Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 30

THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY

The Structure Of Evolutionary Theory


S T E P H E N J AY G O U L D

The Structure Of
Evolutionary Theory

the belknap press of


harvard university press
cambridge, massachusetts
and london, england
Copyright © 2002 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Gould, Stephen Jay.


The structure of evolutionary theory / Stephen Jay Gould.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references (p. )
ISBN 0-674-00613-5 (alk. paper)
1. Evolution (Biology) 2. Punctuated equilibrium (Evolution) I. Title.

QH366.2 .G663 2002


576.8—dc21 2001043556
For Niles Eldredge and Elisabeth Vrba
May we always be the Three Musketeers
Prevailing with panache
From our manic and scrappy inception at Dijon
To our nonsatanic and happy reception at Doomsday
All For One and One For All
Contents

Chapter 1:
Defining and Revising the Structure of Evolutionary Theory 1

Part I, Chapters 2–7


The History of Darwinian Logic and Debate 91

Segue to Part II 585

Part II, Chapters 8–12


Towards a Revised and Expanded Evolutionary Theory 593

Bibliography 1344
Illustration Credits 1388
Index 1393

vii
Expanded Contents

Chapter 1: Defining and Revising the Structure


of Evolutionary Theory 1

Theories Need Both Essences and Histories 1

The Structure of Evolutionary Theory: Revising the Three Central
Features of Darwinian Logic 12

Apologia Pro Vita Sua 24
A Time to Keep 24
A Personal Odyssey 33

Epitomes for a Long Development 48
Levels of Potential Originality 48
An Abstract of One Long Argument 53

Part I: The History of Darwinian Logic and Debate

Chapter 2: The Essence of Darwinism and the Basis of


Modern Orthodoxy: An Exegesis of the Origin of Species 93

A Revolution in the Small 93

Darwin as a Historical Methodologist 97
One Long Argument 97
The Problem of History 99
A Fourfold Continuum of Methods for the Inference of History 103

Darwin as a Philosophical Revolutionary 116
The Causes of Nature’s Harmony 116
Darwin and William Paley 116
Darwin and Adam Smith 121
The First Theme: The Organism as the Agent of Selection 125

ix
x Contents

The Second Theme: Natural Selection as a Creative Force 137


The Requirements for Variation 141
Copious 141
Small 143
Undirected 144
Gradualism 146
The Adaptationist Program 155
The Third Theme: The Uniformitarian Need to Extrapolate:
Environment as Enabler of Change 159

Judgments of Importance 163

Chapter 3: Seeds of Hierarchy 170



Lamarck and the Birth of Modern Evolutionism in
Two-Factor Theories 170
The Myths of Lamarck 170
Lamarck as a Source 174
Lamarck’s Two-Factor Theory: Sources for the Two Parts 175
The First Set: Environment and Adaptation 176
The Second Set: Progress and Taxonomy 179
Distinctness of the Two Sets 181
Lamarck’s Two-Factor Theory: The Hierarchy of
Progress and Deviation 175
Antinomies of the Two-Factor Theory 189

An Interlude on Darwin’s Reaction 192

No Allmacht without Hierarchy: Weissman on Germinal Selection 197
The Allmacht of Selection 197
Weismann’s Argument on Lamarck and the Allmacht of Selection 201
The Problem of Degeneration and Weismann’s Impetus for
Germinal Selection 203
Some Antecedents to Hierarchy in German Evolutionary Thought 208
Haeckel’s Descriptive Hierarchy in Levels of Organization 208
Roux’s Theory of Intracorporeal Struggle 210
Germinal Selection as a Helpmate to Personal Selection 214
Germinal Selection as a Full Theory of Hierarchy 219

Hints of Hierarchy in Supraorganismal Selection:
Darwin on the Principle of Divergence 224
Divergence and the Completion of Darwin’s System 224
The Genesis of Divergence 232
Contents xi

Divergence as a Consequence of Natural Selection 234


The Failure of Darwin’s Argument and the Need for
Species Selection 236
The Calculus of Individual Success 238
The Causes of Trends 240
Species Selection Based on Propensity for Extinction 246
Postscript: Solution to the Problem of the “Delicate Arrangement” 248

Coda 249

Chapter 4: Internalism and Laws of Form:


Pre-Darwinian Alternatives to Functionalism 251

Prologue: Darwin’s Fateful Decision 251

Two Ways to Glorify God in Nature 260
William Paley and British Functionalism: Praising God in the
Details of Design 262
Louis Agassiz and Continental Formalism: Praising God in the
Grandeur of Taxonomic Order 271
An Epilog on the Dichotomy 278

Unity of Plan as the Strongest Version of Formalism:
The Pre-Darwinian Debate 281
Mehr Licht on Goethe’s Leaf 281
Geoffroy and Cuvier 291
Cuvier and Conditions of Existence 291
Geoffroy’s Formalist Vision 298
The Debate of 1830: Foreplay and Aftermath 304
Richard Owen and English Formalism:
The Archetype of Vertebrates 312
No Formalism Please, We’re British 312
The Vertebrate Archetype: Constraint and Nonadaptation 316
Owen and Darwin 326

Darwin’s Strong but Limited Interest in Structural Constraint 330
Darwin’s Debt to Both Poles of the Dichotomy 330
Darwin on Correlation of Parts 332
The “Quite Subordinate Position” of Constraint to Selection 339

Chapter 5: The Fruitful Facets of Galton’s Polyhedron:


Channels and Saltations in Post-Darwinian Formalism 342

Galton’s Polyhedron 342
xii Contents


Orthogenesis as a Theory of Channels and One-Way Streets:
the Marginalization of Darwinism 351
Misconceptions and Relative Frequencies 351
Theodor Eimer and the Ohnmacht of Selection 355
Alpheus Hyatt: An Orthogenetic Hard Line from the
World of Mollusks 365
C.O. Whitman: An Orthogenetic Dove in Darwin’s
World of Pigeons 383

Saltation as a Theory of Internal Impetus: A Second Formalist Strategy
for Pushing Darwinism to a Causal Periphery 396
William Bateson: The Documentation of Inherent Discontinuity 396
Hugo de Vries: A Most Reluctant Non-Darwinian 415
Dousing the Great Party of 1909 415
The (Not So Contradictory) Sources of the Mutation Theory 418
The Mutation Theory: Origin and Central Tenets 425
Darwinism and the Mutation Theory 439
Confusing Rhetoric and the Personal Factor 439
The Logic of Darwinism and Its Different Place in
de Vries’ System 443
De Vries on Macroevolution 446
Richard Goldschmidt’s Appropriate Role as a Formalist
Embodiment of All that Pure Darwinism Must Oppose 451

Chapter 6: Pattern and Progress on the Geological Stage 467



Darwin and the Fruits of Biotic Competition 467
A Geological License for Progress 467
The Predominance of Biotic Competition and Its Sequelae 470

Uniformity on the Geological Stage 479
Lyell’s Victory in Fact and Rhetoric 479
Catastrophism as Good Science: Cuvier’s Essay 484
Darwin’s Geological Need and Kelvin’s Odious Spectre 492
A Question of Time (Too Little Geology) 496
A Question of Direction (Too Much Geology) 497

Chapter 7: The Modern Synthesis as a Limited Consensus 503



Why Synthesis? 503

Synthesis as Restriction 505
The Initial Goal of Rejecting Old Alternatives 505
Contents xiii

R. A. Fisher and the Darwinian Core 508


J. B. S. Haldane and the Initial Pluralism of the Synthesis 514
J. S. Huxley: Pluralism of the Type 516

Synthesis as Hardening 518
The Later Goal of Exalting Selection’s Power 518
Increasing Emphasis on Selection and Adaptation between the
First (1937) and Last (1951) Edition of Dobzhansky’s Genetics
and the Origin of Species 524
The Shift in G. G. Simpson’s Explanation of “Quantum Evolution”
from Drift and Nonadaptation (1944) to the Embodiment of Strict
Adaptation (1953) 528
Mayr at the Inception (1942) and Codification (1963): Shifting
from the “Genetic Consistency” to the “Adaptationist” Paradigm 531
Why Hardening? 541

Hardening on the Other Two Legs of the Darwinian Tripod 543
Levels of Selection 544
Extrapolation into Geological Time 556

From Overstressed Doubt to Overextended Certainty 566
A Tale of Two Centennials 566
All Quiet on the Textbook Front 576
Adaptation and Natural Selection 577
Reduction and Trivialization of Macroevolution 579

Segue to Part II 585

Part II: Towards a Revised and Expanded


Evolutionary Theory

Chapter 8: Species as Individuals in the Hierarchical


Theory of Selection 595

The Evolutionary Definition of Individuality 595
An Individualistic Prolegomenon 595
The Meaning of Individuality and the Expansion of the Darwinian
Research Program 597
Criteria for Vernacular Individuality 602
Criteria for Evolutionary Individuality 608

The Evolutionary Definition of Selective Agency and the Fallacy of
Selfish Genes 613
xiv Contents

A Fruitful Error of Logic 613


Hierarchical vs. Genic Selectionism 614
The Distinction of Replicators and Interactors as a
Framework for Discussion 615
Faithful Replication as the Central Criterion for the Gene-
Centered View of Evolution 616
Sieves, Plurifiers, and the Nature of Selection: The Rejection of
Replication as a Criterion of Agency 619
Interaction as the Proper Criterion for Identifying
Units of Selection 622
The Internal Incoherence of Gene Selectionism 625
Bookkeeping and Causality: The Fundamental Error of
Gene Selectionism 632
Gambits of Reform and Retreat by Gene Selectionists 637

Logical and Empirical Foundations for the Theory of
Hierarchical Selection 644
Logical Validation and Empirical Challenges 644
R. A. Fisher and the Compelling Logic of Species Selection 644
The Classical Arguments against Efficacy of
Higher-Level Selection 646
Overcoming These Classical Arguments, in Practice for
Interdemic Selection, but in Principle for Species Selection 648
Emergence and the Proper Criterion for Species Selection 652
Differential Proliferation or Downward Effect? 652
Shall Emergent Characters or Emergent Fitnesses Define the
Operation of Species Selection? 656
Hierarchy and the Sixfold Way 673
A Literary Prologue for the Two Major Properties
of Hierarchies 673
Redressing the Tyranny of the Organism: Comments on
Characteristic Features and Differences among Six
Primary Levels 681
The Gene-Individual 683
Motoo Kimura and the “Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution” 684
True Genic Selection 689
The Cell-Individual 695
The Organism-Individual 700
The Deme-Individual 701
The Species-Individual 703
Contents xv

Species as Individuals 703


Species as Interactors 704
Species Selection as Potent 709
The Clade-Individual 712

The Grand Analogy: A Speciational Basis for Macroevolution 714
Presentation of the Chart for Macroevolutionary Distinctiveness 714
The Particulars of Macroevolutionary Explanation 716
The Structural Basis 716
Criteria for Individuality 720
Contrasting Modalities of Change: The Basic Categories 721
Ontogenetic Drive: The Analogy of Lamarckism
and Anagenesis 722
Reproductive Drive: Directional Speciation as an Important
and Irreducible Macroevolutionary Mode Separate from
Species Selection 724
Species Selection, Wright’s Rule, and the Power of Interaction
with Directional Speciation 731
Species Level Drifts as More Powerful than the Analogous
Phenomena in Microevolution 735
The Scaling of External and Internal Environments 738
Summary Comments on the Strengths of Species Selection
and its Interaction with Other Macroevolutionary Causes
of Change 741

Chapter 9: Punctuated Equilibrium and the Validation of


Macroevolutionary Theory 745

What Every Paleontologist Knows 745
An Introductory Example 745
Testimonials to Common Knowledge 749
Darwinian Solutions and Paradoxes 755
The Paradox of Insulation from Disproof 758
The Paradox of Stymied Practice 761

The Primary Claims of Punctuated Equilibrium 765
Data and Definitions 765
Microevolutionary Links 774
Macroevolutionary Implications 781
Tempo and the Significance of Stasis 782
Mode and the Speciational Foundation of Macroevolution 783
xvi Contents


The Scientific Debate on Punctuated Equilibrium: Critiques
and Responses 784
Critiques Based on the Definability of Paleontological Species 784
Empirical Affirmation 784
Reasons for a Potential Systematic Underestimation of Biospecies
by Paleospecies 789
Reasons for a Potential Systematic Overestimation of Biospecies
by Paleospecies 792
Reasons Why an Observed Punctuational Pattern Might Not
Represent Speciation 793
Critiques Based on Denying Events of Speciation as the Primary
Locus of Change 796
Critiques Based on Supposed Failures of Empirical Results to
Affirm Predictions of Punctuated Equilibrium 802
Claims for Empirical Refutation by Cases 802
Phenotypes 802
Genotypes 810
Empirical Tests of Conformity with Models 812

Sources of Data for Testing Punctuated Equilibrium 822
Preamble 822
The Equilibrium in Punctuated Equilibrium: Quantitatively
Documented Patterns of Stasis in Unbranched Segments
of Lineages 824
The Punctuations of Punctuated Equilibrium: Tempo and
Mode in the Origin of Paleospecies 839
The Inference of Cladogenesis by the Criterion of
Ancestral Survival 840
The “Dissection” of Punctuations to Infer Both Existence
and Modality 850
Time 851
Geography 852
Morphometric Mode 852
Proper and Adequate Tests of Relative Frequencies: The Strong
Empirical Validation of Punctuated Equilibrium 854
The Indispensability of Data on Relative Frequencies 854
Relative Frequencies for Higher Taxa in Entire Biotas 856
Relative Frequencies for Entire Clades 866
Causal Clues from Differential Patterns of
Relative Frequencies 870
Contents xvii


The Broader Implications of Punctuated Equilibrium for
Evolutionary Theory and General Notions of Change 874
What Changes May Punctuated Equilibrium Instigate in Our
Views about Evolutionary Mechanisms and the History of Life? 874
The Explanation and Broader Meaning of Stasis 874
Frequency 875
Generality 876
Causality 877
Punctuation, the Origin of New Macroevolutionary Individuals,
and Resulting Implications for Evolutionary Theory 885
Trends 886
The Speciational Reformulation of Macroevolution 893
Life Itself 897
General Rules 901
Particular Cases 905
Horses as the Exemplar of “Life’s Little Joke” 905
Rethinking Human Evolution 908
Ecological and Higher-Level Extensions 916
Punctuation All the Way Up and Down? The Generalization and
Broader Utility of Punctuated Equilibrium (in More Than a
Metaphorical Sense) at Other Levels of Evolution, and for Other
Disciplines In and Outside the Natural Sciences 922
General Models for Punctuated Equilibrium 922
Punctuational Change at Other Levels and Scales of Evolution 928
A Preliminary Note on Homology and Analogy in the
Conceptual Realm 928
Punctuation Below the Species Level 931
Punctuation Above the Species Level 936
Stasis Analogs: Trending and Non-Trending in the Geological
History of Clades 936
Punctuational Analogs in Lineages: The Pace of
Morphological Innovation 939
Punctuational Analogs in Faunas and Ecosystems 946
Punctuational Models in Other Disciplines: Towards a
General Theory of Change 952
Principles for a Choice of Examples 952
Examples from the History of Human Artifacts and Cultures 952
Examples from Human Institutions and Theories about the
Natural World 957
xviii Contents

Two Concluding Examples, a General Statement, and a Coda 962



Appendix: A Largely Sociological (and Fully Partisan) History of
the Impact and Critique of Punctuated Equilibrium 972
The Entrance of Punctuated Equilibrium into Common Language
and General Culture 972
An Episodic History of Punctuated Equilibrium 979
Early Stages and Future Contexts 979
Creationist Misappropriation of Punctuated Equilibrium 986
Punctuated Equilibrium in Journalism and Textbooks 990
The Personal Aspect of Professional Reaction 999
The Case Ad Hominem against Punctuated Equilibrium 1000
An Interlude on Sources of Error 1010
The Wages of Jealousy 1014
The Descent to Nastiness 1014
The Most Unkindest Cut of All 1019
The Wisdom of Agassiz’s and von Baer’s Threefold History of
Scientific Ideas 1021
A Coda on the Kindness and Generosity of Most Colleagues 1022

Chapter 10: The Integration of Constraint and Adaptation (Structure


and Function) in Ontogeny and Phylogeny: Historical Constraints
and the Evolution of Development 1025

Constraint as a Positive Concept 1025
Two Kinds of Positivity 1025
An Etymological Introduction 1025
The First (Empirical) Positive Meaning of Channeling 1027
The Second (Definitional) Positive Meaning of Causes outside
Accepted Mechanisms 1032
Heterochrony and Allometry as the Locus Classicus of the First
Positive (Empirical) Meaning. Channeled Directionality by
Constraint. 1037
The Two Structural Themes of Internally Set Channels and Ease
of Transformation as Potentially Synergistic with Functional
Causality by Natural Selection: Increasing Shell Stability in the
Gryphaea Heterochronocline 1040
Ontogenetically Channeled Allometric Constraint as a Primary
Basis of Expressed Evolutionary Variation: The Full Geographic
and Morphological Range of Cerion uva 1045
Contents xix

The Aptive Triangle and the Second Positive Meaning: Constraint as a


Theory-Bound Term for Patterns and Directions Not Built Exclusively
(Or Sometimes Even at All) by Natural Selection 1051
The Model of the Aptive Triangle 1051
Distinguishing and Sharpening the Two Great Questions 1053
The Structural Vertex 1053
The Historical Vertex 1055
An Epitome for the Theory-Bound Nature of Constraint
Terminology 1057

Deep Homology and Pervasive Parallelism: Historical Constraint
as the Primary Gatekeeper and Guardian of Morphospace 1061
A Historical and Conceptual Analysis of the Underappreciated
Importance of Parallelism for Evolutionary Theory 1061
A Context for Excitement 1061
A Terminological Excursus on the Meaning of Parallelism 1069
The Nine Fateful Little Words of E. Ray Lankester 1069
The Terminological Origin and Debate about the Meaning and
Utility of Parallelism 1076
A Symphony in Four Movements on the Role of Historical Constraint
in Evolution: Towards the Harmonious Rebalancing of Form and
Function in Evolutionary Theory 1089
Movement One, Statement: Deep Homology across Phyla: Mayr’s
Functional Certainty and Geoffroy’s Structural Vindication 1089
Deep Homology, Archetypal Theories, and
Historical Constraint 1089
Mehr Licht (More Light) on Goethe’s Angiosperm Archetype 1092
Hoxology and Geoffroy’s First Archetypal Theory of
Segmental Homology 1095
An Epitome and Capsule History of Hoxology 1095
Vertebrate Homologs in Structure and Action 1101
Segmental Homologies of Arthropods and Vertebrates:
Geoffroy’s Vindication 1106
Rediscovering the Vertebrate Rhombomeres 1107
More Extensive Homologies throughout the
Developing Somites 1109
Some Caveats and Tentative Conclusions 1112
Geoffrey’s Second Archetypal Theory of Dorso-Ventral
Inversion in the Common Bilaterian Groundplan 1117
xx Contents

Movement Two, Elaboration: Parallelism of Underlying


Generators: Deep Homology Builds Positive Channels of
Constraint 1122
Parallelism All the Way Down: Shining a Light and
Feeding the Walk 1122
Parallelism in the Large: Pax-6 and the Homology of Developmental
Pathways in Homoplastic Eyes of Several Phyla 1123
Data and Discovery 1123
Theoretical Issues 1127
A Question of Priority 1130
Parallelism in the Small: The Origin of Crustacean Feeding
Organs 1132
Pharaonic Bricks and Corinthian Columns 1134
Movement Three, Scherzo: Does Evolutionary Change Often
Proceed by Saltation Down Channels of Historical
Constraint? 1142
Movement Four, Recapitulation and Summary: Early Establishment
of Rules and the Inhomogenous Population of Morphospace:
Dobzhansky’s Landscape as Primarily Structural and Historical,
Not Functional and Immediate 1147
Bilaterian History as Top-Down by Tinkering of an Initial Set of
Rules, Not Bottom-Up by Adding Increments of Complexity 1147
Setting of Historical Constraints in the Cambrian Explosion 1155
Channeling the Subsequent Directions of Bilaterian History
from the Inside 1161
An Epilog on Dobzhansky’s Landscape and the Dominant
Role of Historical Constraint in the Clumped Population of
Morphospace 1173

Chapter 11: The Integration of Constraint and Adaptation (Structure


and Function) in Ontogeny and Phylogeny: Structural Constraints,
Spandrels, and the Centrality of Exaptation in Macroevolution 1179

The Timeless Physics of Evolved Function 1179
Structuralism’s Odd Man Outside 1179
D’Arcy Thompson’s Science of Form 1182
The Structure of an Argument 1182
The Tactic and Application of an Argument 1189
The Admitted Limitation and Ultimate Failure of
an Argument 1196
Contents xxi

Odd Man In (D’Arcy Thompson’s Structuralist Critique of


Darwinism) and Odd Man Out (His Disparagement
of Historicism) 1200
An Epilog to an Argument 1207
Order for Free and Realms of Relevance for
Thompsonian Structuralism 1208

Exapting the Rich and Inevitable Spandrels of History 1214
Nietzsche’s Most Important Proposition of Historical Method 1214
Exaptation and the Principle of Quirky Functional Shift: The
Restricted Darwinian Version as the Ground of Contingency 1218
How Darwin Resolved Mivart’s Challenge of Incipient Stages 1218
The Two Great Historical and Structural Implications of Quirky
Functional Shift 1224
How Exaptation Completes and Rationalizes the Terminology of
Evolutionary Change by Functional Shifting 1229
Key Criteria and Examples of Exaptation 1234
The Complete Version, Replete with Spandrels: Exaptation and the
Terminology of Nonadaptative Origin 1246
The More Radical Category of Exapted Features with Truly
Nonadaptive Origins as Structural Constraints 1246
Defining and Defending Spandrels: A Revisit to San Marco 1249
Three Major Reasons for the Centrality of Spandrels, and
Therefore of Nonadaptation, in Evolutionary Theory 1258

The Exaptive Pool: The Proper Conceptual Formula and
Ground of Evolvability 1270
Resolving the Paradox of Evolvability and Defining the
Exaptive Pool 1270
The Taxonomy of the Exaptive Pool 1277
Franklins and Miltons, or Inherent Potentials vs.
Available Things 1277
Choosing a Fundamentum Divisionis for a Taxonomy:
An Apparently Arcane and Linguistic Matter That Actually
Embodies a Central Scientific Decision 1280
Cross-Level Effects as Miltonic Spandrels, Not Franklinian
Potentials: The Nub of Integration and Radical Importance 1286
A Closing Comment to Resolve the Macroevolutionary Paradox
that Constraint Ensures Flexibility Whereas Selection Crafts
Restriction 1294
xxii Contents

Chapter 12: Tiers of Time and Trials of Extrapolationism,


With an Epilog on the Interaction of General Theory and
Contingent History 1296

Failure of Extrapolationism in the Non-Isotropy of Time
and Geology 1296
The Specter of Catastrophic Mass Extinction: Darwin
to Chicxulub 1296
The Paradox of the First Tier: Towards a General Theory of
Tiers of Time 1320

An Epilog on Theory and History in Creating the Grandeur of
This View of Life 1332
THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY
CHAPTER ONE

Defining and Revising the


Structure of Evolutionary Theory

Theories Need Both Essences and Histories

In a famous passage added to later editions of the Origin of Species, Charles


Darwin (1872, p. 134) generalized his opening statement on the apparent ab-
surdity of evolving a complex eye through a long series of gradual steps by re-
minding his readers that they should always treat “obvious” truths with
skepticism. In so doing, Darwin also challenged the celebrated definition of
science as “organized common sense,” as championed by his dear friend
Thomas Henry Huxley. Darwin wrote: “When it was first said that the sun
stood still and world turned round, the common sense of mankind declared
the doctrine false; but the old saying of Vox populi, vox Dei [the voice of the
people is the voice of God], as every philosopher knows, cannot be trusted in
science.”
Despite his firm residence within England’s higher social classes, Darwin
took a fully egalitarian approach towards sources of expertise, knowing full
well that the most dependable data on behavior and breeding of domesticated
and cultivated organisms would be obtained from active farmers and hus-
bandmen, not from lords of their manors or authors of theoretical treatises.
As Ghiselin (1969) so cogently stated, Darwin maintained an uncompromis-
ingly “aristocratic” set of values towards judgment of his work—that is, he
cared not a whit for the outpourings of vox populi, but fretted endlessly and
fearfully about the opinions of a very few key people blessed with the rare
mix of intelligence, zeal, and attentive practice that we call expertise (a demo-
cratic human property, respecting only the requisite mental skills and emo-
tional toughness, and bearing no intrinsic correlation to class, profession or
any other fortuity of social circumstance).
Darwin ranked Hugh Falconer, the Scottish surgeon, paleontologist, and
Indian tea grower, within this most discriminating of all his social groups, a
panel that included Hooker, Huxley and Lyell as the most prominent mem-
bers. Thus, when Falconer wrote his important 1863 paper on American fos-
sil elephants (see Chapter 9, pages 745–749, for full discussion of this inci-
dent), Darwin flooded himself with anticipatory fear, but then rejoiced in his
critic’s generally favorable reception of evolution, as embodied in the closing
1
2 THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY

sentence of Falconer’s key section: “Darwin has, beyond all his cotemporaries
[sic], given an impulse to the philosophical investigation of the most back-
ward and obscure branch of the Biological Sciences of his day; he has laid the
foundations of a great edifice; but he need not be surprised if, in the progress
of erection, the superstructure is altered by his successors, like the Duomo of
Milan, from the roman to a different style of architecture.”
In a letter to Falconer on October 1, 1862 (in F. Darwin, 1903, volume 1,
p. 206), Darwin explicitly addressed this passage in Falconer’s text. (Darwin
had received an advance copy of the manuscript, along with Falconer’s re-
quest for review and criticism—hence Darwin’s reply, in 1862, to a text not
printed until the following year): “To return to your concluding sentence: far
from being surprised, I look at it as absolutely certain that very much in the
Origin will be proved rubbish; but I expect and hope that the framework will
stand.”
The statement that God (or the Devil, in some versions) dwells in the de-
tails must rank among the most widely cited intellectual witticisms of our
time. As with many clever epigrams that spark the reaction “I wish I’d said
that!”, attribution of authorship tends to drift towards appropriate famous
sources. (Virtually any nifty evolutionary saying eventually migrates to T. H.
Huxley, just as vernacular commentary about modern America moves to-
wards Mr. Berra.) The apostle of modernism in architecture, Ludwig Mies
van der Rohe, may, or may not, have said that “God dwells in the details,”
but the plethora of tiny and subtle choices that distinguish the elegance of his
great buildings from the utter drabness of superficially similar glass boxes
throughout the world surely validates his candidacy for an optimal linkage of
word and deed.
Architecture may assert a more concrete claim, but nothing beats the ex-
traordinary subtlety of language as a medium for expressing the importance
of apparently trivial details. The architectural metaphors of Milan’s cathe-
dral, used by both Falconer and Darwin, may strike us as effectively identical
at first read. Falconer says that the foundations will persist as Darwin’s leg-
acy, but that the superstructure will probably be reconstructed in a quite dif-
ferent style. Darwin responds by acknowledging Falconer’s conjecture that
the theory of natural selection will undergo substantial change; indeed, in his
characteristically diffident way, Darwin even professes himself “absolutely
certain” that much of the Origin’s content will be exposed as “rubbish.” But
he then states not only a hope, but also an expectation, that the “framework”
will stand.
We might easily read this correspondence too casually as a polite dialogue
between friends, airing a few unimportant disagreements amidst a commit-
ment to mutual support. But I think that this exchange between Falconer and
Darwin includes a far more “edgy” quality beneath its diplomacy. Consider
the different predictions that flow from the disparate metaphors chosen by
each author for the Duomo of Milan—Falconer’s “foundation” vs. Darwin’s
“framework.” After all, a foundation is an invisible system of support, sunk
into the ground, and intended as protection against sinking or toppling of the
Defining and Revising the Structure of Evolutionary Theory 3

overlying public structure. A framework, on the other hand, defines the basic
form and outline of the public structure itself. Thus, the two men conjure up
very different pictures in their crystal balls. Falconer expects that the underly-
ing evolutionary principle of descent with modification will persist as a fac-
tual foundation for forthcoming theories devised to explain the genealogical
tree of life. Darwin counters that the theory of natural selection will persist as
a basic explanation of evolution, even though many details, and even some
subsidiary generalities, cited within the Origin will later be rejected as false,
or even illogical.
I stress this distinction, so verbally and disarmingly trivial at a first and
superficial skim through Falconer’s and Darwin’s words, but so incisive and
portentous as contrasting predictions about the history of evolutionary the-
ory, because my own position—closer to Falconer than to Darwin, but in ac-
cord with Darwin on one key point—led me to write this book, while also
supplying the organizing principle for the “one long argument” of its entirety.
I do believe that the Darwinian framework, and not just the foundation, per-
sists in the emerging structure of a more adequate evolutionary theory. But I
also hold, with Falconer, that substantial changes, introduced during the last
half of the 20th century, have built a structure so expanded beyond the origi-
nal Darwinian core, and so enlarged by new principles of macroevolutionary
explanation, that the full exposition, while remaining within the domain of
Darwinian logic, must be construed as basically different from the canonical
theory of natural selection, rather than simply extended.
A closer study of the material basis for Falconer and Darwin’s metaphors—
the Duomo (or Cathedral) of Milan—might help to clarify this important dis-
tinction. As with so many buildings of such size, expense, and centrality (both
geographically and spiritually), the construction of the Duomo occupied sev-
eral centuries and included an amalgam of radically changing styles and pur-
poses. Construction began at the chevet, or eastern end, of the cathedral in
the late 14th century. The tall windows of the chevet, with their glorious
flamboyant tracery, strike me as the finest achievement of the entire structure,
and as the greatest artistic expression of this highly ornamented latest Gothic
style. (The term “flamboyant” literally refers to the flame-shaped element so
extensively used in the tracery, but the word then came to mean “richly deco-
rated” and “showy,” initially as an apt description of the overall style, but
then extended to the more general meaning used today.)
Coming now to the main point, construction then slowed considerably,
and the main western facade and entrance way (Fig. 1-1) dates from the late
16th century, when stylistic preferences had changed drastically from the
points, curves and traceries of Gothic to the orthogonal, low-angled or gently
rounded lintels and pediments of classical Baroque preferences. Thus, the first
two tiers of the main (western) entrance to the Duomo display a style that, in
one sense, could not be more formally discordant with Gothic elements of de-
sign, but that somehow became integrated into an interesting coherence. (The
third tier of the western facade, built much later, returned to a “retro” Gothic
style, thus suggesting a metaphorical reversal of phylogenetic conventions, as
4 THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY

1-1. The west facade (main entrance) of Milan Cathedral, built in baroque style
in the 16th century, with a retro-gothic third tier added later.

up leads to older—in style if not in actual time of emplacement!) Finally, in a


distinctive and controversial icing upon the entire structure (Fig. 1-2), the
“wedding cake,” or row-upon-row of Gothic pinnacles festooning the tops of
all walls and arches with their purely ornamental forms, did not crown the
edifice until the beginning of the 19th century, when Napoleon conquered the
city and ordered their construction to complete the Duomo after so many
centuries of work. (These pinnacle forests may amuse or disgust architectural
purists, but no one can deny their unintended role in making the Duomo so
uniquely and immediately recognizable as the icon of the city.)
How, then, shall we state the most appropriate contrast between the
Duomo of Milan and the building of evolutionary theory since Darwin’s Ori-
gin in 1859? If we grant continuity to the intellectual edifice (as implied by
Defining and Revising the Structure of Evolutionary Theory 5

comparison with a discrete building that continually grew but did not change
its location or basic function), then how shall we conceive “the structure of
evolutionary theory” (chosen, in large measure, as the title for this book be-
cause I wanted to address, at least in practical terms, this central question in
the history and content of science)? Shall we accept Darwin’s triumphalist
stance and hold that the framework remains basically fixed, with all visually
substantial change analogous to the non-structural, and literally superficial,
icing of topmost pinnacles? Or shall we embrace Falconer’s richer and more
critical, but still fully positive, concept of a structure that has changed in radi-

1-2. The “wedding cake” pinnacles that festoon the top of Milan Cathedral, and
that were not built until the first years of the 19th century after Napoleon con-
quered the city.
6 THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY

cal ways by incorporating entirely different styles into crucial parts of the
building (even the front entrance!), while still managing to integrate all the
differences into a coherent and functional whole, encompassing more and
more territory in its continuing enlargement?
Darwin’s version remains Gothic, and basically unchanged beyond the vi-
sual equivalent of lip service. Falconer’s version retains the Gothic base as a
positive constraint and director, but then branches out into novel forms that
mesh with the base but convert the growing structure into a new entity,
largely defined by the outlines of its history. (Note that no one has suggested
the third alternative, often the fate of cathedrals—destruction, either total or
partial, followed by a new building of contrary or oppositional form, erected
over a different foundation.)
In order to enter such a discourse about “the structure of evolutionary the-
ory” at all, we must accept the validity, or at least the intellectual coherence
and potential definability, of some key postulates and assumptions that are
often not spelled out at all (especially by scientists supposedly engaged in the
work), and are, moreover, not always granted this form of intelligibility by
philosophers and social critics who do engage such questions explicitly. Most
importantly, I must be able to describe a construct like “evolutionary theory”
as a genuine “thing”—an entity with discrete boundaries and a definable his-
tory—especially if I want to “cash out,” as more than a confusingly poetic
image, an analogy to the indubitable bricks and mortar of a cathedral.
In particular, and to formulate the general problem in terms of the specific
example needed to justify the existence of this book, can “Darwinism” or
“Darwinian theory” be treated as an entity with defining properties of “ana-
tomical form” that permit us to specify a beginning and, most crucially for
the analysis I wish to pursue, to judge the subsequent history of Darwinism
with enough rigor to evaluate successes, failures and, especially, the degree
and character of alterations? This book asserts, as its key premise and one
long argument, that such an understanding of modern evolutionary theory
places the subject in a particularly “happy” intellectual status—with the cen-
tral core of Darwinian logic sufficiently intact to maintain continuity as the
centerpiece of the entire field, but with enough important changes (to all ma-
jor branches extending from this core) to alter the structure of evolutionary
theory into something truly different by expansion, addition, and redefini-
tion. In short, “The structure of evolutionary theory” combines enough sta-
bility for coherence with enough change to keep any keen mind in a perpetual
mode of search and challenge.
The distinction between Falconer’s and Darwin’s predictions, a key ingredi-
ent in my analysis, rests upon our ability to define the central features of
Darwinism (its autapomorphies, if you will), so that we may then discern
whether the extent of alteration in our modern understanding of evolutionary
mechanisms and causes remains within the central logic of this Darwinian
foundation, or has now changed so profoundly that, by any fair criterion in
vernacular understanding of language, or by any more formal account of de-
parture from original premises, our current explanatory theory must be de-
Defining and Revising the Structure of Evolutionary Theory 7

scribed as a different kind of mental “thing.” How, in short, can such an in-
tellectual entity be defined? And what degree of change can be tolerated or
accommodated within the structure of such an entity before we must alter the
name and declare the entity invalid or overthrown? Or do such questions just
represent a fool’s errand from the start, because intellectual positions can’t be
reified into sufficient equivalents of buildings or organisms to bear the weight
of such an inquiry?
As arrogant as I may be in general, I am not sufficiently doltish or vainglo-
rious to imagine that I can meaningfully address the deep philosophical ques-
tions embedded within this general inquiry of our intellectual ages—that is,
fruitful modes of analysis for the history of human thought. I shall therefore
take refuge in an escape route that has traditionally been granted to scien-
tists: the liberty to act as a practical philistine. Instead of suggesting a princi-
pled and general solution, I shall ask whether I can specify an operational
way to define “Darwinism” (and other intellectual entities) in a manner spe-
cific enough to win shared agreement and understanding among readers, but
broad enough to avoid the doctrinal quarrels about membership and alle-
giance that always seem to arise when we define intellectual commitments as
pledges of fealty to lists of dogmata (not to mention initiation rites, secret
handshakes and membership cards—in short, the intellectual paraphernalia
that led Karl Marx to make his famous comment to a French journalist: “je
ne suis pas marxiste”).
As a working proposal, and as so often in this book (and in human affairs
in general), a “Goldilocks solution” embodies the blessedly practical kind of
approach that permits contentious and self-serving human beings (God love
us) to break intellectual bread together in pursuit of common goals rather
than personal triumph. (For this reason, I have always preferred, as guides to
human action, messy hypothetical imperatives like the Golden Rule, based on
negotiation, compromise and general respect, to the Kantian categorical im-
peratives of absolute righteousness, in whose name we so often murder and
maim until we decide that we had followed the wrong instantiation of the
right generality.) We must, in short and in this case, steer between the “too lit-
tle” of refusing to grant any kind of “essence,” or hard anatomy of defining
concepts, to a theory like Darwinism; and the “too much” of an identification
so burdened with a long checklist of exigent criteria that we will either spend
all our time debating the status of particular items (and never addressing the
heart or central meaning of the theory), or we will waste our efforts, and poi-
son our communities, with arguments about credentials and anathemata, ap-
plied to individual applicants for membership.
In his brilliant attempt to write a “living” history and philosophy of science
about the contemporary restructuring of taxonomic theory by phenetic and
cladistic approaches, Hull (1988) presents the most cogent argument I have
ever read for “too little” on Goldilocks’s continuum, as embodied in his de-
fense of theories as “conceptual lineages” (1988, pp. 15–18). I enthusiasti-
cally support Hull’s decision to treat theories as “things,” or individuals in
the crucial sense of coherent historical entities—and in opposition to the stan-
Index

ABC Model, 82, 1063–1064, 1093– textbooks and, 577–579


1094 Weismann and, 201–203, 217–219
Abel, 1086 adaptive radiations, test of, 815–816
abrupt appearance of species. See also AEPPS. See Principles of Animal Ecol-
punctuated equilibrium theory; ogy
punctuations African lake mollusks, 769–771, 796,
gradualist view of, 749–755, 758– 845, 853, 867
759, 840 Agassiz, Louis, 51, 271, 382, 383, 687,
inference of cladogenesis and, 840– 1021–1022
850 Essay on Classification, 271–278
migrational incursion and, 748, 840, agency, as Darwinian principle, 14. See
841, 852 also hierarchy theory; levels of se-
acceleration, principle of, 367–368, lection; organismal selection;
371 punctuated equilibrium theory;
Adams, R. McC., 573–574, 956 species selection
adaptation. See also adaptationism; coral model and, 20, 21
nonadaptive origin Darwin’s theoretical argument and,
as evolutionary term, 117n, 263n, 59, 60
662, 671, 1051, 1229–1231 hardening of Modern Synthesis and,
Nietzsche and, 1217–1218 71, 544–556, 585
“adaptation at the edge of chaos,” historical alternatives to Darwinism
1213–1214, 1273–1274 and, 586–587, 588
adaptationism. See also Darwinism; meaning of individuality and, 597–613
Modern Synthesis, hardening of; modern critiques and, 589, 590
structuralist—functionalist di- proposed revisions and, 21, 49
chotomy punctuated equilibrium and, 26, 39,
adaptation as term and, 117n, 263n, 49
662, 671, 1051, 1229–1231 as theme in Origin, 125–137
Bateson and, 406–407, 412–415 age of the earth, 492–502. See also geo-
co-adaptation and, 218 logical time
Darwinian efficacy and, 61, 155–159 Ager, D. V., 753–754, 773, 845
de Vries and, 450–451 Akam, M., 1144, 1145–1146, 1163,
English tradition and, 252–253 1165, 1166
Geoffroy and, 300–301 AL. See Artificial Life
Goethe and, 288–289 Albanesi, G. L., 852
Gould’s personal odyssey and, 42–44, Alberch, P., 1037
397n Alexander, G., 579
Lamarck and, 176–179, 181–186, Allen, J. C., 883
479 Allmacht of selection, 358–359, 505,
Owen and, 324–326 567. See also Weismann, August
Paley and, 117, 118–121, 268–271 theory of germinal selection and, 63,
primacy of, for Darwin, 254–260 197–201, 215, 219, 223–224,
problem of too much, 213 596
1393
1394 Index

allometry, 42 archetypal theories. See also historical


channeled directionality by constraint constraint
and, 80–81, 1037–1051 Darwin and, 337–339
properties of levels of selection and, dismissal of, 1091–1092
683–714 evo-devo results and, 82–83, 1092–
scaling in nature and, 677, 680, 704 1095, 1106–1122
allopatric analysis, 706, 707–709 Geoffroy’s dorso-ventral inversion
Almada, V. C., 1240 and, 83, 1117–1122
alternatives to natural selection. See also Geoffroy’s vertebral archetype and,
Lamarckism; mutation theory; 82–83, 299–306, 320, 321, 1091,
orthogenesis; saltationism 1092, 1101, 1106–1117
cultural biases and, 588 Goethe’s leaf archetype and, 284–286,
Kellogg’s classification and, 353–354, 1064, 1091, 1092–1095
383, 439, 506, 507, 589 Owen’s vertebral archetype and, 316–
logical failure and, 588–590 326, 1091
persistence of critiques and, 586–587 architectural metaphor, 2–6. See also
Alvarez, L. W., 482, 948, 1303, 1306– Pharaonic bricks vs. Corinthian
1308 columns analogy; spandrels
Amalda species, 786, 787 Arendt, 1151–1152
Ambystoma species, 360 “area effects,” 542
American Civil War, 1338, 1341–1342 Aristotle, 85, 234n, 626, 1186–1187,
ammonites, 1315 1207–1208
Amphioxus, 1170 Arkansas equal time law, 989–990
Amphipholis squamata, 1162 Arnold, 901
anagenesis, 190, 357n Arnold, A. J., 611n, 656, 661, 663, 672,
cladogenesis and, 436, 813–822 733
macroevolutionary analogy and, 723– Arnold, E. N., 1234–1238, 1240, 1244
724 art history, 978, 1342
punctuated, 795, 840–841 arthropod and vertebrate developmental
trends and, 78, 777 homologies. See also bilaterian
analogy, as term, 282n, 1077 history; Hox genes
Anasazi people, 956 arthropod hox gene expression and,
ancestral survival criterion, 76, 794– 1148–1149, 1163–1170
796, 840–850 channeling in bilaterian history and,
antelope studies, 78, 866 1161–1173
Antennapedia mutant, 1100 common ancestor and, 1148–1155,
anti-Darwinian theory. See creationism; 1170–1171
natural theology; orthogenesis; deep segmental homologies and,
saltationism 1106–1117
antinomies in Lamarckism, 189–192 dorso-ventral inversion and, 83,
Antonovics, J., 1035 1117
Appel, T. A., 291–293 early discoveries of, 1101–1106
“aptation,” as term, 1051, 1233, 1234 Geoffroy’s vertebral archetype and,
aptive triangle 1101, 1106–1117
functional vertex, 81, 1052, 1053 (see “Hoxology” and, 82–83, 1095–1117
also natural selection) Pharaonic bricks vs. Corinthian col-
historical vertex, 81, 1052–1053, umns analogy and, 1138–1142
1055–1057 (see also deep setting of historical constraint and,
homology; historical constraint) 1155–1161
model of, 1051–1053 throughout developing somites, 1109–
premises of traditional Darwinism 1112
and, 1173–1174 vertebrate Hox gene expression and,
structural vertex, 81, 1053–1055 (see 1170–1173
also spandrels) vertebrate rhombomeres and, 1107–
Arabidopsis, 82, 1063–1064, 1092– 1109, 1112
1095 Arthur, W., 1174–1175
Archegozetes mite, 1163 Artificial Life (AL), 924–925

You might also like