. The importance of the lat- subsumed into a general explanation
ter point is implicit in the realist argument (Shulman, 1986). Because of its emphasis on
above, that validity is not simply deter- general descriptions and causal theories, it
mined by procedures (although procedures tends to impose or generate wide-ranging but
are obviously relevant to the validity of a simplistic models that do not take account of
conclusion) but must be assessed in the spe- individual variation, unique contextual influ-
cific context of a particular study. It is also ences, diverse meanings, and idiosyncratic
an implication of a realist view of causality phenomena.
as inherently local rather than general. However, qualitative researchers also tend
A realist perspective on validity can thus to neglect diversity. Theoretically, this is often
be of value to mixed methods researchers the result of social theories that emphasize uni-
by focusing attention on the specific plausi- formity; such theories include a definition of
ble threats to the conclusions drawn in a culture as beliefs or practices that are shared by
given study, which depend on the context members of a society, and approaches to
and purposes of that study as well on the community and social order that assume a
methods used. dichotomy between consensus and conflict
160–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

(Maxwell, 1999). Methodologically, the sam- than an acknowledgment that realism has
ple size and sampling strategies used in quali- informed the research. For example,
tative studies are often inadequate to fully Weisner (2005), in his introduction to a col-
identify and characterize the actual diversity lection of papers on mixed methods studies
that exists in the setting or population studied of children’s development and family life,
and can lead to simplistic generalizations or paid homage to Campbell’s realist and mul-
the assumption of greater uniformity or agree- tiplist approach, saying that this skeptical
ment than actually exists. realism and holism “provides the context
Mixed methods research provides one and tradition for much of our work”
way to help overcome the theoretical and (pp. 5–6), but he doesn’t discuss how,
methodological characteristics that lead to specifically, realism did so.
the neglect of diversity. Qualitative methods As noted above, the one area in which
and approaches, which focus on particular realist perspectives have had a major influ-
phenomena and processes and their unique ence on mixed methods studies is in pro-
contexts, can help to overcome the biases gram evaluation. The work of Tilley
inherent in universalizing, variable-oriented (described in Pawson & Tilley, 1997) and
quantitative methods. Conversely, quantita- Mark et al. (2000; Henry et al., 1998),
tive methods can provide systematic evidence much of which combined qualitative and
for diversity and can help to correct a ten- quantitative approaches, has provided a
dency to ignore complexity and to focus on realist alternative to traditional ways of
typical characteristics and shared concepts conceptualizing program evaluations. In
and themes. However, doing so effectively addition, Pawson’s (2006) analysis of liter-
requires recognizing the reality of diversity. ature reviews for evidence-based policy
To sum up this section, we are not simply constitutes a major critique of standard
claiming that realism is a productive stance ways of integrating qualitative and quanti-
for mixed method research because it is com- tative results in a literature synthesis, and
patible with both qualitative and quantita- presents a realist alternative to these
tive research and treats the two perspectives approaches.
as equally valid and useful. We have also There is also the potential within realist
argued that realism has important implica- approaches for incorporating features high-
tions for both approaches, ones that push lighted by an emancipatory paradigm and
both qualitative and quantitative researchers promoting social justice (House, 1991); this
to examine more closely some issues that is a significant aspect of Bhaskar’s version
they typically dismiss or ignore. Realism can of critical realism, which has been more
therefore not only help to integrate the two prominent in Europe than in the United
approaches into a more coherent combina- States. Some important advances based on
tion, and promote closer and more equal critical realism have recently been made in
cooperation between qualitative and quanti- mixed methods research in accounting
tative researchers, but can serve to increase (Brown & Brignall, 2007; Covaleski &
the usefulness of both approaches. Dirsmith, 1983, 1990), operations manage-
ment (Mingers, 2000, 2006; Reed, 2005),
economics (Downward, Finch, & Ramsay,
♦ Applications of 2002; Fleetwood, 1999; Lawson, 1989,
Critical Realism in 1997, 1998, 2001; Olsen, 2004), political
Mixed Methods Practice science (Patomäki, 2002), medicine (Clark,
MacIntyre, & Cruikshank, 2007), and
nursing (Lipscomb, 2008; Stickley, 2006).
Explicit use of realist perspectives in mixed Modell (2007) used critical realism to
methods research is still relatively uncom- develop a unified approach for validating
mon and sometimes involves little more mixed methods research in accounting
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––161

management. He argues that whereas critical first and the gendered nature of poverty in
realism shows many similarities to, and has the second. She used both theoretical and
indeed borrowed key concepts from the methodological triangulation in these stud-
pragmatist tradition, it constitutes a more ies. Theoretically, she combined neoclassi-
relevant philosophical foundation to this cal, Marxist political economy and feminist
end. Based on examples from the field of political economy perspectives; method-
management accounting and budgeting in ologically, she used a survey of a random
the U.S. nursing area and the jute industry in sample of farmers, ethnographic observa-
Bangladesh (see Covaleski & Dirsmith, tions, in-depth interviews, family histories,
1983; Hoque & Hopper, 1994, 1997), and the analysis of documents and sec-
Modell’s work explicates how critical real- ondary data. Her results exposed deficien-
ism may inform management accounting cies in both the neoclassical and Marxist
research by effectively integrating qualitative approaches and showed the necessity of
and quantitative methods. The examples adding qualitative to quantitative methods
illustrate the role of context-specific condi- to understand the phenomena studied. She
tions that may be captured only through concludes with three rules of thumb for
deeper empirical probing and reconceptual- realist research: a complex and stratified
ization. In a later study, Covaleski and ontology, explicit value analysis, and get-
Dirsmith (1990) conceded that their quest ting behind the numbers and mathematical
for a deeper understanding of budgeting was models to causal mechanisms.
derived from a growing realization of the Within the field of psychiatry, where
problematic nature of the traditional, posi- hierarchy and control prevail, a critical real-
tivist approach. The authors describe ist perspective offers a model that does not
“freeing” themselves from a priori theories submit to the dominant discourse but
to develop a more contextualized understand- rather recognizes that service users now
ing of the lived experiences of interviewees, possess decision-making power, especially
and to produce a more multifaceted concep- in terms of being able to provide services
tualization of budgeting (Covaleski & that statutory services providers now
Dirsmith, 1990). require (Stickley, 2006). Based on a
In economics, critical realism points power/knowledge discourse, Stickley sug-
to the main limitations of neoclassical gested a critical realist framework that
economics (based on econometrics prin- offers a theoretical explanation for cause
ciples that are reductionist in nature and and change with an argument for an alter-
presuppose that concepts can be mea- native to accepted models of service user
sured, counted, manipulated, and cross- involvement. He argued that because men-
classified), and it provides a philosophical tal health nurses are often the workers who
and methodological foundation for a have the most contact with service users, it
broad set of alternative approaches (see is essential that they give consideration to
Downward et al., 2002; Downward & the philosophies and approaches that
Mearman, 2007; Fleetwood, 1999; underpin these models, which are emanci-
Lawson, 1989, 1997, 1998, 2001). In patory for people who use mental health
this regard, within economics, critical services.
realism supports Lawson’s view that the McEvoy and Richards (2006) justified
exclusive dependence on mathematical/ using a critical realist framework for mixed
statistical modeling in economics is mis- methods in a case study in nursing of how
guided (Castellacci, 2006). and why gatekeeping decisions emerge at
Olsen (2004) illustrated some of the lim- the interface between primary care and
itations of the latter approach in two stud- community mental health teams. The quan-
ies of Indian grain markets and peasant titative survey helped them to identify pat-
farmers, focusing on distress sales in the terns of practice, which were confirmed and
162–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

elaborated by the findings from semistruc- analysis (Bollingtoft, 2007), leading to the
tured interviews. Using mixed methods development of a theoretical model that
gave the inquiry a “better sense of balance explained why gatekeeping decisions tended
and perspective” (p. 66). In addition, the to emerge in the way they did.
findings from both approaches stimulated In summary, we believe that realist
retroductive reasoning, a process that perspectives and approaches can make
involves the construction of hypothetical important contributions to mixed methods
models as a way of uncovering the real research. These contributions involve not
structures, contexts, and mechanisms that simply an overall perspective within which
are presumed to produce empirical phe- qualitative and quantitative methods and
nomena (Bhaskar, 1978, 1986, 1989). In assumptions can be better integrated, but
addition, reliance on retroduction necessi- also specific insights and strategies that can
tates that the researcher is being explicit enable mixed methods researchers to better
about what is being done during the understand the contexts and processes they
process, including data collection and study.

Research Questions and Exercises

1. How does the realist perspective presented in this chapter fit with your own assumptions
about qualitative, quantitative, and mixed methods research? Has the chapter changed your
thinking about any of these? Do you disagree with any of the chapter’s arguments? Why?
2. How could you apply the specific realist approaches described here to an actual study
that you might conduct? What difference would these make in how you design and carry out
the study?
3. How does the perspective on mixed methods research presented in this chapter differ
from that in other chapters of the Handbook? How are these different views helpful to you in
understanding mixed methods research publications or thinking about how to do mixed
methods research?

♦ References Barad, K. (2007). Meeting the universe halfway:


Quantum physics and the entanglement of
matter and meaning. Durham, NC: Duke
Abbott, A. (2001). Chaos of disciplines. University Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Becker, H. S., Geer, B., Hughes, E. C., &
Abbott, A. (2004). Methods of discovery: Strauss, A. L. (1977). Boys in white:
Heuristics for the social sciences. New York: Student culture in medical school. Piscataway,
W. W. Norton. NJ: Transaction Books. (Original work
Archer, M., Bhaskar, R., Collier, A., Lawson, T., published 1961)
& Norrie, A. (Eds.). (1998). Critical real- Bergman, M. M. (Ed.). (2008a). Advances in
ism: Essential readings. London: Routledge. mixed methods research. London: Sage.
Baert, P. (1998). Social theory in the twentieth Bergman, M. M. (2008b). The straw men of the
century. New York: New York University qualitative-quantitative divide and their
Press. influence on mixed methods research. In
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––163

M. Bergman (Ed.), Advances in mixed meth- Conant, J., & Zeglen, U. M. (2002). Hilary
ods research (pp. 11–21). London: Sage. Putnam: Pragmatism and realism. London:
Bernstein, R. (1992). The new constellation: The Routledge.
ethical-political horizons of modernity- Covaleski, M. A., & Dirsmith, M. W. (1983).
postmodernity. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Budgets as a means of control and loose
Bhaskar, R. (1978). A realist theory of science coupling. Accounting, Organizations and
(2nd ed.). Brighton, UK: Harvester. Society, 8, 323–340.
Bhaskar, R. (1986). Scientific realism and Covaleski, M. A., & Dirsmith, M. W. (1990).
human emancipation. London: Verso. Dialectical tension, double reflexivity and
Bhaskar, R. (1989). Reclaiming reality: A critical the everyday accounting researcher: on
introduction to contemporary philosophy. using qualitative methods. Accounting,
London: Verso. Organizations and Society, 15, 543–547.
Biesta, G. (2010). Pragmatism and the philo- Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (2005).
sophical foundations of mixed methods Introduction: The discipline and practice of
research. In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie qualitative research. In N. K. Denzin &
(Eds.), SAGE handbook of mixed methods Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualita-
in social and behavioral research (2nd ed.). tive research (3rd ed., pp. 1–42). Thousand
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Oaks, CA: Sage.
Bollingtoft, A. (2007). A critical realist approach to Downward, P., Finch, J. H., & Ramsay, J.
quality in observation studies. In H. Neergaard (2002). Critical realism, empirical meth-
& J. P. Ulhoi (Eds.), Handbook of qualita- ods and inference: A critical discussion.
tive research methods in entrepreneurship. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 26,
Northampton MA: Edward Elgar. 481–500.
Brown, R., & Brignall, S. (2007). Reflections on Downward, P., & Mearman, A. (2007).
the use of a dual-methodology research Retroduction as mixed-methods triangula-
design to evaluate accounting and manage- tion in economic research: reorienting eco-
ment practice in UK university central admin- nomics into social science. Cambridge
istrative services, Management Accounting Journal of Economics, 31, 77–99.
Research, 18, 32–48. Ezzy, D. (2002). Qualitative analysis: Practice
Buchler, J. (1940). Introduction. In J. Buchler and innovation. London: Routledge.
(Ed.), The philosophy of Peirce: Selected Fielding, N. (2008). Analytic density, postmod-
writings. New York; Routledge & Kegan ernism, and applied multiple method
Paul. research. In M. Bergman (Ed.), Advances in
Campbell, D. T. (1988). Methodology and epis- mixed methods research (pp. 37–52).
temology for social science: Selected papers London: Sage
(S. Overman, Ed.). Chicago: University of Fleetwood, S. (1999). Critical realism in eco-
Chicago Press. nomics: Development and debate, London:
Castellacci, F. (2006). A critical realist inter- Routledge.
pretation of evolutionary growth theoriz- Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures.
ing. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 30, New York: Basic Books.
861–880. Greene, J. (2000). Understanding social pro-
Chambliss, D. (1989). The mundanity of excel- grams through evaluation. In N. K. Denzin
lence: An ethnographic report on stratifica- & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qual-
tion and Olympic swimmers. Sociological itative research (2nd ed., pp. 981–1000).
Theory 7, 70–86. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Clark, A. M., MacIntyre, P. D., & Cruickshank, J. Greene, J. (2007). Mixed methods in social
(2007). A critical realist approach to inquiry. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
understanding and evaluating heart health Greene, J., & Hall, J. (2010). Dialectics
programmes. Health, 11(4), 513–539. and pragmatism: Being of consequence.
164–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

In A. Tashakkori & E. Teddlie (Eds.), research. In D. N. Berg & K. K. Smith


SAGE handbook of mixed methods in (Eds.), Exploring clinical methods for social
social & behavioral research (2nd ed.). research (pp. 351–382). Beverly Hills, CA:
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Sage.
Guba, E. G., & Lincoln, Y. S. (1989). Fourth Johnson, B., & Gray, R. (2010). A history of
generation evaluation. Thousand Oaks, philosophical and theoretical issues for
CA: Sage. mixed methods research. In A. Tashakkori
Haack, S. (1998). Manifesto of a passionate & E. Teddlie (Eds.), SAGE handbook of
moderate. Chicago: University of Chicago mixed methods in social & behavioral
Press. research (2nd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA:
Haack, S. (2003). Defending science—within Sage.
reason. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Press. Kaplan, A. (1964). The conduct of inquiry.
Haack, S. (2006). Pragmatism, old and new: San Francisco: Chandler.
Selected writings. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Keller, E. F. (1992). Secrets of life, secrets of
Books. death: Essays on language, gender, and
Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of science. New York: Routledge.
what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Kulp, C. B. (Ed.). (1997). Realism/antirealism
Press. and epistemology. Lanham MD: Rowman
Hammersley, M. (1992). Ethnography and real- and Littlefield.
ism. In M. Hammersley, What’s wrong Kvale, S. (1995). Interviews: An introduction to
with ethnography? Methodological explo- qualitative research interviewing. Thousand
rations (pp. 43–56). London: Routledge. Oaks, CA: Sage.
Hammersley, M. (2008). Troubles with triangu- Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous
lation. In M. Bergman (Ed.), Advances in things: What categories reveal about the
mixed methods research (pp. 22–36). mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
London: Sage. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy
Hannerz, U. (1992). Cultural complexity: in the flesh: The embodied mind and its
Studies in the social organization of mean- challenge to western thought. New York:
ing. New York: Columbia University Press. Basic Books.
Henry, G., Julnes, J., & Mark, M. (1998). Realist Lawson, T (1989). Abstraction, tendencies and
evaluation: An emerging theory in support of stylized facts: A realist approach to eco-
practice (New Directions for Evaluation, nomic analysis. Cambridge Journal of
No. 78). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Economics, 13, 59–78.
Hoque, Z., & Hopper, T. (1994). Rationality, Lawson, T. (1997). Economics and reality.
accounting, and politics: A case study of London, Routledge.
management control in a Bangladeshi jute Lawson, T. (1998). Transcendental realism. In
mill. Management Accounting Research, 5, J. Davis, D. W. Hands, & U. Ma¨ki (Eds.),
5–30. The handbook of economic methodology.
Hoque, Z., & Hopper, T. (1997). Political and Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
industrial relations turbulence, competition Lawson, T. (2001). Reorienting economics.
and budgeting in the nationalised jute mills London, Routledge.
of Bangladesh. Accounting and Business Leplin, J. (1984). Introduction. In J. Leplin (Ed.),
Research, 27, 125–143 Scientific realism. Berkeley: University of
Howe, K. (2003). Closing methodological California Press.
divides. Boston: Kluwer Academic. Lewontin, R. C. (1973). Darwin and Mendel—
House, E. (1991). Realism in research. The materialist revolution. In J. Neyman
Educational Researcher, 20(6), 2–9. (Ed.), The heritage of Copernicus: Theories
Huberman, A. M., & Miles, M. B. (1985). “more pleasing to the mind.” Cambridge:
Assessing local causality in qualitative MIT Press.
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––165

Lipscomb, M. (2008). Mixed method in nursing Maxwell, J. A. (2004a). Causal explanation,


studies: A critical realist critique. Nursing qualitative research, and scientific inquiry
Philosophy, 9, 32–45. in education. Educational Researcher
MacIntyre, A. (1970). The idea of a social 33(2), 3–11.
science. In B. R. Wilson (Ed.), Rationality Maxwell, J. A. (2004b). Using qualitative meth-
(pp. 112–130). New York: Harper & Row. ods for causal explanation. Field Methods
(Reprinted from Aristotelian society 16(3), 243–264.
Supplement 41, 1967). Maxwell, J. A. (2005). Qualitative research
Manicas, P. T. (2006). A realist philosophy of design: An interactive approach (2nd ed.).
social science: Explanation and understand- Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
ing. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Maxwell, J. A. (2008). The value of a realist
Press. understanding of causality for qualitative
Mark, M. M., Henry, G. T., & Julnes, G. research. In N. Denzin (Ed.), Qualitative
(2000). Evaluation: An integrated frame- research and the politics of evidence
work for understanding, guiding, and (pp. 163–181). Walnut Creek, CA: Left
improving policies and programs. San Coast Press.
Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Maxwell, J. A., & Loomis, D. (2003). Mixed
Maxcy, S. (2003). Pragmatic threads in mixed methods design: An alternative approach.
method research in the social sciences: The In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie (Eds.),
search for multiple modes of inquiry and Handbook of mixed methods in social and
the end of the philosophy of formalism. In behavioral research (pp. 241–271).
A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie (Eds.), Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Handbook of mixed methods in social and Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological
behavioral research (pp. 51–89). Thousand thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheri-
Oaks, CA: Sage. tance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Maxwell, J. A. (1978). The evolution of Press.
Plains Indian kin terminologies: A non- McCawley, J. D. (1982). Thirty million theo-
reflectionist account. Plains Anthropologist ries of grammar. Chicago: University of
23, 13–29. Chicago Press.
Maxwell, J. A. (1990). Up from positivism (essay McEvoy, P., & Richards, D. (2006). Rationale
review of DT Campbell, Methodology and for using a combination of quantitative and
epistemology for social science). Harvard qualitative methods. Journal of Research in
Educational Review, 60, 497–501. Nursing, 11, 66–78.
Maxwell, J. A. (1992). Understanding and valid- Menzel, H. (1978). Meaning—who needs it? In
ity in qualitative research. Harvard M. Brenner, P. Marsh, & M. Brenner
Educational Review, 62, 279–300. (Eds.), The social contexts of method (pp.
Maxwell, J. A. (1995). Diversity and methodol- 140–171). New York: St. Martin’s Press.
ogy in a changing world. Pedagogía 30, Mingers, J. (2000). The contribution of criti-
32–40. cal realism as an underpinning philoso-
Maxwell, J. A. (1999). A realist/postmodern phy for OR/MS and systems, Journal of
concept of culture. In E. L. Cerroni-Long the Operational Research Society, 51,
(Ed.), Anthropological theory in North 1256–1270.
America (pp. 143–73). Westport, CT: Mingers, J. (2006). A critique of statistical mod-
Bergin & Garvey. elling in management science from a critical
Maxwell, J. A. (2002). Realism and the role of realist perspective: its role within multi-
the researcher in qualitative psychology. methodology, Journal of the Operational
In M. Kiegelmann (Ed.), The role of Research Society, 57, 202–219.
the researcher in qualitative psychology. Modell, S. (2007). Integrating qualitative and
Tuebingen, Germany: Verlag Ingeborg Huber. quantitative methods in management
166–––◆–––Conceptual Issues: Philosophical, Theoretical, Sociopolitical

accounting research: A critical realist Ragin, C. C. (1987). The comparative method:


approach. Unpublished manuscript, Moving beyond qualitative and quantitative
Manchester Business School (Manchester) strategies. Berkeley: University of California
and School of Accounting, University of Press.
Technology, Sydney. Reed, M. (2005). Reflections on the “realist
Mohr, L. B. (1982). Explaining organizational turn” in organization and management
behavior. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. studies. Journal of Management Studies,
Mohr, L. B. (1996). The causes of human behav- 42, 1621–1644.
ior: Implications for theory and method in Reichardt, C. S., & Cook, T. D. (1979). Beyond
the social sciences. Ann Arbor: University qualitative versus quantitative methods. In
of Michigan Press. T. D. Cook & C. S. Reichardt (Eds.),
Norris, S. P. (1983). The inconsistencies at the Qualitative and quantitative methods in
foundation of construct validation theory. program evaluation (pp. 7–32). Thousand
In E. R. House (Ed.), Philosophy of evalua- Oaks CA: Sage.
tion (New Directions for Program Eva- Rosenau, P. M. (1992). Post-modernism and the
luation, No. 19, pp. 53–74). San Francisco: social sciences. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Jossey-Bass. University Press.
Olsen, W. (2004). Methodological triangulation Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation
and realist research: An Indian exemplar. In and the causal structure of the world.
B. Carter & C. New, Making realism work: Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Realist social theory and empirical research Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific
(pp. 135-150). London: Routledge. explanation. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon
Patomäki, H. (2002). After international rela- (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 3–219).
tions: critical realism and the (re)construc- Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
tion of world politics. London: Routledge. Press.
Patton, M. Q. (2001). Qualitative research and Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explana-
evaluation methods (3rd ed.). Thousand tion. New York: Oxford University Press.
Oaks, CA: Sage. Sayer, A. (1992). Method in social science: A real-
Pawson, R. (2006). Evidence-based policy: ist approach (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.
A realist perspective. London: Sage. Sayer, A. (2000). Realism and social science.
Pawson, R., & Tilley, N. (1997). Realistic eval- London: Sage.
uation. London: Sage. Schwandt, T. A. (1997). Qualitative inquiry: A
Phillips, D. C. (1987). Philosophy, science, and dictionary of terms. Thousand Oaks, CA:
social inquiry: Contemporary methodologi- Sage.
cal controversies in social science and Shadish, W. R., Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T.
related applied fields of research. Oxford, (2002). Experimental and quasi-experimental
UK: Pergamon Press. designs for generalized causal inference.
Pitman, M. A., & Maxwell, J. A. (1992). Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Qualitative approaches to evaluation. In Shulman, L. (1986). Paradigms and programs.
M. D. LeCompte, W. L. Millroy, & J. In M. C. Wittrock (Ed.), Handbook of
Preissle (Eds.), The handbook of qualitative research on teaching (3rd ed.). New York:
research in education (pp. 729–770). Macmillan.
San Diego: Academic Press. Smith, J. K., & Deemer, D. K. (2000). The
Putnam, H. (1990). Realism with a human face problem of criteria in the age of relativism.
(J. Conant, ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.),
University Press. Handbook of qualitative research (2nd ed.,
Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord: Mind, pp. 877–896). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
body, and world. New York: Columbia Stickley, T. (2006). Should service user involve-
University Press. ment be consigned to history? A critical
Realism as a Stance for Mixed Methods Research–––◆–––167

realist perspective. Journal of Psychiatric (Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in


and Mental Health Nursing, 13, 570–577. social and behavioral research (pp. 3–50).
Tashakkori, A., & Teddlie, C. (1998). Mixed Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
methodology: Combining qualitative and Wallace, A. F. C. (1970). Culture and personal-
quantitative approaches. Newbury Park ity (2nd ed.). New York: Random House.
CA: Sage. Weber, M. (1949). Critical studies in the logic of
Tashakkori, A., & Teddlie, C. (2003). The past the social sciences. In M. Weber, The method-
and future of mixed methods research: ology of the social sciences. New York: The
From data triangulation to mixed model Free Press. (Reprinted from Archiv fuer
designs. In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, 1905)
(Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in Weisner, T. S. (2005). Discovering successful
social and behavioral research (pp. 671–701). pathways in children’s development: Mixed
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. methods in the study of childhood and
Teddlie, C., & Tashakkori, A. (2003). Major family life. Chicago: University of Chicago
issues and controversies in the use of mixed Press.
methods in the social and behavioral sci- Yin, R. (1993). Applications of case study
ences. In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

View publication stats

You might also like