Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

Feature Articles

Mitigating Against Epistemic Injustice in Educational


Research
Jeff Frank1

In this article, I argue that Harvey Siegel correctly points out the limitations of epistemic diversity in educational research.
Building from Siegel’s analysis, I argue that we need to move away from the language of epistemic diversity and to the
language of epistemic injustice. Epistemic injustice allows us to do the work that epistemic diversity sets out to do—that
is, creating more inclusive epistemic practices that lead to more accurate descriptions of the world—without leading to
the untenable and unjustified conclusions that follow from using the language of epistemic diversity. Drawing on recent
work in feminist epistemology, I describe epistemic injustice and argue for its significance. I conclude by drawing out the
implications of epistemic injustice for educational researchers.

Keywords: diversity; feminist theory; philosophy; textual analysis

I
n “Epistemological Diversity and Education Research: Much Siegel’s Argument and Its Implications
Ado About Nothing Much?” Harvey Siegel (2006) argues
Siegel argues that epistemic diversity can mean—broadly—two
that “the call for epistemological diversity is not, where justi-
things. First, epistemic diversity can mean that there are multiple
fied, as radical or significant as it is often taken to be; and that,
ways of approaching the same problem. An individual who uses
where it is radical or significant, it is not justified” (p. 3). This
qualitative methods will approach a problem differently than an
argument can sound harsh and dismissive; Siegel’s tone—at
individual who uses mixed methods; a feminist researcher may
times—can give the impression that the motivation behind
approach a problem differently than a researcher who does not
epistemic diversity is insignificant: much ado about nothing
indentify as a feminist; and so on. Although each of these
much. I will argue that this impression is misleading. One can
researchers will approach the problem differently, they are all
criticize the call for epistemic diversity in education as unjusti-
investigating the same problem: Some of their approaches will be
fied or insignificant without thereby thinking that the motiva-
better suited to the problem than others, and some approaches
tion behind this call is unjustified or insignificant. Although it
will produce better data and more reliable results than others. A
may seem counterintuitive, accepting Siegel’s argument against
diversity of approaches to the problem are used, but there are
epistemic diversity may allow us to build a stronger defense of
ways of deciding which of the approaches better suit the problem,
what motivates arguments for epistemic diversity. But we can-
and there are ways of determining which approach provides the
not build this defense unless we can find a new language: a
most reliable, meaningful, illuminating, or truthful data. Siegel
language that remains responsive to the motivation to epistemic
argues that this understanding of epistemic diversity is justified
diversity without leading us into the problems—problems very
but it is not as radical or significant as proponents of epistemic
clearly described by Siegel—that follow from using the lan-
diversity think it is. Rather, this way of understanding epistemic
guage of epistemic diversity. In this article, I introduce the lan-
diversity can be understood as pluralism, an approach to episte-
guage of epistemic injustice and argue that epistemic injustice
mology that is already widely accepted.
allows us to do the work of creating more inclusive epistemic
The second way to understand epistemic diversity is that there
practices that lead to more accurate descriptions of the world.
are multiple epistemologies, and there is no way of adjudicating
Before describing epistemic injustice and making a case for its
between them: that is, if we don’t share an epistemology, then
significance as an alternative to the language of epistemic diver-
there is no way for us to determine—through discussion or argu-
sity, it is important to understand why someone who supports
mentation—what is the case. What is true for you is true for you,
a more inclusive vision of educational research should—even
though it may seem counterintuitive—accept Siegel’s criticisms
of epistemic diversity. 1Sweet Briar College, Sweet Briar, VA

Educational Researcher, Vol. 42 No. 7, pp. 363–370


DOI: 10.3102/0013189X12457812
© 2013 AERA. http://er.aera.net
October 2013 363
what is true for me is true for me; that is the end of the story. This I can very clearly see the motivation behind the more radical—if
relativistic understanding of epistemic diversity, according to unjustified—form of epistemic diversity criticized by Siegel.
Siegel, leads to the conclusion: “all research efforts are equally (il) Proponents of sexual harassment laws, for example, often find
legitimate or that any approach to (or product of ) research is as themselves wondering: How can anyone think that an unwanted
good as any other” (p. 4). When we reach this conclusion, it fol- sexual advance—especially in an asymmetrical power relation
lows that “there would be no point in conducting research, (like that of boss and subordinate or teacher and student)—is
because any result would either be worthless or stand on an equal anything but offensive and unethical? When proponents of sex-
epistemological footing with any alternative result” (p. 4). By ual harassment laws and their critics continue to find themselves
putting the matter this way, Siegel highlights how the relativistic at odds over a question as basic as this, it can seem like these
understanding of epistemic diversity—because it leads to these groups of individuals do not share the same world. As such, it
types of untenable conclusions—is self-defeating and unjustified. makes sense that someone in this situation might claim: “We
Here again I think Siegel is correct. Siegel notes that standpoint know the truth of harassment; if no one else can accept it, at least
theory, for example, is premised on the idea that perspectives we know that it is true for us.” This type of reasoning leads to the
drawn from the margins of any given discourse are not only dif- problematic relativist position described above, but it is impor-
ferent from mainstream perspectives1 but they result in more tant to see the motivation behind it. Proponents of sexual harass-
truthful representations of the world (p. 8). Elizabeth Anderson ment laws know they have discovered the truth of our social
(1995) makes this point clearly and forcefully in her discussion world, but because of resistance to this truth, it is understandable
of feminist epistemology. Feminist epistemology starts from dif- why they might make relativistic claims. Still, this relativist posi-
ferent assumptions and holds different concerns than other tion—though understandable—is epistemologically unjustified
approaches to epistemology, but it ends by offering better—more and politically ineffective. As such, we need to find another way
accurate, more insightful, more meaningful, truer—descriptions out of the impasse: Instead of reverting back to relativism in the
of the world than its competitors. Although it is a different face of challenges from individuals and groups who do not accept
approach to epistemology, it is not relativistic; its aim is to pres- the truth of, for example, sexual harassment, we need to more
ent a picture of the world that can—and should—be accepted as effectively understand the reasons behind dismissals of harass-
more accurate or more truthful than its alternatives. ment as a step to creating strategies that more adequately address
In addition, we need to appreciate the political implications this dismissal in epistemologically justified and politically effec-
of epistemic relativism.2 If we maintain a relativistic understand- tive ways.
ing of epistemology, then it is difficult to see how widespread It is important to develop an understanding of why the truth
political change is possible. For example, if we accept a relativistic of harassment continues to be dismissed.3 Two main reasons
understanding of epistemology, then someone who has the power come to mind. First, I think it is the case that truth established
to act on knowledge that runs counter to her beliefs or belief outside of the mainstream has a harder time gaining a serious
system has no compelling reason to do so. But if knowledge gen- hearing as the truth. Even though the true nature of harassment
erated by the researcher (who, for example, is marginally posi- has been established—in scholarship and in practice—as the
tioned in and by society) is true—not just true for the person or truth, because this truth originated outside of the mainstream,
people generating the knowledge but true regardless of where one and because many important developments in sexual harass-
is positioned in society—then those with power would be unrea- ment thinking continue to occur outside of mainstream chan-
sonable to ignore or deny that truth. For example, if the experi- nels, there appears to be a resistance to this truth. Because
ence of sexual harassment as experienced by the harassed—who feminism and feminist epistemology allowed the truth of harass-
sees harassment as an insulting, dehumanizing, immoral act— ment to develop and gain the status it has today, it is possible to
were true for her but not for her harasser—who sees harassment discredit this truth as biased—or less than true—because of its
as “boys being boys,” or “not a big deal” and so see its enforce- birth in epistemological practices that readily acknowledge val-
ment as something like “political correctness gone awry”—then ues and commitments that are not shared by other, more seem-
it would be difficult to compel the harasser to see his actions as ingly value-neutral approaches to epistemology. Even though we
unethical, because we would be unable to demonstrate that should accept Siegel’s criticism of epistemic diversity, we need to
harassment as experienced by the harassed is the true nature of appreciate that researchers who use methodologies that deviate
harassment. But if we establish the truth of harassment—the most from mainstream epistemological practices have the most
truth as experienced more pressingly by the harassed, a truth gen- difficult time getting a fair hearing. Even though these method-
erated from that reality—as true for all of us, then we can create ologies offer viable descriptions of the world that we share in
and enforce policies aimed at eradicating sexual harassment common, it remains far too easy to dismiss these methodologies
(Fricker, 2007, p. 149 ff.). In order to bring about meaningful and the results generated from these methodologies without giv-
political change, we need to embrace pluralism and not relativism ing them serious consideration. If we cannot even hear these new
in epistemology (Fricker, 2000). types of truth, it is impossible to see how they can ever be given
The true nature of harassment—the truth generated by indi- anything like the neutral evaluation defended by Siegel and
viduals who experience harassment, but a truth that everyone required by pluralism.4 They deserve this type of evaluation, but
should accept as true—is slowly gaining acceptance as the truth. it is important to acknowledge that this type of evaluative frame-
Nonetheless, it continues to be easily downplayed, especially by work does not exist yet. As such, we need to find a way of
the harassers, or those who enable harassment by excusing it; by addressing this type of epistemic silencing in order to create
downplaying the true nature of harassment’s harm. Here is where more robust epistemic practices.

364 EDUCATIONAL RESEARCHER


Second, in addition to a general distrust of a truth developed Epistemic Injustice and Educational Research
outside of the mainstream, claims for truth that are clearly marked
Where one is positioned within culture is epistemically signifi-
by their outsider status—in language, style of argumentation, and
cant. As Miranda Fricker (2012) argues,
concerns—can feel threatening. For example, arguments for
“White privilege” or “heteronormativity”—if accepted as true—
If we want to achieve a full understanding of a human practice,
would have far-reaching implications. If we take seriously the idea social phenomenon, or pattern of relationships, then we must
that epistemic, ethical, and political practices are marked by take up the point of view of those on the losing end. If you are the
White privilege or heteronormativity, and if an individual is cur- one doing the crushing . . . then not only are you not in a position
rently positioned to benefit from these practices, we may want to to know what it is like to be crushed, but also—and this is a
wonder: Can an individual so positioned fairly and impartially separate point—your general picture of the social world in which
judge these arguments when if she accepts them as true she could such crushings take place will be in an unhelpfully partial per-
lose her status and the benefits that follow from it? In a sense, this spective, the perspective of the powerful. (p. 288)
question can only be answered case by case. But in general, I think
we should be troubled by this line of questioning if we are inter- Fricker makes two points here. First, an individual or a group of
ested in the type of pluralism in epistemology Siegel advocates. individuals positioned on the disempowered end of a social sys-
We should wonder: If my work is being published in leading edu- tem will often have different perspectives on that system than
cational journals, for example, and a group of scholars in my field those positioned with power in the system. Second, the perspec-
claim that those leading journals are biased—in the types of meth- tives of those on the disempowered end of the social spectrum
ods they deem legitimate, the types of concerns and styles of writ- are often invisible to those with power. Because those with power
ing they deem appropriate—will I be able to understand and cannot see the existence of the perspectives of the disempowered,
impartially evaluate this type of criticism? I would like to believe they have an unhelpfully partial view of the social world they live
that we can, but achieving this impartiality will involve a very in. Nonetheless, those with power often determine what per-
great deal of effort. As literature in teacher education illustrates, spectives are important and worth listening to. If the perspec-
future teachers resist acknowledging the truth of their privilege tives of those positioned without power in our social world go
and its multiple effects (Cochran-Smith, 2003; Delpit, 1995; unheard, then our collective epistemic resources are less robust
Ladson-Billings, 1994, 1995; Tatum, 1992, 1994, 1997; Villegas than they otherwise would be. This situation is one of epistemic
& Lucas, 2002). I don’t see why future researchers would be any injustice. Those without power are silenced and this leads to an
less resistant. To realize pluralism in educational research, it is incomplete and inaccurate vision of the social world. One of the
important to address this resistance; we need to understand the main benefits of using the language of epistemic injustice—as
potential for conflicts between truth and privilege, and see the opposed to remaining with the language of epistemic diversity—
difficulty of accepting a truth that destabilizes our status and is that we are able to articulate why everyone—even, or espe-
threatens the benefits that follows from that status. cially, those positioned with power in the social world as it is
Fear of losing privilege and distrust of truth established out- currently configured—should take a diversity of voices seriously.
side of the mainstream are two reasons why we should worry that We silence large segments of the community of knowers of
we can dismiss the truth of an argument before we give it a fair which we are all a part at our own peril. The truth of our social
hearing. If we worry about this—if we worry that achieving the world will elude us until we learn what it means to hear across
neutrality advocated for by Siegel cannot happen if we don’t sig- the social spectrum.5
nificantly rethink the way that educational researchers are edu- In Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing, Fricker
cated—then I think we can also see the need for a new way of (2007) argues that our epistemic practices lead to silencing, and
understanding epistemology that allows us to create more inclu- she illustrates how this type of silence causes us to lose epistemic
sive epistemological practices that are not subject to the episte- resources that can provide us with a more truthful picture of our
mological and political limitations associated with epistemic social world than we currently have. In particular, Fricker is con-
diversity. In order to create this understanding, we need to move cerned with the practice of testimony and she is concerned with
away from the language of epistemic diversity and to the language how knowledge is generated and validated. In the first case—
of epistemic injustice. By bringing injustice to the fore, I mean to what Fricker labels testimonial injustice—an individual is treated
stress that accepting pluralism does not mean that issues related unethically in her capacity as a knower. In the second case—what
to privilege or issues related to difficulties of understanding and Fricker labels hermeneutical injustice—an individual experiences
evaluating methodologies positioned outside of the mainstream “the injustice of having some significant area of one’s social expe-
are unimportant. Rather, stressing injustice in epistemology rience obscured from collective understanding owing to herme-
reminds us that we cannot get an accurate picture of our world if neutical marginalization” (p. 158).
we cannot hear the arguments of individuals who argue differ-
Testimonial Injustice
ently than we do, or who emphasize different aspects of the world
as salient, or who question whether the authority we have estab- Testimonial injustice requires less discussion than hermeneutical
lished for ourselves is due to unearned privilege or to the truthful- injustice. I believe we are familiar with a number of cases where
ness of our arguments. We will never be able to do any of these an individual can convey relevant information to someone with
things—and so consign ourselves to an inaccurate and distorted the power or authority to act on that information, but the infor-
understanding of our shared world—unless we appreciate epis- mation is ignored owing to how the conveyor of knowledge is
temic injustice and the role that it plays in our own thinking. perceived. For example, we can all recall cases where knowers are

October 2013 365


perceived as less competent than they are based on their accent, and because individuals who have seen their credibility ques-
their race, their gender, their age, and so forth. Because of testi- tioned because they don’t fit that image can be resistant to speak-
monial injustice, an individual goes unheard—damaging her ing truths when they don’t trust that these truths will be
status as a competent knower—and we are unable to accurately understood—then we can see that big changes are called for in
judge the veracity of her testimony because she is prematurely graduate education. We need researchers to understand the dif-
silenced. By denying ourselves access to this information, we ficulties of listening, and we need to create an environment where
limit—if not make impossible—the possibility of finding the research participants trust that they will be heard.
truth. We should be very concerned about testimonial injustice The second implication revolves around how doctoral
because it harms the individuals who are silenced, and it harms students engage with existing research in the field. In addition
society by limiting our epistemic resources. What strikes me as to questioning the data, as discussed above, researchers should
particularly challenging about testimonial injustice is how diffi- seriously consider how they understand—and judge—quality as
cult it is to mitigate against. In order to work against testimonial it relates to published educational research. Graduate students
injustice, we must acknowledge that we have an image in our should know how the practice of peer review works and be able
mind of who a competent knower is, and we must also acknowl- to articulate its strengths and weaknesses. Journal editors do their
edge that this image can lead us astray. The paradigmatic image best to ensure that every paper submitted to a journal receives a
of a knower will generally be highly educated; “White, male, fair and unbiased hearing. But journal editors have to work with
middle class, heterosexual, able-bodied, and, more generally, what they have: a preexisting editorial board and the reviewers
privileged” (to use Siegel’s phrasing); and speak Standard English. who agree to review a paper. If a journal editor of a highly
This list is not meant to be exhaustive; it is meant to illustrate regarded or highly ranked journal receives a paper using a meth-
that knowers who fit the paradigm tend to be given credibility odology she is unfamiliar with, and if this methodology has not
(causing us to be too trusting in some cases), whereas individuals been published in the journal before, then it is possible that the
who don’t are often given less credibility than they deserve. If we editor may determine that the paper is not a good fit for the
take testimonial injustice seriously as a potential wrong, then I journal and reject the paper before it is reviewed externally. If this
think there at least two major implications for education. is the way the journal operates, then it is difficult to see how new
The first implication is that in the process of learning to methodologies will find their way into that highly ranked and
become an educational researcher, discussions of testimonial highly regarded journal. Second, even if this hypothetical journal
injustice should play some role. Although many qualitative editor decides to send the paper out for review, if she is not famil-
researchers are already aware of the difficulties of listening, and iar with the methodology, and if the journal has not published
can appreciate how a researcher’s subjectivity can keep her from work using that methodology, then it is likely that it will be hard
attending to the truth of what a participant is expressing, the for that journal editor to find good reviewers for the paper. The
significance of testimonial injustice extends beyond the imme- editor will have to rely on her best judgment for finding review-
diacy of interviews, focus groups, and observations. In addition ers, and then she will have to do her best to determine if the
to wondering how well we are listening, we have to consider the reviewers are fair and accurate. In some cases, the review process
representativeness of who we are listening to; we need to ask: Am will work adequately, but it is reasonable to believe that strong
I listening to the group of people who know this situation best, pieces are rejected simply because the editor has an understand-
or am I selecting a sample based on how closely it resembles what ably difficult time managing the review process. Because of this,
I take to be the image of the paradigmatic knower? As well, testi- strong papers can end up being published in lower ranked or less
monial injustice reminds us that certain knowers are used to hav- highly regarded journals. If this is the case, then future educa-
ing their credibility discounted prematurely. Expecting that their tional researchers need to be aware that the top journals in the
testimony will be misheard, misconstrued, or discounted, they field are not the only place to look for excellent educational
choose not to speak or to speak in ways that intentionally mislead research. This is not a relativistic point; it is a very practical one.
the researcher (Dotson, 2011). Again, this type of point is recog- Compounding this practical difficulty is the potential of
nized by many qualitative researchers, but the implications of a reviewer bias. Again, I don’t think wholesale skepticism or relativ-
point like this extend beyond the training of qualitative research- ism is called for when considering the peer review process, but it
ers. Educational researchers—in general—need to worry about is important to consider the difficulties an author faces when she
the quality of data generated from individuals who have their chooses to write in a way that is clearly marked—in language,
credibility as knowers discounted on a regular basis. Although style of argumentation, and concerns—as outside of the main-
individuals who participate in research studies may give us the stream of work published in the journal she is submitting to or
information they think we are capable of hearing, how can we the field she is working in. We have to acknowledge that work
make it so that research participants share the difficult truths that like this has a hard time getting published, as it very clearly is not
they don’t think we are capable of hearing? Unless we understand a “good fit” for the journal as it is currently configured. Moreover,
the full extent of this problem—there are large numbers of indi- when an author writes in this way—a way that clearly marks the
viduals who feel as if the truth of their experience is something paper as outside of the mainstream—then we have to wonder if
that very few people can understand, or care to understand—we this type of writing will lead reviewers and editors to withhold
will continue to act as if our picture of the social world is more judgments of credibility based on the image of a competent
inclusive than it actually is. If we are worried that we aren’t get- knower discussed above.
ting the best data possible in education—both because we haven’t A clear retort to this line of thinking is that authors, if they
learned to listen beyond our image of the paradigmatic knower want to be published, should conform to the ideals of the practice

366 EDUCATIONAL RESEARCHER


of journal reviewing and publishing as it currently stands. of the knower’s race, gender, accent, etc. Hermeneutical injustice
Although this is sound pragmatic advice, if followed, it would is different because it doesn’t involve—in such a clear and direct
lead to significantly less epistemic diversity in the field than if it way—culpability for silencing, and discrediting, another person
were resisted. In addition, although I believe that it is important in her capacity as a knower. Rather, hermeneutical injustice arises
to establish points of connection with work that is already pub- when an individual cannot make sense of her experience because
lished, and although it is important to be responsive to work that of a lack of available collective epistemic resources. A striking
is already published, making conformity to the language, style of example of hermeneutical injustice, for Fricker (2006, 2007), is
argumentation and concerns of the field as it is currently config- sexual harassment. Fricker describes how the concept of sexual
ured a condition for publication strikes me as deeply misguided. harassment developed. Carmita Wood, who worked at Cornell
Not because epistemic diversity is in itself a good, but because University as a departmental assistant, worked for a senior faculty
many of the problems that continue to concern educational member in the department who, as Wood told the story, “would
researchers—the academic performance gap; the segregation, jiggle his crotch when he stood near her desk and looked at his
desegregation, and resegregation of schools; widespread sexual mail, or he’d deliberately brush against her breasts while reaching
harassment in schools—are, as I see it, particularly amenable to for some papers. One night as the lab workers were leaving their
new and diverse methods. One clear—if possibly overly used— annual Christmas party, he cornered her in the elevator and
example of this comes to mind. When W. E. B. Du Bois (1903) planted some unwanted kisses on her mouth” (Fricker, 2006, p.
was working on The Souls of Black Folk, the language of sociology 96, citing Brownmiller). Wood tried to avoid the faculty mem-
was dominated by the voice of the “car-window sociologist.” ber, experienced medical symptoms that made her work difficult,
Although these sociologists “gleefully count his bastards and his requested a transfer to another department, and when the request
prostitutes, the very soul of the toiling, sweating black man is was denied, she quit. When she applied for unemployment insur-
darkened by the shadow of a vast despair.” In order to present a ance, “the claims investigator asked why she had left her job after
more truthful picture of what it means to be Black in America, eight years, Wood was at a loss to describe the hateful episodes.
Du Bois created a work that expands what it means to write soci- She was ashamed and embarrassed. Under prodding—the blank
ology. Although he employed many of the traditional methods of on the form needed to be filled in—she answered that her reasons
sociology, he also used fiction, mythology, autobiography, poetry, had been personal. Her claim for unemployment benefits was
and song. By using a diversity of methods, Du Bois was able to denied” (ibid.). Only after Wood began speaking with a group of
create a more truthful vision of Black experience in America than other women with similar experiences—as part of the process of
existed in print before he wrote. When undertaking our work as working with feminist lawyers who were appealing her insurance
reviewers and readers of journals, we have to wonder how the claim—did she realize how to describe her reason for leaving her
car-window sociologist felt when reading Du Bois, and we have job: She had been sexually harassed.
to ask ourselves if we are falling into habits of mind that lead us Before Wood had a language for her experience, she suffered
to automatically reject new types of work using new and different a tremendous epistemic and ethical disadvantage. Because the
methodologies as a nonfit, or if we discount a work’s credibility language of harassment was not available, Wood was unable to
because it doesn’t conform to our vision of the type of work a make adequate sense of her experience—causing a gap in her
competent knower produces. capacity as a self-knower—and she was unable to speak in a way
To conclude, if testimonial injustice is a real issue, then how that would illicit just treatment from others: from the individual
we gather and interpret data collected from privileged knowers causing the harassment to the organization that denied her
and knowers used to having their testimony discounted will need unemployment insurance. Hermeneutical injustice arises when
to be made an object of serious consideration. As well, how we an individual is unable to make adequate sense of her experience
understand quality—of journals and of individual papers—will because of a lack of socially available epistemic resources; unable
also need to be reconsidered. Although a wholesale rejection of to make full sense of her experience, she is at a disadvantage when
the peer review process is ill advised, it is important for future she attempts to seek redress for wrongs that she experiences. An
educational researchers to know how the process works, and how important component of Fricker’s analysis is the idea of herme-
the process can cause excellent work to be published in journals neutical marginalization. A poet struggling to find the right way
that may not be the most highly regarded in the field. This will to describe the way she feels about the loss of a childhood friend
lead a future researcher to be better able to assess the quality of she didn’t maintain close ties with can be frustrating, but it is not
work across the spectrum of published work in our field, while an injustice. To qualify as a case of epistemic injustice, the know-
also giving her opportunities to think about the work she will er’s access to epistemic resources has to be limited because of
need to do in order to become the type of peer reviewer who can where she is positioned in society, or because of society’s lack of
provide a “fair-minded, non-question-begging evaluation”6 of concern with the experience she is attempting to articulate. To
work that uses methodologies different from her own, and work make this point, Fricker argues that an individual can be, in gen-
that seems, at first glance, to be a nonfit for the journal she is eral, epistemically privileged, but he can experience moments of
reviewing for. hermeneutical injustice. She illustrates this through the example
of Ian McEwan’s novel Enduring Love. In the novel, Joe, the main
Hermeneutical Injustice
character, is stalked by another man. When Joe tries to articulate
In the case of testimonial injustice, a knower is treated unjustly his concerns to the police, he is not taken seriously. Joe’s concern
because another individual, or group of individuals, discounts as a man being stalked by another man is underconceptualized in
her capacity to convey truthful and accurate testimony because his society, and because of this, he is not able to make others see

October 2013 367


the harm he is enduring and so cannot seek adequate redress. To preemptively dismissed, because, attuned to what is not immedi-
qualify as a case of epistemic injustice, the individual knower is ately present within the experienced world of the dominantly
left unable to have his or her experience make sense—or be taken situated knower, such resources can appear to the dominantly
seriously—by other knowers because of a general social lack of situated knower to attend to nothing at all, or to make something
out of nothing. (p. 8)
concern for that type of experience.
The implications of this form of injustice are more difficult to
If you don’t experience the world as a place where you can be
draw out than in the case of testimonial injustice, because the
demeaned—overtly and through microaggressions—in multiple
injustice is not clearly perpetuated by any single individual. If
ways each day, it is easy to dismiss the truth of arguments that
society, in general, is not concerned with finding ways to express
draw attention to demeaning behaviors; behaviors that, to you,
the harm of sexual harassment, how is individual responsibility
don’t seem all that harmful or demeaning (if they even appear on
possible?7 In the case of harassment, we would like to be able to
the radar at all). Instead of taking the time to see what it would
blame the individual harasser: he should, even in absence of the
mean for these types of arguments to make sense, they are pre-
concept of sexual harassment, know better. We might think the
emptively dismissed because they fail to speak to what is “imme-
same way when it comes to how the police treated Joe. Even
diately present within the experienced world of the dominantly
though Joe’s concerns may be different from the types of concerns
situated knower.” Although there is an understandable side to
they normally hear, the police should nonetheless be more con-
this ignorance—it is difficult to appreciate and assess aspects of
cerned than they are. In a way, Fricker acknowledges that these
the world that you are not used to attending to—this under-
individuals should know better. She argues that as individuals we
standable difficulty is not exculpating. In fact, the difficulty of
can create micro-climates of hermeneutical justice by showing a
attending to aspects of the world that we are not used to seeing is
willingness to listen and engage in dialogue that helps an indi-
often hard to disentangle from an active attempt to not see any-
vidual attempt to make sense of her experience with us (Fricker,
thing that challenges our sense of the world. For example, a
2007, pp. 169-175). Instead of dismissing the concerns of an
White man’s fear that accepting the truth of “White privilege”
individual struggling to make sense of her experience, we help the
could have, as it were, a cascading effect: toppling false beliefs
individual develop ways of understanding her experience that are
that force him to reconsider everything from the meaning of
shareable with others and that can be used to motivate social
words and ideas previous taken as obvious—like work, hard
change. Although there is a lot to commend this view—it
work, success, reward, opportunity, a good school—to areas he
acknowledges the power of social norms, while allowing for the
never gave any serious thought—like the connection between
possibility that individuals can resist and change those norms—
chattel slavery and current social arrangements; the costs of col-
Fricker’s view of hermeneutical injustice has recently been criti-
orblind policies and ways of thinking; the effects and significance
cized for (a) discounting the epistemic resources created
of things like White flight. Because his epistemic worldview
by individuals who experience an injustice and (b) failing to
seems to work well enough as it is, it is easy to see why fear of
account for the significance of individuals who willfully refuse to
new ways of thinking might lead to a willful ignorance of them.
accept the validity of epistemic resources developed by the indi-
Pohlhaus puts it this way: “When a group with material power
viduals experiencing injustice (see Dotson, 2011; Mason, 2011;
is vested in ignoring certain parts of the world, they can, there-
Pohlhaus, in press).
fore, maintain their ignorance by refusing to recognize and by
Pohlhaus (in press) most forcefully illustrates these important
actively undermining any newly generated epistemic resource
limitations of Fricker’s conceptualization of hermeneutical injus-
that attends to those parts of the world that they are vested in
tice by introducing willful hermeneutical ignorance: “willful her-
ignoring” (p. 14). By drawing our attention to willful epistemic
meneutical ignorance describes instances where marginally
ignorance, Pohlhaus shows that individuals have the power to
situated knowers actively resist epistemic domination through
block the circulation and validation of truthful arguments that
interaction with other resistant knowers, while dominantly situ-
are in what they take to be their best interest to block. When
ated knowers nonetheless continue to misunderstand and misin-
Fricker recounts the birth of the concept of sexual harassment,
terpret the world” (p. 2). The truth of sexual harassment is
she seems to suggest that everyone is harmed—though certainly
established by marginalized knowers, and the creation of this type
not equally harmed—without the concept of sexual harassment.
of epistemic resource is ongoing. As such, Pohlhaus doesn’t
Men who would have acted better had they known the fuller
believe that marginalized knowers are at a disadvantage in their
meaning of their conduct are not given the opportunity to cor-
ability to generate truthful arguments aimed at making sense of
rect themselves, and society, as a whole, is at a loss without
their experience. Where marginalized knowers are disadvantaged
resources that provide a more truthful, more just picture of itself.
is in their ability to have these arguments taken seriously. These
Pohlhaus suggests that this account fails to take seriously how
arguments are difficult to take seriously, because they speak to
vested individuals are in maintaining ignorance and that main-
aspects of the world that are more apparent to those who lack
taining ignorance, for these individuals, can be more important
power than those who have it. Pohlhaus sees this happen
than truth or justice. As such, an important implication of
when those situated dominantly dismiss the viability of such Pohlhaus’s critical expansion of hermeneutical injustice is to show
arduously honed concepts like “white privilege,” “date rape,” that achieving the type of evaluative judgments that will allow for
or “heteronormativity.” These epistemic resources, which could a more truthful picture of the social world involves an acknowl-
(and sometimes do) help dominantly situated knowers to edgment of the role that willful hermeneutical ignorance plays in
know the world in light of marginalized situatedness, can be our epistemic practices.

368 EDUCATIONAL RESEARCHER


One main implication of willful hermeneutical ignorance in Epistemic injustice offers a better framework for doing this
doctoral education is that researchers need to see how their posi- type of work than epistemic diversity does. This is so for at least
tion in society can influence what they are capable of seeing—or two reasons. First, epistemic injustice takes seriously what moti-
willing to see—as valuable and useful. When students are pre- vates the call for epistemic diversity without leading to the unjus-
sented with resources that are developed by individuals who do tified epistemological conclusions highlighted by Siegel. Second,
not share the researcher’s background or position in society, the epistemic injustice refocuses our attention on the importance
students cannot assume that they can immediately adequately of reforming our shared epistemic practices so that we can pro-
judge those resources; they need to understand that nonepistemic duce the most accurate picture of the social world that we
factors, like their social privilege, have the power to undermine are capable of creating. If we maintain a relativistic understand-
their ability to accurately determine the value and utility of these ing of epistemology—what is true for you is true for you, what
types of resources. On a more positive note, willful hermeneutical is true for me is true for me—then it is hard to make the case that
injustice reminds us that new resources are being generated by transformative learning experiences are necessary. But if we can
individuals-in-communities (Grasswick, 2004) outside of the see that others might be better able to speak to the truth of our
mainstream epistemic channels and that these resources have the shared experience than we are, then we are in a better position to
power to paint a more truthful picture of our social world. As start doing the difficult work of learning what is true, even if this
Pouhlaus writes, means coming to terms with the privilege-induced vision we use
to filter experience through. If we can do this, then we might
When one genuinely cares to know something about the world achieve the neutrality demanded by epistemology; if not, our
as experienced from social positions other than one’s own, one best attempts to achieve the truth will be stymied by epistemic
must use epistemic resources suited to (and developed from) injustice.
those situations. Prerequisites for acquiring such resources are,
first, to allow the resources to be well developed by persons situ- Notes
ated in them; second, to trust those persons to have developed
1This term is difficult to define, because it is broad and can mean
them well; and third, to take an interest in learning to use those
resources. Or course, where one stands in relation to others may different things that are nonetheless related closely enough to merit
influence whether one does or does not decide to take such an using the same term. One sense of mainstream is what is generally
interest, a decision that reveals one’s moral and epistemic char- accepted as excellent. For example, work published in certain journals—
acter. (p. 17) Teachers College Record, Harvard Educational Review, the AERA
journals—is generally regarded as excellent. Using this understanding of
Can the process of learning to become an educational researcher the term, an article published in a top journal—as measured, e.g., by the
include more opportunities to support the development of various journal-ranking metrics (ISI, Eigenfactor)—will generally be
considered more mainstream than a paper published in a less highly
resources within communities outside of the academy; can it
ranked journal. A related point; these top journals often publish—or
teach future researchers to trust the individuals developing these give the impression of publishing—a certain type of work: work that
resources, even if they work outside of the academy; can it teach employs similar methodologies or shares a similar sense of what prob-
future researchers to take a serious interest in learning what it lems in education are important. Authors who use different methodolo-
might mean to use those resources? If we see epistemic injustice gies than those used in these journals or authors who focus on different
as a threat that can keep us from ever achieving a true picture of problems than those focused on in these journals are often considered
our social world, then we might be able to seriously engage with farther outside of the mainstream. Finally, some researchers—even
these types of questions and, in the process, rethink how educa- researchers who publish in top journals, even authors on the editorial
tional researchers are educated.8 boards of top journals—consider themselves as outside of the main-
stream given the methods they use, the problems they consider impor-
Conclusions tant, the style with which they write. I will use the term mainstream to
encompass all of these senses. While this may be confusing, I think it is
If we are going to create educational research that is responsive to an accurate use of the term.
the concerns of individuals outside of schools of education, we 2This is a point that Siegel doesn’t make explicitly in the paper under
need to learn what it means to hear those concerns. Part of this consideration here, but it is a point he has addressed elsewhere (Siegel,
will involve acknowledging the impact of testimonial injustice in 1997, especially chapters 8 and 9.)
our knowledge-sharing practices, while another part will involve 3If we need evidence of this, we can look at the troubling series of

trusting that individuals are already creating epistemic resources papers written on harassment by the American Association of University
that are responsive to their own concerns. Knowers situated out- Women (AAUW, 2011, 2001) or any of the countless studies on harass-
side of the academy have access to experiences that we don’t have, ment (Brown, Chesney-Lind & Stein, 2007; Gruber & Fineran, 2008;
and have developed resources that we don’t know how to under- Lee, Croninger, Linn & Chen, 1996; Stein & Mennemeier, 2011;
stand and don’t know how to use. The existence of these experi- Meyer, 2009). As these studies show, harassment is recognized as an
illegal and unethical act in schools, but the culture of schools routinely
ences and these resources can serve as an opportunity to learn
denies and ignores its existence: this, despite the overwhelming evidence
more about our social world, and in the process we can come to of its near ubiquity in most school settings.
wonder how much of the social world we are unable to see, 4Siegel knows that neutrality is a charged term, and so makes it clear
understand, and evaluate. Learning to become an educational that he defines neutrality as a “fair-minded, non-question-begging eval-
researcher should help us see these types of limits, and it should uation of the issue, or epistemology, in question” (p. 7). This is the way
give us the knowledge, skills, and dispositions to learn how we I use the term, and though the term remains a charged one, I believe it
might grow through them. is defensible and worthy of our aspiration.

October 2013 369


5It is worth stressing a point made in the introduction. The motiva- Fricker, M. (2006). Powerlessness and social interpretation. Episteme,
tion behind diversity is epistemology is justified, but if our understand- 3, 96-108.
ing of diversity in education leads us to the conclusion that there is no Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing.
way to evaluate and judge different epistemologies, and so determine New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
which perspective—or combination of perspectives—offers the most Fricker, M. (2012). Silence and institutional prejudice. In S. Cransow
truthful or accurate picture of our social world, then we are left con- & A. Superson (Eds.), Out from the shadows: Analytical feminist
signed to our own limited vision of the world. But, if we use the language contributions to traditional philosophy. New York, NY: Oxford
of injustice, then we are given a resource that allows us to make the case University Press.
that failing to listen to a diversity of voices on a given issue will lead to a Grasswick, H. (2004). Individuals in communities. Hypatia, 19(3),
limited and less truthful vision of the world. If we care about the truth 85-120.
and accuracy of our work, then we will need to be sure that our epistemic Gruber, J. E., & Fineran, S. (2008). Comparing the impact of bullying
practices are as inclusive as they can reasonably expected to be. And it and sexual harassment victimization on the mental and physical
will also make us hesitant to presume a complete picture of our social health of adolescents. Sex Roles, 59, 1–13.
world if we feel that we are not confident that we have heard everything Ladson-Billings, G. (1994). The dreamkeepers: Successful teachers of
that needs to be heard on any given issue. African-American children. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
6Siegel’s (2006) definition of neutrality (pp. 7-8). Ladson-Billings, G. (1995). Toward a theory of culturally relevant
7For a closely related discussion—one that is fully centered in ethics pedagogy. American Educational Research Journal, 32, 465–491.
and not the intersections of ethics and epistemology—see Calhoun Lee, V. E., Croninger, R. G., Linn, E., & Chen, X. (1996). The culture
(1989). of sexual harassment in secondary schools. American Educational
8A clear example of this is illustrated by Elizabeth Anderson’s (2006) Research Journal, 33, 383–417.
discussion of how privileging certain ways of knowing over others can Mason, R. (2011). Two types of unknowing. Hypatia, 26, 294–307.
cause us to limit our knowledge of the world. She discusses how forestry Meyer, E. J. (2009). Gender, bullying, and harassment: Strategies to end
groups in South Asia built policies regulating the collection of firewood sexism and homophobia in schools. New York, NY: Teachers College
without taking into account the perspective of women. Because women Press.
were primarily responsible for collecting firewood, they generated epis- Pohlhaus, G, Jr. (in press). Relational knowing and epistemic injustice:
temic resources from and for this practice. Unfortunately, the policy- Toward a theory of willful hermeneutical ignorance. Hypatia.
makers did not take this knowledge into account, causing the women’s Retrieved from http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1527-
daily firewood collecting time to increase from one to two hours a day 2001.2011.01222.x/abstract
up to four to five hours a day. Ignoring epistemic resources already in Siegel, H. (1997). Rationality redeemed: Further dialogues on an educa-
existence lead to a distorted picture of the practice of firewood collec- tional ideal. New York, NY: Routledge.
tion. Instead of using the resources at hand, forestry groups ignored Siegel, H. (2006). Epistemological diversity and education research:
these resources and created policies that did not work. Much ado about nothing much? Educational Researcher, 35(2),
3–12.
References Stein, N. D., & Mennemeier, K. A. (2011). Addressing the gendered
dimensions of harassment and bullying: what domestic and sexual
American Association of University Women. (2001). Crossing the line: violence advocates need to know. Retrieved from www.vawnet.org
Sexual harassment at school. Retrieved from http://www.aauw.org/ Tatum, B. (1992). Talking about race, learning about racism: The
learn/research/crossingtheline.cfm applications of racial identity development theory. Harvard
American Association of University Women. (2011). Hostile hallways: Educational Review, 62, 1–24.
Bullying, teasing, and sexual harassment in schools. Retrieved from Tatum, B. (1994). Teaching White students about racism: The search
http://www.aauw.org/learn/research/upload/hostilehallways.pdf for White allies and the restoration of hope. Teachers College Record,
Anderson, E. (1995). Feminist epistemology: An interpretation and a 95, 462–476.
defense. Hypatia, 10(3), 50–84. Tatum, B. (1997). “Why are all the Black kids sitting together in the caf-
Anderson, E. (2006). The epistemology of democracy. Episteme, 3, eteria?” and other conversations about the development of racial iden-
8–22. tity. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Brown, L. M., Chesney-Lind, M., & Stein, N. (2007). Patriarchy mat- Villegas, A. M., & Lucas, T. (2002). Preparing culturally responsive
ters: Towards a gendered theory of teen violence and victimization. teachers: Rethinking the curriculum. Journal of Teacher Education,
Violence Against Women, 13, 1249–1273. 53, 20–32.
Calhoun, C. (1989). Responsibility and reproach. Ethics, 99, 389-
406.
AUTHOR
Cochran-Smith, M. (2003). Learning and unlearning: The education
of teacher educators. Teaching and Teacher Education, 19, 5–28. JEFF FRANK is an assistant professor at Sweet Briar College, Education
Delpit, L. (1995). Other people’s children: Cultural conflict in the class- Department, PO Box 94, Sweet Briar, Virginia 24595; jfrank@sbc.edu.
room. New York, NY: New Press. His interests focus on inclusive education and American philosophies of
Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of education, with an emphasis on African American thought.
silencing. Hypatia, 26, 236–257.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1903). The souls of Black folk. Retrieved from
http://etext.virginia.edu/toc/modeng/public/DubSoul.html Manuscript received February 13, 2012
Fricker, M. (2000). Pluralism without postmodernism. In M. Fricker Revisions received May 9, 2012; and July 7, 2012
& J Hornsby (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to feminism (pp. Accepted July 19, 2012
146–165). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

370 EDUCATIONAL RESEARCHER

You might also like