Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

DO SUNK COSTS MATTER?

R. PRESTON MCAFEE, HUGO M. MIALON and SUE H. MIALON*

That sunk costs are not relevant to rational decision making is often presented as
one of the basic principles of economics. When people are influenced by sunk costs in
their decision making, they are said to be committing the ‘‘sunk cost fallacy.’’
Contrary to conventional wisdom, we argue that in a broad range of situations, it
is rational for people to condition behavior on sunk costs because of informational
content, reputational concerns, or financial and time constraints. Once all the
elements of the decision-making environment are taken into account, reacting to
sunk costs can often be understood as rational behavior. (JEL D0, D01, D8,
D81, D83, D9, D90)

‘‘Let Bygones Be Bygones.’’ return on additional investment does not seem


—Khieu Samphan, former head of state of the worthwhile. For example, some people remain
Khmer Rouge government, asking Cambodians in failing relationships because they ‘‘have al-
to forget the more than one million people who
died under his government’s rule. ready invested too much to leave.’’ Others buy
expensive gym memberships to commit them-
selves to exercising. Still others are swayed by
arguments that a war must continue because
I. INTRODUCTION lives will have been sacrificed in vain unless
victory is achieved.
Sunk costs are costs that have already been
These types of behavior do not seem to
incurred and cannot be recovered. Sunk costs
accord with rational choice theory and are
do not change regardless of which action is
often classified as behavioral errors. People
presently chosen. Therefore, an individual
who commit them are said to be engaging in
should ignore sunk costs to make a rational
the ‘‘sunk cost fallacy.’’ Students are repeat-
choice. Introductory textbooks in economics
edly taught in economic classes that sunk costs
present this as a basic principle of rational
are irrelevant to decision making so that they
decision making (Frank and Bernanke 2006,
may ultimately learn to make better decisions,
10; Mankiw 2004, 297).
invoking the theory as a normative prescrip-
Nonetheless, people are apparently often
tion. Conditioning on the level of sunk costs
influenced by sunk costs in their decision mak-
is also taken as evidence that people do not
ing. Once individuals have made a large sunk
always make rational choices (Thaler 1991),
investment, they have a tendency to invest
suggesting that the explanatory power of
more in an attempt to prevent their previous
rational choice theory is limited.
investment from being wasted. The greater
In this article, we argue that in a broad
the size of their sunk investment, the more
range of environments, reacting to sunk costs
they tend to invest further, even when the
is actually rational. Agents may rationally
react to sunk costs because of informational
*We are grateful to two anonymous referees for help- content, reputational concerns, or financial
ful comments. and time constraints.
McAfee: Humanities and Social Sciences, California Insti-
tute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125. Phone 626-
395-3476, Fax 626-793-4681, E-mail preston@mcafee.cc
H. M. Mialon: Department of Economics, Emory Univer-
sity, Atlanta, GA 30322-2240. Phone 404-408-8333,
Fax 404-727-4639, E-mail hmialon@emory.edu ABBREVIATION
S. H. Mialon: Department of Economics, Emory University,
Atlanta, GA 30322-2240. Phone 404-712-8169, Fax 404- NPV: Net Present Value
727-4639, E-mail smialon@emory.edu

323
Economic Inquiry doi:10.1111/j.1465-7295.2008.00184.x
(ISSN 0095-2583) Online Early publication February 6, 2009
Vol. 48, No. 2, April 2010, 323–336 © 2009 Western Economic Association International
324 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

A. Informational Content important implications. First, the sunk cost


fallacy is not necessarily evidence that people
Consider a project that may take an
do not make rational choices. Second, in certain
unknown expenditure to complete. The failure
situations, ignoring sunk costs may not be ra-
to complete the project with a given amount of
tional, so people should not necessarily or sys-
investment is informative about the expected
tematically ignore them or be taught to do so.
amount needed to complete it. Therefore,
The possibility of rational explanations
the expected additional investment required
for sunk cost effects has been raised before.
for fruition will be correlated with the sunk
Friedman et al. (2007) list option values and
investment. Moreover, in a world of random
reputational concerns as possible reasons why
returns, the realization of a return is informa-
people might react to sunk costs. However,
tive about the expected value of continuing
they do not provide detailed explanations or
a project. A large loss, which leads to a rational
models. Kanodia, Bushman, and Dickhaut
inference of a high variance, will often lead to
(1989), Prendergast and Stole (1996), and
a higher option value because option values
Camerer and Weber (1999) develop principal-
tend to rise with variance. Consequently, the
agent models in which rational agents invest
informativeness of sunk investments is am-
more if they have invested more in the past
plified by consideration of the option value.
to protect their reputation for ability. We elu-
cidate the general features of these models
B. Reputational Concerns below and argue that concerns about reputa-
tion for ability are especially powerful in ex-
In team relationships, each participant’s plaining apparent reactions to sunk costs by
willingness to invest depends on the invest- politicians. Carmichael and MacLeod (2003)
ments of others. In such circumstances, a com- develop a model in which agents initially
mitment to finishing projects even when they make investments independently and are later
appear ex post unprofitable is valuable be- matched in pairs, their match produces a sur-
cause such a commitment induces more effi- plus and they bargain over it based on cultural
cient ex ante investment. Thus, a reputation norms of fair division. A fair division rule in
for ‘‘throwing good money after bad’’—the which each agent’s surplus share is increasing
classic sunk cost fallacy—can solve a coordina- in their sunk investment and decreasing in the
tion problem. In contrast to the desire for other’s sunk investment is shown to be evolu-
commitment, people might rationally want tionarily stable.
to conceal bad choices to appear more tal- Although several articles have raised the
ented, which may lead them to make further possibility of rational and evolutionary rea-
investments, hoping to conceal their invest- sons, and several have modeled one reason,
ments gone bad. for attending to sunk costs, our article ap-
pears to be the first to systematically model
the main rational reasons for doing so. Before
C. Financial and Time Constraints
presenting our formal arguments about the
Given financial constraints, larger past rationality of reacting to sunk costs in differ-
expenditures leave less ability to make future ent decision-making environments, we now
expenditures, ceteris paribus. Thus, financial review the empirical evidence on the tendency
constraints may lead companies or individuals to react to sunk costs.
to stick with projects that no longer appear to
be the best choice. Moreover, given limited II. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE
time to invest in projects, as the time remain-
ing shrinks, individuals have less time over The greater the sunk investment that indi-
which to amortize their costs of experimenting viduals have already made the more likely they
with new projects and therefore may be ratio- are to invest further. Several studies provide
nally less likely to abandon current projects. empirical evidence of this tendency. In studies
by Staw (1976, 1981), Arkes and Blumer (1985),
Once all the elements of the decision-making Whyte (1993), and Khan, Salter, and Sharp
environment are correctly specified, condi- (2000), subjects were presented with various
tioning on sunk costs can often be understood vignettes describing a business investment
as rational behavior. This has two potentially project. One group of subjects was told that
MCAFEE, MIALON & MIALON: SUNK COSTS MATTER 325

a large amount had already been invested, in billions of dollars wasted and expensive
while another group was told that a small energy, and the Vietnam War resulted in tens
amount had already been invested. In almost of thousands of American deaths and merely
all the cases, the subjects with the large sunk postponed the time until South Vietnam fell.
investment chose to invest more. The choice of examples may in part reflect
Individuals who have made a large sunk a bias on the part of economists and psychol-
investment may also have a tendency to invest ogists trying to teach people a lesson about
further even when the return does not seem ignoring sunk costs. A potentially very effec-
worthwhile. According to evidence reported tive way to teach people to ignore sunk costs is
by De Bondt and Makhija (1988), managers through examples in which people did not
of many utility companies in the United States ignore sunk costs much to society’s, or their
have been overly reluctant to terminate eco- own, ultimate detriment.
nomically unviable nuclear plant projects. In But there are also examples of people who
the 1960s, the nuclear power industry prom- succeeded by not ignoring sunk costs. The
ised ‘‘energy too cheap to meter.’’ But nuclear same ‘‘we-owe-it-to-our-fallen-countrymen’’
power later proved unsafe and uneconomical. logic that led Americans to stay the course
As the U.S. nuclear power program was failing in Vietnam also helped the war effort in World
in the 1970s and 1980s, Public Service Com- War II. More generally, many success stories
missions around the nation ordered prudency involve people who at some time suffered great
reviews. From these reviews, De Bondt and setbacks, but persevered when short-term
Makhija find evidence that the Commissions odds were not in their favor because they
denied many utility companies even partial ‘‘had already come too far to give up now.’’
recovery of nuclear construction costs on Columbus did not give up when the shores
the grounds that they had been mismanaging of India did not appear after weeks at sea,
the nuclear construction projects in ways con- and many on his crew were urging him to turn
sistent with throwing good money after bad. home (see Olson 1967, for Columbus’ jour-
There is also evidence of government repre- nal). Jeff Bezos, founder of Amazon.com,
sentatives failing to ignore sunk costs. The did not give up when Amazon’s loss totaled
governments of France and Britain continued $1.4 billion in 2001, and many on Wall Street
to invest in the Concorde—a supersonic air- were speculating that the company would go
craft no longer in production—long after it broke (Mendelson and Meza 2001).
became clear that the project would generate Anecdotal evidence suggests that individuals
little return because they had ‘‘Too much in- may even exploit their own reactions to sunk
vested to quit’’ (Teger 1980, title of the book). expenditures to their advantage. Steele (1996,
An argument often made to stay the course 610) and Walton (2002, 479) recount stories of
in a war is that too many lives have already individuals who buy exercise machines or gym
been lost and that these lives will have been memberships that cost in the thousands of dol-
lost in vain if the war is not won. In a speech lars, even though they are reluctant to spend
on August 22, 2005, U.S. President George this much money, reasoning that if they do,
Bush made this argument for staying the it will make them exercise, which is good for
course in Iraq. Referring to the almost 2,000 their health. A reaction to sunk costs that
Americans who had already died in the war, assists in commitment is often helpful.
he said ‘‘We owe them something . . .. We will People react to sunk costs not only in
finish the task that they gave their lives for’’ investment decisions but also in consumption
(Schwartz 2005, 1). Similar arguments were decisions. In consumption, people may at-
made during the Vietnam War. As casualties tempt to redeem sunk monetary expenditures
mounted in Vietnam in the 1960s, it became by increasing nonmonetary expenditures of
more and more difficult to withdraw because resources such as time and effort. In a field
war supporters insisted that withdrawal would experiment with season tickets to the Ohio
mean that too many American soldiers would University’s Theater in 1982, Arkes and
have died in vain. Blumer (1985) found that people who were
Many of the examples usually employed to charged the regular price of $15 (about $30
demonstrate the sunk cost fallacy consist of in 2006 dollars) at the ticket counter attended
disasters resulting from not ignoring sunk 0.83 more plays on average, out of the first five
costs. The nuclear power program resulted plays of the season, than those who received an
326 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

unexpected discount of $7 ($14 today). Staw ture. Other things equal, a greater investment
and Hoang (1995) and Camerer and Weber usually implies that success is closer at hand.
(1999) show that National Basketball Associa- Consider the following simple model. A
tion teams initially tend to give their early- firm has an investment project that requires
round draft picks more playing time than their a total cost C to complete and yields a payoff
performance justifies, perhaps in an attempt to V upon completion. The total cost C is uncer-
justify their high salaries. tain and is distributed according to a cumula-
People may invest more money or time if tive distribution function GðCÞ, where G(x) .
their sunk costs are greater (‘‘escalation of G(y) for x . y . 0. Suppose the firm has
commitment’’), but they may also invest less already invested an amount C1 in Period 1
if their sunk costs are greater (‘‘deescalation’’). and the project is not complete. In Period 2,
While the reported evidence typically points to the firm chooses whether or not to invest an
escalation, Garland, Sandefur, and Rogers additional amount C2. For simplicity, suppose
(1990) provide evidence of deescalation in oil the firm cannot invest after Period 2. Denote
exploration experiments. The authors gave pe- by p2 the probability that the project is com-
troleum geologists various scenarios in which pleted after the firm invests in Period 2.
more or fewer wells had already been drilled Using Bayes’ Law, we find that
and found to be dry. The geologists were less
likely to authorize funds to continue explora- GðC1 þ C2 Þ  GðC1 Þ
tion and their estimates of the likelihood of p2 5 p2 ðC1 ; C2 Þ 5 :
1  GðC1 Þ
finding oil in the next well were lower when
the number of wells already found to be dry
was greater. Similarly, Heath (1995) provides This is the cumulative hazard of investment
evidence of deescalation in several experi- and it depends on the amount C1 already
ments with investment vignettes. He attributes invested. The firm therefore rationally takes
the observed ‘‘reverse sunk cost effect’’ to ‘‘men- into account the size of its sunk investment
tal budgeting.’’ According to his theory, peo- when deciding whether to invest further.
ple set a mental limit for their expenditures, Differentiating p2(C1, C2) with respect to
and when their expenditures exceed the limit, C1, we obtain
they quit investing. People who have already
invested a lot are more likely to have reached @p2 1  GðC1 þ C2 Þ
5
the limit of their mental budget and therefore @C1 1  GðC1 Þ
are more likely to quit. We argue later that  
gðC1 þ C2 Þ gðC1 Þ
actual budget constraints can explain not only   :
deescalation but also escalation of commit- 1  GðC1 þ C2 Þ 1  GðC1 Þ
ment in certain investment situations.
Empirical and anecdotal evidence suggests Thus, p2(C1, C2) is increasing in C1 if the
gðÞ
that people are often influenced by sunk costs hazard rate 1GðÞ is increasing. That is, condi-
in their decision making. We now argue that tional on not succeeding, the probability of
this is not necessarily inconsistent with ratio- success with a small additional investment
nal decision making or optimizing behavior. grows, and conversely, p2(C1, C2) is decreasing
in C1 if the hazard rate is decreasing.
The firm’s expected utility of investing in
III. INFORMATIONAL CONTENT Period 2 is p2(C1, C2)V  C2  C1 and its
expected utility from not investing in Period
Agents may rationally react to sunk costs
2 is C1. Therefore, the net gain from invest-
because such costs reveal valuable informa-
ment in Period 2 is p2(C1, C2)V  C2.
tion, both about the likelihood of future suc-
Suppose the hazard rate is increasing, so
cess and about the option value of continuing
p2(C1, C2) is increasing in C1. In this case, the
to invest.
willingness to invest is rationally an increasing
function of the past investment. Similarly, the
A. Changing Hazards
willingness to invest is rationally a decreasing
Past investments in a given course of action function of the past investment if the hazard
often provide evidence about whether the course rate is decreasing. The only case in which the
of action is likely to succeed or fail in the fu- size of the sunk investment cannot affect the
MCAFEE, MIALON & MIALON: SUNK COSTS MATTER 327

firm’s rational decision about whether to con- so da2/dC1 . 0, which makes it more likely
tinue investing is the rather special case in that dp2/dC1 . 0.
which the hazard is exactly constant. While some projects have an increasing
The model suggests that in many environ- hazard, others appear to have a decreasing
ments, the level of sunk costs matters to the hazard. For example, curing cancer, originally
rational inference about the likely needed expected to cost $1 billion (Epstein 1998),
future expenditures and in such environments, probably has a decreasing hazard; given initial
sunk costs matter. The theory admits that the failure, the odds of immediate success recede
effect of sunk costs on the willingness to make and the likely expenditures required to com-
continued investments is ambiguous, hinging plete grow. Oil exploration projects might also
on the derivative of the hazard rate. be characterized by decreasing hazards. Sup-
If the amount required for the project to be pose a firm acquires a license to drill a number
completed cannot exceed some known finite of wells in a fixed area. It decides to drill a well
amount, that is, the support of the distribution on a particular spot in the area. Suppose the
of C has an upper bound, then the project’s well turns out to be dry. The costs of drilling
hazard rate is necessarily increasing close to the well are then sunk. But the dry well might
this upper bound. Even when the upper bound indicate that the likelihood of striking oil on
is not known with certainty, the hazard might another spot in the area is low since the geo-
be increasing. In many investment projects, physical characteristics of surface rocks and
progress toward the goal is observable or mea- terrain for the next spot are more or less the
surable. Sunk investments that have been same as the ones for the previous spot that
insufficient to achieve success then convey turned out to be dry. Thus, the firm might
information about the likelihood of future be rationally less likely to drill another well.
success. Consider an aircraft company engaged In general, firms might be less willing to drill
in a project to develop ‘‘a radar scrambling another well the more wells they had already
device that would render a plane undetectable found to be dry. This may in part explain
by conventional radar’’ (Arkes and Blumer the rapid deescalation observed by Garland,
1985). Suppose the firm has spent $100 million Sandefur, and Rogers (1990) in their oil explo-
to develop the radar-blind plane, and while ration experiments.
it has not achieved its goal yet, the project
is now 90% complete in that, according to
test results that incorporate many variations
B. Option Values
in speed, altitude, and the level of electro-
magnetic emissions, the plane is detectable Experience generally reveals information
only about 10% of the time, which is slightly about likely future values. In a world of uncer-
above the marketable level of 5%. The firm tainty, maintaining an investment generates
must decide whether to invest another $100 information, while terminating often does
million. While this might still be insufficient to not. Therefore, there may be an option value
complete the project, the firm might expect a to maintaining investments (Dixit 1992; Dixit
high probability of completion with the addi- and Pindyck 1994; Pindyck 1991).
tional investment based on the substantial A firm may start a project because the pro-
progress achieved through the first $100 million ject has a positive net present value (NPV) and
invested. then experience a bad outcome that turns the
Learning by doing generally reinforces the NPV negative; but it might nonetheless be
conclusion that greater expenditures should rational for the firm to continue investing in
increase the willingness to continue. In the the project after the bad outcome because of
model described above, if the firm has invested the ‘‘deferral’’ option value of maintaining
more in Period 1, it may have acquired more the investment. Consider the following simple
knowledge and skill that will make it more three-period example. In Period 1, the firm
likely to succeed with the additional invest- chooses whether or not to invest $2 in a pro-
ment in Period 2. That is, the probability that ject. If it chooses to invest then with 1/2 prob-
the firm will succeed in Period 2 may also be ability, the project is completed and yields $6,
a function of the firm’s ability in Period 2, a2, and with 1/2 probability, the project is not
which may be a function of C1. A greater completed. If the project is not completed then
investment in Period 1 may increase ability, in Period 2, the firm chooses whether or not to
328 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

2
invest another $2. If it chooses to invest then This probability is increasing in x if ðxl HÞ
2r2 
ðxlL Þ2 2 2
with 1/2 probability, the project is now com- 2s2 is decreasing. As s , r2 , the Bayesian
pleted and yields $6, and with 1/2 probability, r lL s2 lH
update 2is increasing
2
if x . 2
r s 2 . For x
the project is still not completed and the firm below r lrL2s 2
lH
, a lower return is good news
s
learns that an additional $10 is required for about the prospects for investment; the ex-
completion. If the firm ever chooses not to
pected payoff from future investment increases
invest before completion, it receives zero.
as the return decreases. In this case, the lower
Normalizing the discount factor to 1, in
Period 1, the NPV of the project absent the return signals an increase in variance, which is
abandonment option is 2 + 0.5(6) + good news about the value of further experi-
0.5[2 + 0.5(6) + 0.5(10 + 6)] 5 0.5, and mentation. For any fixed cost of sampling, the
in Period 2, after the bad outcome in Period stopping rule involves a low Bayesian update
1, the NPV of the project is 2 + 0.5(6) + and this occurs on an interval with a very high
0.5(10 + 6) 5 1. However, in Period 2, or a very low return leading to further sam-
the true value of continuing the project after pling. Thus, throwing good money after bad
the bad outcome in Period 1, which includes can readily be an optimal response to the
the value of the deferral option, is 2 + increased option value of a high variance.
0.5(5) + 0.5(0) 50.5 since the firm can stop In most projects, there is uncertainty, and
investing in Period 3 if it learns that an addi- restarting after stopping entails costs, making
tional $10 is required for completion. Thus, the option to continue valuable. This is cer-
even in the bad state after the first round, which tainly the case for nuclear power plants, for
makes the project’s NPV turn negative, it is example. Shutting down a nuclear reactor
rational for the firm to continue investing be- requires dismantling or entombment and the
cause of the deferral option value of maintain- costs of restarting are extremely high. More-
ing the investment. over, the variance of energy prices has been
In investment projects where option consid- quite large. The option of maintaining nuclear
erations are important, larger losses them- plants is therefore potentially valuable. Low
selves might even be ‘‘good news’’ about the returns from nuclear power in the 1970s and
value of further investment. This is an extreme 1980s might have been a consequence of the
form of our argument that it might be rational large variance, suggesting a high option value
to ‘‘throw good money after bad.’’ We illus- of maintaining nuclear plants. This may in
trate the logic in a simple way. Suppose that part explain the evidence (reported by De
an investment project is one of two kinds, Bondt and Makhija 1988) that managers of
either with low risk and negative profit or with utilities at the time were so reluctant to shut
high risk and positive profit. For simplicity, down seemingly unprofitable plants.
suppose the low-risk project has a normally
distributed return with mean lL and variance
s2, while the high-risk project return is also
IV. REPUTATIONAL CONCERNS
normally distributed with mean lH and vari-
ance r2. Assume s2 , r2 and lL , 0 , lH, Agents may also rationally react to sunk
so that the goal of the investor is to terminate costs because of reputational concerns. There
the low-risk project and continue with the are two main classes of relevant reputational
high-risk project. concerns: a reputation for commitment and
Given an observed return x and a prior on a reputation for ability.
the high return of p, the Bayesian update that
the project has a positive return is
ðxlH Þ2 A. Reputation for Commitment
p pffiffiffiffi
1
e 2r2
2pr Refusing to abandon projects with large
1 ðxlH Þ2 1 ðxlL Þ2 sunk costs might be rational because it creates
p pffiffiffiffiffiffi e 2r2 þ ð1  pÞ pffiffiffiffiffiffi e 2s2
2pr 2ps a reputation for commitment. In a team situ-
1 ation, should one agent abandon a joint pro-
5 : ject, the other team members suffer as well. In
1  p r ðxlH2 Þ2 ðxl2L Þ2
1þ e 2r 2s such a complementary situation, the willing-
p s ness to persist with projects with large sunk
MCAFEE, MIALON & MIALON: SUNK COSTS MATTER 329

costs might act as a commitment, inducing An agent matches with another agent, pos-
investment by the other team members. sibly for two periods. The match is an agree-
For example, in cartels and in marriage, an ment to share the sum of payoffs equally and
important aspect of the incentive to partici- therefore the matched agents maximize their
pate and invest in the relationship is the belief joint payoffs. In Period 1, both agents sink
that the other party will stay in the relation- investments x and y, respectively,
pffiffiffiffiffi which pro-
ship. If a member of an illegal price-fixing duce returns for each of 12 xy, and cost 12x2 and
1 2
cartel seems likely to confess to the govern- 2y , respectively. Investment only occurs in the
ment in exchange for immunity from prosecu- first period. The returns are repeated in the
tion, the other cartel members may race to be second period, provided both agents remain
first to confess since only the first gets im- in the relationship. In Period 2, with probabil-
munity (in Europe, such immunity is called ity p, each agent is offered the opportunity to
‘‘leniency’’). Similarly, a spouse who loses faith break the relationship for the return V. The
in the long-term prospects of a marriage in- outside offers to agents are independent. Each
vests less in the relationship, thereby reducing agent learns whether or not he or she has an
the gains from partnership, potentially doom- outside offer (but does not learn whether or
ing the relationship. In both cases, beliefs not the other has one) and then chooses whether
about the future viability matter to the success or not to breach the relationship. If one agent
of the relationship, and there is the potential takes an outside offer but the other agent does
for self-fulfilling optimistic and pessimistic not receive one, the latter obtains zero. For
beliefs. each agent, breaching the relationship also
In such a situation, individuals may ratio- entails a reputation cost q, as it reduces the
nally select others who stay in the relationship agent’s reputation for commitment and desir-
beyond the point of individual rationality, if ability as a partner in future matches.
such a commitment is possible. Indeed, ex ante If both agents breach when given the op-
it is rational to construct exit barriers like portunity to do so in Period 2, then the prob-
costly and difficult divorce laws, so as to ability that both agents breach in Period 2
reduce early exit. Such exit barriers might be is p2, the probability that exactly one agent
behavioral as well as legal. If an individual breaches is 2p(1  p), and the probability
can develop a reputation for sticking in a rela- that no agent breaches is (1  p)2. Thus, ignor-
tionship beyond the break-even point, it pffiffiffiffiffi the sum of payoffs is u 5 ð1 þ
ing discounting,
would make that individual a more desirable ð1  pÞ2 Þ xy þ 2pðV  qÞ  12x2  12y2 , which
partner and thus enhance the set of available is maximized when x 5 y 5 ½ð1 þ ð1  pÞ2 Þ.
partners as well as encourage greater and lon- An agent who breaches receives V  q in
ger lasting investment by the chosen partner. Period 2. An
ffi agent who does not breach re-
pffiffiffiffi
One way of creating such a reputation is to ceives 12 xy 5 14ð1 þ ð1  pÞ2 Þ in Period 2 if
act as if one cares about sunk costs. In some the other agent does not breach, which hap-
sense, the history of a relationship is a sunk pens with probability 1  p, and receives
cost (or benefit); if a person conditions on this 0 if the other agent breaches, which happens
history in a way that makes him or her stay in with probability p, under the hypothesis that
relationships that have a 0 or slightly negative the other agent breaches given the opportunity
expected value going forward, the person has to do so. Thus, an agentpffiffiffiffiffiwho does not breach
created an exit barrier. in Period 2 receives 12 xyð1  pÞ 5 14ð1 þ ð1 
This logic establishes the value of condi- pÞ2 Þð1  pÞ if the other agent breaches given
tioning on sunk costs, or, more realistically, the opportunity to do so. Therefore, breaching
sunk benefits, in the context of coinvestment is subgame perfect if V  q . 14ð1 þ ð1  pÞ2 Þ
and partnership selection. An individual ð1  pÞ.
who uses the logic of ‘‘stay in the relationship If neither agent breaches given the opportu-
until the total value, including the sunk value, nity topffiffiffiffi
doffi so, then the sum of payoffs is
generated by the relationship is zero’’ will be u 5 ð2 xyÞ  12x2  12y2 , which is maximized
a more desirable partner than the individual when x 5 y 5 1. In this case, pffiffiffiffiffi an agent who
who leaves when the value going forward is 0. does not breach receives 12 xy 5 12 in Period
We now formalize this concept using a simple 2 given that the other agent does not breach
two-period model that sets aside consideration in Period 2. Thus, not breaching is subgame
of selection. perfect if V  q , 12.
330 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

Consequently, if 12 . V  q . 14ð1 þ ð1  pÞ2 Þ breaching is not too small. In this model, a ten-
ð1  pÞ, then there are two subgame perfect dency to stay in the relationship due to a large
equilibria, one with breaching and the other sunk investment would be beneficial to each
without breaching. The ‘‘no-breaching’’ equi- party. It would be beneficial for an agent be-
librium offers both parties higher payoffs. It cause of the effort it would induce in the other
results from self-fulfilling optimistic beliefs. agent, as well as for the increase in the agent’s
Given that the agents expect each other not own effort, even when the returns are shared
to breach in Period 2, they invest more in between them. Any mechanism for commitment
Period 1, which in turn makes them want to to stay in the relationship even when the rela-
continue (escalate) the relationship in Period tionship has a negative expected value going
2. On the other hand, the breaching equilib- forward would serve the agents well.
rium results from self-fulfilling pessimistic
beliefs. Given that the agents expect each other
to breach in Period 2, they invest less in Period
B. Reputation for Ability
1, and as a consequence, they do not have suf-
ficient incentive to continue the relationship in Abandoning a project may also reveal an
Period 2. Note that looking across these two agent as a poor forecaster, leading agents to
equilibria, one would see escalation of com- rationally persist with unprofitable projects
mitment: when the investment is small, the to conceal their poor skills. This argument
relationship breaks up and when the invest- has already been made formally by several
ment is large, the relationship continues. If authors, most notably Kanodia, Bushman,
one took a sample of similar relationships, and Dickhaut (1989), Prendergast and Stole
some might be in the breaching equilibrium, (1996), and Camerer and Weber (1999).
where little is invested and the relationship dis- These models share the following features.
solves, while some might be in the no-breaching Managers choose projects, acquire private
equilibrium, where a lot is invested and the information about the productivity of the
relationship lasts. Then, if one regressed the projects while carrying them out, and choose
probability of continuation on the amount in- how much more to invest in them in light of
vested, one would obtain a positive correlation. this information. The quality of the private
In situations where the reputation cost q information that they acquire is related to
from breaching the relationship is large their unobservable ability. Managers learn the
enough that V  q , 14ð1 þ ð1  pÞ2 Þð1  pÞ, productivity of projects more quickly, and
only the no-breaching equilibrium is subgame choose more productive projects if their ability
perfect. Thus, rational concerns about reputa- is higher. Employers rationally make inferen-
tion for commitment might eliminate the ces about their ability from their investment
breaching equilibrium. The agents might choices.
rationally avoid breaching the relationship Because more able managers learn the pro-
even when a great outside option presents ductivity of projects more quickly, they are
itself because they want to protect their repu- more likely to have more productive projects
tation for commitment, which makes both and thus are more likely to continue investing.
agents invest more initially, which in turn Then, if managers stop investing upon learn-
reduces both agents incentives to breach when ing that the projects are not productive,
an outside option arises, leading to the better, employers draw a negative inference about
no-breaching equilibrium. their ability, which in turn reduces their earn-
On the other hand, in situations where the ings opportunities. Once they have started to
reputation cost q of breaching is low enough invest, stopping reveals that they were slow in
that V  q . 12, breaching is the only subgame learning the productivity of the projects,
perfect equilibrium. In this case, the total gains which signals low ability. For this reason,
from trade are u* 5 14ð1 þ ð1  pÞ2 Þ2 þ 2p managers may rationally continue investing
ðV  qÞ. This function is decreasing around even after learning that the projects are
p 5 0 unless V  q exceeds 1. That is, a slight unprofitable. Employers might, of course,
possibility of breach is collectively harmful; eventually find out that the projects are
both agents would be ex ante better off if they unprofitable in which case the managers might
could prevent breach when V  q , 1, which be fired. Nonetheless, managers might ratio-
holds as long as the reputation cost q of nally continue to invest even after learning
MCAFEE, MIALON & MIALON: SUNK COSTS MATTER 331

that the projects are unprofitable, to delay to fail again in the future. Moreover, politi-
being fired, as long as they discount the future. cians who argue, like Khieu Samphan, that
Employers would certainly prefer that their a very large sunk cost, such as more than
managers immediately cease bad projects. one million lives lost, should be forgotten lose
They could prevent them from continuing all reputation for commitment, which also
bad projects if they could credibly promise makes any continued political relationship
not to fire them if they stopped. However, such with them very difficult to justify.
a promise is usually not credible. If the man- Last, reputation concerns may in part
agers stop, the employers learn that the projects explain some reactions to sunk costs in con-
are likely bad, and therefore, the managers sumption. People who buy an exercise
who chose them likely have low ability in machine that costs thousands of dollars, and
which case the employers are often better then only use it a few days, or buy season tick-
off firing the managers. ets to the theater, and then only attend a few
Low ability managers start projects because plays, might make their lapse of judgment
there is always the chance that they would be manifest to others (for example, to their
lucky and choose good ones. Once they start, spouse) and lose their reputation for making
they do not want to stop if they learn that the smart consumption choices. To avoid or delay
projects are bad because they want to delay the reputation loss, they might rationally
a negative inference about their ability and make greater use of their past purchases than
the associated loss in their earnings potential. they would otherwise want to.
Career concerns might be especially power-
ful in explaining the evidence that politicians
often throw good money after bad. Politicians V. FINANCIAL AND TIME CONSTRAINTS
are agents for the people and choose projects
for the provision of public goods and the pro- We have seen that moral hazard in the form
tection of national interests. However, they of career concerns can lead managers to persist
differ in their ability to choose good projects, with unprofitable projects. In general, moral
receive private information about the quality hazard and asymmetric information can cre-
of their chosen projects, make public decisions ate a host of managerial problems to which
about whether to continue them, and continue firms rationally respond by imposing financial
to benefit from being in power only if they can constraints on managers. Abundant theoreti-
maintain a good reputation. Moreover, politi- cal literature in corporate finance shows that
cians are in a position where they heavily dis- imposing financial constraints on firm manag-
count the future if their reelection is not ers improves agency problems (Hart and
assured. If they can maintain their reputation Moore 1995; Lewis and Sappington 1989;
until the reelection date, they may remain in Myers and Majluf 1984; Stiglitz and Weiss
power. If they learn some time before the 1981). The theoretical conclusion finds over-
reelection date that one of their projects is whelming empirical support, and only a small
bad, they are likely to continue the project fraction of business investment is funded by
to avoid a reputation loss at least until after borrowing (Fazzari and Athey 1987; Fazzari
the reelection. and Petersen 1993; Love 2003). When manag-
Politicians might continue a bad project to ers face financial constraints, sunk costs must
delay a reputation loss especially if they are influence firm investments simply because of
more interested in remaining in power than budgets.
serving the public. Ironically, when ultimately Firms with financial constraints might ra-
the project is discovered to be bad and they tionally react to sunk costs by investing more
incur the reputation loss, some among them in a project, rather than less, because the abil-
who are especially crooked and calculating ity to undertake alternative investments
might even turn and argue, as Khieu Samphan declines in the level of sunk costs. Consider
did (see the introductory quotation), that the the following simple model. A firm with a bud-
public should ‘‘let bygones be bygones’’ and get of B . 0 dollars is engaged in an invest-
ignore the sunk costs of the failed project. ment opportunity, Project 1, which requires
However, it is not rational for voters to forget paying a fixed cost M0 . 0 before yielding
their failure, even though its costs are sunk, a rate of return of R1 . 0 on every dollar spent
because the failure is indicative of a propensity beyond M0. The firm is making payments in
332 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

increments across time. Now suppose that a Resource constraints may explain apparent
better investment opportunity, Project 2, sunk costs fallacies not only in business invest-
arises unexpectedly. Project 2 is better than ment but also in other kinds of investment, for
Project 1 in the sense that it has the same fixed example, in careers. People who have already
cost M0 but a higher rate of return R2 . R1. invested a lot of money and time on legal edu-
Project 2 arises unexpectedly in the sense cation, only to learn that a career in law would
that, initially, the probability that it would not interest them much, might nonetheless
arise was low enough that the firm found it persist in this career path instead of switching
worthwhile to start Project 1 (instead of wait- to another one, such as becoming a doctor,
ing for Project 2). even though a career in medicine might now
Let M1 . 0 be the amount that the firm has interest them more, because becoming a doctor
already sunk into Project 1 at the time that requires years in medical school, and they
Project 2 arises. If M1 . M0 then the firm might have already exhausted most of their
switches to Project 2 if and only if (B  M1) time, and opportunities for student loans,
R1 , (B  M0  M1)R2 or equivalently on their legal education.
M0R2 , (B  M1)(R2  R1). If M1 , M0 then With a resource constraint, an individual
the firm switches to Project 2 if and only if can only switch to a new project a limited
(B  M0)R1 , (B M0  M1)R2 or equivalently number of times since starting a new project
M1R2 , (B  M0)(R2  R1). In either case, the is costly. However, with only one more switch
firm rationally continues with Project 1 (the possible, starting a new (better) project entails
inequality is not satisfied) if the amount M1 foreclosing the option to start a new (even
that the firm has already sunk into Project 1 better) project in the future and thus would
is sufficiently large and switches to Project 2 not be a rational choice unless the gains were
(the inequality is satisfied) if M1 is sufficiently sufficiently large—there is substantial ‘‘lock-in’’
small. The firm also continues with Project 1 if even on the penultimate chance. However,
the fixed cost M0 to obtain a return on a project using backward induction, abandoning the
is sufficiently large or if the firm’s budget B is third-to-last project means moving to the pen-
sufficiently small. ultimate one and its substantial lock-in, which
Given limited resources, if the firm has means it is suboptimal to abandon the third-
already sunk more resources into the current to-last project unless the gains are large, and
project then the value of the option to start so forth. Ultimately, one should not abandon
a new project if it arises is lower relative to a project for a small expected gain, which
the value of the option to continue the current entails rejecting better opportunities to con-
project because fewer resources are left over to tinue with the existing project.
bring any new project to fruition and more In general, individuals have limited time to
resources have already been spent to bring devote to investment in projects and a limited
the current project to fruition. Therefore, the number of attempts at new projects. As the
firm’s incentive to continue investing in the time remaining shrinks, individuals might
current project is higher the more resources rationally be more reluctant to abandon cur-
it has already sunk into the project. rent projects to start new ones. Consider the
The above model might be germane to sev- following general model. Time is discrete, with
eral apparent sunk cost fallacies. It might periods 0, 1, 2, . . . , T. At the start of period t,
explain why businesses sometimes stick with the agent will have an existing project of type
projects that no longer appear to be the best v. The agent can stay with the project or
choice. For example, an aircraft company that choose a new project. Starting a new project
had started a project to develop a radar-blind means ending the old project and the old pro-
bomber plane might seem overly reluctant to ject is never recoverable once ended. New
switch to developing a radar-blank fighter plane projects have a type, which is a random draw
if stealth fighters are suddenly in much greater from a distribution G with density g. This dis-
demand; but their reluctance might be rational tribution is assumed to have a well-defined
because they might have a limited budget, mean. A project of type v produces v in every
might have already spent hundreds of millions period it is operated. The agent is risk neutral.
of dollars on developing a cost-effective bomber, Because old projects are not recoverable,
and would have to pay another large fixed cost the agent will use a cutoff strategy and draw
to develop a cost-effective fighter instead. a new project if the existing project is worse
MCAFEE, MIALON & MIALON: SUNK COSTS MATTER 333

than a critical value. Denote the critical value remaining, individuals can amortize the cost
at time t by ct. The agent’s utility at the start of of experimentation over many periods. But
period t is Ut(v) 5 max{v + Ut + 1(v), E(v + Ut + with few periods remaining, they can only
1(v))}. Discounting is assumed away for sim- amortize the experimentation cost over a few
plicity. Let l be the mean. It is readily seen that periods; and with only one period remaining,
the last critical value is cT 5 l. In the Appen- they cannot amortize it at all. Thus, as the time
dix, we prove that the critical values satisfy: remaining shrinks, individuals become ratio-
nally more reluctant to abandon current
l þ EUtþ1 projects.
ð*Þ ct 5
T tþ1 This logic might also help explain instances
l T t of apparent escalation of commitment. For
5 þ example, people have limited time to invest
T tþ1 T tþ1
 ð‘  in education because ability to learn deterio-
rates rapidly after a certain age. As the time
 ctþ1 þ 1  GðxÞdx : they have remaining shrinks, they might ratio-
ctþ1 nally become more reluctant to switch fields of
study (even if their satisfaction with their cur-
Moreover, the sequence ct is decreasing over rent field of study is not great) because they
time, ending at l. Thus, as the time remaining have less time remaining to amortize the cost
becomes shorter, the agent becomes progres- of experimenting with new fields of study.
sively more willing to stay with the existing
project.
When G is uniform on [0, 1], the sequence is VI. CONCLUSIONS
readily computed, and Figure 1 shows the crit-
ical values in the last 1,000 time periods for In a world of uncertainty, future prospects
this case. The cutoffs decrease steadily for are informed by past decisions. In a world of
many periods and then drop rapidly as the last scarce resources and finite time, future pros-
period approaches. pects are limited by past decisions. In a world
Intuitively, with many periods remaining, if of social interaction, future prospects are
individuals switch to another project and get determined by the reputation that is deter-
a bad draw then there is ample time for them mined by past decisions. Therefore, reacting
to make up for it by switching again until the to past decisions, and the sunk costs that they
draw is better. But with only a few periods have entailed, is often rational.
remaining, there is little time to make up for In this article, we have shown that people
a bad draw. Another way to express the intu- might rationally invest more if they have
ition for the result is that with many periods invested more in the past because greater past
investments often indicate that success is
closer at hand and often reduce the ability
FIGURE 1 or willingness to undertake alternative invest-
Critical Switching Values with G Uniform on ments given the presence of financial and time
constraints. We have shown that people might
[0, 1] and T 5 1,000.
rationally throw good money after bad, either
because of the high risks, and therefore high
ct
option values of continuing to invest, which
large losses often indicate, or to avoid imme-
diately losing their reputation for smart invest-
ment choices. And we have shown that people
might rationally react to sunk costs to create
a reputation for commitment, which tends to
improve their welfare in joint investment sit-
uations, by encouraging others to choose them
as partners, and their partners to invest more.
In addition, any of these reasons could be
subject to evolutionary selection; that is, peo-
t
ple who are hard wired to condition their
334 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

behavior on sunk costs in a given set of situa- in Section V. In the model, at the start of the last period,
tions could do better than people who are not, an agent with project v is better off with a new project if
v is less than the mean project value,
so that a preference for conditioning on sunk ð‘ ð‘
costs might prosper. If the target of evolution- ðA1Þ l 5 xgðxÞdx 5 1  Gð xÞ dx:
ary selection permits it, responding to sunk
0 0
costs would be rational given such a prefer-
ence. An evolutionary selection argument Thus, cT 5 l. The agent’s utility at the start of period
has the advantage that people might occasion- T is UT(v) 5 max{v, cT}, which has expected value over
v of
ally condition on sunk costs even when it is ð‘
disadvantageous to do so because, on average, ðA2Þ EUT 5 GðcT ÞcT þ xgðxÞdx
it is advantageous, thus accommodating occa-
cT
sional demonstrably irrational behavior. ð‘
While we have argued that sunk cost effects 5 cT þ 1  Gð xÞ dx:
have a rational explanation, there is also cT
a behavioral explanation for sunk cost effects
originally proposed by Thaler (1980) based This forms the base of an induction. The characteriza-
on the prospect theory of Kahneman and tion of the induction is that the agent uses the critical value:
Tversky (1979). Under this theory, people react l þ EUtþ1
to losses by investing more because they have ðA3Þ cT 5
T tþ1
loss aversion. The result is explained by a prop-
erty of preferences. In contrast, we have derived and
the result from the principles of rationality  ð‘ 
(Bayesian inference and constrained and dy- ðA4Þ EUT 5 ðT  t þ 1Þ cT þ 1  GðxÞdx :
namic optimization) without building it directly cT
into the preferences. Combining our rational
explanation with evolutionary pressures on Note this is trivially satisfied at t 5 T.
preferences would reconcile the rational and First, we show that this induction formula implies that
behavioral approaches to the question. the sequence ct is decreasing in t. We have that ct . ct + 1 if
and only if
Although reacting to sunk costs is rational
in many situations, ignoring sunk costs is l þ EUtþ1 l þ EUtþ2
ðA5Þ 
rational in others. According to our models, T tþ1 T t
it is a requirement of rationality to ignore sunk
costs only in situations in which past invest- if and only if
ments are not informative, reputation concerns
ðA6Þ ðl þ EUtþ1 ÞðT  tÞ  ðl þ EUtþ2 ÞðT  t þ 1Þ
are unimportant, and budget constraints are
not salient.
There is no clear evidence that people react if and only if
to sunk costs in such situations and some evi- ðA7Þ EUtþ1 
1

T tþ1
EUtþ2 :
dence that they do not. Most of the existing T t T t
empirical work has not controlled for chang-
ing hazards, option values, reputations for abil- This is automatically satisfied because EUt + 1  l +
EUt + 2, a fact that is obvious from Ut(v) 5 max{v + Ut + 1(v),
ity and commitment, and budget constraints. E(v + Ut + 1(v))}. Because ct is a decreasing sequence, if
We are aware of only one study in which sev- v . ct then v . cs for all s . t. This simplifies the problem
eral of these factors are eliminated—Friedman because it means that if the agent does not choose a new
et al. (2007). In an experimental environment project at t, the agent never chooses a new project.
To complete the induction, note that
without option value or reputation considera-
tions, the authors find only very small and sta- ðA8Þ Ut1 ðvÞ 5 maxfv þ Ut ðvÞ; Eðv þ Ut ðvÞÞg
tistically insignificant sunk cost effects in the
majority of their treatments, consistent with 5 max fðT  t þ 2Þv; l þ EUt ðvÞg:
the rational theory presented here.
Thus, the critical value satisfies
l þ EUt
APPENDIX A ðA9Þ ct1 5 ;
T tþ2
In this appendix, we derive Equation (*) in the text,
which is the solution to the last model that we develop which is consistent with the induction hypothesis. Last,
MCAFEE, MIALON & MIALON: SUNK COSTS MATTER 335

EUt1 ðvÞ 5 EmaxfðT  t þ 2Þv; l þ EUt ðvÞg Investment Decisions and the Relevance of Sunk
Costs.’’ Journal of Economic Behavior and Organiza-
  tion, 10, 1988, 173–99.
l þ EUt ðvÞ Dixit, A. K. ‘‘Investment and Hysteresis.’’ Journal of Eco-
5 ðT  tÞEmax v;
ðT  t þ 2Þ nomic Perspectives, 6, 1992, 107–32.
Dixit, A. K., and R. S. Pindyck. Investment Under Uncer-
tainty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
5 ðT  t þ 2ÞEmaxfv; ct1 g 1994.
Epstein, S. S. The Politics of Cancer Revisited. New York:
 ð‘  East Ridge Press, 1998.
5 ðT  t þ 2Þ ct1 Gðct1 Þ þ xgðxÞdx Fazzari, S., and M. J. Athey. ‘‘Asymmetric Information,
Financing Constraints, and Investment.’’ Review of
ct1
Economics and Statistics, 69, 1987, 481–87.
 ð‘ 
Fazzari, S., and B. Petersen. ‘‘Working Capital and Fixed
5 ðT  t þ 2Þ ct1 þ 1  GðxÞdx : Investment: New Evidence on Financing Con-
ct1 straints.’’ RAND Journal of Economics, 24, 1993,
ðA10Þ 328–42.
Frank, R. H., and B. Bernanke. Principles of Microeco-
This completes the induction. nomics. 3rd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2006.
The induction on the critical values simplifies: Friedman, D., K. Pommerenke, R. Lukose, G. Milam,
and B. Huberman. ‘‘Searching for the Sunk Cost
l þ EUtþ1 Fallacy.’’ Experimental Economics, 10, 2007, 79–104.
ct 5
T tþ1 Garland, H., C. A. Sandefur, and A. C. Rogers. ‘‘De-
 ð‘  escalation of Commitment in Oil Exploration: When
l T t
5 þ ctþ1 þ 1  GðxÞdx ; Sunk Costs and Negative Feedback Coincide.’’ Jour-
T tþ1 T tþ1 nal of Applied Psychology, 75, 1990, 721–27.
ctþ1
Hart, O., and J. Moore. ‘‘Debt and Seniority: An Analysis
ðA11Þ
of the Role of Hard Claims in Constraining Manage-
ment.’’ American Economic Review, 85 1995, 567–85.
with cT 5 l. Heath, C. ‘‘Escalation and De-escalation of Commitment
If G is uniform on [0, 1], the sequence is: in Response to Sunk Costs: The Role of Budgeting
 ð‘  in Mental Accounting.’’ Organizational Behavior and
l T t Human Decision Processes, 62, 1995, 38–54.
ct 5 þ ctþ1 þ 1  GðxÞdx
T tþ1 T tþ1 Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky. ‘‘Prospect Theory: An
ctþ1
Analysis of Decision Under Risk.’’ Econometrica,
½ þ ðT  tÞðctþ1 þ 1 þ ½ð1  ctþ1 Þ2 Þ 47, 1979, 263–91.
5
T tþ1 Kanodia, C., R. Bushman, and J. Dickhaut. ‘‘Escalation
1 þ ðT  tÞð1 þ ðctþ1 Þ2 Þ Errors and the Sunk Cost Effect: An Explanation
5½ : Based on Reputation and Information Asymme-
T tþ1
tries.’’ Journal of Accounting Research, 27, 1989,
ðA12Þ 59–77.
Khan, B. A., S. B. Salter, and D. J. Sharp. ‘‘Throwing
Figure 1 in the text plots these critical values for T 5 Good Money After Bad: A Comparison of Asian
1,000. and Developed Country Managerial Decision-
Making in Sunk Cost Situations.’’ Asian Pacific Devel-
opment Journal, 7, 2000, 105–20.
Lewis, T., and D. E. M. Sappington. ‘‘Countervailing
Incentives in Agency Problems.’’ Journal of Eco-
nomic Theory, 49, 1989, 294–313.
REFERENCES Love, I. ‘‘Financial Development and Financing Con-
straints: International Evidence from the Structural
Arkes, H. R., and C. Blumer. ‘‘The Psychology of Sunk Investment Model.’’ Review of Financial Studies, 16,
Cost.’’ Organizational Behavior and Human Decision 2003, 765–91.
Processes, 35, 1985, 124–40.
Mankiw, N. G. Principles of Microeconomics. 3rd ed.
Camerer, C. F., and R. A. Weber. ‘‘The Econometrics and Mason, OH: Thomson South-Western, 2004.
Behavioral Economics of Escalation of Commit-
ment: A Re-examination of Staw and Hoang’s Mendelson, H., and P. Meza. ‘‘Amazon.com: Marching
NBA Data.’’ Journal of Economic Behavior and Toward Profitability.’’ Stanford University Graduate
Organization, 39, 1999, 59–82. School of Business Case Number EC-25, 2001.
Carmichael, L., and B. W. MacLeod. ‘‘Caring About Myers, S., and N. S. Majluf. ‘‘Corporate Financing and
Sunk Costs: A Behavioral Solution to Holdup Prob- Investment Decisions when Firms Have Information
lems With Small Stakes.’’ Journal of Law, Economics, that Investors Do Not Have.’’ Journal of Financial
and Organization, 19, 2003, 106–18. Economics, 13, 1984, 187–221.
De Bondt, W. F. M., and A. K. Makhija. ‘‘Throwing Olson, J. E. The Northmen, Columbus and Cabot, 985-
Good Money After Bad? Nuclear Power Plant 1503. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1967.
336 ECONOMIC INQUIRY

Pindyck, R. S. ‘‘Irreversibility, Uncertainty, and Invest- sional Basketball.’’ Administrative Science Quarterly,
ment.’’ Journal of Economic Literature, 29, 1991, 40, 1995, 474–94.
1110–52. Steele, D. R. ‘‘Nozick on Sunk Costs.’’ Ethics, 106, 1996,
Prendergast, C., and L. Stole. ‘‘Impetuous Youngsters and 605–20.
Jaded Old-Timers: Acquiring a Reputation for Stiglitz, J. E., and A. Weiss. ‘‘Credit Rationing in Markets
Learning.’’ Journal of Political Economy, 104, with Imperfect Information.’’ American Economic
1996, 1105–34. Review, 71, 1981, 393–410.
Schwartz, B. ‘‘The Sunk-Cost Fallacy: Bush Falls Victim Teger, A. I. Too Much Invested to Quit. New York:
to a Bad Argument for the War in Iraq.’’ Slate, Permagon, 1980.
September 9, 2005. Thaler, R. ‘‘Toward a Positive Theory of Consumer
Staw, B. M. ‘‘Knee-Deep in the Big Muddy: A Study of Choice.’’ Journal of Economic Behavior and Organi-
Escalating Commitment to a Chosen Course of zation, 1, 1980, 39–60.
Action.’’ Organizational Behavior and Human Per- ———. Quasi-Rational Economics. New York: Russell
formance, 16, 1976, 27–44. Sage Foundation, 1991.
———. ‘‘The Escalation of Commitment to a Course of Walton, D. ‘‘The Sunk Cost Fallacy or Argument from
Action.’’ Academy of Management Review, 6, 1981, Waste.’’ Argumentation, 16, 2002, 473–503.
577–87. Whyte, G. ‘‘Escalating Commitment in Individual and
Staw, B. M., and H. Hoang. ‘‘Sunk Costs in the NBA: Group Decision-Making.’’ Organizational Behavior
Why Draft Order Affects Playing Time in Profes- and Human Decision Processes, 54, 1993, 430–55.

You might also like