Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Family interaction and psychopathology: Theories,

methods, andfindings (pp. 67-116). New York: Plenum. child temperament Journal of Consulting and Clinir
Straus, M. A. (1964). Measuring families. In H. T. Chris- Psychology, 56, 473-477. 1
tensen (Ed.), Handbook of marriage and thefamily (pp. Walker, L. S., McLaughlin, J. F., & Greene, J, W. (19sg^
335—400). Chicago: Rand McNally.
Functional illness and family functioning: A compariSon
Straus, M. A. (1969). Family measurement techniques: Ab­ of healthy and somaticizing adolescents. Family Proces CHAPTER 9
stracts of published Instruments, 1935—1965. 14, 317-324.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Wampler, K. S. (1982). Bringing the review of litcraturc int
Straus, M. A. (1981). Protecting human subjects in observa- the age of quantification: Meta-analysis as a strategy f0
tional research: The case of family violence. In E. E. Fil- integrating research findings in family studies,7onrua/
singer & R. A. Lewis ( Eds.), Assessing marriage (pp. 272— Marriage and the Family, 44, 1009-1024.
286). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Wampler, K. S., & Halverson, C. F. (1990). The Georgjj
Straus, M. A., & Brown, B. W. (1978). Family measurement
techniques: Abstracts of published instruments, 1935-
marriage q-sort: An observational measurc of marital
functioning. American Journal of Family Therapy, /g Structural—Functionalism
1974 (rev. ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
169-178.
Wampler, K. S., Halverson, C. F., Moore.J. J., & Wakers, L. H
ii
Straus, M. A., & Tallman, I. (1971). simfam: A technique for
observational measurement and experimental study of
(1989). The Georgia family q-sort: An observational mea-
c Nancy Kingsbury and John Scanzoni
sure of family functioning, Family Process, 14, 223-238
families. In J. Aldous (Ed,), Family problem solving (pp.
Weiss, R. I„, & Perry, B. A. (1983) The spouse observation
380—438). Hinsdale, IL: Dryden.
checklist; Development and clinical applications. In H. E.
Strosahl, K. D., & Linehan, M. M. (1986). Basic issues in
Filsinger (Ed ), Marriage and family assessment (pp
behavioral assessment. In A. R. Ciminero, D. S. Calhoun, & 65-85). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
H. E. Adams (Eds.), Handbook of behavioral assessment
Weiss, R. L, Hops, H„ & Patterson, G. R. (1973). A frame- Introduction Main Problems and Questions
(pp. 12-46). New York: Wiley,
work for conceptualizing marital conflict: A technology
Szinovacz, M. E. (1987). Family power. In M. B. Sussman &
for altering it, some data for evaluating it. In F W. Clark & f In unraveling the essence of Talcott Parsons
S. K. Steinmetz (Eds.), Handbook of marriage and the Our task in this chapter is unique and thus extra-
family. New York: Plenum.
L. A. Hammcrlynck ( Eds.), Critica! issues in research and
]I ordinarily challenging. The task is unique bccause (the progenitor in the late 1930s of American
practice. Proceedings of the fourth Banff conference on functionalism), no one is more eloquent than
Terraan, L. M. (1938). Psychological factors in married
behavior modification. Champaign, IL: Research Press. unlike the remaining theory chapters, we consider
happiness. New York: McGraw-Hill. a framework that has become virtually obsolete Jeflfrey Alexander (1990), a vigorous proponent of
Wiggins, J. S. (1982). Circumplex models of interpersonal
Thompson, L., & Walker, A. J. (1982), The dyad as the unit
behavior in clinical psychology In P. C. Kendall & F. N. throughout general sociology (Coleman, 1990). weo-functionalism;
of analysis: Conceptual and methodological issues.
Butcher (Eds ), Handbook of research methods in Thirty years ago, structural—functionalism (or There is a profound moralism at the heart of Parsons’
Journal of Marriage and the Family, 44, 889-900. clinical psychology (pp. 183-222). New York; Wiley. simply, functionalism) occupied a central place in theory. His actors are imbued with a desire to be
Tomm, K (1986). On incorporating the therapist in a scien-
Winter, W D„ & Ferreira, A. J (Eds.) ( 1969). Research in good, and they are understood as trying to conform
tiflc theory of family therapy. Journal of Marital and family anthologies (Mdntyrc, 1966; Pitts, 1964).
family interaction: Readings and commentary. Palo with principles that express this moral aspira-
Family Therapy, 12, 373—378.
Alto, CA: Science and Behavior Books. 1 But in more recent collections, no one noticed or
Touliatos, J., Perlmutter, B. F., & Straus, M. A. (Eds.) (1990). f cared that it was omitted (Burr et ai, 1979; Sus­
tion. . . . [And because] human beings. . , . Have the
Woehrer, C. E. (1988). Ethnic families in the circumplex ability to make choices . . . normative standards of
Handbook offamily measurement techniques. Newbury sman & Steinmetz, 1987). Nevertheless, this book
model: Integrating nuclear with extended family Sys­ evaluation become essential. (p. 342)
Park, CA: Sage.
tems. Journal of Psychotherapy and the Family, 4, must address functionalism (1) because of its his­
Victor, J. B,, Halverson, C. F., & Wampler, K. S. (1988). 199-238. Much earlier (Parsons, 1951, p. 42) labeled those
torie significance for studies of families, and (2)
because functinalist assumptions remain central to ideas as the “sociologistic theorem,” and in ex-
■ family sociology and family studies, in spite of ar- plaining the theorem, one of Parsons’s most influ-

II
I
guments to the contrary (Brodcrick, 1971a;
Holman & Burr, 1980). To understand why func­
ential students said that
In the . . . perfect case, conformity to institu-
tionalism was once considered important, then tionalized role-expectations brings gratifying re-
feil into disreputc, but continues to be significant sponses from akers, is instrumentally effective, and is
i for family research, we must first grasp what it was a source of direct gratification as welf Everyone
wants to do that which others want him to do, and
and is trying to say. others always act as he expects and wishes. . . . Al-
though such perfect integration is . . . not found em-
pirically . . , normative integration is . . . regarded
I
I
B1
Nancy Kingsbury • Department of Family Sciences,
Texas Woman’s University, Denton, Texas 76204 (Formerly:
bept. of Family Studies, University of Manitoba). John
as fundamental in all actual social Systems. (Williams,
1961, p, 75)
Scanzoni • Department of Sociology, University of Flor According to Alvin Gouldner (1970), Parsons be-
: •da, Gainesville, Florida 32611. lieved that “behavior is accounted for by efforts to
Sourcebook ofFamily Theories and Methods: A Contextual conform with an internalized moral code . . .
. APproach. Editcd by P.G. Boss, WJ. Doherty, R. LaRossa,
where, it is emphasized, men need pay no heed to
Wft. Schumm, & S.K. Steinmetz. New York; Plenum Press,
New York, 1993.
consequences but seek to conform to the code for
196 197
PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930 cHAPTEr 9 • STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM

its own saké” (p. 139). “Parsons tacitly assumes satisfy the physical and psychological nceds of • “instrurnental” and “expressive.” Instrumental ac- was integral to a major theoretical issue that lies at
what Durkheim explicitly postulated, that the members and also to maintain the larger socieu jivities are assigned to the husband-father both the core of all his work.
main function of moral values is to restrain men’s Societal maintenance depended on the transmis . dominant values and norms, but also out of From the very beginning. . . . Over and over again,
wants and claims” (p. 241), Parsons (1965) be- sion of values and norms from parents to chil(jreri ^ioiogical necessity (Pitts, 1964). The biological now from one perspective, now from another, we
lieved that what he called “solidarity” is crucial through the socialization process. It was imper thetnes followed by Parsons were Freudian in ori- are brought back to the broad question of the condi-
for the adequate functioning of a social system. ative that children be socialized so that they werg ein; in his later work those themes became tions for system-raaintenance or “equilibrium." The
Solidarity is members’ “motivational readiness to motivated to take on specialized adult roles: “Cni part played by common values in social stability and
“strong and pervasive” (Williams, 1961, p. 65). As
accept their common belongingness as members tural values and other patterns can become inter change has been a focus of analysis in all of Parsons’
jjje “instrumental hub” of the family, the “task- major works. Continually, we fmd attention directcd
of a collective system and to trust each other nalized in the personality system and, hence, af oriented” man specializes in being the breadwin- to the Hobbesian problem: how is order in society
to fulfil mutual expectations attached to mem- fect that system’s need structure, which, in turn ner or chief, if not sole, provider of the family’s possible? . . . [How can] the war of each against all
bership in their respective roles” (p. 38). The determines an actor’s willingness to enact roles in sociocconomic needs, By coping with the vagaries [be prevented]? (Williams, 1961, p. 66)
essence, then, of functionalism is “Actor’s” the social system” (Turner, 1978, p. 35). and onslaughts of the external world, he protects
conformity to a set of preexisting standards that Parsons’s foundational or bedrock response to the
To perform its functions in an optimal fash- the family from “disequilibrium.” In complemen-
promotes the greater good of the larger whole to ion, that is, increase its degree of “functionality" question of societal survival was shared values and
tary fashion, expressive activities are assigned to
which Actor belongs. norms. In the family, for example, he argued that if
the wife-mother also by culture and biology. As
'ZIf that is so, a pivotal question becomes, what (Winch, 1963), the family must have a particular men and women properly learned and effectively
kind of structure. Structure is the “arrangement of the “expressive hub,” the “person-oriented”
is the “greater good?” To answer that question, we woman specializes in enhancing emotional rela­ enacted their instrumental and expressive roles,
the roles of which a socjal 'system is composed” respectively, then family stability would be en-
consider some “basic assumptions” of func­ (Mclntyre, 1966, p. 60). Ifhe term “social system” tions among family members; “While the hus­
tionalism (Mclntyre, 1966, p. 63). First among is absolutely crucial to functionalists; it is the band-father is away at work the mother may stay sured and societal order enhanced. Nevertheless,
these is that “certain functional requirements broader construct under which “structure,” that home, responsible for the emotional satisfactions Williams (1961) observes that in Parsons’s later
must be satisfied if a society is to survive at a given is, role arragement, is subsumed (Bell & Vogel of the family and symbolizing the integrative focus work, “the existence of a common value system
level.” Fundamentally, “greater good” means “sur­ has itself become a problem” (p. 66). Parsons
1960). Mclntyre (1966, p. 58) observes that a sys­ of the home” (Mclntyre, 1966, p. 60). She pro­
vival.” functionalists assert that the “whole,” for tects the family from disequilibrium stemming became painfully aware of the reality that sim-
tem has four “defining properties.” First, a social ply knowing what “good and moral” persons
example, the groups and society to which Actor system such as the family has “differentiated” or from unsatisfactory emotional relations, Accord­
belongs, “must” survive—they must persist and specialized kinds of roles. Below, we discuss the ing to Parsons, this type of gender role specializa­ “should” do is in and of itself insufficiënt to moti-
endure. To promote survival, a second assumption idea that role specialization increases a system’s vate them to behave accordingly. Consequently,
tion maintained family equilibrium while enabling
(p. 63) is that “functional subsystems” exist for functionality. Second, the roles are organized the family to perform its prime functions of re- Parsons’s later work addresses “power and politi-
that very purpose or “function.” Function is de- around shared values and norms that establish the cal processes. . . [Along with] deviance, alienation,
production and socialization:
fmed (p. 54) as “the contribution that an item actors’ rights and obligations to one another, and and social control” (p. 66).
makes to the maintenance of the whole.” Hence, thus to society as well. Third, “a system is bound- In our opinion the fundamental explanation of the Moreover, his later work, pervaded (as we
the family is an example of a subsystem that func- ary-maintaining” because internal actors are more allocation of the roles between the biological sexes saw) by Freudian themes, gave a “strikingly en­
tions, or operates, for the survival and mainte­ tightly bound to each other than they are to exter- lies in the fact that the hearing and early nursing of hanced focus [to] the microsociology of interper-
children establishes a presumption that the man, sonal relations” (Williams, 1961, p. 66). Such “re­
nance of society. Hence, the family’s purpose or nal actors. Finally, and most important, a social
who is exempted from these biological functions, lations” included the family, and the issue over
function is to foster societal survival First by pro- system has a"tendency toward homeostasis, or should specialize in the alternative instrumental di-
ducing new members; “Replacements for dying equilibrium, which means that it has “built-in which Parsons agonized most in this regard was
rection. (Parsons et al., 1955, p. 23)
members of the society must be provided” (p. mechanisms which operate to hold it in some sort what in addition to shared norms would keep hus-
67). Second, these “human replacements must be of steady state, either a static or moving stability, Parsons held that deviance from these roles would bands and wives from deviating from prescribed
trained to become participating members of the lead to “family disorganization” as measured by roles. He was troubled by “the continuous ‘veer­
over a period of time” (Mclntyre, 1966, p. 59). ing off-course’ of social actors from the cultural
society” (p. 67). Since “society” is defined as “a Below we argue that this issue is the central con- divorce and juvenile delinquency. Thus, when
social system which survives its original members ceptual problem of contemporary family studies. men and women conform to prescribed roles blueprint. He sees this recalcitrance to conformity
[and] replaces them through biological reproduc- scripted by shared values and norms, the greater arising from constitutional diffcrences among indi-
In passing, we should note that in addition to viduals, idiosyncratic [role] learning . . . and from
tion” (Winch, 1963, p. 8), then children must be social system, Parsons often spoke of the culture, good of two larger wholes is achieved: the wholes
born to the family and in turn socialized to con­ or value system, and also of the personality sys­ being the family itself, as well as the larger society. several other sources” (Williams, 1961, p. 86). To
form to the society’s culture, that is, its dominant tem. Bell and Vogel (1960) describe connections By enhancing family equilibrium, societal equi­ overcome actors’ seemingly inherent proclivities
values and norms. The nuclear family was defmed among these three systems in conjunction with librium was simultaneously reinforced. And that toward deviance, Parsons posited the existence of
by Pitts (1964) as the “socially sanctioned co- encapsulates the central image of structural—func­ social control mechanisms. Among these was the
the family.'Furthermore, they spell out what they “need” of actors in a system to “counteract a ten-
habitation of a man and woman who have prefer- call reciprocal “interchanges” between the family tionalism: The family, organized around a unique
ential or exclusive enjoyment of economie and and the economie, politica!, and community and unalterable type of role structure, operates dency to deviance [by their alters] from the fulfill-
sexual rights over one another and are committed subsystems, or functions for something larger than itself. ment of role-expectations” through applying re-
to raise the children brought to life by the wom­ For Parsons the question of homeostasis, or wards and punishments (Parsons, 1951, p. 206).
According to Parsons’s colleagues Bales and If, for instance, the husband conforms in superior
an” (p. 56). Defined in this manner, functionalists Slater (1955, p. 259), adult roles in the family are equilibrium, that is, stability under stress and
viewed the family as the structure most able to divided into specialized sets of activities called strain from outside of and within social systems, fashion to his role obligation to provide, then the
198 PART IV FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930.
r'<xir»TTj'-''T'Tto at er nvrr’T'Tnxr A T IQM 199
1945 cHAPrEH9
wife rewards and reinforces him with affection frustrations attendant upon continuing to scek ectations which are shared and recognized as explaining the “need” for role specialization, Par­
and deference, thus warding off mere mediocre these rewards.” Among other things, they are P^timate within a social system.” However, Co- sons added biological determinism. Consequently,
conformity (deviance) (Scanzoni, 1966, 1968, oblivious to negative sanctions imposed on thctn ^en (like Merton) départs significantly from Par­ Parsons “went wrong” not merely because of his
1970). But if the husband provides at a low level to try to get them to conform. Merton’s final qe os by rejecting the idea that deviance neces- “simplistic” view of social life, but also because of
or not at all, then the wife “punishes” him with viance category is rebellion, and while the thrce ;iv leads to disorganization. Instead, Cohen his attempt to shore up that view by resorting to
low affection and less deference, In Parsons’s ; garuy ... . . , Freudian ideas.
prior types have ventured somewhat beyond par. afgues that systems are in disorganization only to
view, negative sanctions would motivate the hus­ sons’s ideas, this takes us a Virtual quantum lcap the degree that they depart from “continued or-
band to increase his role obligation to provide; Although men of this type reject both culturally derlV functioning—that is, functioning in accor-
but William Goode (1959) observed that one approved goals and means, they simultaneously j^ce with their own constitutive rules” (1959, p. Historie Foundations
“dysfunction” of her sanctions may be divorce. “seek to bring into being a new, that is to say, a I 479)-
[“Dysfunction” is “the negative consequences of In effect, Cohen says that deviance leads to Besides the influence of Freud, Parsons’s
greatly modified social structure” (p. 155). They
an activity for a given System” (Mclntyre, 1966, p. agitate for the acceptance of fresh goals and means disorganization only to the extent that it under- thinking regarding “shared values” derived from a
61).] mine5 t^ie sytem s “orderly functioning.” If de­ long-standing intellectual tradition that can be
Examples would be nineteenth-century “Bohe-
Besides Parsons, many of his influential stu- viance occurs, but functioning continues anyhow, traced back to Aristotle and Plato, and on through
mians,” 1950s beatniks, and the 1960s counter­
dents likewise wrestled with ways to control veer­ tjten the system remains “organized” and is not the eighteenth-century Scottish Moral Philoso-
culture. Men and woraen in these categories argue
ing ffom the “blueprint,” that is, deviance. In most disorganized. For example, if a mother ceases to phers. Many pre-twentieth-century social thinkers
for instance, that material success is corrosive and
cases, by responding to critiques of Parsons’s the- be the expressive hub but an older sister in the were grappling with the Hobbesian problem of so­
should be replaced with goals of spiritual and intel-
ories, his students went considerably beyond him household takes on that role, then the family is cial order. Thomas Hobbes, a seventeenth-century
lectual development; and that laboring to achieve
by seeking to make his ideas more congruent with likely to continue “functioning.” Merton used the social philosopher, viewed humans as self-in-
success is ultimately sterile and should be replaced
empirical realities. Among those students was term “functional equivalent” to describe situa­ terested beings who were in constant danger of
with efforts to explore the meanings and depths of
Robert Merton (1957), who proposed a classic humanness. tions in which a system goal (e.g., nurturance) is “the war of each against all.” The problem of order
“typology of deviant behavior” (p. 140). If we use achieved by other than institutionalized means became paramount in the minds of many social
This last category of “deviance” is highly
as an example the husband’s role obligation to be (older sister). Unlike Merton, Cohen does not ad- thinkers following political unrest and social up-
important because a major functionalist thinker
what Bernard (1981) calls a “good-provider,” we dress conditions under which systems create new heavals beginning with the eighteenth-century
squarely addresses the central complaint made by
turn to the first category in Merton’s typology, norms. Nevertheless, by showing that deviance French Revolution. In addition, nineteenth-century
Parsons’s critics: “In Parsons’ writing there is no
which is conformity, that is, nondeviance. When does not necessarily undermine stability and European urbanization and industrialization cre-
true embrace of the idea that structure is being
Actor (the husband) accepts both the “culture order, Cohen reinforces the possibility that de­ ated social and political strains that contributed to
continuously opened up and reconstructed by the
goals” to be a good provider as well as the cultur- viance and social order may coexist indefinitely. the concern for order. At the same time, the biolog­
problem-solving behavior of individuals respond­
ally approved “means” to achieve that goal (hard “How and why did Parsons go wrong?” asks ical Sciences were unraveling the mysteries of
ing to concrete situations” (Sclznick, 1961, p.
work and achievement in the occupational Sys­ James Coleman (1990, p. 338). Because, he con- bodily functions; and evolutionary ideas of adapta-
934). By arguing that deviance from role expecta-
tem), he is highly rewarded by both the society cludes, “Parsons . . . saw the relations between tion and survival were creating controversy and
tions would not necessarily undermine social sta-
and his wife. Merton’s second category was different persons’ interests (or values) in a sim- stimulating intellectual thought. Consequently, a
bility and societal order, Merton “embraced” the
innovation, in which Actor (husband) accepts plistic way. For him, action is social through the number of social philosophers used the human
idea of genuine change. And he went still further
the goal of material success but rejects the ap­ existence of common values which generale body as an analogy for society. The “organic analo-
by describing some of the mechanisms generating
proved means to achieve it, and instead adopts norms.” Recall, however, that Williams (1961) ar- gy” is based on the idea that society, like the body, is
change, as well as by describing the kind of new
illegal means for success and is thus deviant. Alters gued that one reason Parsons introduced Freudian a cohesive whole served by its parts. Moreover, just
social order that might emerge. Moreover, unlike
feel torn between rewarding him for his success
but sanctioning him negatively for his deviance.
A third category of deviance is ritualism in
Parsons who viewed the family as the place where
children learned only culturally approved values
and norms, Merton ( 1957, p. 158) considered the
I notions into his later schemas was precisely be­
cause he became conscious of the limitations of
the “shared value” approach. Parsons (1950) ap-
as bodily health is measured by observing whether
its parts are functioning properly or not (e.g., arms
and legs are present and movable), societal health
which the husband rejects the goals but not the parently believed that biology would reinforce his was likewise observed through the “proper” func­
part “played by the family in these patterns of
means. Merton deflnes this as a “scaling down” of view of social stability; and the implications of tioning of its parts. A well-fimctioning body is said
deviant behavior.” Merton suggested varied con-
achievement goals. The husband gives up wantlng ; Freudian themes for the family were laid out most to be in a state of equilibrium, and the same was
ditions under which children’s socialization ex-
to be a “success,” but not the idea of “hard work.” clearly by one of his students (Pitts, 1964). And alleged to be true about society. In addition to
pcriences in their families might influence them
Nonetheless, no matter how hard he tries, he is although in their own essay elaborating Parsons’s being able to ascertain equilibrium in both bodies
to move in one or more of the four deviant di-
unable to fulflll his wifc’s good provider expecta- rections. notions, Bell and Vogel (1960) strayed little into and societies, it was argued that societies and their
tions. A fourth category of deviance is retreatism, Freudian territory, other contributors to their an- parts experience evolution just as organisms do.
During this same period, Albert Cohen
describing husbands who give up both cultural thology were more explicit in connecting Freud A. R. Radcliffe-Brown (1952) observed that
(1959), another of Parsons’s influential students,
goals and means, for example, “vagrants, vaga- to the family. The basic functionalist argument the eighteenth-century philosopher Montesquieu
also sought to elaboratc the ideas of deviant
bonds, tramps, chronic drunkards, and drug ad­ Was that husbands and wives are biologically “pre- was perhaps the first to talk about societies as
behavior and “social disorganization.” Recall that
dicts” (Merton, 1957, p. 153). Merton observes disposed” to fulfill their instrumental and ex- “social systems,” and to describe them via the
Parsons saw the former inevitably pressing to-
(p. 155) that “if they have none of the rewards pressive roles (Pitts, 1964). Thus, to the degree organic analogy, or “organicism.” The goal of eigh­
ward the latter. Like Parsons, Cohen (p. 462) de-
held out by society [they] also have few of the that cultural determinism might be insufficiënt in teenth-century social philosophy, following the
fincs the former as “behavior which violates ■
200 • STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM 201
PART IV • FAMU.Y THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930,
~1945 ■ü CBAFTER
lead of the biological Sciences, was to organize had very little to offer sociologists attempting to lies. Simmel believed that although cultural forms
functionalism, namely that a “future consequence
society by classificatory schemes. The early nine- “become fixed . . . they stand in . . . perpetual
of an event causes that very event to occiir’> study complex societies.”
teenth-century French phüosopher Auguste Com- tension with the ongoing life processes, which
(Turner, 1974, p. 19). Don Martindale (196q)
te (1875) (the “father” of sociology) introduced bring about recurrent efforts to modify those
noted that prior to Parsonian functionalism, “func,
“positivism” into social thought, thus marking a forms or create new ones” (Levine et al, 1976, p.
tion . . . had been treated as a dependent variable Early American Sociology
shift front merely philosophical logic to a “scien- or faculty of a fixed structure or form. Now all ihjs 824),
tific” perspective based on empirical observa- precisely because the pioneers of American In short, a major theme pervading main-
was reversed and function was regardcd as the
tions. Comte’s conceptions of society were sociology were prcoccupicd with “complex so­ stream sociology prior to Parsons (1937) was di-
independent variable while form or structure was
“organic” because he viewed it as a living entity cieties,” they had much less affinity for the “soci­ alectics, a process of change and progression de­
demoted to second place” (p. 443). Martindale
analogous to biological organisms. Comte used a ety as an organism” analogy (also called “holism”) scribed, in modern times, by the phüosopher
illustrated this notion with an extreme example-
favorite term of Parsons—solidarity—to refer to than they did for the oppositc intellectual per­ George Wilhelm Hegcl (1770—1831), and subse-
“whcreas in the past it was assumed that a man
interconnectedness in social life. Comte also con- spective that society is a “multiplicity of parts” quently referred to as the “Hegelian dialectic.”
had a pair of legs (structure) and he walked, now
ceived of “consensus,” another Parsonian term, as struggling to achieve order, that is, nominalism Persons and groups (AB) create social arrange-
it is assumed that a man walks (function) and this
the source of social unity. According to Parsons (Jesser, 1975, p. 83). Like organicism, the roots of ments to achieve certain goals—thesis. Inevitably,
activity produces a pair of legs” (p, 443). For ex­
(1982), Durkheim transformed Comte’s idea of nominalism can be traced to the ancient Greek A and/or B challenge existing arrangements—an­
ample, the functionalist answer to the existence of
consensus into his famous conscience collective. philosophers and on into the nineteenth century. tithesis. Consequently, over time, the arrange­
social structures such as the family was that they
Squarely in the nominalist tradition, Albion W. ments are either altered, or new arrangements are
are “explained by the functiorts that they serve for
Small established the first department of sociology devised—synthesis. Although over time that syn-
society” (Collins, 1988, p. 54).
The Influence of Durkheim in the United States at the University of Chicago in thesis becomes established as a new thesis, it is
1892. Small had studied in Berlin with Georg Sim- inevitably challenged by subsequent antitheses, In
Radcliffe-Brown (1952) credited the late mel, as did Robert E. Park who succeeded Small as attempting to grasp what social life was all was
The Influence of British
nineteenth- and early twentieth-century French department head. Park became “the most influen- about, professionals and students of that era ap-
social thinker Emilc Durkheim (1956, 1962) with Anthropology proached it from a dialectical perspective. And
tial of Simmel’s American students” (Levine et aL,
the most comprehensive systematic formulation 1976, p. 816). Small used Simmel’s ideas to estab- over the past three decades, sociologists, while
Malinowski (1930) and A. R. Radcliffe-Brown
of the analogy between social and organic life. The (1952) were leading early twentieth-century pro- lish the legitimacy of sociology as a professional deserting functionalism, have been reexamining
British anthropologists, Radclilfe-Brown and Bro- ponents of functionalism. Radcliffe-Brown accept- domain. Park and Erncst W Burgess disseminated their pre-Parsonian dialectic roots and extending
nislaw Malinowski (1930), who have been called Simmcl’s ideas widely via their Introduction to them in numerous and complex directions (Cole­
ed Durkheim’s ideas of solidarity and integration,
the titular (along with Durkheim himself) found- which later became a cornerstone of Parsons’s the Science of Society first published in 1921, fol- man, 1990).
ers of functionalism, were influenced by Durk­ functionalism (Stocking, 1984). Those constructs lowed by many editions. The “Chicago School”
heim (Turner, 1986). According to Parsons were viewed as “needs” of social structure that maintained the single greatest influence on gener-
(1982), the primary concern of Durkheim was helped explain cultural phenomena such as al sociology prior to Parsons. Organicism and Family Studies:
“the integration of social Systems, of what holds kinship rules and religious rituals (Turner, 1986). Recall that above we cited Coleman asking 1890s-1940s
societies together” (p. 189). Parsons (1982) ar- Radcliffe-Brown attempted to avoid the tele- “how and why” Parsons “went wrong.” One re-
gued that the construct of “social solidarity” was : sponse is that Parsons did not pay much attention It is curious that although a dialectic ap-
ological fallacy by the assertion that “every item
central to Durkheim’s work, as it was to his own. to Simmel and the “Chicago School.” Interestingly proach pervaded mainstream sociology, Howard
of a culture must have a function and that items in
Solidarity derives from norms bolstered by shared enough, Merton and one of his influential students (1981) shows that family sociology developed
different cultures must have the same function”
values. Durkheim also described role specializa- (Coser, 1956) did try to elaborate Simmel’s no­ largely outside the mainstream. Because family so­
(Turner, 1974, p. 22). Spencer had been an influ-
tion between the genders in ways later ex- tions. Levine and co-workers (1976) showed that ciology remained largely untouched by Simmel’s
ential nineteenth-century organicist social philos-
pounded by Parsons (see previous section). Durk­ Simmel’s ideas differed significantly from earlier thinking, it became much more the product of
opher, and Malinowski reintroduced his ideas of
heim’s incisive analyses of numerous topics organicism and later Parsonianism. Society, argued nineteenth-century organicism. Although Toc-
hierarchical levels in society (biological, social
(suicide, religion) accounted for the attractive Simmel, is not a “corporate entity distinct from queville had a great deal to say about what he
structural, and symbolic), each level having differ­
nature of his functional mode of analyses to subse- and exerting constraints upon individuals” nor called the “democratie” family in America during
ent “needs.” At the structural level, Malinowski
quent sociologists and anthropologists (Turner, can it be reduced to the “motives and acts of indi- the 1830s, it was not until the latter part of that
suggested four functional needs: “economie adap-
1986). In his description of the “integration theo- viduals” (Levine et al., 1976, pp. 823—824). The century that the family became a major focus of
tation, political authority, educational socializa-
ry of society,” which “conceives of social struc- essence of social life is instead, said Simmel, scholars and social critics, as well as the lay public
tion, and social control.” These notions of “levels
ture as a functionally integrated system regulated interaction. Individuals and groups generate in- (Howard, 1981). The end of the Victorian century
of Systems” along with their “needs” surfaced in
by normative consensus,” Durkheim rejected feraction in order to achieve their goals, Interac- was a period of convulsive social changes in the
Parsons’s later work (Williams, 1961), even
“methodological individualism,” which located fion is inevitably reciprocal: A impacts B who in- United States owing to powerful forces of ur-
though in his earlier writings Parsons (1937, p. 3)
the source of purposive actions within the indi- fluences A who impacts B, and so on. Persons and banization and industrialization. From the coun-
had quipped, “Who now reads Spencer?” In-
vidual (Knorr-Cetina, 1981, p. 2). groups that are interacting devise certain patterns, tryside, great numbers of persons were migrating
terestingly enough, Turner (1986, p. 50) remarks
Durkheim was also aware of the dangers of 0r cultural forms, to facilitate their goals. Exam- to expanding factories and burgeoning cities,
that if Parsons had not intervened, “functionalism
the teleological fallacy, a criticism often leveled at Ples of these created patterns would include fami­ joined by a steady influx of immigrants from een-
would have ended with Radcliffe-Brown because
202 PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930 -1945 CHAPTER 9 STRUCTURAL-FUNCTIONALISM 203
tral and Southern Europe. In 1889, “the discovery
that the United States had the highest divorce rate
model as the product of societal evolution. Hence L
Ijt w0uld attain “a new state of cquilibrium.” Unlike east. His earliest academie interests were in biolo-
gy and political economy. Although he read
sociologists used labels such as “adaptation” and lll gijnmel, Burgess never accepted the notion that
in the world” (Mintz & Kellogg, 1988, p, 109)
triggered the dismaying conclusion that the family
was in “disintegration and disorganization.” That
“survival” to describe how the family was reacting
to the enormous societal changes being brought
about by early twentieth-century industrialization
Iiijl' oagoing struggle and change is inevitablc within
families- Nor did Burgess ever scriouslv pursue the
idea that struggle might bring about new ways of
Sumner, Cooley, Durkheim, and Veblen, he had
little early exposure to the Chicago School or to
Simmel (Hamilton, 1983). Following the comple-
assessment was shored up by “the increasing num- and urbanization. The family’s capability to “sur­ lil arranging family rclationships. Although Burgess tion of his B.A. degree in 1924, Parsons went to
bers of working mothers; the rebelliousness of vive” was prima facie evidence of its enormous fe pushed to the limits the forms of interaction that the bondon School of Economics where he at-
youth; the falling birth rate; and the growing inci- resilience, as well as assurance of its continued «jS, ^ possible within family parameters, Gubrium tended lectures by Radcliffe-Brown and Mal-
dence of illegitimacy, adultery, and premarital existence. «€ and Holstein ( 1990, p. 38) show that he was never inowski. After his year in bondon he went to
sex” (Mintz & Kellogg, 1988, p. 131). These kinds Consequently, nineteenth-century organi- t able to overcome the organicist notion that the Heidelburg University, where Max Weber had
of data troubled many citizens and stimulated two cism became the theoretical foundation on which j parameters themselves could not be rearranged. studied 40 years previously, and earned a Ph.D. At
contrasting public policy positions. One stance family sociology/studies was built and developed Ia, The pre-Parsonian family scholar to wrestle that time Parsons, like Max Weber, was intensely
called “progressivism” sought “to protect society as a profession throughout the first four decades lip most seriously with Simmelian ideas was Willard interested in the debate over Karl Marx’s views of
against the family’s failures” (Mintz & Kellogg, of the twentieth century (Howard, 1981). Al­ mk waller (1938). His analyses of college student dat- capitalism. Parsons went to Harvard University in
1988, p. 119). Protection was best achieved, though conservatives and progressives often dif- ing were innovative applications of the ideas of 1927 to teach economics and further explore eco­
thought progressives, through legislating pro­ fered over speciflc strategies to “help” the family, IpS simmel, Small, and Park. Waller’s discussions of nomie theory. In 193T he became a faculty mem-
grams that enhanced the economie and physical there was never any question as ‘to what “help” |p gender differentiation, prestige hierarchies, costs, ber of the newly formed Department of Sociology.
well-being of families, thereby increasing the like- meant, that is, enhancing family organization and l rewards, implicit calculations, rationality, bargain- In 1946, Parsons became the first chair of the De­
lihood of their stability. thereby contributing to societal well-being. Fami­ ing, exploitation, conflict, dissolution, and so on partment of Social Relations, an interdisciplinary
On the other side, the “conservative” view, ly disorganization (deflned as the incapability of al| emerge from an image of persons struggling to unit that significantly influenced the course of
endorsed most vigorously by religieus spokesper- impairment of the family to fulfill its functions for fi create rclationships whose outcomes cannot be post—World War II sociology.
sons (O’Neill, 1967), held that family disorganiza­ or obligations to society) was to be avoided at all ®|j| predicted with certainty. His treatment of conflict Parsons first major work was published in
tion could be reversed—and society protected—
if persons ceased their relentless pursuit of “indi-
vidualism” (a term coined by Tocqueville). In-
costs. Howard shows that the most influential re­
search strategies surfacing during this period were
based on organic assumptions. In particular, there
ÏJ|F
*
P*
was particularly Simmelian (antedating Coser’s
1956 treatment of Simmel and conflict), because
Waller argued that under certain conditions con-
1937. His intention was to “formulate an adequate
general analytical and voluntaristic theory of ac-
tion” (Adriaansens, 1980, p. 5). He conceptualized
stead of individualism, conservatives encouraged emerged a research tradition in the 1930s that ■ flict may contribute to the maintenance of rela- volunteerism as the subjective decision-making
citizens to conform to “responsible” nineteenth- today still accounts for the bulk of published arti- V* tionships and under other conditions contribute processes of individuals. According to Bourricaud
century patterns regarding marltal permancncy, cles in family studies, namely, marital “adjust- S to their dissolution, Waller’s work stood in sharp (1981), Parsons’s use of the term “action” indi-
sex, children, women’s roles, and so on, ment,” “quality,” and so forth. Although severely Jk contrast to the dominant “marital adjustment” cated his revolt against twentieth-century positiv-
Although programmatically very different, criticized for many years by numerous scholars on school (and to later functionalism) where conflict ism. In rejecting positivistic views of observable
Howard (1981) shows that conservatives and pro­ methodological grounds, this tradition persists was viewed primarily as a threat to system sta- cause-and-effect rclationships, he believed they
gressives alike shared a common commitment to owing to its central conceptual rationale; if family bility. Intriguingly, Waller’s analyses of marital re- overlooked the functioning of the mind and en­
the organic analogy and that they maintained an organization (stability) is the ultlmate theoretical W* lationships were far less dynamic and innovative, couraged reductionism (Turner, 1978). Over
uneasy coexlstence within the developing field of and policy issue because of its consequences for E Although he could describe premarital rela- time, Parsons’s (1951) ideas gradually shifted
family studies up through the 1930s, Both per- children and thus society, and if marital quality is ■aBaglIl' tionships in nominalist fashion, the organic model from an emphasis on Actor’s volunteerism to a
spectives tended to anthropomorphize and reify the chief means to avoid disorganization, then r ' tended to prevail when he shifted to postwedding major concern with action constrained by nor-
society and the family (i.e., treat them “as if” they ipso facto marital quality must be the most impor­ phenomena. mative and situational clements. Recall that
are corporeal entities) instead of being what Jay tant research question to explore in family studies. Waller’s untimely death cut off the possibility Williams’s (1961) explanation for this shift was
Gubrium and James Holstein (1990) call “ar- Although Ernest Burgess was a central flgure jPp; of any further contributions he might have made Parsons’s growing awareness that shared values
tificially” or “humanly created.” Family analysts of in the Chicago School, he failed to develop fully IHS: toward the start of a Simmelian tradition in family were insufficiënt to counteract disorder. Conse­
both persuasions viewed the society-family con- the Simmelian dialectic with regard to the family. »' research. As the decade of the 1930s ended, the quently, his second major work, The Social Sys­
nection as an organic whole in which the family His definition of the family as a “unity of interact- K organic model of family and society prevailed, re- tem, published in 1951, departed substantially
served society and was in turn served by society. ing personalities” (explicitly rejected by Norman ' inforced empirically by the emerging “marital ad- from his 1937 volume, as did a number of addi-
Simultaneously, persons served both family and Bell and Ezra Vogel in 1960) and his insistence justment” tradition. At that same time, Parsons tional influential works (Parsons & Bales, 1955;
society, and were in turn served by them. Any that the family is essentially a process influenced «IjjBr (1937) took center stage in mainstream sociology Parsons, Bales & Shils, 1953; and Parsons & Shils,
“interruptions” in these mutual services owing, by its members were insightful. However, he equa- with the schema summarized above. 1951) published during that time. Throughout the
for example, to “family disorganization” pre- ted family conflicts with disorganization (Howard, 1950s and 1960s, functionalism “developed dis-
vented society from getting what it needs in order 1981, pp. 66—67) and he attributed discord to the IBIlPi' Parsons’s Intellectual Development tinctive forms in more empirically oriented ‘mid-
to survive and thrive, Religious conservatives at- changes occurring in the larger society. He be- wÊk dle range’ areas, [and] thus became the primary
tributed this organic model of family and society lieved that once politica! and economie condi- The son of a Congregational minister, Talcott organizing paradigm for most of American so­
to Divine decree. Secular progressives viewed the tions in the larger society stabilized, family life i Parsons was educated in the conservative north- ciology” (Hamilton, 1983, p- 45).
204 PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930-I94S cHAPTER 9 • STRUCTURAI.—FUNCTIONALISM 205

Parsons; Social Change and Even by 1965, Parsons still described the pfie- riod when a number of eminent scholars were Demographers (Bumpass & Sweet, 1980; Es-
nomenon of men not providing adequately f0r yjgorously producing works aimed at explicitly penshade, 1985; Sweet & Bumpass, 1987; Teach-
Deviance
their families as attributable to “a failure of so- connecting family sociology to general theory. In man et al., 1987) and historians (Mintz & Kellogg,
The 1960s and 1970s were marked by dra­ cialization,” and thus an example of deviant 1975, Collins (p. 225) concluded that although 1988; Modell, 1988, 1989) have amassed evi-
matic upheavals throughout North American soci­ behavior. functionalism had virtually disappeared from gen­ dence documenting significant variations in be­
ety, and the resulting tumult underscored critics’ eral sociology, “the sociology of family, kinship, haviors pertaining to families and relationships—
charges that functionalism had no satisfactory the- and socialization has been the bastion of func­ particularly during recent decades. In response to
ory of change. Parsons responded by reverting to tionalism, framing its analysis against an ideal Sys­ this mass of data, a dichotomy has emerged in the
The Influence of Goode
his earlier training in biology, drawing on the twin tem in which men, women, and children all fit family literature couched in classic Parsonian
ideas of organic analogy and evolutionary devel- Goode (1959) observed that family theory of nicely in their placcs.” In sum, organicism was terms (Blumstein & Schwartz, 1983, pp. 318-
opment. To these notions, he added ideas from the that era lagged behind the development of main- endemic to pre-Parsonian family sociology. Dur­ 324). On the one side, stands the family—the nor-
then-emerging field of cybernetics, for example, stream, that is, functionalist, theory: “There re- ing the h™6 that structural—functionalism per­ matively legitimized social system uniquely fltted
sources of change could be either excesses or de- mains a feeling, primarily aesthetic, which most of vaded general sociology, family studies (apart to benefit Society. On the other side stand “alter-
ficiencies in supplies of information and energy us share, that family theory at best does not have front exceptions such as Goode and others) main- native” or “other” life-styles—documented be-
(Turner, 1978). Parsons argucd that just as organ- the sweep, the drama, the ear-compelllng sonori- tained its preoccupation with organicism as well havioral variations that may have dysfunctions for
isms adapted to external forces, and thus changed ties of good theory” (p. 181). To try to achieve as applied matters. And in spite of the demise of children and society. Although numerous euphe-
in order to survive, this same process of evolution that “good theory,” Goode (1961, 1963, 1964) functionalism in mainstream sociology, organicist misms are applied to these nonconforming varia­
takes place within social systems. The prein- produced a number of influential works explicitly assumptions continue the course set in family tions, in effect they are conceptualized as deviant
dustrial family, for example, was changed by the connecting Parsonian ideas to family sociology. studies a century ago. behaviors.
forces of industrialization into something differ­ And like Merton and Cohen, Goode went beyond Although the label “deviant” seldom appears
ent, that is, the nuclear family based on the instru- Parsons in trying to address notions of deviance in the family studies’ literature, the fact that other
mental and expressive role specialization de- and change. But in view of the reality that Ma in Contemporary Problems life-styles are called “other” indicates that they
scribed above. Parsons’s argument that the fam- organicism pervaded family sociology long before Addressed represent something besides “The Family”. If one
ily’s evolutionary adaptations demonstrate its re- Parsons, how can it be that family sociology of that posits a theory of social organization based on
silience was not new. Recall that earlier family era lagged behind genera! sociology? Given their If we were to follow the conclusions of Bro- normative conformity, then one must forever
analysts, sharing his organlcism, had for many de­ common heritage, why did Parsons’s ideas not be- derick ( 1971a) and Holman and Burr ( 1980), this wrestle with the empirical reality that large num-
cades made precisely the same point. Interestingly come central to family sociology long before the chapter would now end because according to bers of persons are not conforming. Recall that
enough, the identical explanation for change can efforts of Goode, Pitts (1964), and Bell and Vogel them there is nothing “contemporary” to address once the shortcomings of the normative confor­
be found in the contemporary family studies’ liter- (1960)? The answer appears to lie in Goode’s use via functionalism. Contrariwise, Mclntyre’s obser- mity approach became clear, Parsons and his stu-
ature: “The major factors determining the direc- of “aesthetic.” Apart from Waller, the family so­ vation (1966, p. 64) remains trenchant: "Of the dents agonized over the implications for decades.
tion of [family] change will be the realities of eco- ciology that existed prior to the 1960s was not large body of empirical research concerning the The life-styles literature represents the realm of
nomics and demographics” (Taubin & Mudd, oriented primarily toward the development of sci- family . . . only a relatively small proportion has family studies where nonconformity (deviance
1983, p. 265). entific theory (Hill & Hansen, 1960), Instead, Col- consciously used a structural-functional . . . from dominant norms) is most apparent. Conse-
Parsons’s approach to change casts additional lins (1975, p. 225) remarks that its chief focus was framework. Dcspite this apparent lack the frame- quently, we examine it in conjunction with the
light on Coleman’s (1990) query as to where Par­ on applied matters, namely, “how to” help per­ work has had an impact on research greater than homeostatic model central to contemporary fami­
sons “went wrong.” For Parsons, actors failing to sons have “happy” marriages and thus avoid di- its deliberate use would indicate.” “Deliberate ly studies.
conform to preexisting group norms is necessarily vorce. This preoccupation with practical matters use” is the key phrase, because aside from some
deviance as described earlier. Unlike Merton, Par­ fit perfectly with the “marital adjustment” school exceptions (Beer, 1989), few family analysts today Altemative Life-styles
sons never viewed deviance as a potential source described above. It also, of course, fit entirely with explicitly use functionalist jargon, much less call
of System change. Change is not legitimately gen­ organic concerns that “family survival” is requi- themselves functionalists. Nevcrthcless, the argu­ Buunk and van Driel (1989) state that their
eraled by persons from within organic systems; site to the well-being of children and thus the ment can be made that the central theoretical is­ use of the label “variant” life-styles escapes the
instead, change is imposed by impersonal forces survival of society. But since most family research sue that dominates contemporary family studies is opprobrium attached to labels such as “deviant”
from the outside and the “system must adapt to” consisted of what Merton (1957) called “isolated the condition of equilibrium—maintaining a or “altemative.” By “variant” they mean “life-
or “cope with” it in order to survive. Turner empirical generalizations” about “adjustment,” steady state in the face of external and internal styles that are different from the sexually ex-
(1988, p. 3) quotes George Homans as saying that and so on, it was neither scientiflcally nor, ulti- threats to that homeostasis (e g., Olson & McCub- clusive, legally sanctioned marriage couple that
for a theory of “action,” Parsons’s ideas contained mately, of any practical importance. Conse- hin, 1983). That was the issue long before Par­ lives together in a joint household” (p. 19). In
“darn little action.” If Parsons had somehow been quently, Goode (and Ruben Hill, but not from an sons; it became the question that preoccupied terms of what Parsons called dominant norms and
able to resonate with Simmel that the essence of explicitly structural—functionalism perspective) bint; and it continues today. Put another way, the also legal statutes, this latter deflnition (factoring
sociology is interaction, he might then have been and others purposely set out to raise the level of entral matter to which functionalism speaks is in the presence of the couple’s own natural chil­
able to move toward a theory of change in which theoretical sophistication in the field. Neverthe- e general issue of social organization; How do dren under 18) describes what Hofferth (1985)
interaction between persons and between groups less, it seems ironie that mainstream sociology ’e onderstand the structures and changes of fami- called the Benchmark Family, or what we earlier
gives rise to ever-changing patterns of behaviors. was repudiating Parsonianism during the very pe' hes and primary relationships? identifled as the “Nuclear Family,” or simply the
204 ;r 9 • STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM
205
PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING
CHAPTC
Parsons: Social Change and K Demographers (Bumpass & Sweet, 1980; Es-
Even by 1965, Parsons still described the p{je ■0d when a number of eminent scholars were
Deviance vigorously producing works aimed at explicitly penshade, 1985; Sweet & Bumpass, 1987; Teach-
nomenon of men not providing adequately f01, man et al, 1987) and historians (Mintz & Kellogg,
their families as attributable to “a failure of connecting family sociology to general theory. In
The 1960s and 1970s were marked by dra­ jp75, CoUins (p. 225) concluded that although 1988; Modell, 1988, 1989) have amassed evi-
cialization,” and thus an example of dev
matic upheavals throughout North American soci­ functionalism had virtually disappeared from gen­ dence documenting significant variations in be­
behavior.
ety, and the resulting tumult underscored critics’ eral sociology, “the sociology of family, kinship, haviors pertaining to families and relationships—
charges that functionalism had no satisfactory the- jud socialization has been the bastion of func­ particularly during recent decades, In response to
ory of change. Parsons responded by reverting to tionalism, framing its analysis against an ideal sys­ this mass of data, a dichotomy has emerged in the
his earlier training in biology, drawing on the twin The Influence of Goode family literature couched in classic Parsonian
tem in which men, women, and children all fit
ideas of organic analogy and evolutionary devel- nicely in their places.” In sum, organicism was terms (Blumstein & Schwartz, 1983, pp- 318—
Goode (1959) observed that family theory 0f 324). On the one side, stands the family—the nor-
opment. To these notions, he added ideas from the that era lagged behind the development of main- endemic to pre-Parsonian family sociology. Dur­
then-emerging field of cybernetics, for example, ing the time that structural-functionalism per­ matively legitimized social system uniquely fltted
stream, that is, functionalist, theory; “There re- to benefit Society. On the other side stand “alter-
sources of change could be either excesses or de- vaded general sociology, family studies (apart
mains a feeling, primarily aesthetic, which most of native” or “other” life-styles—documented be-
flciencies in supplies of information and energy from exceptions such as Goode and others) main-
us share, that family theory at best does not have havioral variations that may have dysfunctions for
(Turner, 1978). Parsons argued that just as organ- tained its preoccupation with organicism as well
the sweep, the drama, the ear-compelling sonori- children and society. Although numerous euphe-
isms adapted to external forces, and thus changed as applied matters. And in spite of the demise of
ties of good theory” (p. 181), To try to achieve misms are applied to these nonconforming varia­
in order to survive, this same process of evolution that “good theory,” Goode (1961, 1963, 1964) functionalism in mainstream sociology, organicist
takes place within social Systems, The prein- assumptions continue the course set in family tions, in effect they are conceptualized as deviant
produced a number of influential works explicitly
dustrial family, for example, was changed by the studies a century ago. behaviors.
connecting Parsonian ideas to family sociology. Although the label “deviant” seldom appears
forces of industrialization into something differ­ And like Merton and Cohen, Goode went beyond
ent, that is, the nuclear family based on the instru- in the family studies’ literature, the fact that other
Parsons in trying to address notions of deviance life-styles are called “other” indicates that they
mental and expressive role specialization de- Main Contemporary Problems
and change. But in view of the reality that represent something besides “The Family”. If one
scribed above. Parsons’s argument that the fam- Addressed
organicism pervaded family sociology long before posits a theory of social organization based on
ily’s evolutionary adaptations demonstrate its re- Parsons, how can it be that family sociology of that
silience was not new. Recall that earlier family era lagged behind general sociology? Given their If we were to follow the conclusions of Bro- normative conformity, then one must forever
analysts, sharing his organicism, had for many de­ common heritage, why did Parsons’s ideas not be- derick ( 1971a) and Holman and Burr (1980), this wrestle with the empirical reality that large num-
cades made precisely the same point. Interestingly come central to family sociology long before the chaptcr would now end because according to bers of persons are not conforming. Recall that
enough, the identical explanation for change can efforts of Goode, Pitts (1964), and Bell and Vogel them there is nothing “contemporary” to address once the shortcomings of the normative confor­
be found in the contemporary family studies’ liter- (1960)? The answer appears to lie in Goode’s use via functionalism. Contrariwise, Mclntyre’s obser- mity approach became clear, Parsons and his stu-
ature: “The major factors determining the direc- of “aesthetic.” Apart from Waller, the family so­ vation (1966, p 64) remains trenchant; “Of the dents agonized over the implications for decades.
tion of [family] change will be the realitics of eco- ciology that existed prior to the 1960s was not large body of empirical research concerning the The life-styles literature represents the realm of
nomics and demographics” (Taubin & Mudd, oriented primarily toward the development of sci- family . . . only a relatively small proportion has family studies where nonconformity (deviance
1983. p. 263). consciously used a structural-functional , . . from dominant norms) is most apparent. Conse-
entific theory (HUI & Hansen, 1960). Instead, Col- quently, we examine it in conjunction with the
Parsons’s approach to change casts additional lins (1975, p. 225) remarks that its chief focus was framework. Despite this apparent lack the frame-
light on Coleman’s (1990) query as to where Par­ on applied matters, namely, “how to” help per­ work has had an impact on research greater than homeostatic model central to contemporary fami­
sons “went wrong.” For Parsons, actors fading to sons have “happy” marriages and thus avoid di- its deliberate use would indicate.” “Deliberate ly studies.
conform to preexisting group norms is necessarily vorce. This preoccupation with practical matters use” is the key phrase, because aside from some
deviance as described earlier. Unlike Merton, Par­ fit perfectly with the “marital adjustment” school exceptions (Beer, 1989), few family analysts today Altemative Life-styles
sons never viewed deviance as a potential source described above. It also, of course, fit entirely with explicitly use functionalist jargon, much less cal!
of system change. Change is not legitimately gen­ organic concerns that “family survival” is requi- themselves functionalists. Nevertheless, the argu­ Buunk and van Driel (1989) state that their
eraled by persons from within organic Systems; site to the well-being of children and thus the ment can be made that the central theoretical is­ use of the label “variant” life-styles escapes the
instead, change is imposed by impersonal forces survival of society. But since most family research sue that dominates contemporary family studies is opprobrium attached to labels such as “deviant”
from the outside and the “system must adapt to” consisted of what Merton (1957) called “isolated die condition of equilibrium—maintaining a or “altemative.” By “variant” they mean “life-
or “cope with” it in order to survive. Turner empirical generalizations” about “adjustment,” steady state in the face of external and internal styles that are different from the sexually ex-
(1988, p. 3) quotes George Homans as saying that
and so on, it was neither scientifically nor, ulti- direats to that homeostasis (e.g., Olson & McCub- clusive, legally sanctioned marriage couple that
for a theory of “action,” Parsons’s ideas contained mately, of any practical importance. Conse- hin, 1983). That was the issue long before Par­ lives together in a joint household” (p. 19). In
“darn little action.” If Parsons had somehow been
quently, Goode (and Ruben Hill, but not from an sons; it became the question that preoccupied terms of what Parsons called dominant norms and
able to resonate with Simmel that the essence of explicitly structural—functionalism perspective) hint; and it continues today. Put another way, the also legal statutes, this latter definition (factoring
sociology is interaction, he might then have been and
others purposely set out to raisc the level of central matter to which functionalism speaks is in the presence of the couple’s own natural chil­
able to move toward a theory of change in which theoretical sophistication in the field. Neverthe- die general issue of social organization: How do dren under 18) describes what Hofferth (1985)
interaction between persons and between groups less, it seems ironie that mainstream sociology we understand the structures and changes of fami­ called the Benchmark Family, or what we earlier
gives rise to ever-changing patterns of behaviors. was repudiating Parsonianism during the very pe- identified as the “Nuclear Family,” or simply the
lies and primary relationships?
206 STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM
207
PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930

“Family.” Hill (1982) labeled it the “Standard atl no longcr be conccptualized objectively as Following this reasoning, the life-style that
the Left, another 20% seek to label diversity of perhaps represents the most severe dilemma for
package”; Taubin & Mudd (1983) called it “con- primary' relationship patterns as desirable and t leviant. Nevertheless, Thompson and Gongla
temporary traditional” by also factoring in the op- functionalist thinking is remarriage and step-
define all patterns potentially as equally desirable M983,
' P- 113)y acknowlcdge ^
that because single
families. On the one hand, all divorced persons
tion of the wife engaged in paid labor that is sec- as the benchmark. They also seek rcpeal of stat arenthood is nonbenchmark, it continucs to be
ondary to the husband’s paid labor. In his review nerceived as deviant—it is something less desir­ with or without childrcn are deviant, as are per­
utes restricting primary relationship diversity and sons who have what functionalists call “illegiti-
of deviance theory, Gibbs (1981) observes that the passage of new legislation supporting it. Xhe able (dysfunctional) than the cultural id“al, and
deviance is both “objective” and perceived or “la­ i receives neither social nor cultural supports. mate” childrcn but who are not married (Mal-
center consists of the 60% majority, who akin to
beled.” For example, in the United States it is Significantly, they underscore a key issue in assess- inowski, 1930). Because those patterns are
the Right, label most nonbenchmark patterns as
against the law for unmarried persons to have sex deviant. Nevertheless, their behaviors at one 0r whether behavior is deviant or not; and al- nonbenchmark, there is enormous network pres­
or for married persons to have sex with anyone more points throughout their life courses are non- tbough they apply it to single parenthood, it ap- sure (kin and friends) to move those persons from
other than their spouses. In addition, many States benchmark, that is, deviant, and thus akin to the plies to all life-styles as wcll. The key is time, that their “temporary” status to a permanent and nor-
maintain statutes against married persons doing Left. According to Hofferth, these persons endorse is duration: “The conventional wisdom is that the matively more desirable one—re- or first mar­
“unnatural” sex.
the benchmark even though they do not now, nor ilH single-parent family will ‘go away’ when the single riage. But on the other hand, by definition neither
Hence, in spite of what Buunk and van Driel may ever be able to, expcrience it. Importantly parent (re)marries” (Thompson & Gongla, 1983, can remarriage nor stepfamily be the benchmark:
maintain, from an “objective” view, “life-styles” this majority, unlike the two polar extremes, tencis ; p. 112). The argument is that behavior that is not they are less than ideal and may be fraught with
that include illegal sex are deviant. Furthermore, not to advocate either legal enforcement or stat- institutionalized is thought of as temporary. Fur­ dysfunctions. Consequently, Ganong and Coleman
although marginally enforced, severe penalties utory changes. Nevertheless, if they perceive their thermore, because the behavior is less than desir­ (1987) described them as “nonnuclear” families;
(sanctions) can be imposed for breaking laws freedom to “behave deviantly” threatened by leg. able (dysfunctional), there is no impetus to make and others (Ahrons & Rodgers, 1987) use the la­
about sex, as some homosexual couples and pros- islation, they will politically resist that incursion, it permanent by providing it with any kind of bel “binuclear.” Ironically, fresh labels distinguish-
titutes have discovered. In addition, persons wish- as witnessed by their recent responses to the New positive sanctions except those that would result ing these life-styles from the benchmark tend to
ing to represent sexual life-styles (or even legal Right efforts to restrict abortion options. in its termination, that is, via (re)marriage. If a reinforce their deviant status even though accord­
ones such as marital sex) through art or the media
Earlicr we noted Cohen’s (1959) distinction nonbenchmark pattern becomes legitimized as ing to Pasley and Ihinger-Tallman (1988), “43% of
may be punished for doing so on the grounds that between deviance and social (including family) permanent and thus just as desirable as the all [U.S.] marriages contracted now are remar-
they are violating norms held by the “communi- disorganization. Deviance is nonconforming be­ benchmark, then the latter is in effect sharing riages for one or both spouses” (p. 204). Pasley
ty.” Community norms shift us to Gibbs’s labeling havior that has degrees of dysfunction for organi- some of its alleged unique functions for societal and Ihinger-Tallman argue that by moving beyond
perspective; and it can be argued that the majority zation; some forms of family deviance may be well-being: it becomes a “functional equivalent.” the “deficit model approach” (p. 218), the study
of U.S. citizens define virtually all relationship pat- “worse” or more dysfunctional (create more dis- The issue of duration is extraordinarily rele­ of remarriage is becoming more complex and so­
terns that are different from the benchmark as de­ equilibrium) for society than others. For over a vant for cohabitation (both homo- and heterosex- phisticated, that is, less naively functionalist.
viant to a greater or lesser degree. This is so First century the prime reason divorce has been con- ual; especially since cohabitation and solo parent- Nevertheless, a recent essay employed func­
because what is different is defined as “less desir- sidered highly dysfunctional deviance is because it ing are increasingly overlapping phenomena. tionalist labels to identify three types of stepfamily
able” (dysfunctional for persons and society) than allegedly undermines the proper socialization of Although increasing numbers of U.S. heterosex- structures, each of which was predisposed to
the ideal; and second because what is different is childrcn, thus threatening society’s well-being re- uals cohabit at varying points in their life courses, some type of dysfunction (Mills, 1989). In another
either sanctioned negatively and/or receives nei- sulting in disorganization. Accordingly, the single- the median length of their relationships is 1.3 essay employing functionalist concepts, Beer
ther cultural nor social supports. Thorton (1989) parent life-style (often stemming from divorce) is years (Bumpass & Sweet, 1989). Hence, one could (1989) sought to identify “the basic features of
makes the point that although in recent decades also thought to be highly dysfunctional for society argue that cohabiters’ social networks (friends, the stepsibling subsystem . . . [that] might con-
there have been substantial increases in noncon- because childrcn fail to receive inputs from two kin) expect their unions to be temporary. Al­ tribute to its dynamic equilibrium” (p. 132).
forming primary relationship behaviors, there is parents. That situation is perceived as particularly though no longer prohibited, the option of co­
no evidence to suggest that they have yet become negative for boys, since the “missing” parent is habitation appears to append the clause that at
normative, that is, endorsed. usually the father. According to Parsons (1965) some point cohabitants “must make a decision”: Family Stress Perspectives
Yankelovich (1981) suggested that the U.S. and many current observers, the economie prob- either marry or terminale. Although permanence
population can be divided into three broad cate- is valued within marriage, it is devalued within A survey of the current literature reveals that
lems of African-Amcricans are in large measure the topic of family stress is a widely researched
gories, and his continuüm is useful to relnforce owing to a high proportion of boys growing up cohabitation. The “decision” to remain together
our arguments regarding deviant primary rela­ “forever informally” receives little social support area. The construct of stress was first introduced
without a resident male figure. A “deficit” of male
tionship behavior and labeling. On the Right, in the United States. “Informal marriage” is not yet into family studies by researchers examining im­
providers, he said, threatens society by staggering
evangelicals make up some 20% of citizens who viewed as a “functional equivalent” to the “rcal pacts of the 1930s’ Great Depression (Boss,
welfare costs and by serious crimes perpetrated
not only label nonbenchmark behaviors as de­ by black males. thing,” as is evidently more the case in Scandinavia 1987). Since family studies were then (as now)
viant, they also tend to behave in benchmark (Popcnoe, 1988). Incidentally, one could specu dominated by organic assumptions, it is not sur-
As single parenthood becomes increasingly prising that family studies spawned an instant af-
terms (Bellah et al., 1985). Moreover, they seek commonplace throughout white society, Thomp­ 'ate that one reason for the higher rates of marita
vigorous enforcement of existing laws against pri­ mstability among Americans who cohabited prioi finity with stress notions. Citing Reuben Hill, Boss
son and Gongla ( 1983) have taken a position sim- i
mary relationship deviance, resist all attempts to io marriage (Bumpass & Sweet, 1989) was the (1987) defines “family stress as an upset in the
ilar to Buunk and van Driel (1989), namely, that steady state of the family” (p. 695). She describes
weaken current statutes, and advocate the passage since this life-style is becoming so widespread and mtense pressure to marry—resulting in “unsuit
of new legislation curbing further deviance. On able” formal unions. Hill’s (1949) pioneering ABC-X model in which A
is thus in “the mainstream of American society',” R
208 PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930. STRUCTU RAL—FUNCTIONALISM 209
-1945 CllAPTER 1
represents the “provoking event or stressor,” X is sons’ feclings of distress when they do not con I organic analogy: the notion that there is a “real varying degrees of consensus and equity
the “crisis and stress” stemming from it, B is the form to dominant values and norms. For the most ■ vvh0le' seeking homeostasis, or equilibrium, and (Scanzoni et al, 1989). In contrast to that nomi­
“resources or strengths” possessed by the family, part, the family stress perspective appears to oper ater than the parts that comprise it. In that nalist image of parts struggling to achieve and bal-
and C is how the family deflnes the event. HUI ate within a contemporary version of the orgatlj pegard, Boss’s work is complemcntary with the ance often-competing interests, Boss images a sys­
defined crisis as a “period of disorganization” in eist framework that has dominated family studies efforts of a number of contemporary general theo- tem seeking to maintain its equilibrium much as
the family if it is vulnerable to a stressor, If it has for so long. The focus of attention tends to be a I rists wrestling with neo-functionalism who con- Coser (1956) did when he addressed the func-
enough resources, “the family reverses this disor­
ganization and begins to reorganize and . . . May
reified benchmark family. McCubbin and Fig|ey
(1983b) conclude in functionalist fashion that
I tintte to hold that the “whole” is “more than the tions of social conflict.
At the same time, Boss’s “neo-functionalism”
inerc sum ‘ts Parts (Alexander, 1985, p. 15).
reach a new level of reorganization” (Hill, 1949, p. “Families generally operate on a predictable, nor- For instance, in another place, Boss (1987) moves the stress perspective much closer to gen­
697), exceeding the level it experienced prior to mal cycle, anticipating and accepting a sequence States that she is more interested in “why families eral theory in both psychology and sociology.
the event. Without belaboring the point, it seems of events that will occur throughout the life succeed,” instead of “why families fail” (p. 701). Mirowsky and Ross (1989) note that general liter­
apparent that these ideas are another way of stat- course. These predictable transitions may, how- jjowever, phrasing the question in that manner ature does not conceptualize stress in group
ing Parsons’s notions of system (re)equilibrium. ever, be disrupted by unanticipated or traumatic i jssumes first that there is in fact an actual entity terms. If a study examines women who work 12
Thus, from its inception, stress perspectives and events” (p. 219). Events (whether predictable or called the family; and second that this entity may hours per day at paid and nonpaid work, or per­
functionalisn. shared common theoretical ground. unpredictable) disturb the family’s equilibrium I experience stress but yet it can and should “suc­ sons who are divorced, or are single, or are solo
A recent volume examined coping with fami­ and require coping if it is to “succeed,” that is ceed.” Boss seems to leave little doubt that the parents, or are child-free, or who are laid off, and
ly stress resulting from what were called “nor- regain homeostasis and remain organized in a sta- I ftmily is a real entity when she asks “whether the so on, the goal is to measure the stress levels of
mative transitions.” Some of the transitions con- ble fashion. The ultimate purpose, or function, of phenomenon offamily coping exists or whether these persons qua persons. Mirowsky and Ross
sidered there also appear in the life-styles family equilibrium is to stave off societal disor­ some individuals in the family are simply coping also question the assumption that events external
literature. Included, for instance, is “dual-career
families; strains of sharing” (Skinner, 1983), which
ganization, although it is assumed that family suc- I collectively. The answer is . . . both” (1987, p. to persons (e.g., life course transitions) are the
cess is functional for individuals as well. It follovvs I 704, italics added). To elaborate her argument, prime “causes” of stress. They argue instead that
was called “a growing family life-style” (McCub- that analysts who define alternatives as deviating she cites (p. 704) Buckley’s (1967) distinction persons’ evaluations of the events are the main
bin & Figley, 1983a, p. xxviii). Also included is from the benchmark and thus potentially dysftme- between types of systems theories—the home­ predictors of their own stress levels. That asser-
divorce (Ahrons, 1983), the postdivorce single tional, would focus on the degree of stress experi­ ostatic (functionalist) type versus the “dialectical tion is akin to Boss and co-worker’s (1990) discus-
family (Hogan et al., 1983), stepparenting and enced by those nonconforming alternative pat- 1 process” type. She adapts the latter because she sion of coping. When Mirowsky and Ross identify
blended families (Visher & Visher, 1983), work terns. The assumption seems to be that , says it permits her to incorporatc individuals into the variable that in the literature appears most
and family (Porter, 1983), and the black family nonbenchmark patterns are vulnerable to a great her family stress perspective. For her the dialcc- powerfully to predict a person’s-well-being (low
(McAdoo, 1983). As part of their “Families in deal of disequilibrium and thus stress. Conse- ; tical approach examincs how “elements of a uni- stress levels), they converge closely with Boss’s
Trouble” series, Chilman, Nunnally, and Cox com- quently, stress researchers want to know how per­ I verse are held together by opposition” (1987, p. (1987) emphasis on a sense of mastery. A “sense
piled an anthology called Variant Family Forms sons in deviant primary relations “cope” with the I 704). In the family, the “elements” are individuals of control,” they contend, is the single most signif­
(1988). They exceeded McCubbin and Figley by stress that comes from being deviant. who are “held together” in spite of stress, and thus icant factor influencing well-being. Elements af-
considering the full range of alternative life-styles. Boss (1987), however, is a stress theorist the family “succeeds.” Boss (1987, p. 704) deflnes fecting a strong sense of control include, they say,
Chilman and colleagues (1988) argued that who wants to “move in new directions” (p. 697); the synthesis emerging from antithesis as “a uni- education, a “good job,” and a “supportive rela­
“many of today’s families are in serious trouble, as hence she rejects “conservative , . . structural- tionship—fair and caring” (Mirowsky & Ross,
Bed whole.”
rising rates of divorce . . . suggest. The stresses functionalism” marked by actors’ “passive” con- Nevertheless, there are sharp dififerences be­ 1989, p. 184). They argue that the prime goal in
imposed by a rapidly changing society are creat- formity (1986, p. 15). Furthermore, she dismisses tween Boss’s neo-functionalism and classic dialec- persons having greater control over their political,
ing severe strains for families and their members” the necessary association between life-styles and tical theory described above. Dialectical theorists economie, and primary relationship destinies is a
(p. 7). Their viewpoint echoes a century of stress: “The assumption of normaley in the . . . focus on the struggles between the partners sense of their own well-being.
organicist thought—societal upheavals are dis- nuclear family with the . . . instrumental-ex- (adults, children) in a relationship and on the The most vexing conceptual problem inher­
rupting families, producing variant (and dysfunc- pressive . . . role delineations is rejected, as is the ever-changing structuring, or structuration, of pat­ ent in applying homeostatic family stress notions
tional) forms; hence, families must be assisted to assumption of conflict as evidence of pathology” terns emerging from the struggles (Turner, 1988). to alternatives sterns from the century-long image
avoid disintegration and disorganization. How- (Boss, 1986, p. 23). Boss goes on to assert that the Continuing struggle and change stem from the re- of the family besieged by events not of its own
ever, to bring their perspective up to date, “larger society wül not be threatened by this ality that persons have both divergent as well as making. That image ignores persons’ degree of
Chilman and colleagues “build on the work more radical perspective” (p. 23). Having so thor- convergent interests. The question is never the control over their primary relationships. McCub­
of. . . [homeostatic] systems theorists . . , [and]
family stress and coping theorists” (p. 11).
In short, there appears to be a growing liter­
oughly undermined Parsonian notions of deviance
and societal disorder, Boss nonetheless embraces
a “neo-structural—functionalism” based on “cy-
Ï conditions of “moving equilibrium,” but instead bin and Figley (1983b, p. 220) drew a distinction
k what kinds of changing arrangements are the per- between what they called stress stemming from
SOns able, or not able, to achieve? Change can predictable or normative transitions versus “cata-
ature that brldges (deviant) life-styles with stress.
And reasoning from a functionalist perspective, a
strong theoretical case can be made for just such a
bernetics systems theory [in which] . . . Family
health depends on interaction of all potential
members within that system toward a mutual
! range all the way from total cessation of interac- strophic stress.” The latter include ‘Tape, war, ter-
tions (it may or may not be in persons’ best in­ roristic captivity, and natural disasters,” along
terests to terminale a relationship), to rela- with chronic illness, drug abuse, abandonment,
connection. Merton (1957), for example, em- maintenance of [moving] equilibrium” (p. 15). As Wonships that are constrained and uneasy (e.g., sudden divorce, and unemployment (p. 220). The
ployed Durkheim’s term anomie to describe per- a neo-functionalist, Boss seems to retain the Certain kin obligations; “utilitarian marriages”), to issue is degree of control over the generation of
210 PART IV FAMILY THEORIE* AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930. STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM 211
cHAPTER9 •
'1945
the event. Since persons are able to exercise rela- “dare to be deviant” and try coitus. Increasingiy that “heady” emotional feclings play in motivating elaborate his position, he First observes that the
tively less control over a catastrophic event, their more couples chose the latter option because r persons to structure their primary relationships in “metaphor” of “social system” as it has been em-
stress levels are likely to be high. By way of con­ was rewarding and its costs tolerable. After 5q nonconforming, or deviant, fashion. ployed in family studies “is only distantly related
trast, matters of choice and control become rela- years the latter option pervades the entire society Expanding on his idea of “capture,” Modell to . . . the ‘morphogenic systems’ theories of
tively more central in the case of alternatives. Per­ except for evangelicals who continue to choose t0 (1989) States that for over five decades youth Buckley” (1988, p. 48). Instead of focusing on the
sons choosing, for instance, to cohabit and feeling “say no to sex.” Modell’s nominalist model of so have “come into their own,” that is, “individuals activities of persons in recreating, and perhaps ter-
they have control over their voluntary deviance cial change derives from Giddens’s (1981) reason- are responsible for crafting their own biographies, minating systems, family scholars have applied the
are likely to experience less stress than married ing that change occurs out of the interplay of mac- f0r discerning and nurturing their ‘selves’ and pre­ organic metaphor to systems and have been con-
persons feeling they have no control over their roconditions and human choices. The Depression senting these to the world. , . . Young people . . . cerned chiefly with their maintenance, or success.
constrained conformity. generated the societal conditions that provided have increasingly taken control of the construc- Hansen also suggests that assigning organic reality
the rationale for certain (nonevangelical) couples tion of the youthful life course: adult-maintained to the metaphor “role” binders our understanding
to choose to deviate from formal norms. Follow- convention has crumbled, and [youth] . . . con­ of how persons are “‘making roles’ . . . [And] ‘un-
Remaking Relationships: Evolution ing the Depression, it became clear to increasing struct it afresh” (p. 326), He adds that “the making’ the roles we are discarding” (p. 51). Thus,
versus Choice and Control numbers of persons that deviance was more re­ youthful life course has been an arena in which instead of the functionalist assumption that
warding than conformity. Hence, Modell argued [youth] have . . . been innovators. A central theme changes per se generale stress, Hansen focuses
During functionalism’s heyday, it was fashion- that today persons have created “innovative” sets in their innovation has been the injection of in­ our attention on persons as innovators: their
able to quip that economics was about how of nonformal norms regarding sex. creasing volition” (p. 331). Referring to fears of choices, shared role making, negotiation dynam-
people made choices, whereas sociology was During that era, Kuhn (1948) observed that societal disorganization, Modell observed that ics, emotional reactions, and outcome uncertain-
about how people had no choices to make, Se- the “chief function of engagement” was getting to “sexuality [is] increasingly understood as an ele­ ties (Godwin & Scanzoni, 1989; Scanzoni et al.,
Iznick (1961, p. 934) complained that in Parsons’s know the other person prior to their commitment ment of individuai good rather than as a socially or 1989; Scanzoni & Godwin, 1990).
work and, we would add, in family studies, there to lifelong marriage and monogamous sex. But he divinely proscribed misjudgment” (p. 332). He
has been “no true embrace of the idea that struc- noted that "engagement . . . has gone much fur- cautions that none of these innovations “would Limitations
ture is being contlnuously opened up and recon- ther over into the realm of alternatives than have have been possible” apart from certain macrocon-
structed by the problem-solving behavior of indi- marriage and the family” (p. 281, italics added), ditions: in particular, the increasing access of Scientific
viduals responding to concrete situations.” Kuhn interpreted engagement—sex as a “cultural youth—especially women—to economie re­
However, recent studies by Modell (1988, 1989) alternative” causing stress with which the family sources not controlled by their elders. Because the status of functionalism has re-
and Hansen (1988) focus on the “opening up” was successfully coping. By its ability to cope, the Contrast Modell’s theory of change with Tau- quired us to weave its shortcomings into the chap-
and “reconstruction” of primary relationships in- family was once again demonstrating its evolu- bin and Mudd’s (1983, p. 265) functionalist view ter’s fabric, our aim here is to summarize them
stead of on their equilibrium. Both scholars ap- tionary resilience as it had since the nineteenth that changes in the family have been and will con­ under the overarching constraint imposed on fam­
peared in a family stress anthology; and the editors century. Instead of creating disorganization in the tinue to be “evolutionary” and “determined” by ily studies because of its tacit acceptance of an
observe that the volume should be viewed in the family and society, Kuhn stated that deviant sex “economics and demographics.” Like Kuhn equilibrium model of social organization. Eisen-
light of a major trend “throughout the social Sci­ was actually functional for the family. The benefit, (1948) and McCubbin and Figley (1983b), they stadt (1985) States that general theorists like him
ences. . . . Theory and research are moving more according to Kuhn, was that since persons learned see the family as “normally” in a steady state, yet departed functionalism because of their “un-
toward dynamic models in which concepts and to be “instrumental and rational” through deviant subject to impinging macroforces that “require” it willingness . . . to accept the ‘natural’ givenness of
measures of change occupy a central and explicit sex, they can be more successful spouses in an era to “adapt” in order to survive and continue to any . , . institution [including families] ... in
role” (Aldous & Klein, 1988, p. 13). requiring these qualities. However, Modell ( 1988) fulfill its basic societal functions. For example, al­ terms of the . . . needs of the social system to
Modell explores why premarital sex has be­ rejects Kuhn by saying “that a less functionalist though earlier theorists (Hofffnan & Nye, 1963) which it belonged” (p. 15). Real world data re-
come so widespread since the 1930s in spite of account of the history of engagement might well viewed wife-mother employment as potentially quired them to shift their focus from system suc­
dominant values and norms proscribing it as de­ argue that the change . . . was not so much the dysfunctional for the family, Taubin and Mudd cess and survival to persons/groups struggling:
viance that would undermine both family and so­ result of evolution as of the capture of the institu- (1983) stated that the family has now successfully “Institutional order develops, is maintained and is
ciety. He reported that because the Great Depres- tion by the cohort most directly affected by it” (p. incorporated her employment (albeit as second- changed through a process of continuous interac-
sion made it very difflcult for men to find jobs, 190 ). Their reasons for wanting to be deviant and ary to the male’s) into its structure, thus adapting tion, negotiation and struggle among those who
engagement periods became extended far beyond capture it are numerous and complex. One rcason to changing economie conditions demanding participate in it. . . . The explanation of any in­
what persons wanted. Prior to this period, the in­ seldom considcred by functionalists or anyone dual-income families. Hence, like premarital sex, stitutional arrangement . , . [lies with] power rela­
terval between engagement and marriage-sex else is that persons often define deviance of any what was once viewed as dysfunctional is said tions and negotiations, power struggles and con-
tended to be brief. Faced with the inability of men sort (especially sex) as a “heady experience,” an now to contribute to the family, and thus to soci- flicts, and the coalitions [formed] during the
to fulfill their good provider role and thus marry, “emotional high” (Katz, 1988). Atwater’s (1982) etal organization. processes” (p. 15). Moreover, because struggle
Modell argued that large numbers of engaged per­ study of married women having afifairs indicated Hansen (1988) concurs with the Mirowsky takes place at both the micro- and macrolevels, he
sons faced a dilemma: they could follow sacred “headiness” to be one factor accounting for their ^d Ross (1989) argument that life course transi- argued that a theory about an institution (fami­
norms and remain chaste or, in spite of the dire deviance. Although probably inconceivable to Pat' tions are stressful only to the degree that persons lies) must show the mutual influences between
warnings from church and media, they could sons, an important research question is the part lack a sense of control over the transitions. To these levels. He noted that interest group struggle
212 PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING I930. cBApTER 9 • STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM 213
-1945
becomes as theoretically pivotal as interpersonal analysts begin with “natural” systems (society tudie5 since its inception. Dumon (1988) ob- field of family studies has avoided researching
struggle: Institutional change is not determined by benchmark) as cultural or structural givens serves that American family policy sterns from the political struggles between the Right and Pro-
the “environment” (technology, economie or de- with persons? Homans (1961) argued that mam svhat he calls “social work” values “in terms of gressives over policies for families (Scanzoni,
mographic trends), but is instead “created” by re- stream sociology needed to “bring men back m» qelp or self-hcip to overcomc inadequacics ... [in 1983, 1989, 1991). Most empirical studies of
latlonships and groups “reconstructing . . . envi­ as an antidotc to functionalism. Do family schoi^ fulfilling family functions]” (p. 242). Instead, says these struggles are carried on by researchers out-
ronments by using different technologies” (p. 18). now need to “bring people in” to their analyses to I pumon, in Europe family policy sterns from values side the field. And although feminist advocates cri-
The limitation of fimctionalism for family overcomc the limitations of functionalism? In 0ne I “Social justice . . . [and is concerned with] the tique the Right in terms of oppression and in­
studies derives from the image of Eisenstadt’s of the pioneer anthologies examining the enter |: o0]jtics of scarce resource allocation” (p. 239). justice, few voices in the family field are raised in
“natural givenness in terms of System needs,” As gence of life-styles, Otto (1970) asked: “To what I ^nerican functionalism was consistcntly accused public support of feminist critiques. It can be ar­
long as the benchmark is imaged as a “given” that extern does the American family structure con- I 0f laving a conservative political and social bias gued that this situation is in part a result of the
“naturally” serves the needs of society and its tribute to the optimum development of the ? (Martindale, 1960). Collins (1988) explained the affinity between the functionalist mode of the
members, family studies will continue to be iso- human potential of its members? This is perhaps I c[lirge by saying that functionalism discovered field and that of the Right.
lated from the scientific cross-fertilization that oc- the key question for the assessment of any alter- “what is,” and legitimated it in terms of its ser- The centrality of justice is a second aspect of
curs from interacting with scholars wrestling with native structure” (pp. 4—5). The theoretical issue | vices for society. In no way does functionalism Dumon’s public policy that is intrinsic neither to
struggle and change in many social spheres. Isola- addressed by Otto’s anthology is one of focus: do | address issues such as injustice and oppression. functionalism nor to the Right. Recall that
tion is unfortunate because the subject matter, structures serve persons, or the other way Merton (1957) vigorously attempted to refute Mirowsky and Ross (1989) pointed out that one
“the scientific stuff,” of primary relationships is around? Given the substantial increases in behav- ' such charges but they persist nonetheless. purpose of economie and political participation
struggle over divergent interests (Scanzoni et al, ioral variations since Otto’s time, and based on ■ Charges of a conservative bias intrinsic to family (the European indicators of “justice”) is to facili-
1989). Collins (1975) observed that struggle is studies such as Modell’s, our contention is that the studies have been brought most consistcntly by tate participation in the shaping of families of all
pervasive not only between genders as feminist more valid approach is to focus on persons strug- ? feminist thinkers. As a response to the 1960s’ sorts. They expand Dumon by asserting that the
theorists have long argued, but also across genera- gling to make structures serve them. Women’s Liberation Movement, the Journal of ultimate goal of public policy, including policies
tions. Seeley, Sim, and Loosley (1956) seemed Inevitably, when discussions proceed to this v Marriage and Family devoted a segment to the for families, is to generale the conditions of per-
puzzled to report that: “If the picture of confu- point, the question arises as to “how far” persons J question of feminism and family studies (Bro- sonal well-being. Their target is not to reduce
sion, internal contradiction, and incompatibil- can and will depart form the “natural given derick, 1971b). Several authors asked why there “family” stress and increase “family” well-being.
ity . . . between . . . persons . . . has any veracity, benchmark” in rccreating their primary' arrange- had been no theoretical propositions in family so- Instead, their goal is to facilitate persons living in
it may well be asked how it is possible ... for ments. Will persons venture to create patterns I ciology during the 1960s that might have allowcd families and in primary networks to create what-
families to remain visibly intact as families” p. that are “wholly other” and thus totally unrecog- for the logical possibility of the gender-generated ever social arrangements mitigate personal stress
395). Not much had changed in 30 ycars since, in nizable, as well as socially irresponsible? In con­ ) changes that were emerging. Collins (1988) de- and enhance personal well-being (J. Scanzoni &
their study aimed at understanding conditions of trast to that historie organicist fear, the historie r; scribed Parsons as an “unconscious sexist” (p. W. Marsiglio, 1993). Well-being springs, they say,
“normal family equilibrium” (p. 19), Olson and nominalist response has been that persons and 70), and the same appellation might apply to not from exploitative or one-sided arrangements
McCubbin (1983) seemed equally puzzled [as did groups tend inexorably to redress imbalanccs be­ many pre-1970s’ students of the family. ff one ex- or the pursuit of hedonistic self-indulgence; but


HUI (1983)] to report that they found “little tween self-intercst and other-interest—either be­ amines the Christensen (1964) Handhook or the instead from “supportive relationships—fair and
agreement between husbands and wives over ma­ cause they want to or because struggle requires it 1970 “decade review” (Broderick, 1971a), there caring”—whatever their structure.
jor family variables . . . and even less agreement (Ellis, 1971). Witness the recent monumental is no evidence of conscious chauvinism. Instead,
between adolescents and their parents” (p. 235). events in the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe. an assumption underlying family research was that
They stated that instead of assuming the steady- Thus, just as persons and groups must be “trust- white married women do not work because that
state image of families—“an integrated and highly ed” to create and recreate “responsible” political ( “works best” for society. Hence, one of the very The Future: Neo-Functionalism?
congruent group of individuals”—the researcher and economie arrangements instead of conform- first volumes to document married women’s cm-
should "assume disagreement and lack of con- ing to “natural givens”—whether monarchist or ployment (Hoffman & Nye, 1963) was permeated Although Alexander (1982, 1988) is sym-
gruence” to be intrinsic to families. communist—persons must also be “trusted” to by the question “if women do something that is pathetic with many of Parsons’s early ideas, he has
For over a century it has been difficult for create/rccrcatc “responsible” primary rela­ non-normative, what are the potential dysfunc- produced a number of critical works through
family researchers to conceptualize struggle over tionships stemming from basic emotional and eco­ I tions for husbands and children?” Thirty years which he hopes to develop a modern “neo-func-
divergent interests as intrinsic to their models be­ nomie needs (Bell, 1990). In any case, our taskas ; later, researchers continue to concern themselvcs tionalist” tradition. (Recall that Boss is located in
cause they accept the “natural givenness” of the scientists is to document the unfolding ascen- i with the dysfunctions of family nonconformity. this tradition.) In an anthology devoted to neo-
benchmark. Struggle and change include the po- dance of struggle over conformity at both micro- Recall that Dumon (1988) addressed the functionalism, Alexander (1985, p. 15) notes that
tential for complete cessation of partners’ interac- and macrolevels of primary' relationships Politics of scarce-resource allocation.” In short, “It is a remarkable fact . . , that almost every con-
tions. That potential returns us to the century- (Scanzoni et ai, 1989). . struggle over rights and resources is not only a tribution ... is a ‘conflict theory’ of one sort or
long fear that divorce and its consequences for | focus at the interpersonal level, but at the macro- another.” He also remarks that “These references
children will result in social disorganization. Anx- | P^'tical level as well. In the United States the New to conflict . . . are often accompanied by an em-
Public Policies phasis on contingency and interactional
iety over disorder pervades Popenoe’s (1988) de- Igious Right has bccome the major political
scription of families experiencing changes in Swe- Iloward (1981) reports that the values of so­ Ce a(lvocating the functionalist model of the creativity” (p. 15). Ideologically, moreover, “vir-
den. The basic theoretical question is this: do cial workers have been highly influential in family and society (Bauer, 1986). By and large the tually every contributor [rejects functionalism’s
214 215
PART IV FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930
-1945
gernard,). (1981). The good-provider role: lts rise and fall. ground, development and indications. In S. N. Eisenstadt
conservative sociopolitical image and] pushes field will move toward genuincly dialectical mod­
American Psychologist, 36, 1—12. & H. ). Helle (Eds.), Macrosociological theory I (pp. 7-
functionalism to the left” (p. 14). els of change depends on researchers both as sci- II glumstein, P., & Schwartz, P. (1983). American couples: 24). London: Sage.
In his summary of Alexander’s work, Collins entists and as citizens. From a scientific point of Money, work, sex. New York: William Morrow. Ellis, D. P. (1971). The Hobbesian problem of order: A crit­
(1988) observes that Alexander would prefer to view, will we become persuaded that dialectica! Boss, P- (1986). Psychological absence in the family: A Sys­ ical appraisal of the normative solution. American So­
drop the label “structural—functionalism” in favor models provide the best fit between data and the- tems approach to a study of fathering. In M. B. Sussman ciological Review, 36, 692-703.
of “theory of action.” Nonetheless, Alexander ac- ory? From an applied point of view, will we be­ (Ed.), The Charbydis Complex (pp. 11-32), New York: Espenshade, T. J. (1985). Marriage trends in America: Esti­
knowledges that “‘functionalism’ seems to be a Haworth. mates, implications and underlying causes. Population
come persuaded that providing resources to per. and Development Review, 11, 193-245.
name that has stuck” (1985, p. 9)- Collins notes mm Boss, P- (1987), Family stress, In M. B, Sussman & S. IC
sons struggling with primary relationships is an Steinmetz (Eds), Handbook of marriage and the family Ganong, L. H., & Coleman, M. (1987). Effects of parental
that Alexander is highly critical of Parsons’s em- overarching policy objective? Positive responses remarriage on children: An updated comparison of theo­
(pp, 695-724). New York: Plenum.
phases on role conformity based on socialization to both questions would indeed begin to move Boss, P., Caron, W., Horbal,)., & Mortimer,). (1990). Predic- ries, methods, and findings from clinical and empirical
into values and norms. Instead, Alexander is in- the field in new directions. tors of depression in caregivers of demetia patients: research. In K. Palsey & M. Ihinger-Tallman (Eds.),
terested in leasing out from Parsons hints of his Boundary ambiguity and mastcry. Family Process, 29, Remarriage and stepparenting today: Research and the-
early interest in conflict derived from Max Weber. 245-254. ory (pp. 231-255). New York: Guilford.
References Bourricaud, F. (1981), The sociology of Talcott Parsons. Gibbs, J. P. (1981). The sociology of deviance and social
In that regard, Collins observes that Alexander re-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. control. In M. Rosenberg & R. H. Turner (Eds.), Social
jects Parsons’s notion of social systems in equi- psychology: Sociological perspectives (pp, 483-522).
Adriaansens, H. P. ( 1980). Talcotl Parsons and the concep- Broderick, C. B. (1971a), Beyond the five conceptual frame-
librium. Alexander’s aim is to “purify” Parsonian New York: Basic Books.
tual dilemma London: Routledgc & Kegan Paul. works: A decade of development in family theory.
theory and “to introducé the insights of conflict Ahrons, C. H. (1983). Divorce: Befbre, during, after. In H. I, Journal of Marriage and the Family, 33(1). 139-155. Giddens, A. (1981). Agency, institution, and time-space
theory and phenomenology” (p. 73). To achieve McCubbin & C. R. Figiey (Eds.), Stress and the family: Broderick, C. B. (1971b). Sexism in family siuAies. Journal analysis. In K. Knorr-Cetina & A. V. Cicourel (Eds.),
that aim, “Alexander throws out Pareto and in- Vol. I Coping with normalive transitions (pp. 102- of Marriage and the Family, 33, 345-505. Advances in social theory and methodology (pp. 161-
cludes instead . . . Marx. It is Marx’s [views] of 115). New York: Brunner/Mazel. Buckley, W. ( 1967). Sociology and modem systems theory. 174). Boston; Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Englewood Cliffs, N): Prentice Hall. Godwin, D, D,, & Scanzoni, J. (1989). Couple consensus
conflict and domination and his dialectical drives Ahrons, C. R., & Rodgers, R. H. ( 1987). Divorcedfamilies: A
multidisciplinary developmental view. New York: Bumpass, L L., & Sweet,). A. (1989). National estimates of during marital joint decision making: A context, process,
towards human liberation that Alexander wishes outcome tao<\e\.Journal ofMarriage and the Family, 51,
Norton. cohabitation. Demography, 26, 615—635.
to incorporate into his . . . system of action” (Col­ Burr, W., Nye, F. I., HUI, R., & Reiss, I (Eds.) (1979). 943-956.
Aldous, J., & Klein, D. M. (1988). The linkagcs between
lins, p. 73). Turner (1988), likewise, is sym- family development and family stress. In D. M. Klein &J. Contemporary theories ahout the family, Vols. /, //. New Goode, W. J. (1959). The sociology of the family. In R. K.
pathetic to Parsons, but argues that he “took so- Aldous ( Eds.), Social stress andfamily development (pp York: Free Press. Merton, L. Broom, & L. S, Cottrell, Jr. (Eds,), Sociology
ciology off the mark. The basic unit of sociological 3—15). New York: Guilford. Buunk, B. P., & van Driel, B. (1989) Variant lifestyles and today (pp. 178—196). New York; Basic Books,
analysis is not action, but interaction" (p. 3). Alexander, J. C. (Ed.) (1982). Theoretical logic in so­ relationships. Newbury Park, CA: Sage Goode, W. J. (1961). Illegitimacy, anomie, and cultural pen-
ciology, Vol. 4. Bcrkclcy: University of California Press. Chilman, C. S., Nunnally, E. W., & Cox, M. (Eds.) (1988). etration. American Sociological Review, 26, 910-925.
Consequently, it seems plain that in general Goode, W. J. (1963). World revolution and family pat-
Alexander, J. C. (1985). Introduction. In J C. Alexander Variant family forms. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
sociology traditional Parsonianism has no future, tems. New York: Free Press.
(Ed ), Neo-Functionalism (pp. 7-18). Newbury Park, Christensen, H. T. ( Ed.) ( 1964 )JHandbook of marriage and
although a theory of interaction infused with di­ CA: Sage. the family. Chicago: Rand McNally. Goode, W, J. (1964), The family. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Pren-
alectical clements that explains the ongoing struc- Alexander,). C. (1988). Parsons’ “structure” in American Cohen, A. K. (1959). The study of social disorganization tice-Hall.
turing of social life (including families) is pre- sociology. Sociological Theory, 6( 1), 96-102. and deviant behavior. In R. K. Merton, L. Broom, & L. S. Gouldner, A. W. (1970). The coming crisis of western so­
ferred by increasing numbers of scholars. “No one Alexander,). C. (1990). Commentary; Structure, Value, Ac­ Cottreü, )r. (Eds.), Sociology today: Problems and pros­ ciology. New York: Basic Books.
pects (pp. 461—484). New York: Basic Books Gubrium, J. F., & Holstein, J. A, (1990). What is family?
knows . . . whether a neofunctionalist school ac- tion. American Sociological Review, 55, 339-345.
Atwater, L. ( 1982). The extramarital connection: Sex, inti- Coleman,). S. (1990). Commentary: Social institutions and Mountain View, CA: Mayfteld.
tually will emerge. . . . The movement to reap- Hamilton, P. (1983). Talcott Parsons. Chichester: Ellis
macy, and identity. New York: Irvington social theory. American Sociological Review, 55, 333-
propriate Parsons in a neofunctionalist way is Horwood.
Bales, R„ & Slater, P. (1955). Role differcntiation in small 339.
gaining momentum. Whether it is simply old wine dccision-making groups. In T. Parsons & R. Bales (with). Collins, R, (1975). Conflict sociology. New York: Academie Hansen, D. A. (1988). Schooling, stress, and family develop­
in new bottles, or a new brew, is something histo- Olds, M. Zelditch, )r., & P. Slater) (Eds ), Family so­ Press. ment: Rethinking the social role metaphor. In D. M. Klein
ry will decide” (Alexander, 1985, p. 16). cialization and interaction process (pp 259-306). Collins, R, (1988), Theoretical sociology. New York: Har- & J. Aldous (Eds.), Social stress andfamily development
And what are the prospects for conflict-based Glencoe, 1L: Frec Press. court, Brace, )ovanovich, (pp. 44—78). New York: Guilford.
Bauer, G. L. ( 1986). The family: Preserving America's fu­ Comte, A. (1875). System of positive policy or treatise on Hill, R, (1949), Families under stress. New York: Harper &
theories of any stripe in family studies? From an
ture. Washington, D.C.; White House Working Group on sociology. London: Burt Franklin. Row.
empirical point of view, the prospects should be Hill, R. (1982). American families during the twentieth cen­
the Family. Coser, L (1956). The functions of social conflict. New
promising. The dynamic nature of the data “out Beer, W R. (1989). Dynamics of stepsibling and half sibling York: Free Press. tury. In T. C. Caplow, H. M. Bahr, B. A. Chadwick, R. Hill,
there” demand theories that can account for vari- relationships. In W. R. Beer (Ed ), Relative strangers (pp Dumon, W. (1988). The meaning of family policy in west­ & M. H, Williamson (Eds.), Middletown families: Fifty
eties of primary relationships and household ar- 112-134). Totawa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield ern Europe and the United States. In D. M. Klein & ). years of change and continuity (pp, 271-321). Min-
rangements of all sorts—arrangements explained Bell, D. (1990). Resolving the contradiction of modernity Aldous ( Eds.), Social stress and family development ( pp. neapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
by struggles and choices, as well as by oppression and modernism, Part II. Society, 27, 66-75. 234-245). New York; Guilford. Hill, R. (1983). (Foreword) In D. H. Olson et al, Families:
Bell, N., & Vogel, E. (1960). A modem introduction to the Durkheim, E. (1956). The division of labour in society. WhatMakes Them Work? (pp. 7-10). Beverly Hills; Sage,
and violence and obligation and duty. Neverthe- Hill, R., & Hansen, D. (1960). The identification of concep­
family. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press. (Revised 1968) New York: Free Press.
less, the history of the field suggests that the pros­ tual frameworks utilized in family study. Marriage and
Bellah, R. H., Madsen, R., Sullivan, W. L, Swidler, S., & Tip- Durkheim, E. (1962). The rules of sociological method
pects are uncertain. “Dynamic data” have been ton, S. M. ( 1985). Hahits of the heart: Individualism and New York: Free Press. Family Living 23, 299—311.
“out there” for over a century, yet were in- commitment in American life. Berkeley: University of Eisenstadt, S. N. (1985). Macro-societal analysis: Back- Hofferth, S. (1985). Children’s life course: Family structure
terpreted by homeostatic models. Whether the California Press.

You might also like