An Overview of Corporate Governance

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 23

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/4989092

Shareholding Versus Stakeholding: A Critical Review of Corporate Governance

Article in Corporate Governance An International Review · February 2004


DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-8683.2004.00367.x · Source: RePEc

CITATIONS READS

407 7,331

3 authors:

Letza Steve William X.P. Sun


European Centre for Corporate Governance Leeds Beckett University
34 PUBLICATIONS 1,052 CITATIONS 40 PUBLICATIONS 1,106 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

James Kirkbride
Liverpool John Moores University
30 PUBLICATIONS 868 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by James Kirkbride on 14 June 2019.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


242 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

Shareholding Versus Stakeholding:


a critical review of corporate
governance
Steve Letza*, Xiuping Sun and James Kirkbride

The current debate and theorising on corporate governance has been polarised between a
shareholder perspective and a stakeholder perspective. While advocates and supporters of
each camp attempt to justify the superiority, rationality and universality of each model in
theory, they rarely pay attention to the age-old conceptions, assumptions and presuppositions
underpinning their perspectives which are less credible and valid in matching the continu-
ally changing practice of corporate governance. This paper serves as a survey and critical
review of major current theories on corporate governance. In so doing, it reveals the inade-
quacy of conventional approaches employed in corporate governance theorising. It calls for a
new mode of thinking in analysing corporate governance and concludes by outlining a new
direction of research in this field.

Keywords: Shareholding, stakeholding, corporate governance, modes of thought, dichotomy,


critical review

Introduction governance. The debate has touched many


deep-seated, fundamental questions, for

M uch of the current debate on corporate


governance has centred on practical
issues, including corporate fraud, the abuse of
example what is the purpose of the corpora-
tion? In whose interest is the corporation is
run? Who should control the corporation?
managerial power and social irresponsibil- How should they control it? In general, cor-
ity. In essence, the debate is about how to porate governance is about the understanding
solve these perceived problems in corporate and institutional arrangements for relation-
practice. For many commentators corporate ships among various economic actors and cor-
governance is about building effective porate participants who may have direct or
mechanisms and measures, either in order to indirect interests in a corporation, such as
satisfy current social expectations or to satisfy shareholders, directors/managers, employees,
the narrower expectations of shareholders. In creditors, suppliers, customers, local commu-
the UK, several influential proposals have nities, government, and the general public (see
been produced in recent years in an attempt Figure 1). Different perspectives in theory
to settle the practical issues (Cadbury Com- result in different diagnoses of and solutions
mittee, 1992; Greenbury Committee, 1995; to the problems of corporate governance
*Address for correspondence:
Hampel Committee, 1998; Turnbull Commit- practice.
The Centre for Director tee, 1999; Higgs 2003). In conjunction with the Some current perspectives on corporate
Education, Leeds Metropoli- practical debate sits a debate on the theoreti- governance have been categorised into two
tan University, Bronte Hall,
Beckett Park, Leeds LS6 cal framework and the quest for the optimal contrasting paradigms: shareholding and stake-
3QS. E-mail: srletza@lmu.ac.uk or superior theoretical model of corporate holding (see, for example, O’Sullivan, 2000;

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004. 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford,


Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 243

model (Jensen, 2001). The analyses seldom


step outside the narrow confines of their
Government
respective interests to investigate the theoreti-
cal genealogy, ideology, presuppositions and
Shareholders value systems behind and underpinning the
perspectives or paradigms. This conventional
approach constrains their views and raises
Creditors Customers serious questions as to the theoretical validity
Directors and credibility of these models. To understand
Managers the current fierce debate on corporate gover-
Suppliers Community
nance, it is important to stand back from the
one-sided arguments with their taken-for-
granted ideas. Reflexive thinking is needed
Employees through critical examination of the major the-
orems, assumptions and origins of both per-
spectives. This paper serves as a survey and
General Public
critical review of both the shareholder and
stakeholder perspectives on corporate gover-
nance. A major finding in this paper is that
Figure 1: Relationships in corporate governance although the current prevailing analyses may
have some merits and insights at a particular
point in time, they are, however, over-
Kakabadse and Kakabadse, 2001; Friedman abstracted and over-static in modelling and
and Miles, 2002). Such a division hinges on theorising corporate governance. They build
the purpose of the corporation and its asso- their “rational” arguments and “ideal” models
ciated structure of governance arrangements on traditional assumptions and theories that
understood and justified in theory. On the one were generated and/or constructed in cen-
side is the traditional shareholding perspec- turies-old societal contexts, far removed from
tive, which regards the corporation as a legal the current modern business environment
instrument for shareholders to maximise their where, for example, the boundary of the firm
own interests – investment returns. A three- has become blurred in terms of global markets
tier hierarchal governance structure, i.e. the and where physical assets are far less impor-
shareholder general meeting, the board of tant than human resources, knowledge and
directors and executive managers, is given in information. They ignore the continuous
company law in an attempt to secure share- change of natural and social realities and dis-
holders’ interest (it is often called the mecha- tance themselves from the dynamics of corpo-
nism of “checks and balances”). On the other rate governance in practice. The economic
side is the stakeholding perspective newly approach mostly employed in their analyses
emerged in the later 20th century, which posi- tends to be culture-free, historically separated
tions itself on the contrary to the traditional and contextually unrelated. We note that very
wisdom and views the corporation as a locus recent studies have seriously questioned the
in relation to wider external stakeholders’ traditional theory of the firm and called for a
interests rather than merely shareholders’ new direction in building a new theory of the
wealth. Employees, creditors, suppliers, cus- firm that reflects the modern day business
tomers and the local community are major environment (e.g., Zingales, 2000; Rajan and
stakeholders often mentioned and empha- Zingales, 2000). Other studies in law, sociol-
sised within a broad definition of stake- ogy, politics and culture in relation to corpo-
holding (e.g. Freeman, 1984). Stakeholders’ rate power and control may also offer some
participation in corporate decision-makings, insights into rethinking corporate governance
long-term contractual associations between and overcome part of the shortcomings of
the firm and stakeholders, trust relationships current models. It is the conventional modes
and business ethics are the main proposals for of thought and associated approaches such as
stakeholding management. dualism/dichotomy, idealism/perfectionism,
Current analyses on corporate governance universality and permanency that endorse
draw more attention to evaluating and and justify the polarised shareholding and
judging the superiority of either the share- stakeholding models.
holder model or stakeholder model and often This paper is structured as follows. In the
take part in one-sided arguments, sometimes next section current major theoretical models
with a slight modification such as an enlight- in corporate governance are summarised
ened shareholder model (see Gamble and based on the mainstream typology. These
Kelly, 2001) and an enlightened stakeholder models are presented as examples to indicate

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


244 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

how the two academic schools of sharehold- of stakeholders and emphasises corporate effi-
ing and stakeholding have been divided into ciency in a social context. Departing from the
opposing camps. Following this, the major prevailing economic analysis of corporate
theorems and arguments of the shareholding governance, the political model (e.g. Pound,
and stakeholding perspectives are examined 1992, 1993), according to Hawley and Williams
respectively, from which their basic assump- (1996), is a non-market approach for monitor-
tions and presuppositions are clearly ob- ing management, such as shareholder democ-
served. Attention is given to the shifting racy and negotiation. In Turnbull’s (1997b)
character of the corporate reality as well as the view, such a political model focuses only on
perspectives themselves, from which the the micro level of politics in corporations, the
superiority of both theoretical models is broader political context such as the political
questioned. Recent new challenges to the tradition, ideology, government intention, reg-
traditional theory of the firm and stakeholder ulation and institution is considered elsewhere
theory are reviewed. Finally, we conclude the (e.g. Letza and Smallman, 2001). Turnbull also
paper with some remarks on the limitations of reviews other models based on culture, power
current approaches, particularly the conven- and cybernetics, in addition to the above four
tional modes of thought, on analysing corpo- models.
rate governance issues and call for a new way Based on Blair’s (1995) taxonomy, Keasey
of thinking. The conclusion of this paper is et al. (1997) also summarise four competing
that modes of thought do matter in under- models in the current studies of corporate gov-
standing corporate governance. ernance, each with its own diagnosis of and
solutions for the Anglo-American governance
issues. The four schools of thought are the
principal-agent or finance model, the myopic
The corporate governance debate: market model, the abuse of executive power
shareholding vs stakeholding model, and the stakeholder model. Here,
the principal-agent or finance model and the
As current analyses on corporate governance stakeholder model are the same as those in the
approach the governance issue from different classification of Hawley and Williams, as men-
perspectives and base their views on different tioned above. In the view of the principal-
assumptions and presuppositions, there exist agent or finance model (e.g. Manne, 1965;
quite diverse theoretical models which can be Jensen and Meckling, 1976), although the sep-
identified in the literature. Major surveys aration of ownership and control may provide
and/or reviews of corporate governance the opportunities for managerial divergent
models have been conducted by Hawley and behaviours from maximising shareholders’
Williams (1996), Shleifer and Vishny (1997), value, the markets – particularly the capital
Turnbull (1997b) and Keasey et al. (1997). market, the managerial labour market and the
Hawley and Williams (1996) suggest four market for corporate control – provide the
major views in the corporate governance most effective restraints on managerial discre-
debate in the US, i.e. the finance model, the tion (note that this assumption is rejected by
stewardship model, the stakeholder model Pound (1992, 1993) for the reason that a new
and the political model. The dominant model form of governance based on politics rather
in the late 20th century is the finance view of than finance would be more effective and less
corporate governance, which is concerned expensive). This school claims that corporate
with a universal agency problem and how to governance failures are best addressed by
adopt appropriate incentive systems and/or removing restrictions on factor markets and
the mechanism of takeover to solve this the market in corporate control, together
problem. While the finance model is focused with strengthening the incentive system
on shareholder rights and control in publicly (bonuses, stock options, etc.), introducing a
held corporations, Shleifer and Vishny (1997) voluntary code and appointing non-executive
extend the finance view of the firm to include directors.
not only shareholders, but also debt-holders Though the myopic market model (e.g.
and bankers. In contrast to the dominant Charkham, 1994; Sykes, 1994; Moreland, 1995)
finance model, the stewardship model (see agrees with the principal-agent or finance
Donaldson and Davis, 1994) assumes a differ- model that the maximisation of shareholders’
ent nature of agent/managerial behaviour and interests is the focus, it argues that the
argues that managers are trustworthy and fundamental flaw of the Anglo-American
should be fully empowered. The stakeholder corporate governance system is its excessive
model further extends the purpose of the concern with short-term market value. Certain
corporation from maximising shareholders long-term expenditures, particularly capital
wealth to delivering wider outputs to a range investment and research and development

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 245

spending, are systematically undervalued by issues in corporate governance issues, i.e.


the markets because of the immediate pressure self-interest behaviour of agents, short-term
or interest from hostile takeovers. The short- market forces, the abuse of power by manage-
sighted markets thus force otherwise diligent ment and the neglect of stakeholders’ involve-
managers to concentrate solely on the current ment. Each model offers its own diagnosis
share price and ignore the long-term value cre- as the “true” cause of corporate governance
ation of the firm, or take decisions against the defects and based on the diagnosis each tries
threat of hostile takeover at the expense of to search and find an optimal solution. They
shareholders interest. The solution for improv- concentrate on the mechanisms of internal
ing corporate governance is to provide an monitoring or external market discipline from
environment in which shareholders (particu- which to prescribe peculiar recipes to treating
larly large and/or institutional shareholders) the ailments. While the principal-agent model
and managers are encouraged to share long- highly values the mechanism of market gov-
run performance horizons, such as increasing ernance, the other three rely on non-market
shareholders’ loyalty and voice, reducing the measures, such as shareholder loyalty and
shareholder exit, encouraging “relationship voice, institutional shareholders’ monitoring,
investing”, and empowering other groups and independent non-executive directors’
(employees, suppliers, etc.) to have long-term empowerment, and stakeholders’ participa-
relationships with the firm. tion in decision-making. Table 1 summarises
Rejecting the principal-agent or finance the main viewpoints and their contexts in the
model, the abuse of executive power model four models.
(e.g. Hutton, 1995; Kay and Silberston, 1995) The above four models (and other main-
claims that the purpose of a corporation is to stream models previously mentioned) are
serve the corporate interest as a whole. The constructed as theoretical models and are
major problem with the current corporate gov- primarily drawn from within the Anglo-
ernance arrangements is that they allow exces- American context. They do not purposefully
sive power to executive managers who may cover all types of companies and all societies
abuse their power in pursuit of their own in the world, nor do they include all corporate
interests. The supporters of this model argue governance and control studies (for more
that the current institutional restraints on details on the limitations of the Hawley and
managerial behaviour based on the notions of Williams’ perspective see Turnbull, 1997b).
self-regulation and market discipline are inef- But what is significant is that these models
fective and inadequate. They appeal for statu- represent a conventional mode of thinking
tory changes in corporate governance, such about corporate governance, which has
as a fixed four-year term for chief executive long been underlining and dominating our
officers, independent nomination of non- research, ideas and governance practices,
executive directors and more powers for and which can be found everywhere all over
non-executive directors. the world, not merely limited to the Anglo-
The major challenge to the principal-agent American societies (although such a mode of
or finance model stems from the stakeholder thought can be found more easily and more
model (e.g. Freeman, 1984; Blair, 1995), which explicitly in the Anglophone context). With the
claims that the firm should serve wider inter- conventional mode of thought, all the theoret-
ests of stakeholders rather than shareholders ical models neatly fall within two opposing
only. Stakeholders such as employees, credi- perspectives: the shareholder perspective and
tors, suppliers, customers and local com- the stakeholder perspective. For example, the
munities have long-term relationships (both former two models in the above belong to a
contributions and risk-sharing) with the firm shareholder perspective as they share the
and affect its long-term success. Their welfare common assumption that the purpose of cor-
must be taken into account in corporate porations is the maximisation of shareholders’
decision-making. This model argues that the wealth. And the latter two commonly hold a
current corporate governance system in the stakeholder perspective, since both insist on a
Anglo-American environment fails to en- broad sense of stakeholding welfare. Such
courage stakeholder involvement with the a convenient taxonomy has been used by
firm, including inter-firm cooperation and O’Sullivan (2000) and Kakabadse and Kak-
employee participation, which indicates a dis- abadse (2001), among others. It is notable that
advantage of national performance and inter- the separation and polarisation of sharehold-
national competition, in comparison with the ing and stakeholding is not only popular
corporate governance structures in Germany among scholars, but also among practitioners
and in Japan.1 and societies The fundamental issue behind
The above four models as presented in the approach and associated modes of thought
Keasey et al. (1997) have explored specific has not been recognised so far in the field of

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


246 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

Table 1: Summary of current mainstream corporate governance models

The principal- The myopic The abuse of The stakeholder


agent or finance market model executive power model
model model

Major contributor Jensen and Charkham (1994); Hutton (1995); Kay Freeman (1984);
Meckling (1976); Sykes (1994) and Silberston Blair (1995)
Manne (1965) (1995)
Purpose of Maximisation of Maximisation of Maximisation of Maximisation of
corporation shareholder wealth shareholder wealth corporate wealth as stakeholders’
a whole wealth
Problem of Agency problem Excessive concern Abuse of executive Absence of
governance with short-term power for their own stakeholders’
market value interests involvement
Cause Shareholders do not Ineffective market Institutional Governance failure
have enough forces arrangements leave to represent
control excessive power to stakeholders’
management interests
Background The separation of The takeover Managerialism Different styles of
ownership from movement in the capitalism
control 1980s
Assumption about Self-interest human Market dysfunction Authoritarian Traditional
the causation behaviour governance mentality of private
ownership
Rejection Any external Market governance The principal-agent The principal-agent
interventions model model
Proposition Market efficiency Importance of long- Manager as Social efficiency of
term relationship trusteeship economy
Solution • Removing • Increasing • Statutory changes • Trust
restrictions on shareholder loyalty in governance relationships and
markets and voice • Fixed four-year long-term
• Strengthening the • Reducing the ease terms of CEO contractual
incentive system of shareholder exit • Independent associations
• Introducing a • Encouraging nomination of between the firm
voluntary code relationship directors and stakeholders
investing • Greater power of • Inter-firm
• Empowering non-executive cooperation
long-term offer directors • Employees’
groups participation
• Business ethics

Source: Based on Keasey et al. (1997), Blair (1995).

corporate governance. While the two main the subject. Therefore, in what follows, we
perspectives are deliberately duplicated in attempt to capture the central arguments, core
many studies, the theorems, origins, assump- assumptions and philosophies of the share-
tions and theoretical contexts embedded in or holding and stakeholding perspectives respec-
behind the perspectives are less well examined tively, from which the sharp differences on
and articulated in the literature. The validity assumptions and presuppositions between the
of modes of thinking is rarely questioned. In two perspectives are clearly observed. These
general, the understanding of the debate and analyses are necessary for our further ques-
the models and perspectives of corporate gov- tions about the current way of theorising in
ernance are merely scratching the surface of corporate governance.

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 247

The shareholding perspective: century. One side of the debate is referred to


corporate governance as a as the aggregate or “fiction” theory, advocated
by the German jurisprudent Rudolf von
private matter Jhering (1818–1892) and the American juris-
The mentality of individual prudent Wesley N. Hohfeld (1879–1918).
That doctrine asserts that the corporation as a
private property
legal group is simply created by the state and
The shareholding perspective as an orthodox is no more than a private association of share-
and dominant approach to the understanding holders. The new form of corporate property
of corporate governance has its ideological is the aggregation of individual property
and theoretical origin in the fundamental rights under a collective name, united by con-
mentality of individual private ownership tract and protected by company law. Since
rights as the foundation of capitalism. The tra- shareholders are the owners of the corpora-
ditional wisdom is that private ownership is tion, the corporation has legitimate obligations
fundamental to a desirable social order and to and the managers have a fiduciary duty to act
the development of an efficient economy, and in the interest of shareholders (a summary of
thus private ownership rights are inviolable to the above theory is shown in Table 2) (Barker,
corporate governance (see Gamble and Kelly, 1958; Mayson et al., 1994).
2001). Underlying the notion of private own- In the 20th century, the traditional liberal
ership is the ideology of individualism which and individualist approach to property and
emerged in England in the 15th and 16th cen- corporate governance was further justified
turies as a result of the emerging mercantilism in neoclassical economics along with the
and the Reformation and Renaissance which principle of free market, economic efficiency
gradually broke from the old feudal society and profit maximisation. Hayek (1969), for
and required a new definition of social order example, argues that individuals owning
and regulation. Individualism initially empha- private property and pursuing self-interests
sised such conceptions as individual separa- ensure the most efficient economic activities
tion (with self-confidence, self-awareness and outcomes. The corporation owned by
and self-help), freedom (free mobility, free shareholders must aim at maximising profits
exchange and free competition) and autonomy to enhance shareholders value. If a corpora-
(private contract, self-determination and self- tion acts for any social purpose beyond share-
regulation) (Macfarlane, 1978; see also Tricker, holders’ interest, it will provide opportunities
2000). With the development of the capitalist for managers to justify their abuse of power
economy during the 17th, 18th and 19th cen- and for government to intervene in corporate
turies, when incorporation began to emerge in decisions, which will lead to the allocation of
England at first as a chartered form for over- corporate resources in an inefficient way.
seas trading (such as the East India Company Friedman (1962, 1970) also asserts that the
in 1600) and subsequently as a legislated form function of business in a society is to make
as a mechanism for raising capital and busi- profits in a free market for shareholders,
ness expansion,2 the individualist ideology which should not be confused with other
was inherited by corporate law theory in social functions performed by governments,
interpreting the nature of incorporation. It was institutions and charities. The request for
assumed that the right to incorporate is inher- social responsibility of business is harmful to
ent in the right to own property and write the foundations of a free society with a free-
contracts, and that the corporation is a legal enterprise and private-property system. Thus,
extension of its owners – shareholders (see for Friedman, the only social responsibility of
Allen, 1992). The inherent property rights business is to increase its profits.
theory also insisted that although a company
is regarded as a legal person separate from its
owners, the nature of shareholders as the A universal agency problem
company’s owners never changes and the In the shareholding perspective, a basic issue
company is legally obliged to serve the in- in corporate governance is whether or not
terest of its shareholders (as the corporate shareholders’ interest can be effectively pro-
members). Corporate property should be tected under the current institutional arrange-
treated as a private association which de- ments. Since shareholders have to delegate
mands the minimum of government regu- control to a few directors and managers to run
lation and interference (see Gamble and Kelly, the company on behalf of all the shareholders,
2001). there is a potential risk that directors and man-
This theory obtained further support during agers may serve their own interests at the
a fierce debate in corporate law theory on the expense of all the shareholders. This problem
nature of corporate personality in the late 19th was initially identified by Adam Smith in 1776

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


248 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

Table 2: Contrasting views in the 19th century’s debate on corporate governance

Major theories Inherent property rights theory Social entity theory


(also the fiction theory) (also the organic theory)

Nature of corporation Association of shareholders Independent legal person


Purpose Shareholders’ interest Social/corporate interest
Objective Profit maximisation Long-term growth
Ownership Private property/individual rights Corporate property/collective
rights
Legal instrument Contract Law
Regulation Self-regulation Legislation/state intervene
Governance structure Internal monitoring: managers as Internal monitoring: managers as
agents with fiduciary duty and organs/representatives with
accountability loyalty, authority and social
responsibility
Legal system Anglo-American legal system Continent-European legal system

Source: Based on Allen (1992), Mayson et al. (1994).

(1937), who noted that the directors in a joint- appropriately. The second issue is that the
stock company could not be expected to be principal and the agent may prefer different
as vigilant and careful with other people’s actions because of the different attitudes
money as they are with their own. Manage- toward risk (Eisenhardt, 1989, p. 58). Those
ment’s potential negligence and profusion two problems incur a particular type of man-
always prevail as an issue in public compa- agement cost – “agency cost” – as principals/
nies. This problem has become wider and owners attempt to ensure that agents/
more serious since the early 20th century, as managers act in the principals’ interests
the separation of ownership and control (Jensen and Meckling, 1976). The best solution
increased the power of professional managers to those problems is to determine the most
and leaves them free to pursue their own efficient contract governing the principal-
interests (Berle and Means, 1932). Concerned agent relationship and an optimal incentive
with this issue, agency theory was built by scheme to align the behaviour of the managers
Jensen and Meckling (1976), among others, in with the interest of owners.
the 1970s, employed for their diagnosis of The concept of contract is the most favoured
and solution to the corporate governance metaphor used in agency theory. It believes
ailments. that all social relations in economic interaction
Beginning with the aged assumption of the are reducible to a set of contracts between
nature of self-interest human behaviour, principals and agents. The role of contracts
which intrinsically underpins individualism serves as a vehicle for voluntary exchange
and classical and neoclassical economics, (Alchian and Demsetz, 1972). The firm can be
agency theorists assert that the agency best viewed as a “nexus of contracts” and con-
problem can occur in all cooperative efforts tractual relations exist not only between share-
where there exist principal-agent relation- holders, but also with all other stakeholders
ships, namely, in all organisations and at every (Jensen and Meckling, 1976). But only share-
level of management in organisations (Jensen holders have profit incentive and investment-
and Meckling, 1976, p. 309). This implies that risk awareness to ensure the most efficient and
managers as agents may naturally use the effective governance arrangements to protect
delegated power in their hands to maximise their interests (see Dallas, 1988, p. 24). To align
their own utility instead of shareholders/ the interest of the agent with that of the prin-
principals’ welfare. Therefore, managers are cipal, a complete contract containing specifi-
basically untrustworthy and must be fully cations of the agent duties, rewards and the
monitored. There are two issues occurring in rights of the principal to monitor their perfor-
the agency relationship with which agency mance is required (see Fligstein and Freeland,
theory is concerned. The first is that because it 1995, p. 26). According to the proponents of
is difficult or expensive for the principal to principal-agent theory, adopting appropriate
know the performance of the agent, the prin- incentive systems to reward managers is a key
cipal cannot verify that the agent has behaved solution to the agency problem.

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 249

The focus of agency theory is on determin- indicator of corporate performance and the
ing the most efficient contract governing stock market is the only objective evaluation
the principal-agent relationship. An optimal of management performance. If a firm under-
choice between a behaviour-oriented contract performs its share price will drop, which pro-
(e.g. salaries, hierarchical governance) and an vides a chance for outsiders to purchase the
outcome-oriented contract (e.g. commissions, firm’s stock at a lower price and run the firm
stock options, transfer of property rights) more efficiently in order to obtain a greater
becomes critical (Eisenhardt, 1989, p. 58). It reward. The threat of a takeover forces man-
ultimately depends on the trade-off calcula- agement to make efforts for better perfor-
tion between the cost of measuring behaviour mance and maximise shareholders’ return in
(through purchasing complete information order to prevent takeover.
and rewarding hard-working behaviours) and Supporters of the finance model argue that
the cost of measuring outcomes (e.g. prof- corporate governance failure can be best
itability) and transferring risk to the agent addressed by removing restrictions on factor
(Eisenhardt, 1985, p. 136). markets and the market for corporate control
While agency theory focuses on writing (Fama, 1980). Shareholders’ voting rights on
complete contracts and implementing effec- takeover should be enhanced. Any external
tive monitoring to secure shareholders’ inter- interventions and additional obligations
est, it also views the managerial labour market imposed on corporations may distort free
as a disciplinary tool on managerial misbe- market mechanisms and thus should be
haviour. There exists both external managerial avoided (Hart, 1995). Self-regulation, as well
labour market (each manager’s outside oppor- as some additional measures without compul-
tunity wage is determined by the performance sion, such as a voluntary code (Cadbury
of the firm) and internal managerial labour Committee, 1992), is more efficient than any
market (top managers in a firm compete to legislative change.
become the boss of the bosses), which can
effectively discipline managers who may have
incentive to expropriate shareholders wealth
Controvertible marketisation
(Fama, 1980). The market solution to corporate governance
problems is, however, rejected by another
school of thought, the myopic market model
Market efficiency and market governance (Blair, 1995; Keasey et al., 1997). Sharing the
Within the shareholding camp, there is an common position of the shareholding per-
argument on how to solve the agency spective, the myopic market model argues
problem. Like all bureaucratic organisations, a that the Anglo-American model of corporate
hierarchical check and balance mechanism governance is fundamentally flawed by
was designed in company law, which includes an over concern with short-termism due to
the three-tier structure – the shareholders’ huge market pressures – short-term return
general meeting, the board of directors and on investment, short-term corporate profits,
executive managers. However, in the 20th short-term management performance, short-
century, with the increasing separation of term stock market prices and short-term
ownership and control within the Anglo- expenditures. Thus, the most serious problem
American culture, shareholders’ internal with corporate governance is that the current
monitoring became less effective. Under these institutional arrangement encourages man-
circumstances, many financial economists agers to focus on short-term profit return
advocate that market governance is the most (even less than half a year) by sacrificing long-
effective mechanism, because the pressure of term value (e.g. R&D investment) and com-
capital markets and takeovers can heavily dis- petitive capacity of the corporation (e.g. Hayes
cipline managerial discretion of deviating and Abernathy, 1980; Charkham, 1994; Sykes,
from shareholders value of profit maximisa- 1994; Moreland, 1995). It is argued that the
tion (Alchian and Kessel, 1962; Manne, 1965). stock market is not a good indicator of corpo-
The rationale behind the finance model of cor- rate performance because it is unable to cope
porate governance is a theorem prevailing in with uncertainty and often misprices assets.
financial economics, which assumes that the The share prices can change without any cor-
share price today fully reflects the market responding change in corporate fundamental
value of all future profits and growth that will values and may simply result from guesses
accrue to the company. Thus, the advocates of about the behaviour and psychology of
the “market for corporate control” hold that market participants and the changing moods
shareholders wealth is best served by max- and prejudices of investors (Keynes, 1936;
imising share price; unfortunately this tends Shiller, 1989). Therefore, the market for corpo-
towards the short run. The share price is an rate control is not an efficient disciplinary

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


250 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

mechanism. The threat of hostile takeover may there emerged a “nature-entity” or “organic”
distort and distract from true value creation as theory, which is particularly associated with
managers may be forced to act against hostile the German legal historian Otto von Gierke
takeover at the expense of corporate wealth. (1841–1921). This theory asserts that an asso-
The myopic market model turns back to ciation of persons has a real personality that is
internal mechanisms, rather than external not fictionally created by the state or law, but
markets, for effective corporate governance by really existent and recognised by the group in
stressing long-term economic relationships the process of incorporation. The law simply
and long-run corporate performance horizons found the existence of the group or association
shared by shareholders and managers. Share- and endowed it with a corporate personality
holders’ loyalty and voice rather than exit with legal powers. Thus, the corporation as a
should be encouraged. The takeover process real, rather than an artificial, person is not the
and shareholders’ voting rights for short-term aggregation of its members and individual
return should be restricted (see Keasey et al., rights. It has a distinctive mind/will and
1997). capacity to act, has its own rights and duties,
and is responsible for its own actions and
their consequences. Individuals in the corpo-
ration carry out duties and other activities
The stakeholding perspective: and as such are not acting as independent
stakeholder interest as end or means persons but as organs of the corporate person
(for a summary of the above theory, see Table
The corporation as a social entity 2) (see Barker, 1958; Arthur, 1987; Mayson et
Stakeholder theory has been categorised into al., 1994).
three aspects, i.e. normative, instrumental, and Based on the grounds of fundamental value
descriptive, based on their different research and moral order of the community, the social
approaches (Donaldson and Preston, 1995). entity theory views the corporation as a social
Two types of main stakeholder theory can be institution in society. As Sacks (1997) posits,
identified – the normative stakeholder theory our attachments and affiliations, loyalties and
and the instrumental stakeholder theory. loves are both moral and fundamental: “they
While the former emphasises “intrinsic value” enter into our identity, our understanding of
in stakeholding and views stakeholders as the specific person we are” and “they cannot
“end”, the latter is only interested in how be reduced to contractual alliances for the
stakeholders’ value can be used for improving temporary pursuit of gain” (quoted in Warren,
corporate performance and efficiency and 2000, p. 130). The justification of “intrinsic
regards stakeholders as “means”. In corporate value” as good or morally right and ideal does
governance, the normative stakeholder theory not necessarily depend on factual reasons, but
has its origin in the social entity conception of rather on an emotional faith and social belief
the corporation, as developed in the later part (Campbell, 1997, p. 446; Stoney and Winstan-
of the 19th century. It was observed that the ley, 2001, p. 608). It is argued that corporations
modern corporation had large scale and scope are granted by the state not only as an eco-
that required distinctive professional manage- nomic entity for a commercial purpose but,
ment expertise and a great amount of capital more importantly, as a social entity for general
investments. Through stock markets, share community needs such as “honouring indi-
ownership in a corporation become dispersed vidual dignity and promoting overall welfare”
and fragmented and shareholders are more (Sullivan and Conlon, 1997, p. 713). The cor-
like investors rather than owners. Since cor- poration has a collective rather than individ-
porations are involved in many aspects of ual identity and executives are representatives
social life and affect many people in both and guardians of all corporate stakeholders’
welfare and potential risks, a public corpora- interests (Hall, 1989). To resolve disputes and
tion should be conscious of its social obliga- conflicts of interests and overcome market
tions such as fairness, social justice and failures and transaction costs, legal interven-
protection of employees. In this regard, cor- tion within a public law framework and an
porations became more like independent improved system of checks and balances are
entities with their own purpose, their own necessary (Millon, 1990; Allen, 1995).
properties and their own duties (see Allen, In recent years, several concepts or perspec-
1992). tives advocated are linked to the social entity
This view is strongly supported by corpo- conception of the corporation, such as eco-
rate law theory in which the corporation is nomic democracy promoted by democratic
defined as a legal person separate from its political theorist Robert Dahl (1985), associa-
members.3 In the debate against the aggregate tionalism by Paul Hirst (1994), and communi-
or “fiction” theory as mentioned previously, tarian notion of property by Jonathan Boswell

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 251

(1990) (see Warren, 2000, pp. 130–142). The This line of stakeholding theory views its
recent resurgence of the normative or moral instrumentality as “intrinsic value” which
aspect of stakeholder perspectives (e.g. is more attuned to the traditional Anglo-
Handy, 1993, 1997; Carroll, 1991, 1996) has in American corporate governance mentality of
general reflected the social entity conception private ownership (Gamble and Kelly, 2001). It
of the corporation. suggests that corporate governance should not
depart from ownership rights, but that such
rights should not be solely claimed by, and
The instrumentality of stakeholding thus concentrated in, shareholders; ownership
rights can also be claimed by other stakehold-
The most popular perspective in stakeholder ers, particularly employees. Turnbull (1994,
theory is the instrumental stakeholder theory 1997a, 1998), for example, advocates stake-
promoted by economists and others (e.g. holder ownership and governance in line with
Cadbury Committee, 1992; Parkinson, 1995; a property rights analysis. He suggests that
Campbell, 1997; Plender, 1997; Centre for a perpetual shareholder ownership permits
Tomorrow’s Corporation, 1998; Slinger, 1998). investors to be overpaid, which “is inconsis-
It holds the same claim as the social entity tent with either economic efficiency or social
theory, that a corporation should serve multi- equity” (1997a, pp. 11–12). He also supports
ple interests of stakeholders, rather than share- stakeholder theory from a cybernetic perspec-
holder interest alone, in order to make the tive, and claims that stakeholder participation
corporation more legitimate. Unlike social in corporate governance can generate more
entity theory that justifies stakeholder inter- accurate and unbiased information for busi-
ests on the basis of moral value and funda- ness operation and management and thus
mental human rights, the instrumental improve governing efficiency and effective-
stakeholder theory legitimises stakeholder ness (1997a, 2002). For Blair and others (e.g.
value on the grounds of stakeholding as an Blair, 1995; Kelly and Parkinson, 1998), stake-
effective means to improve efficiency, prof- holders who make firm specific investments
itability, competition and economic success. and contributions and bear risks in the corpo-
As Campbell explicitly posits, “I support ration should have residual claims and should
stakeholder theory not from some left wing participate in the corporate decision-makings
reason of equity, but because I believe it to be to enhance corporate efficiency. In Blair’s view,
fundamental to understanding how to make in the case of firm-specific investments, “com-
money in business” (1997, p. 446). Freeman’s petitive markets are of little use in deter-
(1984) initiative on stakeholder management mining how to allocate the rents and risk
as a business strategy also has an instrumen- associated with those investments” (Blair,
tal orientation. He argues that as the forces 1995, pp. 267). Thus, stakeholding governance
of stakeholder groups such as stockholders, is better exercised through internal control
lenders, customers, employees, suppliers and mechanisms rather than external markets,
management are increasingly and vitally such as corporate boards acting as representa-
affecting business success and corporate sur- tives of stakeholders in the corporation. Cor-
vival, corporate strategy must sensitise this porate governance systems and contractual
change and ensure that stakeholder interests arrangements “should be devised to assign
are incorporated into, rather than ignored, in control rights, rewards, and responsibilities to
corporate strategy. In recent years, stakeholder the appropriate stakeholders – the parties that
theory has been associated with a political contribute specialised inputs” (Blair, 1995, p.
position such as New Left (Stoney and Win- 274).
stanley, 2001) and has tended to be seen as a
reconciliation of the competing claims of eco-
nomic efficiency and social justice (O’Sullivan, Managerial trusteeship
2000). However, the final end of justification is The economic approach in conventional cor-
still instrumental. For example, in the book porate governance analysis (such as the share-
Stakeholder Capitalism edited by Kelly et al., holding perspective and the instrumental
stakeholder theory is based on the grounds stakeholder theory as indicated above) typi-
that cally presupposes a taken-for-granted human
Individuals well endowed with economic and nature as “self-interested” and therefore con-
social capabilities will be more productive; com- cludes that managers as agents cannot be
panies which draw on the experience of all of trusted (note that agency relationship is also
their stakeholders will be more efficient; while assumed in stakeholder theory, Hill and Jones
social cohesion within a nation is increasingly (1992), for example, assert a stakeholder-
seen as a requirement for international compet- agency theory). However, the assumption of
itiveness. (Kelly et al., 1997, p. 244) untrustworthy managers is rejected in the

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


252 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

management literature (e.g. Marris, 1964; whole corporation. Empowering independent


Nichols, 1969; Etzioni, 1975). As a contrast, it directors and fixing CEOs’ term of office to a
is suggested that managers are good stewards maximum of four years are also necessary for
of the corporation and diligently work for the the corporation as a social institution.
maximisation of corporate profit and share-
holder returns. The stewardship theory argues
that managers have a wide range of motives
beyond self-interest, such as the need for Shareholding vs stakeholding:
achievement and recognition, the intrinsic sat- do they map the territory?
isfaction of good performance and success,
respect for authority, the work ethic, and so The current fierce debate between the share-
forth. Thus, managers as stewards are trust- holding and stakeholding perspectives (for the
worthy and a professional management is recent arguments, see Sternberg, 1998, 2000;
beneficial for corporate performance and Vinten, 2001; Turnbull, 1997a, 2002; for a
shareholder wealth (Donaldson and Davis, survey of the recent dispute and tendency in
1994). the UK, see Gamble and Kelly, 2001) repre-
While stewardship theory is mostly consis- sents two extreme positions and a polarised
tent with a shareholder perspective (but from approach in understanding corporate gover-
a different assumption of human nature), a nance (Prabhaker, 1998; Friedman and Miles,
trusteeship model is proposed by Kay and Sil- 2002). Underlining the argument are two con-
berston (1995) in connection with the stake- flicting and competing ideologies, cultures
holder perspective. They start their argument and value judgements within capitalism. As
by describing the current practical state of a examined in the last two sections, at one end
publicly held corporation that shareholders do is the traditional dominant wisdom of “indi-
not actually possess the ownership of a cor- vidualism” – private property and individual
poration and are not interested in running liberty, and thus the justification of maximis-
corporate business. Further, they suggest that ing shareholders’ value as the sole purpose of
company law does not explicitly grant share- the firm. At the other end is the communitar-
holders ownership of corporations, since the ian notion of property and social institutional
corporation is an independent legal person conception of the firm and the idea of “justice
with its own ownership separated from its for all”, and thus the legitimisation of accom-
shareholding members and shareholders are modating all stakeholders’ interests by a firm.
merely the “residual claimants” of the corpo- On the surface the instrumental stakeholder
ration (see also Deakin and Slinger, 1997; theory seems to bridge the two ends, but in
Warren, 2000, p. 18). Thus, Kay and Silberston fact it either falls within a shareholder purpose
reject the idea that directors/managers are of the firm or claims for stakeholder intrinsic
agents of shareholders and argue that man- value in forming business strategy. These
agers are trustees of the corporation. Tricker polarised conceptualisations insist on their
(1996) also notes that in company law, behind own ideologies and paradigms as apparently
the idea of directors having a fiduciary duty is universally valid and unchangeable, and
a philosophy of directors as trustees. They are exclude the possibility of incorporating ideas
principals rather than agents (Dallas, 1988). and assumptions from other or even opposite
Sympathising with the assumption made by positions. While both perspectives of share-
the earlier organic theory in company law, holding and stakeholding presuppose a fixed
which is more prevalent in continental notion of social reality as ideal or optimum,
Europe, Kay and Silberston (1995) suggest that reality itself does not have such a fixed nature
the corporation is not simply created by and property. Nor does it hold some enduring
private contract, but by the company law, and and universal form and principles of gover-
the corporation is a social institution with a nance. Rather, there has been a continu-
corporate personality which has its own assets ous shift of paradigms and mindsets from
and rights and duties, its own will, capacity shareholding to stakeholding in the Anglo-
and responsibilities for its actions. Hence, American setting.
directors as trustees should not serve the The paradigmatic shift from the shareholder
financial interest of shareholders alone, but model to the stakeholder model was mostly
promote the broader interests of the corpora- observable in the late 20th century. The
tion as a whole. For this reason, statutory stakeholder model employed in practice can
change in corporate governance is needed be traced to the 1930s’ Depression, when the
(such as the amendment of company law) to General Electric Company promoted stake-
change the current statutory duties of the holders’ interests such as shareholders, em-
directors from maximising shareholder inter- ployees, customers and the general public
est to pursuing the long-term value of the in order to survive the economic crisis

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 253

(Preston and Sapienza, 1990). This stakehold- theorists often claim. For example, in Rail-
ing notion was followed by Robert E. Wood, track, a privatised railway infrastructure
then CEO of Sears, in the 1950s, who sug- company in the UK in the 1990s, stakeholder
gested that shareholders’ long-run profit interests were explicitly emphasised by its
could be enhanced by satisfying the needs and management and in its annual reports. But in
expectations of other stakeholders (Hummels, the firm’s decision-making, customer services
1998). From the 1960s through to the 1980s, and safety remained secondary to short-term
the stakeholder concept was popular among shareholder value maximisation. Railtrack’s
consumerists, environmentalists and social Chairman publicly admitted that there was a
activists. It was also used by corporate execu- conflict between profit and safety, between
tives to defend against takeovers in the 1980s. shareholder value and stakeholder interest
It was nevertheless in the 1990s that the stake- (for more details, see Wolmar, 2001; Murray,
holding perspective began to be widely used 2001). Evidence also shows that in the UK the
in the corporate governance debate (Blair, real demand of stakeholder groups on caring
1995). The change of mindsets in practice was about corporate reports and performance did
first signified by the Delaware Chancery Court not increase, but actually decreased, between
at the end of the 1980s. In the case of Para- the 1970s and the early 1990s (Letza and Small-
mount Communications v. Time Inc. in 1989, the man, 2001). Large empirical investigations
Chancery allowed Time’s directors to reject also suggest that corporate social performance
Paramount’s takeover offer even though that does not necessarily result in positive corpo-
offer maximised shareholders’ financial value. rate financial performance. In a meta-analysis
That was a very influential case in which the of 51 studies within 25 years from the 1970s to
traditional shareholder model was denied. In the 1990s, Griffin and Mahon (1997) find that
the case of Credit Lyonnais Bank N.V. v. Pathe 33 research results support, while 18 do not
Communications Corp. (1991), the Chancery support, the correlation between corporate
further promoted a stakeholder model on the social performance and corporate financial
basis that directors do not owe duties to any performance. In fact, the massive media cov-
single interest group, but to the corporation as erage largely influenced the socially perceived
a whole and “the community of interests that importance of stakeholders’ interests in the
the corporation represents” (quoted in Sulli- 1990s, due to academic and political concerns
van and Conlon, 1997). Since then, the new about the issues of corporate social irrespon-
perspective has been so influential that up to sibility, short-termism and the negative con-
2000, 25 states of the USA had amended their sequences of the takeover movement in the
General Corporation Laws to incorporate the 1980s (see Berglof, 1997; Gamble and Kelly,
stakeholder concept, while most of the states 2001). Media, politicians and scholars may
had expressly permitted directors to take into represent part of indirect stakeholders and
account the interests of stakeholders in their exert influences at a time, but the true forces
decision-making (Stoney and Winstanley, and powers of direct stakeholders of a firm are
2001; Van der Weide, 1996). In the UK, a still unclear. They are dynamic and fluctuated
similar paradigmatic shift has been experi- because they do not merely follow any pure
enced since the early 1990s (Dine, 2000). It is economic principle and rationality such as effi-
not only perceived by judiciaries, academics ciency, but also are affected by many factors
and politicians, but also by corporate practi- such as politics, ideology, culture, social con-
tioners and managers. A longitudinal study of ventions and modes of thought. Shareholding
British managerial mindsets between 1980 and and stakeholding are socially constructed
2000 (Poole et al., 2001) indicates a sharp rather than pre-given and taken-for-granted.
increase (20 per cent on average) of mana- Social crisis and political power are two major
gerial emphasis on stakeholder interests and a stimulators for social changes (Fligstein, 1990).
drop (10 per cent) of emphasis on shareholder Therefore, it is obvious that as social reality
value in 2000, compared with those in 1990. itself (including corporate practices and soci-
Most of the managers (nearly 80 per cent on etal mindsets) is completely flowing and
average) attach importance to stakeholders in changing, the assumed extremity and thus
2000, compared with only 50 per cent in 1980. endurability and universality of corporate
In the USA, 75 per cent of managers are now governance models are less valid and cred-
familiar with the term stakeholder (Vinten, itable. What is fixed is the artificial conception
2001). and the entrenched position of either share-
Arguably, such a paradigmatic shift does holding or stakeholding, insisted by advocates
not necessarily represent a true dominance of as pre-given and taken-for-granted. The para-
stakeholder forces since the 1980s or a real digmatic shift between the shareholding
managerial consideration of intrinsic moral and stakeholding perspectives also implies
value in business operation as the stakeholder that historically, even theorising or ideal-

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


254 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

construction itself is transformable and unfix- employees, suppliers and distribution system.
able. At one time, we may give priority to The concept of ownership is traditionally per-
shareholder interest and at other times we ceived as the ownership of physical assets
may emphasise stakeholder interests due to such as capital and the means of production.
practical and social reasons or simply, Power and authority and residual claims are
beliefs/faiths. Ideal social conditions are never all based on the source of ownership. Thus,
available in practice, nor capable of being rep- Berle and Means (1932) framed corporate gov-
resented in theory as permanent, as once-and- ernance as the determination of ownership of
for-ever. Only process and change is absolute. the firm and whether the true owners can
For example, while the dominant shareholder exercise their rights adequately and effectively
model subscribes to a single optimal form of (see Zingales, 2000). With this underlying
governance such as internal monitoring or theory of the firm, both the traditional share-
market discipline for efficiency considerations, holder model and the challenging stakeholder
it is hard to find evidence that either the hier- model make their basic assumptions and
archical or market form is totally effective. theorems seemingly justifiable. For example,
Quite on the contrary, both types of gover- with the conventional sense of ownership and
nance structures and mechanisms have failed the firm as a clearly bounded entity, the share-
in practice (e.g. Bishop, 1994; Hart, 1995; holder perspective enjoys its theorising of
Hawley and Williams, 1996; Latham, 1999). As corporate governance upon the notions or
Wolf (1988) points out, we do not have a assumptions of private property, the nexus
perfect choice between market and hierarchy; of contract, self-interest human behaviour, the
we only have a choice between imperfect principal-agent relationship, self-regulation
markets and imperfect hierarchies as well as and the optimum of market governance. The
imperfect combinations of both. Fligstein and stakeholder perspective also legitimises its
Freeland note that there is no universal gover- claims for stakeholder involvement in corpo-
nance structure ever found throughout the rate governance based on the assumption of
world and “there is also little evidence that the firm as a solid and permanent social entity
relations between firms are converging toward and some universal principles, such as moral
markets, hierarchies, networks, or strategic value, social justice, mutual trust and/or own-
alliances as the dominant form of governance” ership rights as naturally produced. All those
(1995, p. 39). Governance practices reflect the justifications implicitly presuppose that the
priorities, preoccupations, political inclina- conventional theory of the firm is as pre-given
tions and local conditions of a particular com- and unchangeable.
munity. Mueller (1995) also argues that Zingales and others (e.g. Zingales, 2000;
governance structure cannot be pre-designed Rajan and Zingales, 2000) suggest that the tra-
as optimal or “appropriate”. It must emerge ditional definition of ownership and the firm
through a dynamic process in which there are could be valuable in a society where intensive
continuous interactions between choices made assets is far more significant for the exploita-
and their complex contexts. It is hard to find a tion of economics of scale and scope, such as
reliable structural solution to the governance that during the industrial revolution. How-
issue, especially when working across cultural ever, business reality is not fixed and “The
boundaries and historical periods. nature of the firm is changing” (Zingales,
2000, p. 1624). Several important features of
corporate change are notable here. Large con-
glomerates have been broken up into several
Recent challenges to the smaller and independent companies. Verti-
understanding of cally integrated manufacturers have changed
corporate governance their direct control over suppliers into looser
collaborations. Financing in capital market is
Very recent studies of the theory of the firm much easier and physical assets are easily
and corporate governance may help in part to replaceable and less unique to business
understand the static limitations of both share- development. In the era of the knowledge
holding and stakeholding models. Current economy and with the increase of global com-
analysis of corporate governance relies very petition, the demand for process innovation
much on an old conception of the firm, which and quality improvement is much higher and
was characterised as asset intensive and verti- therefore the human resource base becomes
cally integrated in the late 19th and early 20th much more vital to a firm’s survival and
centuries (Chandler, 1977, 1990). In company development. The global markets offer many
law the modern corporation is defined as an employment opportunities and make human
independent and permanent entity with clear- capital more independent, enabling individ-
cut boundaries and with direct control over its uals to build their own business. All these

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 255

changes, as Zingales points out, make the corporation over time. Managerial percep-
boundaries of the firms unfixable and con- tions of stakeholder-corporation relationships,
stantly floating. actual power possessed by stakeholders, and
stakeholding legitimacy and urgency are
The change nature of the firm forces us to
totally dynamic (Mitchell et al., 1997). In dif-
abandon the illusion that firms’ boundaries are
ferent organisational life cycle stages, certain
clear cut and remain unchanged when we
stakeholders may be perceived to be more
change the capital structure or the governance
important than others to satisfy critical or-
structure. (Zingales, 2000, p. 1644)
ganisational needs (Jawahar and Mclaughlin,
If the firm is not perceived and conceived as a 2001). Friedman and Miles (2002) suggest that
solid and enduring entity and a pre-given and organisation–stakeholder relations always
fixed object of study, the consequence would change, not necessarily materially, but also
be that the current analysis of corporate gov- ideologically, and their relations may change
ernance based on the static conception of the in any direction. The triggers of such a
firm and its ownership structure is less con- change could be from institutional support
vincing and reliable. Indeed, we need to rede- changes, contingent factors emerging, sets of
fine the concept of ownership to include not ideas held and changed by stakeholders
only physical assets, but also human capital and organisations, and material interests
and social capital. In addition to traditional changed from stakeholders and organisa-
physical assets, a range of resources are be- tions. They argue that “the weakness of stake-
coming increasingly important to today’s holder theory lies in the underspecification of
business, such as creative knowledge, ideas the organisation/stakeholder relation itself”
and unique skills, professional control, social (Friedman and Miles, 2002, p. 15).
relationships and corporate reputation. Finan-
cial capital, human capital and social capital
are all crucial (but always dynamic and Some concluding remarks
context-dependent) for a corporation. The tra-
ditional analysis of corporate governance that Current mainstream schools of corporate gov-
relies on a fixed boundary of the corporation ernance rest their ideas and assumptions on a
(such as the assumptions of a physical entity, theory of the firm and associated ideologies
a natural entity or a social entity as previously which were created and constructed by com-
mentioned) is unrealistic. The split of share- pany law theory and classical economics in
holding and stakeholding as universally the 18th and 19th centuries. Under this con-
applicable is not reliable in matching to reality. ventional wisdom, physical assets are per-
While the inadequacy of the shareholder ceived to be more important than human
and stakeholder models is easily found from resources. Corporate power and authority is
the above analysis, the limits of the stake- legitimately built on the exclusive possession
holder perspective can be further displayed of financial capital, raw materials and the
here. In addition to the earlier critiques of the means of production. Free market exchange
stakeholder model, such as the stakeholder and vertically integrated bureaucracy are jus-
identity problem (Donaldson, 1989), no clear tified as ideal and universal principles for effi-
yardstick for judging corporate performance ciency reasons. The corporation is regarded as
(Bishop, 1994) and no clear guidance for a solid and enduring entity or the aggregation
stakeholding application to managerial prac- of individual entities, with a clear division
tice (Blair, 1995), more fundamental issues between inside and outside, the corporation
remain within the stakeholder paradigm. For and its environment, and with a fixable iden-
example, Friedman and Miles (2002), among tity of shareholders and stakeholders. These
others, note that the stakeholder theory pre- ideal-constructions, as argued above, might
sumes a clear-cut, stable and homogeneous have been acceptable in earlier times and
boundary among stakeholding groups, be- under certain conditions and contexts. If we
tween stakeholder legitimacy and illegiti- accept that our society and environments are
macy, and in managerial perception of continually fluxing with an uncertain future,
stakeholder–corporation relationships. How- we must critically scrutinise whether or not
ever, in practice stakeholder interests are so the conventional wisdom and assumptions are
diverse and conflicting that not only may it still compatible with current situations of
be incompatible between different stake- corporate practice and societal development
holder groups, but also within a single group. (including social expectations). The split
For example, individual employees or sup- between shareholding and stakeholding in
pliers or even shareholders always have dif- current theorising of corporate governance is
ferent as well as changeable attitudes toward, less valuable, since both material conditions
interests in and relationships with a particular and ideological perceptions have changed sig-

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


256 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

nificantly in recent times making the polarisa- ically rational manner, or that the corporate
tion of shareholding and stakeholding now governance process will, over time, tend toward
somewhat redundant. greater economic efficiency. (Grundfest, 1990,
In order to make their theories universally quoted in Hawley and Williams, 1996, part
justifiable, both the shareholding and stake- II)
holding perspectives attempt to generalise
and simplify their theories, even though cor- Indeed, corporate governance is not science,
porate governance practice is very dynamic but an art,4 as William Allen (2001), the former
and complex. For example, the universal Chancellor of Delaware Chancery Court in the
principal-agent relationship, self-interested US, suggests. For Allen, good corporate gov-
human behaviour, the inherent individual ernance may have good effects on long-term
property rights and the uninterruptible corporate financial performance. But the defi-
self-regulation mechanism underpinning the nition of good standards of governance cannot
shareholder model and the pre-given moral be measured by scientific precision. “Corpo-
value, trusteeship and other social principles rate governance functions only through
and the single and simple identity of stake- human action, which itself is affected by a high
holder groups underpinning the stakeholder number of changing, interacting variables”
model. All those assumptions and presuppo- (Allen, 2001, p. 2). Any single model and struc-
sitions tend to abstract and fix reality and ture of corporate governance cannot work
ignore or neglect the flux and heterogeneity of well for all firms at all times. Corporate gov-
corporate governance in practice. In so doing, ernance needs to be flexible, adaptable and
however, the advocates seem rather puzzled innovative. Therefore, for theoretical models
about the lack of evidence in support of their to be workable and explicable in practice, we
theoretical models. need to develop approaches and models
The most popular approach in corporate which better explain the idiosyncratic work-
governance research is economic analysis. ings of local corporate governance, rather than
This is manifested in both the shareholder try to force-fit reality into the established
model and stakeholder model. Underpinning abstracted templates. We need a new mode of
both models is the continuous search for the thinking in the analysis of corporate gover-
optimal governance structure which purport- nance, which goes beyond the conventional
edly lies in the most efficient form. Further, the static approaches. A new mode of thinking
models claim that there exists a rational that would explain some important phenom-
process of selecting more efficient governance ena in corporate governance, contrary to
structures and mechanisms either through the the conventional theoretical assumptions. For
“invisible” hand of the market or the “visible” example:
hand of managers or stakeholders (see Whereas the shareholder perspective
Solomon and Higgins, 1996; Roy, 1997). regards the corporation as the extension of
Although the shareholder and stakeholder individual private property and a nexus of
perspectives are different, common to both free exchange, corporate legal relationships
models are the notions of profit maximisation, show that the corporation is actually an inde-
an increasing market value and economic pendent organisation with its own rights and
rationality and efficiency. The economic ratio- liabilities separate from its members/share-
nale employed in the governance debate holders. The traditional rationale of private
ignores the basic fact that corporate gover- ownership has been transformed. The process
nance is a social process, which cannot be of incorporation (for both public and private
isolated from social and other non-economic companies) can no longer be viewed as a
conditions and factors such as power, legisla- purely private ownership matter in the
tion, social relationships and institutional traditional sense. Shareholders do not have
contexts (Roy, 1997). Theories grounded on individual free rights and claims on the
economic rationality tend to neglect or corporation. They bear only very limited lia-
marginalise the importance of irrationality, bility and risk. The entire liability and risk of
emotion, value, belief and ideology, which the corporation are shared by many stake-
often play a significant role in the process of holders including shareholders, bondholders,
decision-making and governance (see, for creditors, employees, suppliers, the govern-
example, Welcomer et al., 2000; Jawahar and ment and the public at large. In this sense, all
Mclaughlin, 2001). Consequently, the limita- companies have some public character. The
tions of the economic approach are obvious, as nature of incorporation cannot be explained
Grundfest posits: by the current shareholder perspective
based on a purely economic and financial
There is no reason to believe that corporate analysis that totally ignores corporate legal
agency problems can be resolved in an econom- relationships.

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 257

Whilst the stakeholder perspective might governance or market governance as an


justify its rationale based on the 19th century’s optimal governance mechanism, in practice
conception of social entity or natural entity, governing forms may vary. Hollingsworth
it neglects to acknowledge that companies and Lindberg (1985), for example, identify
are not the same as other social institutions. four distinctive forms of governance, includ-
As business operators, companies are duty- ing hierarchies, market, the clan or community
bound with economic and profit-making func- and associations. Whilst economists only
tions for society’s survival and development. recognise the former two forms, the latter two
Furthermore, there has long been an argument forms may offer more value in corporate gov-
in corporation law theory about whether or ernance in non-Anglo cultures, such as in
not the corporation, as a legal person, is a real Asian countries (Tricker, 1990; Porta et al.,
person or an artificial person (Mayson et al., 1997). Even within the Anglo-American envi-
1994). The current stakeholder model regards ronment, network forms of governance based
the corporation as a discrete social entity and on mutual trust, friendships, reputation,
is compatible with the “real personality” shared ideology and reciprocity have also
assertion. This logically supposes that the cor- attracted attention in business practices since
poration is a real person, independent of its the 1980s (Powell, 1990). Thus, Turnbull (1997)
members, and draws the image of an empty suggests that economists such as Coase (1937)
entity where all stakeholders are external to and Williamson (1975, 1985) ask the wrong
and influential on the corporation. This simply question, why are economic transactions
ignores the actual process of incorporation, organised through hierarchy rather than
where the corporation is a constituent of its through markets? They “should have asked
members. Without its members, no corpora- when are economic transaction organised by
tion can exist in law (throughout the world, a any combination of the four different ways (as
corporation must have at least one member). mentioned above) in which transactions can
In company law, the corporation is seen as a be governed” (Turnbull, 1997b, p. 186, empha-
complex rather than a simple phenomenon sis added).
where it is seen as both the association of its Both shareholder and stakeholder perspec-
members and a legal person separate from tives claim superiority of their models respec-
its members. A simple stakeholding model tively; however, in reality we have seen a
ignores this complexity. dynamic shift with both models becoming
Both the shareholding and stakeholding increasingly mutually attractive all over the
perspectives present the corporation in terms world in the last two decades. This paradig-
of “entity” (either individual entity or social matic shift has been a major theme in this
entity). However, the corporation as a social paper. For example, evidence shows that even
and legal product is not so entitative and solid Germany and Japan, which traditionally pre-
in practice over time. For example, Zingales ferred a stakeholder-committed model, have
(2000) realises that whereas in physical-asset- recently changed towards a more shareholder-
intensive firms their boundaries might be stable valued and market-based model due to the
and corporate governance could rely on “share- pressure of globalisation and world-wide
holder ownership” (note that this assumption is competition (Stoney and Winstanley, 2001,
also problematic in company law theory as p. 618; Schilling, 2001). All this implies that
mentioned above), in human-capital-intensive the so-called superiority and priority of any
firms their boundaries become diffused and model is not permanent and universal, but
governance under the traditional approach rather temporary and contextual. The static
becomes more problematic. Indeed, neo- conceptualisation of shareholding and stake-
classical economics regards the firm as a legal holding is less compatible with the fluidity
fiction, a nexus of contracts. But in so doing and diversity of practical reality.
economists do not question the notion of indi- The current dichotomised and static theo-
vidualistic entity behind their assumptions retical approach used in corporate governance
such as a fixed shareholder ownership, perma- research, which presupposes two extreme and
nent interest and group homogeneity. They talk opposite ideal models, cannot fully explain the
about agency problem in corporate governance, complexity and heterogeneity of corporate
but neglect the principle problem, such as reality. Instead, we call for a more inventive
shareholders being reluctant, less interested, and flexible approach to the understanding of
legally restrained or mutually conflicting in corporate governance practice and the search
monitoring agents’ performance. It is those for effective and efficient governance. What
dynamic practices that challenge the assumed would be involved with such an approach?
boundary and fixed entity of a corporation. It is a processual, rather than a static
While both shareholder and stakeholder approach. This approach explains the tempo-
models suggest either a hierarchical form of rary, transient and emergent patterns of cor-

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


258 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

porate governance on a historical and con- a useful review, see Turnbull, 1997b), which
textual interface in any society. Corporate may offer insightful views from different
governance is completely changeable and angles and quite distinct from the mainstream
transformable and there is no permanent or analysis.
universal principle which covers all societies, It is a dynamic and flexible approach which
cultures and business situations. It acknowl- continually weighs and adjusts the method of
edges that corporate governance models governing in practice. It cannot design and
around the world have developed from their specify any ideal model in advance and cannot
own unique cultural, historical and social cir- be fixed as a “once-and-for-ever” solution. It is
cumstances. It also acknowledges that each a principle of collibration, that is, the design
model will continue to evolve. For exam- and management of institutions through
ple, actors in the Anglo-American and the explicitly juxtaposing rival viewpoints in a
German–Japanese governance environments constant process of dynamic tension with no
will learn from each other, each taking aspects pre-set equilibrium (Hood and Jones, 1996).
of the other’s model, in order to compete more It is an enlightening approach that attempts
effectively in a globalised market in an era to transcend our habitual, inertial, static and
where information is increasingly becoming stagnant ways of thinking about corporate
more freely available. Learning is a continuous governance. As Morgan (1997) notes, people
process; it never stops and has no end. are easily trapped by favoured ways of think-
It is a balanced approach which never ing that serve specific sets of interests and con-
assumes that any extreme model, such as pure sequently our conventional modes of thought
shareholding or pure stakeholding, can work may in turn bind and control our views. We
perfectly in practice. A firm is neither a purely need to think outside of the current polarised
private nor a purely public affair. A firm does models framework. We need to understand
not just consistent of physical assets, but also deeply what corporate reality is, how and why
of human beings, and shareholders and other we have constructed it both collectively in
stakeholders. In today’s civilised society, history and in different contexts, and what
human beings should not be treated as assets, trends and patterns could be most likely to
machines or any form of instrument (e.g. emerge in the uncertain future. Certainly, we
Handy, 1993). Also, governance forms should need more radical research in this area.
not be polarised into either “hierarchy” or
“market”. Other forms of governance, such as
networks, may have much value.
It is a relational approach which views the Notes
reality as fundamentally interconnected and
1. There are two disputes in the literature on
interdependent and mutually influential. In whether or not the German and Japanese gover-
order to learn business relationships must nance style is a stakeholding model and whether
think about corporate interrelationships and or not their governance model is more advanta-
social interactions. Thus, shareholder interest geous in international competition. It seems that
is not independent of stakeholder interests many scholars tend to recognise that there are
and vice verse. A firm is not independent of two different governance styles of capitalism,
its constituents. Any externalised views that one is the Anglo-American style and the other is
separate and isolate the corporation and its the continental European-Asian style. While the
stakeholders, or shareholders and stake- former tends to adopt a shareholder interest
holder, indeed over-simplify and make the maximisation and market governance, the latter
is less shareholder-focused and more stake-
social reality artificial. Dichotomy approaches holder-oriented and does not rely primarily on
or binary values are less applicable to the stock market control over the large corporations.
complex real world. A “fuzzy logic” is Some scholars also argue that whilst the
more valuable in understanding corporate Anglo-American style dominates the world, the
relationships. German–Japanese model appeared to be more
It is a pluralist approach which suggests efficient, more equitable and more successful in
that corporate governance is not only condi- the 1980s (for more details, see Albert, 1993;
tioned to the economic logic such as economic Charkham, 1994; Kay and Silberston, 1995; Hirst,
rationality and efficiency, but also shaped and 1998; Weimer and Pape, 1999).
influenced by politics, ideologies, philoso- 2. A Joint-Stock Companies Act was passed by
Parliament in 1844 and an Act for limiting the
phies, legal systems, social conventions, cul- liability of a corporation’s members passed in
tures, modes of thought, methodologies, etc. A 1855. Both legislations laid down the foundation
purely economic and financial analysis of cor- of modern corporations. For more details, see
porate governance is too narrow. We have Tricker (2000).
already seen some research in this field based 3. In corporate law theory, members of a corpora-
on politics, culture, power and cybernetics (for tion refer to its shareholders. But in the 19th

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 259

century there was a German view of the corpo- Campbell, A. (1997) Stakeholders, the Case in
ration, which regarded the employees, rather Favour, Long Range Planning, 30, 446–449.
than the shareholders, as the members of a cor- Carroll, A. B. (1991) The Pyramid of Corporate
poration (Pejovich, 1990). Social Responsibility: Toward the Moral Man-
4. However, some scholars suggest the opposite, agement of Organisational Stakeholders, Business
that corporate governance is a science, not an art. Horizons, 34, 39–48.
Turnbull (2002) argues that corporate gover- Carroll, A. B. (1996) Business and Society: Ethics and
nance could be grounded in the science of infor- Stakeholder Management, 3rd edn. Cincinnati:
mation and control (i.e. cybernetics) and thus a South-Western.
compound board has a cybernetic advantage Centre for Tomorrow’s Corporation (CTC) (1998)
over the unitary board. We do accept that infor- The Inclusive Approach and Business Success: the
mation is an important issue in corporate gover- Research Evidence. London: CTC.
nance; however, we doubt the assumption Chandler, A. D. (1977) The Visible Hand: The Man-
underpinning the science of governance that agerial Revolution in American Business. Cam-
information is the main issue of governance and bridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University
information itself is a natural phenomenon. In Press.
fact, the information problem is far beyond an Chandler, A. D. (1990) Managerial hierarchies. In D.
issue of human ability of dealing with informa- S. Pugh (ed.) Organisation Theory: Selected Read-
tion overload or natural bias and errors. There ings. London: Penguin Books, 89–105.
are a variety of social, cultural, legal, political Charkham, J. (1994) Keeping Good Corporation: A
and psychological factors influencing and dis- Study of Corporate Governance in Five Countries.
torting the process of information. Furthermore, Oxford: Clarendon.
human beings are unlike computers that can be Coase, R. H. (1937) The Nature of the Firm, Eco-
precisely and relatively easily controlled. nomica, 4, 386–405.
Dahl, R. A. (1985) A Preface to Economic Democracy.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Dallas, L. L. (1988) Two Models of Corporate Gov-
References ernance: Beyond Berle and Means, Journal of Law
Reform, 22, 19–116.
Albert, M. (1993) Capitalism against Capitalism. Deakin, S. and Slinger, G. (1997) Hostile Takeovers,
London: Whurr. Corporate Law, and the Theory of the Firm,
Alchian, A. A. and Demsetz, H. (1972) Production, Journal of Law and Society, 24, 124–151.
Information Costs, and Economic Organisation, Dine, J. (2000) The Governance of Corporate Groups.
American Economic Review, 62, 777–795. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Alchian, A. A. and Kessel, R. A. (1962) Competition, Donaldson, T. (1989) The Ethics of International Busi-
monopoly and the pursuit of pecuniary gain. In ness. New York: Oxford University Press.
Aspects of Labour Economics. Princeton: National Donaldson, T. and Davis, J. H. (1994) Boards and
Bureau of Economic Research. Corporation Performance – Research Challenges
Allen, W. T. (1992) Our Schizophrenic Conception the Conventional Wisdom, Corporate Governance,
of the Business Corporation, Cardozo Law Review, 2, 151–160.
14, 261–281. Donaldson, T. and Preston, L. E. (1995) The Stake-
Allen, W. T. (1995) The Evolution of Corporate holder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evi-
Boards, Corporate Board, July–August, 1–4. dence and Implications, Academy of Management
Allen, W. T. (2001) The Mysterious Art of Corporate Review, 20, 65–91.
Governance, Corporate Board, 22, 130, 1–5. Eisenhardt, K. M. (1985) Control: Organisational
Arthur, E. E. (1987) The Ethics of Corporate Gover- and Economic Approaches, Management Science,
nance, Journal of Business Ethics, 6, 59–70. 31, 134–149.
Barker, E. (1958) Introduction. In O. Gierke Natural Eisenhardt, K. M. (1989) Agency Theory: An Assess-
Law and the Theory of Society: 1500 to 1800, trans. ment and Review, Academy of Management Review,
E. Barker. Cambridge: Cambridge University 14, 57–74.
Press. Etzioni, A. (1975) A Comparative Analysis of Complex
Berglof, E. (1997) Reforming Corporate Gover- Organisations. New York: Free Press.
nance: Redirecting the European Agenda, Eco- Fama, E (1980) Agency Problems and the Theory
nomic Policy, 12, 91–123. of the Firm, Journal of Political Economy, 88,
Berle, A. A. and Means, G. C. (1932) The Modern 288–309.
Corporation and Private Property. New York: The Fligstein, N. (1990) The Transformation of Corporate
Macmillan Corporation. Control. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bishop, M. (1994) Corporate Governance, The Econ- Fligstein, N. and Freeland, R. (1995) Theoretical and
omist, 29, January, 3–18 (in survey section). Comparative Perspectives on Corporate Organi-
Blair, M. M. (1995) Ownership and Control: Rethink- sation, Annual Review of Sociology, 21, 21–43.
ing Corporate Governance for the Twenty-first Freeman, R. E. (1984) Strategic Management: A Stake-
Century. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. holder Approach. Boston: Pitman.
Boswell, J. (1990) Community and the Economy: The Friedman, A. and Miles, S. (2002) Developing Stake-
Theory of Public Co-operation. London: Routledge. holder Theory, Journal of Management Studies, 39,
Cadbury Committee (1992) Report of the Committee 1–21.
on the Financial Aspects of Corporate Governance. Friedman, M. (1962) Capitalism and Freedom.
London: Gee. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


260 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

Friedman, M. (1970) The Social Responsibility of tional Life Cycle Approach, Academy of Manage-
Business is to Increase its Profits, New York Times ment Review, 26, 397–415.
Magazine, 13 September, 32–33, 122, 124, 126. Jensen, M. C. (2001) Value Maximisation,
Gamble, A. and Kelly, G. (2001) Shareholder Value Stakeholder Theory, and the Corporate Objective
and the Stakeholder Debate in the UK, Corporate Function, European Financial Management, 7,
Governance, 9, 110–117. 297–317.
Greenbury Committee (1995) Directors’ Remunera- Jensen, M. C. and Meckling, W. H. (1976) Theory of
tion: Report of A Study Group. London: Gee. the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs,
Griffin, J. and Mahon, J. F. (1997) The Corporate and Ownership Structure, Journal of Financial Eco-
Social Performance and Corporate Financial nomics, 3, 305–360.
Performance Debate, Business and Society, 36, Johnson, J., Daily, C. and Ellstrand, A. (1996) Boards
5–32. of Directors: A Review and Research Agenda,
Grundfest, J. A. (1990) Subordination of American Journal of Management, 22, 409–439.
Capital, Journal of Financial Economist, 27, 89–114. Kakabadse, A. and Kakabadse, N. (2001) The Geopol-
Hall, K. L. (1989) The Magic Mirror: Law in American itics of Governance. Hampshire: Palgrave.
History. New York: Oxford University Press. Kay, J. and Silberston, A. (1995) Corporate Gover-
Hampel Committee (1998) Committee on Corporate nance, National Institute Economic Review, 84,
Governance: Final Report. London: Gee. August, 84–97.
Handy, C. (1993) What is a Corporation for? Corpo- Keasey, K., Thompson, S. and Wright, M. (1997)
rate Governance, 1, 14–16. Introduction: The corporate governance problem
Handy, C. (1997) The Hungry Spirit. London: – Competing diagnoses and solutions. In K.
Hutchinson. Keasey, S. Thompson and M. Wright (eds) Corpo-
Hart, O. (1995) Corporate Governance: Some rate Governance: Economic and Financial Issues.
Theory and Implications, The Economic Journal, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 10–15.
105, 678–689. Kelly, G. and Parkinson, J. (1998) The Conceptual
Hawley, J. P. and Williams, A. T. (1996) Corporate Foundations of the Corporation: A Pluralist
governance in the United States: The rise of fidu- Approach, Corporation Financial and Insolvency
ciary capitalism – A review of the literature. The Law Review, 2, 174–197.
first prize of Lens 1996 Corporate Governance Kelly, G., Kelly, D. and Gamble, A. (1997) Stake-
Paper Competition (available on-line at: http:// holder capitalism. In G. Kelly, D. Kelly and A.
www.lens-library.com/info/competition. Gamble (eds) Stakeholder Capitalism. London:
html). Macmillan.
Hayek, F. A. (1969) The Corporation in a democra- Keynes, J. M. (1936) The General Theory of Employ-
tic society: In whose interest ought it and will it ment, Interest and Money. London: Macmillan.
be run? In H. I. Ansoff (ed.) Business Strategy. Latham, M. (1999) The Corporate Monitoring Firm,
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 124–146. Corporate Governance, 7, 12–20.
Hayes, R. H. and Abernathy, W. J. (1980) Managing Letza, S. and Smallman, C. (2001) In Pure Water
Our Way to Economic Decline, Harvard Business There is a Pleasure Begrudged by None: On
Review, 58, 67–77. Ownership, Accountability and Control in a Pri-
Higgs, D. (2003) Review of the role and effec- vatised Utility, Critical Perspectives on Accounting,
tiveness of non-executive directors (http:// 12, 65–85.
www.dti.gov.uk/cld/non_exec_review/pdfs/ Macfarlane, A. (1978) The Origins of English Individu-
higgsreport.pdf). alism: The Family, Property and Social Transition.
Hill, C. W. L. and Jones, T. M. (1992) Stakeholder- Oxford: Blackwell.
Agency Theory, The Journal of Management Manne, H. G. (1965) Mergers and the Market for
Studies, 19, 131–154. Corporate Control, Journal of Political Economy, 75,
Hirst, P. (1994) Associative Democracy: New Forms of 110–126.
Economic and Social Governance. London: Polity Marris, R. (1964) The Economic Theory of “Manager-
Press. ial” Capitalism. London: Macmillan.
Hirst, P. (1998) Ownership and Democracy, The Mayson, S. W., French, D. and Ryan, C. L. (1994)
Political Quarterly, 6, 354–364. Corporation Law. London: Blackstone Press.
Hollingsworth, J. R. and Lindberg, L. N. (1985) The Michell, R. K., Agle, B. R. and Wood, D. J. (1997)
governance of the American economy: The role Toward a Theory of Stakeholder Identification
of markets, clans, hierarchies, and associative and Salience: Defining the Principle of How and
behaviour. In W. Streeck and P. C. Schmitter (eds) What Really Counts, Academy of Management
Private Interest Government: Beyond Market and Review, 22, 853–886.
Stake. London: Sage. Millon, D. (1990) Theories of the Corporation, Duke
Hood, C. and Jones, D. (1996) Accident and Design: Law Journal, 201–262.
Contemporary Debates in Risk Management. Moreland, P. W. (1995) Alternative Disciplinary
London: UCL Press. Mechanisms in Different Corporate Systems,
Hummels, H. (1998) Organising Ethics: A Stake- Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organisation, 26,
holder Debate, Journal of Business Ethics, 17, 17–34.
1403–1419. Morgan, G. (1997) Images of Organisation, 2nd edn.
Hutton, W. (1995) The State We’re In. London: California: Sage.
Jonathan Cape. Mueller, F. (1995) Organisational Governance and
Jawahar, I. M. and Mclaughlin, G. L. (2001) Toward Employee Cooperation: Can We Learn from Eco-
a Descriptive Stakeholder Theory: An Organisa- nomics? Human Relations, 48, 1217–1235.

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


SHAREHOLDING VERSUS STAKEHOLDING 261

Murray, A. (2001) Off the Rails. London: Verso. Sternberg, E. (2000) The Defects of Stakeholder
Nichols, T. (1969) Ownership, Control, and Ideology. Theory, Corporate Governance, 5, 3–10.
London: Allen and Unwin. Stiglitz, J. E. (2000) The Contributions of the
O’Sullivan, M. A. (2000) Contests for Corporate Economics of Information to Twentieth Century
Control. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Economics, The Quarterly Journal of Economics,
Parkinson, J. (1995) The role of “exit” and “voice” November, 1441–1478.
in corporate governance. In S. Sheikh and W. Stoney, C. and Winstanley, D. (2001) Stakeholding:
Rees (eds) Corporate Governance and Corporate Confusion or Utopia? Mapping the Conceptual
Control. London: Cavendish. Terrain, Journal of Management Studies, 38, 603–
Pejovich, S. (1990) The Economics of Property Rights: 626.
Towards a Theory of Comparative Systems. Dor- Sullivan, D. P. and Conlon, D. E. (1997) Crisis and
drecht: Kluwer. Transition in Corporate Governance Paradigms:
Plender, J. (1997) A Stakeholder in the Future: the Role of the Chancery Court of Delaware, Law
the Stakeholding Solution. London: Nicholas and Society Review, 31, 713–763.
Brearley. Sykes, A. (1994) Proposals for Internationally Com-
Poole, M., Mansfield, R. and Mendes, P. (2001) Two petitive Corporate Governance in Britain and
Decades of Management. London: Institute of America, Corporate Governance, 2, 187–195.
Management. Tricker, R. I. (1990) The Corporate Concept:
Porta, R. L., Lopez-de-Silanes, F., Shleifer, A. and Redesigning a Successful System, Human Systems
Vishny, R. W. (1997) Trust in large organizations, Management, 9, 65–76.
National Bureau of Economics Research working Tricker, R. I. (1996) Pocket Director. London: The
paper no. 5864, Cambridge, MA. Economist Books.
Pound, J. (1992) Beyond Takeovers: Politics Comes Tricker, R. I. (2000) The evolution of the corporation.
to Corporate Control, Harvard Business Review, In R. I. Tricker (ed.) Corporate Governance. Alder-
March–April, 83–93. shot: Ashgate/Dartmouth, 20–28.
Pound, J. (1993) The Rise of the Political Model of Turnbull Committee (1999) Internal Control:
Corporate Governance and Corporate Control, Guidance for Directors on the Combined Code.
New York University Law Review, 68, November, London: The Institute of Chartered Accountants
1003–1071. in England and Wales.
Powell, W. W. (1990) Neither Market nor Hierarchy: Turnbull, S. (1994) Stakeholder Democracy:
Network Forms of Organisation, Research in Redesigning the Governance of Firms and
Organisational Behaviour, 12, 295–336. Bureaucracies, Journal of Socio-Economics, 23,
Prabhaker, S. (1998) Governance and Stakeholding, 321–361.
New Economy, 5, 119–122. Turnbull, S. (1997a) Stakeholder Governance: A
Preston, L. E. and Sapienza, H. J. (1990) Stakeholder Cybernetic and Property Rights Analysis, Corpo-
Management and Corporate Performance, The rate Governance, 5, 11–23.
Journal of Behavioural Economics, 19, 361–375. Turnbull, S. (1997b) Corporate Governance: Its
Rajan, R. G. and Zingales, L. (1999) The firm as a Scope, Concerns and Theories, Corporate Gover-
dedicated hierarchy: A theory of the origins and nance, 5, 180–205.
growth of firms. Working paper, University of Turnbull, S. (1998) Should Ownership Last Forever?
Chicago Graduate School of Business. Journal of Socio-Economics, 27, 341–364.
Roy, W. G. (1997) Socialising Capital. Princeton: Turnbull, S. (2002) The Science of Corporate
Princeton University Press. Governance, Corporate Governance, 10, 261–
Sacks, J. (1997) The Politics of Hope. London: 277.
Jonathan Cape. Van der Weide, M. E. (1996) Delaware’s New
Schilling, F. (2001) Corporate Governance in Mandate in Class Action Settlements: Expand-
Germany: The Move to Shareholder Value, Cor- ing the Scope and Intensity of Settlement Review,
porate Governance 9, 148–151. Delaware Journal of Corporate Law, 20, 496–534.
Shiller, R. J. (1989) Do stock prices move too much Vinten, G. (2001) Shareholder versus Stakeholder –
to be justified by subsequent changes in divi- Is There a Governance Dilemma? Corporate Gov-
dends? In R. J. Shiller (ed.) Market Volatility. Cam- ernance, 9, 36–47.
bridge: The MIT Press. Warren, R. C. (2000) Corporate Governance and
Shleifer, A. and Vishny, R. W. (1997) A Survey of Accountability. Bromborough: Liverpool Acade-
Corporate Governance, The Journal of Finance, LII, mic Press.
727–783. Weimer, J. and Pape, J. C. (1999) A Taxonomy of
Slinger, G. (1998) Spanning the gap: The theoretical Systems of Corporate Governance, Corporate Gov-
principles that connect stakeholder policies to ernance, 7, 152–166.
business performance. Working paper 111, ESRC Welcomer, S. A., Gioia, D. A. and Kilduff, M. (2000)
Centre for Business Research. Resisting the Discourse of Modernity: Rationality
Smith, A. (1937) The Wealth of Nations. New York: versus Emotion in Hazardous Waste Siting,
Random House. Human Relations, 53, 1175–1205.
Solomon, R. C. and Higgins, K. M. (1996) A Short Williamson, O. E. (1975) Markets and Hierarchies:
History of Philosophy. New York: Oxford Univer- Analysis and Antitrust Implications. New York:
sity Press. Free Press.
Sternberg, E. (1998) Corporate Governance: Account- Williamson, O. E. (1985) The Economic Institutions of
ability in the Marketplace. London: The Institute of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting.
Economic Affairs. New York: Free Press.

© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004 Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004


262 CORPORATE GOVERNANCE

Wolf, C. (1988) Markets and Governments. Cam- search interests include corporate governance,
bridge: The MIT Press. risk and corporate reporting.
Wolmar, C. (2001) Broken Rails, 2nd edn. London: Xiuping Sun is lecturer in Strategy at Leeds
Aurum. Business School, Leeds Metropolitan Univer-
Zingales, L. (1998) Corporate governance. In P.
sity. His PhD is from Leeds Metropolitan
Newman (ed.) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Eco-
nomics and the Law. London: Stockton Press, University, England. His research interests
36–49. include corporate governance, regulation and
Zingales, L. (2000) In Search of New Foundations, philosophy.
The Journal of Finance, LV, 1623–1653. James Kirkbride is Dean of the Faculty of
Business and Law at Liverpool John Moores
University and Professor of International Busi-
Steve Letza is Professor of Corporate Gover- ness Law. His PhD is from Leeds Metropolitan
nance and Director of Law at Leeds Metro- University, England. His research interests
politan University, England. His PhD is from include corporate law and governance, regu-
the University of Bradford, England. His re- lation and competition controls.

“[Having a non-executive chair is] about having somebody to take a lot of responsibility
for the governance of the company and information flow and discussion flow. It’s a deci-
sion based on improved governance.” Michael Eisner, In “Corporate Governance Alliance
Digest”, March 2004, www.corporategovernancealliance.com

Volume 12 Number 3 July 2004 © Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004


View publication stats

You might also like