Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Organised Sound

http://journals.cambridge.org/OSO

Additional services for Organised Sound:

Email alerts: Click here


Subscriptions: Click here
Commercial reprints: Click here
Terms of use : Click here

Code­notes­music: an epistemological investigation of algorithmic music


DOMINIQUE RICHARD

Organised Sound / Volume 1 / Issue 03 / December 1996, pp 173 ­ 177


DOI: 10.1017/S1355771896000246, Published online: 08 September 2000

Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1355771896000246

How to cite this article:


DOMINIQUE RICHARD (1996). Code­notes­music: an epistemological investigation of algorithmic music. Organised Sound,
1, pp 173­177 doi:10.1017/S1355771896000246

Request Permissions : Click here

Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/OSO, IP address: 146.164.3.22 on 08 Jan 2013


Code–notes–music: an epistemological
investigation of algorithmic music

D OMIN IQ UE RICH ARD


305 Martin Lane, Wallingford, PA 19086, USA

This paper deals with the role of the composer in use and integration of these two components – sound
algorithmic music. This role departs from traditional models and language – and alternatively in terms of the type
because of the way computers are used in the compositional of formalism (formal model) they use. An evaluation
process, particularly when signal processing techniques are of several types of formal model in terms of structure
being integrated with sophisticated formal models to
and the philosophy of knowledge implied will help to
generate musical compositions. We shall examine several
situate the composing subject in the process of algor-
types of ‘musical formalism’ in order to bring out the active
role of the composer in the compositional process. ithmic music.

1. INTRODUCTION 2. SOUND/LANGUAGE
Composing algorithmically – using a computing pro- First introduced in the early 1950s, computerised
cess to devise a composition – has been considered in algorithmic music formalisations were primarily con-
the past. We could trace the history of such practice cerned with the structure of a composition, its lan-
from Vaucanson’s flute player automaton to the com- guage, and were for the most part written for
positional potential that Ada Lovelace saw in Babba- traditional musical instruments which provided the
ge’s analytic engine. We could argue that the advent sound. A newly articulated information theory
of modern electronic computers simply permits (Shannon 1948) seemed to reasonably model linguis-
implementation of similar automation in real time, tic as well as musical expectations (Meyer 1967) and
with a level of complexity and thoroughness which inspired this privileged interest in structure. Struc-
does not in any new way change the compositional tural methodology used by many linguists and
process. In contrast, if the involvement of computers musicologists (Ruwet 1972) was also a factor in this
in composition is seen as significantly different from research of musical structure.
the simple programming of an automaton, it raises At that time, the large computational requirements
the question of dehumanisation of the process of of signal processing, a science still in its infancy, pro-
composition and casts doubt on the idea of creation, hibited any real-time processing of sound. However,
the production of the new. several technical and aesthetic changes prompted a
Algorithmic music can be defined as a music which focus on sound analysis and its possible processing
is ‘automatically’ composed by formal mathematical by computer. Iannis Xenakis in reaction to total ser-
algorithms that operate deterministically or stochasti- ialism, which he argued could not possibly correlate
cally on sound attributes andyor musical structures. the row writing of the score with the perceptual effect
This compositional process may be used in ‘real time’ of the sound, proposed to systematically compose
or in ‘deferred time’. Early examples of algorithmic ‘clouds of sounds’. Inspired by the evolution of the
music include Xenakis’ formal music (Xenakis 1971), sciences toward a probabilistic framework, he sug-
Pierre Barbaud’s algorithmic music (1966) and Hil- gested literally computing sounds from stochastic
ler’s Illiac Suite (1959). More contemporary uses of combinations of elementary textural components
this technique include the fractal experiments of Voss such as string pizziccati or glissandi. Xenaxis effec-
and Clark (1978) and Holtzman’s experiments in gen- tively demonstrated this technique in Metastasis
erative grammar (Holtzman 1981). Algorithmic (1954) and Pithoprakta (1956). From another per-
music, in effect, uses formal models, defined by a spective, Jean-Claude Risset pursued the timbral
choice of representation and a finite set of axioms and analysis which Pierre Schaeffer (1952) had initiated.
rules (Hofstadter 1979) to help control the sounds After dismissing Helmholtz’s theory of musical
which constitute music or the language which struc- acoustics as unsatisfactory, Risset (1969) dissected
tures musical forms. Various approaches to algor- the micro-variations of the spectra of trumpets or
ithmic music can thus be compared in terms of the violin tones and succeeded in resynthesising them by
Organised Sound 1(3): 173–7  1996 Cambridge University Press
174 Dominique Richard

generating credible sound samples from the short- Algorithmic music has also structured compo-
time Fourier transforms of their dynamically varying sition through generative models simply thought to
spectra. At the same time, Max Mathews (1969) laid be ‘more representative’ of the musical process on a
the first foundation of the first patchwork software, strictly philosophical ground. Fractal models and
Music V, to automate the computations similar to chaotic models are prime examples of this type of for-
those suggested by Risset. Music V was a program- malism because processes with fractal dimension are
ming language capable of describing the computation thought to be ‘between order and chaos’, where music
required for the generation of series of complex is also assumed to be. In the same way Thom’s appli-
sounds, with varying spectral and envelope character- cation of catastrophe theory to morphology exhibits
istics. To this day, Music V has remained a model of a formal structure which describes the macrostructure
musical software organisation. Today the integration as a direct isomorphism of the microstructure. This
of real-time signal processing and structural language formal property of Thom’s morphological model
control is possible thanks to the speed and capability gives the composer a way to formulate the relation-
of modern computers. Entire pieces of music can be ships between sound structure and the language
algorithmically processed in real time, as the Chanty structure framing the compositional process as one
Formes system demonstrates. Indeed, technology is of organic growth. In general, choosing a structuring
so advanced that a composer can realise ‘spectral’ formalism often becomes the expression of a deep
compositions which intimately relate the micro- and belief of what music is and how it relates to the world.
the macrostructure of the composition by making the As a consequence the composer can arbitrarily
structure of the musical language directly dependent choose formalisms on the basis of aesthetic prefer-
on the characteristics of the sounds used in the ence or mysticism. Cage’s use of the ‘I Ching’ for the
composition (Born 1995). composition of Music of Changes (1952) or Xenakis’
explicit relationship between music and architecture
in Metastasis (1954) or the relationship of music to
3. A MENAGERIE OF MODELS
visual traces in Mycenae-Alpha (1978) are emblematic
The range of formal processes used in algorithmic of this approach.
music differs significantly when it comes to pro-
cessing sounds and processing form. Although the
4. TEXTUALITY
formal models used in the synthesis of sonic material
usually provide significant control, these models have Reliance on what appear to be arbitrary models or at
always remained close to acoustics and the pro- best models informed by the composer’s ‘spon-
cedures of signal processing. In contrast the formal taneous philosophy’ may put into question the very
models of structural musical language have been scientific justification of algorithmic music. But, more
influenced by a number of models related to music. profoundly, the process of algorithmic composition
Formalist models of music based on statistical and which ‘textualises’ music to the extreme by crystallis-
linguistic theories were developed, but other formalist ing its very ‘being’ into a code and, possibly, into a
models only loosely related to the musical process complex of hardware and software, raises an epis-
were also tried. For example, mathematical models temological question. Artistic creations using formal
derived from information theory, in particular systems ought to be critically considered as they
Markov chains, were used by Xenakis, Hiller and appear to suggest the possibility of the completeness
Isaacson. Moreover, Barbeau and Xenakis also used of textual representation while the principle of their
more formal mathematical models such as set theory genesis defines a fragmented and fundamentally
and game theory as organising principles for their incomplete domain of expression of knowledge
compositions. Since music and language are formally (Hofstadter 1979). In other words, is formal musical
and informally described within generative and semi- knowledge a knowledge of music or a knowledge
otic paradigms in a structural description (e.g. about music? This question, in effect, raises the very
Schenker 1954, Lerdahl and Jackendoff 1983, Cope possibility of creation, the production of the new.
1991) or temporal implication description (e.g. Meyer To establish key relationships between music and
1973, Narmour 1977, 1990, 1992), formal models knowledge, critical in unravelling the epistemological
more specific to music were also used. In these gener- status of algorithmic music, we must first evaluate
ative and semiotic models ‘language’ was represented various modes of thinking which will necessarily
by a finite set of production rules. The generative frame the analysis. On the one hand, the formalist
approach (Chomsky 1975, Schank 1972) derived its position is strongly supported by a Western philo-
rules from a priori formalisms, while the semiotic sophical tradition exemplified by Plato, Descartes,
approach derived its rules from experience through Hegel and Husserl, that systematically describes the
the recursive application of arbitrary trans- ‘world’ in logocentric terms and that postulates an
formations. authority, a judge (URteil) at its origin. As Husserl
Code–notes–music 175

states in his Formal and Transcendental Logic, ‘We the development of theories which, by means of ever
must place ourselves above this whole life and its cul- complicated notations, have acted in many different
tural tradition’ (Husserl 1969: 5) to partake in the roles. Milton Babbitt (1972) identifies four prevalent
project of apprehension of the real. This movement functions of theory which appeared, almost chrono-
of dominance and control is the mark of the modern logically, as symbolic description, as structured for-
project which believes ‘in the possibility of an mulation of statements of relations among observed
advance of humanity toward perfection’ (Bury 1932: phenomena, as collections of rules for the represen-
164–5). The German prefix UR (Super-) of the judge tation of observables, and as an interpreted model of
(URteil) signifies this position by establishing a trans- a formal system. This progression in the status of the-
cendence best approximated by formalisms. This UR ory is marked by an ever increasing domain of oper-
is the governing principle of the ‘UR-text’ of the Rus- ation coupled with a higher level of formalisation.
sian formalist, Freud’s ‘UR-Sein’ and Schenker’s Today, with the help of computers, formalisation of
‘UR-Satz’. Science is privileged to fully explicate the music has heightened in complexity and speed. How-
single truth of the real. Knowledge is the result of this ever, the epistemological question stated earlier
apprehension ultimately expressed in an all- remains: Is this knowledge a knowledge of music or
encompassing univalent textual description. a knowledge about music? Will the formalisation and
However, other currents of thought, present in the computerisation of musical composition turn the
philosophy of Heraclitus, Nietzsche, Foucault and activity of music writing and music playing into a
Deleuze, keep the issue of knowledge an open one. new branch of engineering? In response to these ques-
Instead of organising ‘complete systems’, these phil- tions I propose looking at the formalisation of music
osophers rest on the UNdefined, proceed through the along two axes of reflection. The first axis character-
UNdecidable and profess the ‘UNheimlich’, the ises how various modes of formalisation are con-
UNfamiliar. This position is one grounded in history structed and seeks to understand how the
which focuses on daily practices. In this view, truth formalisations explicate knowledge. The second axis
is a product of the historical complex of powery of reflection provides a critical reading of the
knowledge. This approach, metonymically marked by relationship of ‘scientific’ formalisations in music
the German prefix UN, is one of openness which does with respect to time and to the composing subject.
not engage in a work of purification of the real but
allows all realms of possibilities at the crux of UNde-
5. MODEL STRUCTURE
cidable propositions. Knowledge participates in a
dynamic which ‘untangle[s] the lines of the recent past Formalisation of music comprises the development
and those of the near future’ following the inter- of representational attributes which describe musical
related movements of ‘power, knowledge and subjec- objects and rules which logically relate these objects’
tivity which constitute social apparatuses’ (Deleuze attributes with each other. The purpose of formalis-
1992: 163). ation is to understand and explain a phenomenon.
The UR discourse is modelled on the objective The core device of such a formalisation is the well-
rationality of the sciences: Descarte’s dream. This dis- known IF . . . THEN logical pair which computer
course follows the Hegelian logic which in its con- scientists, knowledge engineers and automation
clusion leaves no room for the arts. The UN engineers use to make knowledge explicit.
discourse explodes in Dyonisian excess witnessing Three main types of formulations exist in music,
UNmediated expressions of the field of experience. each addressing different aspects of musical knowl-
One discourse is tediously chained to the many steps edge and each having slightly different purposes.
of a logical construction, erecting, over time, the They are, following Kant’s typology: (i) pure musical
development of a timeless structure; the other knowledge, (ii) practicalyprocedural musical knowl-
appears, at once, in the dance of Zarathustra partici- edge, and (iii) judgemental musical knowledge.
pating in the historical reality of a mosaic of instan- The most ‘complete’ knowledge representation of
taneous moments. music, pure knowledge, is certainly present in Iannis
Knowledge of music has been traditionally trans- Xenakis’ compositions where the compositional
mitted through apprenticeship. In western culture this structure is literally formulated by a priori formal
relationship of quasi-ritual initiation existed until the concepts such as the groups of transformation used
middle of the eighteenth century when musical in NomosyAlpha (1971). The musical analysis of such
notation was codified along with the tempered scale a piece is almost irrelevant as it is derived entirely
to formalise communication. This textualisation of from a stated formal structure, the consequences of
music is almost contemporaneous with the encyclo- which are already present. Fractal music, Markovian
pedic period which predates and prepares the scien- music, cellular automata, chaos and catastrophy the-
tific revolution. Since this period of ‘enlightenment’ ories fall under that same category of musical for-
the rationalisation of music has expanded through malisation which assumes a universal isomorphy
176 Dominique Richard

between all natural phenomena. These models con- is to understand some invariance in musical percep-
sider phenomena strictly as they appear under the tion. Rather than relying on mathematics or physics
conditions of space and time. In this ‘we find nothing or on the determination of creation of an utterance,
that resembles freedom: phenomena are strictly sub- its core principle focuses on perception and on
ject to the law of a natural causality’ (Deleuze 1983: developing implication rules based on gestalt. The
29–30). These approaches indeed provide rules which purpose of these rules is limited to the field of musical
are predictable and repeatable at least as much as the analysis; they are used to explain systematic struc-
phenomena from which they are copied; however, tures encountered in musical composition but do not
they rest on the reductionist belief that what is for- claim to explicate all possible music. This rule system
mally equivalent should have the same effect. There- is literally a system of local heuristics used as an ana-
fore a ‘beautiful geometrical fractal’ should translate lytical tool. Although the basis of this system of rules
into an equivalently ‘beautiful fractal musical’ com- is somewhat general in its formulation, it never claims
position as if the experience of beauty was a matter universality because it does not seek provability and
of equivalent formulations between disjoint sets of can be replaced on the spot by other working hypoth-
parameters mapped onto one another through an eses. The rule system, thus provided, only sets a con-
arbitrary equivalence relation. text for the composer. The implicationyrealization
The second form, practicalyprocedural knowledge, theory developed by Narmour (1977, 1990, 1992) is a
results in a music formalisation which uses pro- prime example of this approach. Narmour proposes
duction rules and recognises that an absolute knowl- certain operating rules for analysis but always allows
edge of composition is not strictly attainable with the specificity of the piece to speak with or against the
mathematical and physical representations of the formal backdrop framed by the theorist. Paralleling
musical phenomena. But, following a structuralist Kantian typology the theorist who practices judge-
approach, this form posits that by studying the cor- mental musical knowledge ‘know[s] that there are two
pus of written musical texts one can unveil the funda- types of legislations, thus two domains corresponding
mental rules which have been used in writing a set to nature and freedom, to sensible nature and supra-
sensible nature. But there is only one terrain, that of
of compositions. As an example, Noam Chomsky’s
experience’ (Deleuze 1983: 40). This third category of
approach to linguistics which resulted in the theory
formalisation is the only one to focus on the subject
of generative grammar, was applied to tonal music
of perception in the actuality of hisyher experience,
by Lerdahl and Jackendoff and resulted in a set of
and in that, significantly differs from the other two.
‘well-formedness’ rules and ‘preferences rules’ which
This final category inherently recognises and respects
are used for the analysis or composition of music.
the difference between the arbitrary de jure provided
Similarly, Baroni and Jacoboni (1978) through an
by the rules and the reality of the de facto perceived
analysis of Bach’s chorales derived a set of rules
in the particular realisation of a particular space.
which explicated the writing of soprano voices in
Bach’s Chorales in general. In the same vein, Cope
(1991) formalised a meta-theory of style by statisti- 6. THE SUBJECT OF THE MODELS
cally characterising a stratified corpus of compo-
The image that comes to mind when one speaks of
sitions. However, these approaches are either very
sciences is a domain of well-defined concepts, unam-
limited in their scope or somewhat open in their biguous definitions and clear procedures. This some-
implications. The formal rules leave visible cracks in what caricatural view shows every phenomenon
the system. In particular, contrary to Chomsky’s the- destined to be reduced to its minimal explicative
ory of linguistics whose pivots are the transform- nucleus. What remains, the difference, must be
ational rules which aim at universal explanation, the squeezed out, discarded as an error later to be
theory developed by Jackendoff and Lerdahl revolves reduced to zero. We recognise in this model the cer-
around the concept of preference rules which, by tainty of Newtonian physics as seen through nine-
definition, allows diversity and choice. Following the teenth century ideology: one formula to explain the
Kantian approach, this practical reason ‘legislates in world where everything works on the same universal,
the faculty of desire that is to say in its practical inter- uniform principle. To be sure, the scientific method
est’. The knowledge of the practical reason is a pro- has been very successful within the confines of what
cedural knowledge made up of chosen ad hoc laws our society has decided to call successful, but dis-
which operates on the ‘things in themselves thought senting voices can be heard. In particular, Freud’s
as noumena, in so far as they form a suprasensible discovery of the unconscious established that experi-
nature’ (Deleuze 1983: 31). ence embedded in history cannot be reduced to this
The third type of music formalisation does not proverbial formula. In line with this reflection on the
even attempt to explain the structure of compositions unconscious, the formal models of semiology or
per se. Its only rationale for the development of rules structuralism can be criticised as lacking reference to
Code–notes–music 177

that unconscious. It can thus be argued that the Barthes, R. 1977. Roland Barthes by Roland Barthes. New
reality of language resides in the speaking subject York: Hill and Wang.
which is fundamentally heterogeneous. Musically Born, G. 1995. Rationalizing Culture. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
speaking, this reference to the unconscious subverts
Bury, J. B. 1932. The Idea of Progress: an Inquiry into its
a traditional ‘scientific spirit’ by letting the subject
Origin and Growth. New York: Dover Publications Inc.
in hisyher temporal reality take the forefront of the Chomsky, N. 1975. The Logical Structure of Linguistic
scientific scene, and by letting the composing subject Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
cut through the formalities and allow expression of Cope, D. 1991. Computers and Musical Style. Madison: AR
pleasure and desire. Edition.
Pure formal systems provide an explanation of the Deleuze, G. 1983. Kant’s Critical Philosophy. Minneapolis:
world that is posited as universal and independent of University of Minnesota Press.
time and space. Formal models of music do not Deleuze, G. 1992. Foucault. Minneapolis: Minnesota
University Press.
escape this objective: they attempt to find an expla-
Foucault, M. 1973. Madness and Civilization: A History of
nation for every structure that can be encountered. Insanity in the Age of Reason. New York: Vintage
However, there is a paradox when theories of music Books.
deny or completely control time, the very principle of Hiller, L. H. 1959. Experimental Music. New York:
music’s existence, and when, in the same move, these McGraw-Hill.
all-encompassing formalisms deny or repress the sub- Hofstadter, D. R. 1979. Godel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal
ject of music: the composer, the interpreter or the list- Golden Braid. New York: Basic Books Inc.
ener. Indeed, the parametric time of physics or even Holtzman, S. R. 1981. Using generative grammar for music
composition. Computer Music Journal 5(1): 51–64.
the time coded in musical symbols (Chronos) is not
Husserl, E. 1969. Formal and Transcendental Logic. The
the same as the psychological time of musical dur- Hague: Nijhoff.
ations and musical experience (Aion). These formalis- Lerdahl, F., and Jackendoff, R. 1983. A Generative Theory
ations could, in fact, border on an extreme caricature of Tonal Music. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
of the tradition of our technological society. By solely Mathews, M. V. 1969. The Technology of Computer Music.
representing the pure expression of a symbolic lingo, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
music formalisation leads to the logic of madness Meyer, L. B. 1967. Music, the Arts and Ideas. Chicago:
described by Foucault (1973). University of Chicago Press.
Meyer, L. B. 1973. Explaining Music: Essays and Explo-
But there are alternatives to such a univocal totali-
rations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
tarian world. Barthes suggests that we let multiple Narmour, E. 1977. Beyond Schenkerism. Chicago: Univer-
meanings wink at each other ‘as if the words’ mean- sity of Chicago Press.
ings were in that wink, so that one and the same Narmour, E. 1990. The Analysis and Cognition of Basic
word, in one and the same sentence, means at once Melodic Structures. Chicago: University of Chicago
and the same time different things’ (Barthes 1977: Press.
72). Music formalisation can take advantage of such Narmour, E. 1992. The Analysis and Cognition of Melodic
an alternative when used as a metaphor, a tool for Complexity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Risset, J. C., and Mathews, M. V. 1969. Analysis of musi-
the explanation of something bigger than whatever it
cal instrument tones. Physics Today 22(2): 23–30.
spans, while acknowledging the composing subject. Ruwet, N. 1972. Language, Musique, Poesie. Paris: Le
The freedom of interpretation is at the core of this Seuil.
practice. It is the practice of specific intellectuals who Schaeffer, P. 1952. A la Recherche d’une Musique Concrete.
do not ‘admit to the universality of the founding Paris: Le Seuil.
subject . . . but also do not admit of univeral catas- Schank, R. C. 1972. Conceptual dependency: a theory of
trophes in which reason becomes alienated and col- natural language understanding. Cognitive Psychology
lapses once and for all’ (Deleuze 1992: 182). 1: 552–631.
Schenker, H. 1954. Harmony. Edited and annotated by O.
Jonas, translated by E. M. Borgese. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
REFERENCES Shannon, C. E. 1948. A mathematical theory of communi-
cation. Bell System Technical Journal 27(3): 379–423
Babbitt, M. 1972. Set structure as a compositional determi- and 623–56.
nant. In B. Boretz and E. T. Cone (eds.) Perspective of Voss, R. F., and Clark, J. 1978. 1yf noise in music: music
Contemporary Music Theory, pp. 129–47. New York: W. from 1yf noise. Journal of the Acoustical Society of
W. Norton. America 63(1): 258–63.
Baroni, M., and Jacoboni, C. 1978. Proposal for a Gram- Xenakis, I. 1971. Formalized Music. Bloomington: Indiana
mar of Melody. Montreal: Les Presses de l’Université de University Press.
Montreal. Xenakis, I. 1971. Musique Architecture. Paris: Flammarion.

You might also like