Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 16

Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

www.elsevier.com/locate/obhdp

Playing for peanuts: Why is risk seeking more common


for low-stakes gambles? 夽
Bethany J. Weber ¤, Gretchen B. Chapman
Psychology Department, Rutgers University, 152 Frelinghuysen Road, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8020, USA

Received 19 February 2003

Abstract

Previous research has found that decision makers are more risk seeking for small-stakes gambles than for large-stakes gambles. This
“peanuts eVect” is not easily explained by Prospect Theory. Two experiments examined the range of circumstances in which peanuts
eVects occur and tested the hypothesis that anticipated disappointment or anticipated regret explains the peanuts eVect. The results
suggest that the peanuts eVect is related to disappointment, but do not support a connection between the peanuts eVect and regret.
 2005 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Risk; Probability; Outcome magnitude; Magnitude eVect; Disappointment; Regret; Peanuts eVect; Preference reversals

Introduction $0.10 for certain and a 10% chance of winning $1. A risk-
averse decision-maker would choose the $0.10 for certain;
Generally speaking, decision-makers prefer not to however, Markowitz believed, quite plausibly, that most
take chances. Given the choice between playing a gamble people presented with such a small-stakes choice would
and receiving the expected value of the gamble, most prefer the gamble for $1. We can continue working our
decision-makers choose the latter. This risk-aversion is a way up the payout scale with similar choices: what about
very common and robust phenomenon; Kahnman and a choice between $1 and a 10% chance of $10? Between
Tversky once called the tendency to be risk-averse “per- $10 and a 10% chance of $100? Markowitz proposed that
haps the best known generalization regarding risky for each person there comes a point where his or her pref-
choices” (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). erences reverse. I might prefer to take a 10% chance of
There are, however, exceptions to this general rule. $100 over $10 for sure, but given the same choice at a
The tendency of decision-makers to be risk-averse is higher monetary level, I would choose $100 for certain
widespread, but applies only when the outcomes con- over a 10% chance of $1000 (Markowitz, 1952).
cerned are gains. When faced with a potential loss, deci- Note that in both cases, I am being asked to accept 10
sion-makers tend to be risk seeking—that is, given the times the risk in exchange for 10 times the money, yet I
choice between a possibility of loss and a certain loss do not make the same choice in both circumstances. I am
with the same expected value, they prefer the risky more risk-averse for small gains than for large ones. (In
option (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979; Markowitz, 1952). fact, in Markowitz’s example I am actually risk-seeking
Another example of risk-seeking behavior was Wrst for very small gains.) The eVect of decreasing risk aver-
noted by Markowitz (1952). Consider a choice between sion with decreasing monetary amounts was christened
夽 the “peanuts eVect” (Prelec & Loewenstein, 1991)—deci-
This research was supported by an NSF graduate fellowship to the
Wrst author and NSF grant SES 99-75083 to the second author.
sion-makers are more willing to take risks when playing
*
Fax: +1 732 445 2640. for “peanuts.” (By this deWnition, it is not actually neces-
E-mail address: bweber@eden.rutgers.edu (B.J. Weber). sary to become risk-seeking for very small gains, merely

0749-5978/$ - see front matter  2005 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.obhdp.2005.03.001
32 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

to become less risk-averse for smaller payouts.) Marko-


witz also suggested that the peanuts eVect is reXected in
the domain of losses: that decision makers are more risk
seeking for small losses than for large losses.
Although Markowitz himself did not test his eVect
experimentally, a number of subsequent demonstrations
of the peanuts eVect exist. Green, Myerson, and Ostaszew-
ski (1999) determined subjects’ indiVerence points
through a series of choices, and found subjects to be less
risk-averse for small gain amounts than large ones.
Green, Myerson, and colleagues have also demonstrated
the peanuts eVect in other experiments. (Du, Green, &
Myerson, 2002; Holt, Green, & Myerson, 2003; Myerson,
Green, Hanson, Holt, & Estle, 2003). Rachlin, Brown, and
Cross (2000) found subjects to be less risk averse for small
amounts than for large amounts when making a graphi-
cal rating response, but did not Wnd the same pattern for
choice responses. Hershey and Schoemaker (1980) asked
subjects a series of risky choice questions and found a
peanuts eVect in the domain of gains and a reXected pea-
Fig. 1. Utility function proposed by Markowitz (1952).
nuts eVect in the domain of losses. Hogarth and Einhorn
(1990) asked subjects to chose between and rank options,
and found a peanuts eVect for both gains and losses, using
both hypothetical and real payouts. In a meta-analysis
of published Asian-disease framing eVects problems,
Kühberger, Schulte-Mecklenbeck, and Perner (1999)
found a peanuts eVect for a gains frame, but not for a
losses frame. Casey (1991, 1994) has demonstrated the
peanuts eVect for both bidding and choices.
The peanuts eVect can potentially be explained via the
utility function. Markowitz explained the peanuts eVect by
postulating an inXected slope for the utility function of
money. In gains, he proposed the utility function is convex
for small values and concave for large values. The inXec-
tion point of the function represents the magnitude at
which the decision-maker switches from risk-seeking to
risk-averse behavior. He proposed that in losses the utility
function was concave for small losses and convex for large
ones. Thus his proposed utility function contains three
inXection points: one at the origin and two more represent-
ing the monetary points at which behavior switches from
being risk seeking to risk averse or vice versa (see Fig. 1). Fig. 2. Utility function proposed by Kahneman and Tversky (1979).
Under Prospect Theory it is now generally accepted
that the utility function for gains is everywhere concave amounts increase. Thus, initially it seems that the pea-
and for losses everywhere convex (Kahneman & Tver- nuts eVect is not inconsistent with Prospect Theory.
sky, 1979; Tversky & Kahneman, 1992) (see Fig. 2). This
is inconsistent with Markowitz’s original postulate that The peanuts and magnitude eVects
decision-makers are actually risk-seeking for small
amounts of money, which requires a convex utility func- Examination of a similar bias in the domain of inter-
tion. However, it is not inconsistent with the more com- temporal choice casts some doubt on the ability of Pros-
monly used deWnition of the peanuts eVect suggested by pect Theory to explain the peanuts eVect. The magnitude
the previous experimental data: that decision-makers are of a payout inXuences time preferences as well as risk
less risk averse for small gain amounts than large ones. preferences. Time preferences reXect preferences for the
This behavior would be consistent with a concave utility timing of a delayed outcome and can be quantiWed as the
function that is almost linear (approaching risk neutral- percentage increase in value needed to oVset a given
ity) near the origin but gets more curved as payout delay. When given the choice between $10 now and $20
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 33

in 1 year, for example, many decision-makers may prefer factor that applies only to risk (or only to time) is at
to receive $10 now, indicating that more than a doubling work. Prelec and Loewenstein (1991) suggest that the
of value would be needed to compensate for the 1-year explanation for the peanuts eVect may lie in the realm of
delay. However, given a choice between $100 now and disappointment.
$200 in 1 year, the delayed $200 becomes the more pre-
ferred option, now indicating that less than a doubling Regret and disappointment
of value is needed to compensate for the 1-year delay.
Thus, decision makers tend to have a more positive time When picking a 10% chance of $1 over $0.10 for sure,
preference for small magnitude outcomes than for large one is inclined to think, “Who cares if I pick the gamble and
magnitudes (e.g., Chapman, 1996; Chapman & Winquist, lose? I’m only passing up 10 cents!” Passing over a chance
1998; Thaler, 1981). to receive a dime is no big deal. However, giving up $1000
The magnitude eVect is similar to the peanuts eVect in for sure, even in exchange for a 10% chance of $10,000, is
all respects but one: the two eVects run in opposite direc- likely to give one pause. What happens if I choose the gam-
tions if risk seeking corresponds to greater willingness to ble? It’s likely I’ll lose and be unhappy that I could have
wait for an outcome, as is usually assumed. This poses a had $1000 but wound up with nothing instead.
problem for attempts to develop a common explanation According to decision aVect theory (Mellers, Schwartz,
for eVects of risk and delay, something that has been Ho, & Ritov, 1997), negative emotions resulting from
proposed by numerous researchers (e.g., Keren & Roe- decision outcomes take two forms. Disappointment is the
lofsma, 1995; Prelec & Loewenstein, 1991; Rachlin, emotion experienced when a diVerent state of the world
Logue, Gibbon, & Frankel, 1986; Rachlin, Raineri, & would have produced a better result. If I am oVered a 10%
Cross, 1991). Both Green, Myerson, and colleagues (Du chance of winning $10,000 and lose the gamble, I will be
et al., 2002; Green et al., 1999; Holt et al., 2003; Myerson disappointed that I didn’t win (Bell, 1985; Loomes & Sud-
et al., 2003) and Rachlin et al. (2000) have found the gen, 1986). Regret is the emotion experienced when a
magnitude eVect and peanuts eVect in the same experi- diVerent choice on the part of the decision-maker would
ment and both noted the problems this entails for any have produced a better result. Suppose I am asked to
attempt to reduce the eVects of risk and delay to a com- choose between $1000 for sure and a 10% chance of
mon psychological mechanism. Prelec and Loewenstein $10,000. I choose to take the 10% chance of $10,000 and
(1991) have noted this diYculty as well. lose the gamble, ending up with nothing. Now I still feel
The existence of the magnitude eVect also poses a seri- disappointed that I didn’t win, but I also feel regret over
ous problem for a utility function explanation of the choosing the gamble instead of $1000 for sure (Bell, 1982;
peanuts eVect. The magnitude eVect requires a utility Loomes & Sudgen, 1982). In a nutshell, disappointment
function that increases in proportional sensitivity (Prelec means wishing things had turned out diVerently; regret
& Loewenstein, 1991). That is, the ratio between the util- means wishing one had made a diVerent choice.
ities of two monetary values with constant ratio must Disappointment theory deWnes disappointment as a
increase as the monetary values increase. In the example function of the diVerence between the actual outcome
above, decision-makers appear to view the ratio between and the expected value of the gamble (Bell, 1985; Loo-
the utilities of $100 and $200 as psychologically larger mes & Sudgen, 1986); regret theory deWnes regret as a
than that between the utilities of $10 and $20—thus they function of the diVerence between the outcome of the
are willing to wait a year for the former increase, but not chosen option and the outcome of the foregone option
the latter. However, the peanuts eVect demands a utility (Bell, 1982; Loomes & Sudgen, 1982). Therefore, both
function that decreases in proportional sensitivity. The theory and intuition imply that disappointment and
ratio between the utilities of $100 and $200 must be psy- regret are smaller, and thus play a smaller role, in small-
chologically smaller than that between the utilities $10 stakes decisions than in large-stakes ones. No one is
and $20 to explain why subjects would be less willing to likely to be disappointed when they gamble on a 10%
take risks to obtain the former increase than the latter. chance of $1 and lose, or regret not choosing to accept a
Neither the magnitude eVect nor the peanuts eVect is certain $0.10 instead. Because the expected values of
in principle non-normative, since either could be both gambles are very small, when I lose the gamble and
explained under Expected Utility Theory by the shape of receive nothing, the resulting regret or disappointment is
the utility function. Either can be explained under Pros- very small as well. Therefore, disappointment and regret
pect Theory, also by the shape of the utility function. may not be major factors in these small-outcome gam-
However, they cannot both be explained by the shape of bles. Decision makers can aVord to take risks when play-
the utility function, as the two eVects require utility func- ing for peanuts, as they know they will not feel very
tions with opposing properties. much regret or disappointment about the outcome. In
If the utility function cannot explain both the peanuts contrast, for large-stakes gambles, where regret and dis-
and magnitude eVects, what can? The diVering directions appointment are much larger, the anticipated negative
of the peanuts and magnitude eVect suggest that some aVect may drive them to be more risk-averse.
34 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

Thus, disappointment, regret, or some combination One complication to a regret account of the peanuts
could well explain the peanuts eVect. Generally, avoiding eVect is the issue of feedback. According to the original
disappointment or regret drives people to more risk- Regret Theory, feeling regret requires knowing what the
averse decisions. If disappointment and regret play little outcome of the forgone choice would have been, allow-
role in decisions with small outcomes, decision makers ing easy comparison between the obtained and unob-
will be more risk-seeking for these small outcomes than tained outcomes. However, experiments involving
when making decisions for larger outcomes which do choices between gambles usually tell the subject nothing
involve the possibility of signiWcant disappointment or about the result of the gamble not chosen—including
regret. studies that have demonstrated the peanuts eVect. If
If disappointment is responsible for the peanuts eVect, there can be no regret without anticipated feedback then
it could also explain why the magnitude and peanuts regret cannot be the explanation for the peanuts eVect.
eVect run in opposite directions. By deWnition, disappoint- However, if regret depends on feedback it is not par-
ment occurs when a diVerent state of the world would ticularly useful for explaining real-world decision mak-
have produced a better outcome. This can only occur if ing either. Although sometimes we learn the outcome of
there are multiple possible states of the world with foregone options, usually we will never know what
regards to the outcome in question—in other words, if the would have happened if we would married our high
outcome is risky. A certain outcome has no alternate pos- school sweethearts (or failed to marry them), but it
sible states of the world and thus no potential for disap- seems unreasonable to suggest that we cannot regret our
pointment. Because the magnitude eVect involves certain choice if the outcome we did obtain was unfavorable.
outcomes, the choices that produce it are free of the possi- Empirically, the evidence for regret in the absence of
bility of disappointment. A decision-maker whose utility feedback is mixed. Some studies suggest it does not
functions displays increasing proportional sensitivity occur (e.g., Mellers, Schwartz, & Ritov, 1999) and others
could then show both the magnitude eVect and the pea- have found that that it does (e.g., Bar-Hillel & Neter,
nuts eVect: the magnitude eVect produced by the underly- 1996; Zeelenberg et al., 1998). Faced with mixed evidence
ing utility function, and the peanuts eVect produced by it seems reasonable to take the suggestion of Zeelenberg
the diVerential levels of disappointment incurred by out- (1999) and assume that regret is weaker but not absent
comes of diVerent sizes. Although such a utility function when decision-makers receive no feedback about the
would by itself result in the opposite of the peanuts eVect, unobtained outcome. If this is the case, regret could be
instead the peanuts eVect occurs because of the inXuence an explanation for the peanuts eVect.
of disappointment the domain of risky choice. Disappointment and regret are negative emotions
The question of regret and the magnitude eVect is associated with decisions with outcomes that were less
more complicated. Regret is experienced when a decision than ideal. However, decisions can also have positive
maker feels that a diVerent choice would have produced outcomes and the emotions associated them can likewise
a better outcome (Gilovich & Medvec, 1995), and this be positive. The disappointment one feels after losing a
could occur in both risky choice and intertemporal gamble goes hand and hand with the elation one feels
choice. For example, a dieter may impulsively eat two after winning; regret over making a choice that resulted
pieces of cheesecake, but regret the choice the next in a poorer outcome turns into rejoicing when the choice
morning when he steps on the scale. In fact, he may eat you made proves to be the optimal one.
the cheesecake even though he knows he will regret it It is possible that when making decisions, decision
later because the present utility of the cheesecake out- makers seek to experience elation and rejoicing as well as
weighs the future utility of losing weight—and the future to avoid disappointment and regret. However, such
disutility of the anticipated regret. behavior cannot explain the peanuts eVect: like disap-
Notice what happens as anticipated future regret pointment and regret, elation, and rejoicing increase as
increases. Eventually, the disutility of the regret associ- the size of the payout increases. The desire to experience
ated with making an impulsive choice becomes large elation and rejoicing would therefore drive decisions in
enough that the discounted future regret outweighs the the opposite direction of that seen in the peanuts eVect: as
appeal of the impulsive option. Thus, as anticipated the payouts increase, the potential for elation and rejoic-
regret increases, the willingness to wait for a future out- ing increases and we would expect to see subjects become
come should increase as well. This is precisely what more risk seeking for larger payouts, not more risk averse
occurs in the magnitude eVect in intertemporal choice. as seen in the peanuts eVect. Therefore we concentrate on
As the size of the outcome increases, and with it the disappointment and regret in the present studies.
associated regret, decision-makers become less impulsive
and more willing to wait. Regret can therefore poten- Current studies
tially explain the diVering directions of the peanuts and
magnitude eVect, as any inXuence of anticipated regret The purpose of the present experiments is twofold.
would drive the two eVects in diVerent directions. First, few studies have been conducted speciWcally to
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 35

investigate the peanuts eVect since it was Wrst proposed gamble means a large additional risk and a large addi-
by Markowitz in 1952 (e.g., Du et al., 2002; Holt et al., tional reward? Because both gambles in a choice pair
2003; Hogarth & Einhorn, 1990; Green et al., 1999; have the same expected value, the ratio between the
Myerson et al., 2003; Rachlin et al., 2000). To our knowl- probabilities corresponds to a complementary ratio
edge, no investigation of the peanuts eVect has extended between the two non-zero payouts.
far beyond the observation that it exists, and factors that Thus, in Experiment 1 we examined how the percent-
moderate the peanuts eVect have not been examined in a age of subjects selecting the less risky of two gambles var-
systematic fashion. Experiment 1 in the current paper ied with the magnitude of the non-zero outcomes, the
addresses this deWcit by examining when a peanuts eVect ratio between the probabilities to win in the two gambles,
is obtained and what factors inXuence its size and pres- and the size of the probabilities of the nonzero outcomes.
ence. This experiment provides an initial test of whether An eVect of the magnitude of the outcomes comprises a
the peanuts eVect can be explained by any utility func- peanuts eVect. If probability ratio or size interacts with
tion. It also examined what factors produce sizable pea- outcome magnitude, it would indicate that these factors
nuts eVects so that appropriate stimuli could be chosen (probability ratio or size) moderate the peanuts eVect.
for future experiments. Experiment 2 provided an addi- Besides being useful for providing future experiment
tional test of whether the peanuts eVect can be explained stimuli, Experiment 1 serves as a test of the ability of the
by the shape of the utility function and contrasted this Prospect Theory value function (or any utility function)
account with an alternative hypothesis that disappoint- to explain the peanuts eVect. A moderating eVect of
ment and/or regret are responsible for the peanuts eVect. probability size would require that the utility function
vary with outcome probability if an explanation based
on the utility function is to be tenable. Such dependence
Experiment 1: Payouts and probabilities is not permitted in either Prospect Theory or normative
Expected Utility Theory, in which the utility function is
The purpose of Experiment 1 was to explore the inXu- independent of the probability level.
ence of a variety of factors on the peanuts eVect, with an
eye towards Wnding values that would produce large Method
peanuts eVects for use in future experiments. Subjects
made choices between gamble pairs. Each gamble had Participants
one positive and one zero outcome. The two gambles in Two hundred and eleven undergraduates at Rutgers
a choice pair had the same expected value, but one was University participated in the experiment. They were
riskier than the other. Compared to the less risky gam- oVered the opportunity to Wll out the questionnaire after
ble, the riskier gamble had a higher positive outcome completing a Wnal exam for a lower-level psychology
and lower probability to obtain that outcome. class, in exchange for a $1 payment.
When considering possible peanuts eVect choice ques-
tions, it quickly became apparent that there are three Design
factors that can vary. One is the size of the magnitude Each subject was presented with the 12 questions
increase between the small-stakes gamble and the large- shown in Table 1. Each question was a binary choice
stakes gamble. Would contrasting a pair of gambles between a larger but riskier positive outcome and a
where the payout of the smaller, safer gamble was $10 vs. smaller but more probable positive outcome.
a pair where the smaller, safer payout was $100 be a There was one between-subjects manipulation: the
large enough increase to show a strong peanuts eVect, or ratio between the probabilities to win in the two gam-
should the larger pair of gambles have payouts in the bles. In each gamble pair, the less risky gamble had a
range of $1000 instead? Another factor was the magni- probability to win that was either 1.25 times, 2 times, or
tude of the probabilities used in the gambles. Markowitz 4 times the probability to win in the more risky option.
used choices between gambles and certain amounts in Comparing the three levels of probability ratio allowed
his examples. Is certainty necessary to produce a strong us to evaluate how the ratio between the probabilities
peanuts eVect, or can both options of the choice pairs be inXuenced the size of the peanuts eVect.
gambles? Should the probabilities of the gambles be There were two within-subject experimental manipu-
small or large? The third factor was the ratio between lations in Experiment 1: the magnitude of the payouts,
the probabilities of the non-zero payouts in the two and the magnitude of the probabilities of the outcomes.
gambles. If the winning outcome in the smaller, safer First, each gamble pair had one of four magnitude lev-
gamble occurred with 100% probability, how probable els: the nonzero outcome of the less risky gamble was
should the outcome in the larger, riskier gamble be to either $1, $10, $100, or $1000. The nonzero outcome of
produce a large peanuts eVect? Should it be 80%, so that the riskier gamble was either 1.25, 2, or 4 times the size of
choosing the gamble entails a small additional risk and the smaller outcome (depending on the probability
small additional reward, or 25%, so that choosing the ratio), so that the expected value of the two gambles was
36 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

Table 1
Experiment 1 questions
Probability ratio Probability magnitude Outcome magnitude
$1 $10 $100 $1000
1.25 Low 8%, $1.25 8%, $12.50 8%, $125 8%, $1250
10%, $1 10%, $10 10%, $100 10%, $1000
Medium 40%, $1.25 40%, $12.50 40%, $125 40%, $1250
50%, $1 50%, $10 50%, $100 50%, $1000
High 80%, $1.25 80%, $12.50 80%, $125 80%, $1250
100%, $1 100%, $10 100%, $100 100%, $1000
2 Low 5%, $2 5%, $20 5%, $200 5%, $2000
10%, $1 10%, $10 10%, $100 10%, $1000
Medium 25%, $2 25%, $20 25%, $200 25%, $2000
50%, $1 50%, $10 50%, $100 50%, $1000
High 50%, $2 50%, $20 50%, $200 50%, $2000
100%, $1 100%, $10 100%, $100 100%, $1000
4 Low 5%, $4 5%, $40 5%, $400 5%, $4000
20%, $1 20%, $10 20%, $100 20%, $1000
Medium 12%, $4 12%, $40 12%, $400 12%, $4000
48%, $1 48%, $10 48%, $100 48%, $1000
High 25%, $4 25%, $40 25%, $400 25%, $4000
100%, $1 100%, $10 100%, $100 100%, $1000

equal. Comparing the four levels of payout magnitude Each question presented the participant with two gam-
aVords a demonstration of the peanuts eVect. bles. The participants were asked to circle the alternative
Second, the probabilities of the nonzero outcomes they preferred.
could be small, medium, or large. The value of the prob-
abilities at these three levels varied with level of the Results and discussion
probability ratio: they were chosen so that, at the largest
level of probability, the less risky gamble had a probabil- As shown in Table 2, participants displayed a signiW-
ity to win of 100%. Comparing the three levels of proba- cant peanuts eVect. A 4 (payout magnitude) £ 3 (proba-
bility magnitude indicates whether the peanuts eVect bility magnitude) £ 3 (probability ratio) mixed model
varies with the size of the probability, and in particular, logistic regression analysis used choice of the safer gam-
whether the peanuts eVect depends on one of the out- ble as the dependent variable. (Results are identical to
comes being certain. The 4 (outcome magnitude) £ 3 the results obtained if choice of the riskier gamble is
(probability magnitude) £ 3 (probability ratio) mixed- used.) It showed a signiWcant main eVect of payout mag-
factors design resulted in three questionnaire versions nitude (2 (3, N D 211) D 91.65, p < .05), indicating that
with 12 questions in each (see Table 1). subjects were less likely to choose the riskier gamble as
payout magnitude increased. This result comprises the
Materials peanuts eVect. The interaction between payout magni-
Each participant was presented with a one-page ques- tude and probability magnitude was also signiWcant,
tionnaire that included 12 questions. Half of the subjects (2 (6, N D 211) D 16.85, p < .05), indicating that the pea-
saw the 12 questions in one random order and half saw a nuts eVect was larger for larger probability magnitudes.
reverse of that random order to control for order eVects. In addition, the interaction between payout magnitude
Table 2
Percentage (n) of subjects choosing the risky option in Experiment 1
Probability ratio Probability magnitude Outcome magnitude
$1 $10 $100 $1000 DiVerence ($1 ¡ $1000)
1.25 Low 50% (28) 46% (26) 45% (25) 62% (35) ¡12%
Medium 36% (20) 30% (17) 25% (14) 48% (27) ¡12%
High 21% (12) 14% (8) 14% (8) 14% (8) 7%
2 Low 67% (70) 59% (62) 43% (45) 44% (46) 23%
Medium 59% (62) 44% (46) 23% (24) 16% (17) 43%
High 42% (44) 29% (30) 9% (9) 7% (7) 35%
4 Low 61% (30) 39% (19) 22% (11) 18% (9) 43%
Medium 63% (31) 31% (15) 10% (5) 10% (5) 53%
High 55% (27) 23% (11) 8% (4) 6% (3) 49%
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 37

and probability ratio was signiWcant, (2 (6,N D211) D odds that a subject chose the risk-averse alternative
63.46, p <.05), indicating that the peanuts eVect was larger based on a linear combination of binary dummy vari-
for the larger probability ratios. These choice percentages ables comparing each level of the dependant variables to
are reported numerically in Table 2 and graphically in a reference level. The coeYcients of the logistic regres-
Fig. 3. The logistic regression analysis modeled the log sion are displayed in Table 3. Results are modeled such

Fig. 3. Percentage of subjects choosing the risky option in Experiment 1.

Table 3
Logistic regression coeYcients for the log odds of choosing the safer optiona
Factor Levels Regression coeYcient Lower 95% Upper 95%
conWdence conWdence
Payout magnitudeb $1 vs. $10 1.40 0.72 2.07
$1 vs. $100 2.62 1.60 3.65
$1 vs. $1000 2.93 1.67 4.20
Probability magnitudeb High vs. medium ¡0.34 ¡0.96 0.28
High vs. low ¡0.25 ¡0.89 0.38
Probability ratiob 4 vs. 2 0.53 ¡0.16 1.21
4 vs. 1.25 1.50 0.65 2.36
Payout magnitude ¤ probability magnitude $1 vs. $10 and high vs. medium ¡0.04 ¡1.03 0.96
$1 vs. $10 and high vs. low ¡0.48 ¡1.31 0.34
$1 vs. $100 and high vs. medium 0.09 ¡1.06 1.24
$1 vs. $100 and high vs. low ¡0.93 ¡2.10 0.24
$1 vs. $1000 and high vs. medium ¡0.27 ¡1.62 1.09
$1 vs. $1000 and high vs. low ¡0.99 ¡2.35 0.24
Payout magnitude ¤ probability ratio $1 vs. $10 and 4 vs. 2 ¡0.81 ¡1.61 ¡0.01
$1 vs. $10 and 4 vs. 1.25 ¡0.90 ¡1.98 0.17
$1 vs. $100 and 4 vs. 2 ¡0.59 ¡1.86 0.69
$1 vs. $100 and 4 vs. 1.25 ¡2.13 ¡3.41 ¡0.86
$1 vs. $1000 and 4 vs. 2 ¡0.62 ¡2.13 0.90
$1 vs. $1000 and 4 vs. 1.25 ¡2.44 ¡3.92 ¡0.97
a
Regression was performed on the log odds of choosing the safer option so that positive coeYcients for magnitude and its interactions would
represent a peanuts eVect. Regressing on the log odds of the riskier option reverses the sign of all coeYcients.
b
In a logistic regression, the coeYcients of a main eVect represent the eVect of that variable when the variables it interacts with are at their refer-
ence levels. For example, the coeYcients for magnitude represent the eVects of magnitude when the probability ratio D 4 and the probability
level D high, and so forth. The overall eVect of a variable can be found by adding the coeYcients for the main eVect and all the interactions the vari-
able participates in.
38 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

that positive coeYcients for outcome magnitude and its probability ratio were more risk averse at the $1 payout
interactions represent a peanuts eVect. level than those who saw the higher ratios. At the 1.25
The signiWcant interaction between payout magni- ratio, there is only a small incentive for taking the
tude and probability ratio indicates that the size of the greater risk, and this incentive does not appear to be
peanuts eVect depends on the ratio between the proba- enough to induce the subjects to gamble for peanuts.
bilities of the nonzero outcomes in the choice pair. Conversely, at the $1000 magnitude the subjects who
When the probability ratio is 1.25, the peanuts eVect is saw the 1.25 probability ratio were much less risk averse
non-existent—in fact, for some probability levels there than those who saw the higher ratios. Here, the compar-
appears to be an reverse peanuts eVect, with subjects atively small additional risk was apparently small
giving less risk-averse responses for the $1000 payout enough to be ignored in favor of the larger reward. Only
magnitude than for the smaller payouts. A logistic when making the riskier choice would mean forgoing a
regression analysis conducted on only the group of sub- certain $1000 (i.e., at the high probability magnitude)
jects where probability ratio was 1.25 shows a main were the 1.25 probability ratio subjects as risk averse as
eVect of payout magnitude, indicating that this reverse those who saw higher ratios.
peanuts eVect is signiWcant. (2 (3, N D 56) D 11.11, Our initial hypothesis was that the size of the peanuts
p < .05) When the larger probability is 2 or 4 times the eVect would always increase as the ratio between the
smaller, there is a noticeable peanuts eVect. Repeating high and low magnitude payouts increased. That is, we
the logistic regression analysis without the group of had assumed that the peanuts eVect produced by a
subjects where probability ratio was 1.25 still reveals a 1000-fold increase (as between the $1 and $1000 payout
signiWcant interaction between magnitude and proba- magnitude levels) would be substantially larger than
bility ratio (2 (3, N D 155) D 10.05, p < .05), indicating that produced by a 100-fold increase. Surprisingly, this
that the peanuts eVect obtained when the probability did not turn out to be the case. As seen in Fig. 3, the
ratio is 4 is larger than that obtained for probability additional increase in risk aversion gained by going from
ratio 2. the $100 level to the $1000 level was not signiWcant. That
The signiWcant interaction between payout magni- is, comparing the $100 and $1000 payout levels did not
tude and probability magnitude indicates that the size reveal a peanuts eVect except in the 1.25 probability ratio
of the peanuts eVect increases with increasing case, when a reverse peanuts was evident when compar-
probability magnitude. The reverse peanuts eVect pres- ing the $100 and $1000 levels.
ent at the lower probability levels for the 1.25 probabil- Evidently, the size of the peanuts eVect produced by a
ity ratio disappears at the highest probability level. For 10-fold increase depends on where in the scale the
the 2 and 4 probability ratios, the peanuts eVect is increase occurs. The reasons behind this Wnding are not
slightly smaller at the lowest probability level than at entirely clear. One possibility is that the undergraduates
the largest two levels. The logistic regression analysis completing this survey tend to lump the $100 level and
performed on only the 2 and 4 probability ratios indi- $1000 level magnitudes together into one “more money
cates that the outcome magnitude by probability mag- than I am likely to deal with on a regular basis” level.
nitude interaction is still signiWcant (2 (6, N D 155) However, the reverse peanuts eVect displayed when the
D 14.97, p < .05). probability ratio was 1.25 does suggest that subjects
The main eVect of probability magnitude was also sig- were distinguishing between the $100 and $1000 payout
niWcant, (2 (2, N D 211) D 61.20, p < .05), indicating that magnitudes. It would be interesting to see whether the
subjects were less inclined to choose the riskier outcome $100 to $1000 change produced a peanuts eVect for
at higher levels of probability. The tendency of decision- higher-income subjects who are more accustomed to
makers to become more risk averse as probability levels dealing with larger amounts of money.
increase is called the Common Ratio EVect and has been These data do not suggest any special role of certainty
found in other studies (e.g., Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). in the peanuts eVect—for the two probability ratios that
The main eVect of probability ratio was not signiWcant, displayed a peanuts eVect, the eVect was no larger for the
(2 (2, N D 211) D 2.89, p > .05), indicating that the ratio highest level of probability (which involved a certain
between the probabilities of the two outcomes had no option) than for the second highest level. The lowest
eVect on the risk preferences of the subjects.1 probability level, however, did show a somewhat smaller
It is clear from the results of Experiment 1 that the peanuts eVect. This pattern is further examined in
peanuts eVect is only evident when the ratio between the Experiment 2.
probabilities—and hence the payouts—of the two What do these results say about the compatibility of
options is above a certain size. Subjects who saw the 1.25 the peanuts eVect and Prospect Theory? As noted above,
the peanuts eVect itself is compatible with Prospect The-
1
The two-way interaction between probability ratio and probability
ory so long as subjects are never actually risk seeking for
level and the three-way interaction are of no theoretical interest and gains. The subjects in the current study, however,
are not reported. showed a slight tendency to be risk seeking at the lower
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 39

two levels of probability when the probability ratio was and regret on the peanuts eVect. Additionally, Experi-
2 or 4. This is not compatible with the utility function ment 2 tested whether a reXected peanuts eVect occurred
postulated by Prospect Theory, which is concave in the domain of losses.
throughout in the domain of gains. Consider opening a soft drink bottle with the adver-
An interaction between probability ratio and payout tisement, “Find the winning game piece to win a new
magnitude is not necessarily incompatible with Prospect car!” Opening the bottle, you Wnd “Sorry, you are not a
Theory. Larger probability ratios must also have larger winner” written under the lid. Are you disappointed?
ratios between the magnitudes of the nonzero payout— Probably not—the chances of winning such a contest are
if the probability ratio is 4, the larger payout must be 4 small, and you weren’t really expecting to win. Were you
times greater than the smaller payout for the expected to Xip a coin for the same car and lose, the resulting feel-
values of the two gambles to be equal. The greater diVer- ings could well be diVerent.
ence between the nonzero payouts magniWes the eVects Why are you less disappointed about failing to win the
of utility function shape. For example, a concave utility car in the bottle cap case than in the coin Xip case? Bell
function that becomes more curved (i.e., increasing risk (1985) postulated that experienced disappointment is
aversion) as the payout increases would result in the pea- linked to the probability of the outcomes. The disappoint-
nuts eVect. Because the risk aversion of the function ment engendered by an unfavorable outcome is inversely
increases with magnitude, risk aversion is higher in the proportional to the probability of the outcome being unfa-
choice between $100 and $400 (at the probability vorable. If the probability of winning is high, a loss is dis-
ratio D 4 level) than in the choice between $100 and $200 appointing; if the probability of winning is low, the loss is
(at the probability ratio D 2 level). However, the small expected and thus disappointment is low. Mellers et al.
$1, $2, and $4 outcomes all show more or less the same (1997) showed subjects spinners representing gambles of
low level of risk aversion. Thus the peanuts eVect is varying payout size and probability. After subjects
larger at the probability ratio D 4 level. However, the fact “played” each gamble on the computer, they were asked
that subjects showed a reverse peanuts eVect at the $1000 to report their disappointment with the outcome. Subjects
magnitude for the 1.25 probability ratio remains puz- were less disappointed by obtaining $0 instead of a gain
zling. This result is not strictly incompatible with Pros- when the probability of obtaining the gain was small than
pect Theory—it could be explained by a utility function when it was large. This Wnding has been replicated in
in which risk aversion increases overall, but which has a numerous studies (e.g., Mellers et al., 1999; van Dlijk &
small region of decreasing risk aversion in the area of van der Pligt, 1997). Moreover, Mellers et al. (1999) found
$1250. However, such a utility function would be non- that subjects are excellent at anticipating the disappoint-
parsimonious and post hoc. Consequently, the current ment they would actually feel following a losing gamble.
data suggest that perhaps the shape of the utility func- If decreasing levels of probability corresponds to
tion is not the proper explanation for the peanuts eVect. decreasing levels of disappointment, then probability
The interaction between payout magnitude and prob- can be used as a disappointment manipulation. We
ability magnitude is entirely incompatible with Prospect hypothesized that the peanuts eVect occurs because dis-
Theory. A utility function explanation of this result appointment is very small for decisions with small out-
would require a utility function that changes as the comes. Without the inXuence of disappointment,
probability of the outcome changes. Such a utility func- decision-makers are more risk-seeking for these deci-
tion is not permitted by Prospect Theory. Even in Cumu- sions. Therefore, if disappointment can be eliminated
lative Prospect Theory (Tversky & Kahneman, 1992), from the large outcome gamble as well as the small out-
where utility and probability are not separable, the come gamble, the peanuts eVect should go away. If par-
shape of the utility function is not inXuenced by the ticipants show a reduced peanuts eVect at lower levels of
probability level. Therefore, this result suggests that the probability, where disappointment is also low, it sup-
shape of the utility function cannot be the correct expla- ports the disappointment hypothesis. However, if the
nation for the peanuts eVect. peanuts eVect is not due to disappointment—for exam-
If the utility function cannot explain the peanuts ple, if it is due to the shape of the utility function—then
eVect, what can? Experiment 2 explores the possibility it is unlikely to be inXuenced by probability level.
that the cause of the peanuts eVect lies in the realm of Regret is another emotion that may contribute to the
Decision AVect Theory (Mellers et al., 1997). peanuts eVect. Regret depends upon making a choice. If
you are presented with only one option, and it turns out
badly, you may be disappointed, but you cannot regret a
Experiment 2: Regret, disappointment, and loss decision you never made. Therefore, regret can be
manipulated by presenting participants either with a sin-
In Experiment 1, we established sets of gambles that gle option to evaluate or asking them to choose between
yielded a strong peanuts eVect. In Experiment 2, we used two options. With no choice, there is no possibility for
this information to study the impact of disappointment regret. If the peanuts eVect is reduced when no choice is
40 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

involved, it lends support to the hypothesis that regret is design. There were two levels of payout magnitude: the
a cause of the peanuts eVect. If the peanuts eVect $1 level (with single-digit payouts) and the $100 level
is unaVected by the presence or absence of choice, then it (with triple-digit payouts). The three levels of probability
is unlikely to be due to regret. magnitude were low (less than 10%), medium (30% or
In Experiment 2, we manipulated the probability level less) and high (40–90%) probability to win (or lose).
in the gamble pairs and whether subjects evaluated the Each subject saw both choice questions and rating
gambles by choosing between pairs of gambles or by rat- questions. In choice questions, subjects were presented
ing individual gambles. These manipulations provided a with two gambles of the same expected value and asked to
test of whether disappointment and regret moderate the select the one they preferred. In rating questions, subjects
peanuts eVect. were presented with a single gamble and asked to rate its
One concern with manipulating regret in this fashion attractiveness on a scale from 1 to 100 for gain gambles
is the possibility that the response mode may interact (where higher numbers meant more attractive) or ¡100 to
with the peanuts eVect for reasons unrelated to regret. ¡1 for loss gambles (where more negative numbers meant
There is a large body of literature demonstrating that more unattractive). The ratings responses were converted
response mode (e.g., ratings vs. selling prices vs. choices) to choice responses by putting the gambles into pairs cor-
can have considerable inXuence on decision-makers’ responding to the pairs used in the choice response and
preferences (e.g., Lichtenstein & Slovic, 1971; Tversky, determining which gamble had been given the higher rat-
Sattath, & Slovic, 1988). Could response mode aVect the ing. This gamble was considered preferred.
peanuts eVect for reasons unrelated to regret? Few stud- Although each subject saw both types of questions,
ies have been done on the interaction between payout no subject saw the same questions for both choice and
magnitude and response mode. Casey (1991, 1994) found rating. Instead, two sets of questions were used. Each
results that seem to suggest the peanuts eVect might be subject made choices for one set of questions and rated
stronger for rating than for choice. However, these stud- gambles for the other set. Each set of questions was seen
ies were designed to examine the eVects of magnitude on by about half the subjects for choice and by the other
preference reversals that occur between response modes, half for rating, as determined randomly by the computer.
rather than examining the eVects of response mode on Additionally, each subject saw both gain questions and
the peanuts eVect as we do in Experiment 2. Thus, while loss questions. For each subject, the loss questions were
suggestive, the Casey results are inconclusive. Moreover, identical to the gain questions except for the sign of the
response mode is as strongly correlated with regret in the payout. This design resulted in 36 questions for each sub-
Casey studies as it is in the current Experiment 2. ject. Two levels of probability magnitude and three levels
Whether the use of response mode as a regret manipu- of payout magnitude resulted in six choice gain questions
lation is a problem will ultimately depend on the outcome for each subject. As each half of the subjects rated gambles
of the experiment. If there is a signiWcant interaction that the other half had chosen between, there were 12 rat-
between response mode and the peanuts eVect, additional ing gain questions per subject. Each subject saw the same
experiments will be necessary to determine if the interac- questions for losses as they saw for gains, for 36 total ques-
tion was driven by regret rather than by some other fac- tions. The various questions are presented in Table 4.
tor inherent in diVering response modes. However, if
there is no diVerence between choice and rating, the fail- Materials
ure to Wnd a diVerence could not be attributed to any The experiment was conducted on the subject’s com-
inherent diVerences between the response modes. If the puter via the World Wide Web. After reading some
peanuts eVect appears full strength when there is no pos-
sibility for regret it would clearly indicate that regret is Table 4
Experiment 2 questions
not the cause of the peanuts eVect.
Probability magnitude Outcome magnitude
Method $1 $100
Question Set 1 Low 2%, $6 2%, $600
Participants 4%, $3 4%, $300
One hundred forty-six undergraduates at Rutgers Medium 10%, $6 10%, $600
20%, $3 20%, $300
University participated in the experiment in partial ful- High 40%, $6 40%, $600
Wllment of a research participation requirement for an 80%, $3 80%, $300
introductory psychology class.
Question Set 2 Low 3%, $4 3%, $400
6%, $2 6%, $200
Design Medium 15%, $4 15%, $400
The experiment used a 2 (response mode: choice vs 30%, $2 30%, $200
rating) £ 2 (outcome sign: gains vs. losses) £ 2 (payout High 45%, $4 45%, $400
90%, $2 90%, $200
magnitude) £ 3 (probability magnitude) within-subject
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 41

Table 5
Percentage (n) of subjects choosing the risky option in Experiment 2
Sign Probability magnitude Outcome magnitude choice Outcome magnitude ratinga
$1 $100 Peanuts eVect $1 $100 Peanuts eVect
($1 ¡ $100) ($1 ¡ $100)
Gains Low 42% (61) 41% (60) 1% 37% (35) 32% (37) 5%
Medium 40% (58) 27% (40) 13% 31% (36) 26% (32) 5%
High 24% (35) 10% (14) 14% 22% (29) 3% (4) 19%
Losses Low 62% (90) 59% (86) 3% 58% (57) 57% (69) 1%
Medium 62% (91) 64% (94) ¡2% 59% (70) 66% (84) ¡7%
High 69% (101) 82% (119) ¡13% 53% (69) 89% (118) ¡36%
a
Percentages shown are choices inferred from ratings.

instructions, subjects were presented with four screens of magnitude) £ 3 (probability magnitude) £ 2 (response
questions: a screen of gains choice questions, a screen of mode) logistic analysis, performed on gains responses,
gains rating questions, a screen of losses choice ques- showed a signiWcant main eVect of payout magnitude
tions, and a screen of losses rating questions. Thus sub- (2 (1, N D 146) D 25.20, p < .05), indicating that the per-
jects always saw the ratings and choice questions centage of risk-averse responses was lower for low pay-
separately: they were never on the screen at the same out magnitudes than for high ones. We did not Wnd that
time. The two gains screens were always presented con- subjects actually became risk-seeking for very small
secutively, as were the two losses screens. Whether gains gains as we did in Experiment 1; however, this is not a
or losses were presented Wrst was determined randomly requirement for the peanuts eVect.
for each subject. For each subject, the choice screen in The interaction between payout magnitude and
each domain always preceded the ratings screen, or vice probability magnitude was also signiWcant, (2 (2, N D
versa; to prevent order eVects, whether the ratings or 146) D 26.60, p < .05). This indicates that the peanuts
choices screen was presented Wrst was determined ran- eVect occurred when probabilities were high but not
domly for each subject. The two ratings questions com- when probabilities were low. The interaction between
pared to infer a choice were not presented side-by-side, payout magnitude and response mode was not signiW-
but separately as part of a list of single-evaluation rat- cant, (2 (1, N D 146) D 1.72, p > .05). This indicates that
ings. To avoid order eVects, within each screen of ques- the peanuts eVect did not diVer in size between ratings
tions, the questions were presented in a random order and choice responses. The main eVects of probability
for both rating and choice questions.2 magnitude and response mode were signiWcant,
(2 (1, N D 146) D 75.21, p < .05) and (2 (1, N D 146)
Results and discussion D 4.31, p < .05), respectively, with participants being
less risk-averse for lower probabilities and for choice
Participants’ ratings were converted to choices by responses. Data for gains responses are reported
comparing the separately given ratings of the two numerically in Table 5 and graphically in Fig. 4. The
options. The gamble with the higher rating was consid- coeYcients of the logistic regression are displayed in
ered preferred; if the two ratings were equal, the Table 6.3
response was not used in the analysis.
A logistic regression on outcome sign (gains vs. Losses
losses) showed a signiWcant eVect, (2 (1, N D 146) D Data for losses is also displayed in Table 5. In the
235.59, p < .05). (The regression coeYcient for outcome domain of losses participants displayed a signiWcant
sign was 2.05.) This indicates that subjects were indeed reXected peanuts eVect. That is, they were more risk
risk averse for gains and risk seeking for losses, as pre- seeking for large losses than for small ones. A 2 (payout
dicted by Prospect Theory. Further analyses of data for magnitude) £ 3 (probability magnitude) £ 2 (response
gains and losses were conducted separately. mode) logistic analysis, performed on losses responses,
showed a signiWcant main eVect of payout magnitude
Gains (2 (1, N D 146) D 15.10, p < .05), indicating a reXected
As shown in Table 5, participants displayed a signiW- peanuts eVect.
cant peanuts eVect in the domain of gains. A 2 (payout The interaction between payout magnitude and prob-
2
ability magnitude was also signiWcant, (2 (2, N D 146) D
Including order in the analysis resulted in only one signiWcant inter-
action, a four-way interaction between payout magnitude, probability
3
magnitude, response mode, and rating/choice order in the domain of The two-way interaction between probability level and response
losses (2 (2, N D 146) D 8.33, p < .05). Therefore, order was not includ- mode and the three-way interaction are of no theoretical interest and
ed in any of the other analyses for Experiment 2. are not reported.
42 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

Fig. 4. Percentage of subjects choosing the risky option in Experiment 2: Gains.

Table 6
Logistic regression coeYcients for the log odds of choosing the safer option: gains
Factor Levels Regression Lower 95% Upper 95%
coeYcient conWdence conWdence
Payout magnitude $1 vs. $100 2.17 1.26 3.08
Probability magnitude High vs. medium ¡0.55 ¡1.03 ¡0.07
High vs. low ¡0.68 ¡1.24 ¡0.13
Response mode Choice vs. rating ¡0.09 ¡0.62 0.45
Payout magnitude ¤ probability magnitude $1 vs. $100 and high vs. medium ¡1.83 ¡2.76 ¡0.90
$1 vs. $100 and high vs. low ¡2.00 ¡3.01 ¡0.99
Payout magnitude ¤ response mode $1 vs. $100 and choice vs. rating ¡1.08 ¡2.19 0.03

35.46, p < .05). This indicates that the reXected peanuts cates that the peanuts eVect was slightly larger in ratings
eVect occurred when probabilities were high but not responses than in choice responses—the opposite of
when probabilities were low. The interaction between what was predicted by the regret hypothesis. The main
payout magnitude and response mode was signiWcant, eVect of probability magnitude was signiWcant, (2 (1,N
(2 (1, N D 146) D 4.62, p < .05); however, this eVect indi- D146)D 28.19, p<.05), indicating that participants were
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 43

Fig. 5. Percentage of subjects choosing the risky option in Experiment 2: Losses.

Table 7
Logistic regression coeYcients for the log odds of choosing the safer option: losses
Factor Levels Regression Lower 95% Upper 95%
coeYcient conWdence conWdence
Payout magnitude $1 vs. $100 1.89 1.32 2.47
Probability magnitude High vs. medium 0.18 ¡0.24 0.60
High vs. low 0.21 ¡0.29 0.71
Response mode Choice vs. rating 0.65 0.19 1.12
Payout magnitude ¤ probability magnitude $1 vs. $100 and high vs. medium ¡1.61 ¡2.27 ¡0.94
$1 vs. $100 and high vs. low ¡2.00 ¡2.76 ¡1.24
Payout magnitude ¤ response mode $1 vs. $100 and choice vs. rating ¡1.22 ¡1.87 ¡0.57

more risk seeking for higher probability gambles. The are reported numerically in Table 5 and graphically in
main eVect of response mode was not signiWcant, Fig. 5. The coeYcients of the logistic regression are dis-
(2 (1, N D 146) D 0.27, p > .05). Data for losses responses played in Table 7.3
44 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

Discussion Hogarth and Einhorn (1990), which found that decision-


makers are more risk averse for both large losses and
As in Experiment 1, the interaction between probabil- large gains than they are for small losses and small gains.
ity magnitude and payout magnitude cannot be The reason for this discrepancy is not clear. Some of the
explained by the shape of the utility function. This result gambles used by Hogarth and Einhorn involved much
instead suggests that the peanuts eVect is related to dis- larger losses than those used in the present study, with
appointment. When probabilities, and therefore disap- expected values of ¡$20,000. It has been suggested that
pointment, are low, neither a peanuts eVect (gains) nor a the usual pattern of risk-seeking behavior for losses may
reXected peanuts eVect (losses) occurs. The peanuts eVect break down when the losses incurred are large enough to
materializes only when probabilities are high, making result in Wnancial ruin (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979).
disappointment possible. It should be noted that the cur- Therefore we might expect to Wnd a peanuts eVect for
rent study did not include a direct measure of disap- losses with outcomes in this range, rather than a
pointment. Instead we infer that the moderating eVect of reXected peanuts eVect. However, some of the gambles
probability level of the peanuts eVect is due to the eVect used in Hogarth and Einhorn (1990) had values compa-
of probability level on anticipated disappointment. rable to those used in the present experiment, with
In contrast, the results do not support a role of regret expected values of ¡$200, and they found the peanuts
in the peanuts eVect. In the domain of gains there was no eVect (rather than the reXected peanuts eVect) for these
eVect of response mode on the peanuts eVect. Because a gambles as well. While the results of Experiment 2 sug-
choiceless response must by deWnition be regretless, this gest that a reXected peanuts eVect may sometimes occur
suggests that regret is not related to the peanuts eVect. In for losses, it remains unclear whether this occurs at all
the domain of losses, the reXected peanuts eVect was times or for all sizes of monetary payouts.
actually slightly larger for rating responses than for
choice responses. This is the opposite of what the regret
hypothesis predicts—if the reXected peanuts eVect is due General discussion
to regret, the eVect should be smaller in the absence of
regret, not larger. Why this counter-predicted eVect The peanuts eVect is not a well-understood or well-stud-
occurs, and only in the domain of losses, is unclear. ied phenomenon. The current studies provide evidence as
Casey (1991, 1994) also found results that seem to sug- to the conditions under which the phenomenon occurs and
gest the peanuts eVect might be stronger for rating than the psychological factors that may produce the eVect.
for choice. However, these studies were not designed to
examine the peanuts eVect, and thus the results are only Conditions that produce the peanuts eVect
suggestive.
Earlier we discussed the possibility that diVerences The current experiments help to Xesh out understand-
between rating and choice not related to regret could ing of what conditions generate peanuts eVect responses
inXuenced the outcome of the present experiment: had in decision makers. The size of the magnitude increase
we found that the peanuts eVect diVered between rating between the small-magnitude gambles and the large-
and choice, it would have been impossible to determine magnitude gambles is an important factor, but by no
if the diVerence was due to the eVects of regret or to means the only one. Decision makers certainly choose
unrelated diVerences between the two response modes. diVerently when asked to pick between a 50% chance of
As we did not Wnd a diVerence in the size of the peanuts $20 and $10 for sure than when asked to chose between
eVect between ratings and choice, at least in the domain a 50% chance of $200 and $100 for sure, but this same
of gains, this is not an issue. We can safely conclude that 10-fold payout increase does not induce the peanuts
the evidence suggests that regret is not responsible for eVect at all points on the magnitude scale—the diVerence
the peanuts eVect. between $100 and $1000 is less likely to induce a peanuts
The fact that a reXected peanuts eVect occurs in the eVect than the diVerence between $10 and $100.
domain of losses is consistent with the common Wnding The peanuts eVect is larger for larger probabilities;
that decision makers are risk averse for gains but risk however, it does not require certainty. Although Marko-
seeking for losses (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). The witz’s original example of the peanuts eVect involved
results of the present study suggest that this “reXection certainty, it is not required to obtain the phenomenon.
eVect” inXuences the peanuts eVect as well, reXecting it The peanuts eVect is also larger when the ratio between
across the origin. In the domain of gains, decision mak- the probabilities of the two outcomes is larger. In fact,
ers generally risk averse, but are less so for small Experiment 1 found a reverse peanuts eVect for the
amounts of money than for large ones. In the domain of smallest probability ratio. At least in some cases, the
losses, decision makers are generally risk seeking, but are peanuts eVect reXects across the origin into the domain
less so for small amounts of money than for large ones. of losses, with decision makers becoming more risk-seek-
However, the results of the present study disagree with ing for large losses than for small losses.
B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46 45

It is not clear whether subjects actually become risk magnitude eVect in intertemporal choice, it is problem-
seeking for suYciently small gains, as Markowitz pos- atic for any common account of the two types of deci-
tulated, or if they merely become less risk averse. sions. This puzzle may be solved if, as the current data
Experiment 1 found that subjects were slightly risk suggest, disappointment is the psychological mecha-
seeking for the smallest gain payouts. However, Experi- nism that produces the peanuts eVect. That is, it may be
ment 2 did not replicate these Wndings. Markowitz’s that risky choice and intertemporal choice are parallel
examples of risk seeking involved very small gains of for the most part, with a common set of decision pro-
less than $1, smaller than the outcomes included in the cesses underlying both and producing analogous sets of
current experiments. Future experiments that include biases in the two domains. Some decision processes,
gambles for very small payouts may help shed light on such as disappointment, however, may apply only to
this issue. one domain and thus produce occasional diVerences
between risky and intertemporal choice. If inXuences
Psychological accounts of the peanuts eVect such as disappointment could be removed, the two
domains would appear more parallel than they ordinar-
Markowitz’s (1952) account of the peanuts eVect ily would be.
speculated that it was caused by the shape of the utility The peanuts eVect has practical importance as well.
function for money. This account would make the pea- Most studies of decision making (including the current
nuts eVect not only consistent with Prospect Theory, but studies) use either hypothetical scenarios or decisions
also potentially normative, since normative EUT allows with real but small consequences. Decisions for trivial
for any utility function shape. The current studies, how- laboratory outcomes may not always be similar to deci-
ever, indicate that the peanuts eVect cannot be plausibly sions made in the real world about weighty conse-
explained by the shape of the utility function. A utility quences. Consider studies by Casey (1991, 1994): besides
function cannot account for the decrease in the size of demonstrating the peanuts eVect, these studies also
the peanuts eVect for smaller probabilities. This results found that a well-studied bid/choice preference reversal
pattern would require many diVerent utility functions phenomenon occurs in the opposite of the standard
for diVerent probability levels, which is not permitted by direction when studied using large payouts instead of the
either normative theories or by Prospect Theory. There- more usual small ones. This unexpected reversal of a
fore the present results suggest that the peanuts eVect is widely established Wnding underscores the importance of
nonnormative and cannot be accounted for by Prospect remembering that decision makers do not behave the
Theory. Although it would be possible to posit a descrip- same way for small payouts as they do for large ones
tive theory where the shape of the utility function was Decision making studies often involve choices
inXuenced by probability level, such an account would between (usually modest) amounts of money or scenar-
be ad hoc and non-parsimonious. ios about everyday, low-stakes outcomes, such as aca-
Experiment 2 supports the hypothesis that avoidance demic assignments or consumer products. In contrast,
of anticipated disappointment is a cause of the peanuts the real-world choices where good decision making is
eVect. The peanuts eVect vanishes at low probabilities, most crucial involve high stakes such as life-and-death
precisely when previous researchers have found that dis- medical treatment choices, policy decisions about
appointment is also low. Future research that includes whether to go to war, or personal decisions about whom
direct measures of the anticipated disappointment expe- to marry. The peanuts eVect illustrates one respect in
rienced by subjects who display the peanuts eVect would which the low payout, low-stakes decisions studied in
strengthen this conclusion. laboratory tasks will likely diVer from the high-stakes
The results of the current studies do not seem to indi- decisions made in real life.
cate that regret is related to the peanuts eVect in any
way. The size of the peanuts eVect is not reduced when
subjects rate options rather than choosing between them, References
circumstances that cannot produce regret. Future
research measuring anticipated regret of subjects who Bar-Hillel, M., & Neter, E. (1996). Why are people reluctant to
display the peanuts eVect when choosing between pea- exchange lottery tickets?. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
ogy, 70(1), 17–27.
nuts would help strengthen this conclusion, as well. Bell, D. E. (1982). Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Opera-
A clearer understanding of the mechanisms underly- tions Research, 30, 961–981.
ing the peanuts eVect has both theoretical and practical Bell, D. E. (1985). Disappointment in decision making under uncer-
value. The peanuts eVect has implications for under- tainty. Operations Research, 33, 1–27.
standing the parallels between decision processes in Casey, J. (1991). Reversal of the preference reversal phenomenon.
Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Making, 48, 224–251.
risky choice and those in intertemporal choice (Prelec & Casey, J. (1994). Buyer’s pricing behavior for risky alternatives: Encod-
Loewenstein, 1991). Because the peanuts eVect runs in ing processes and preference reversals. Management Science, 40(6),
the opposite direction from the otherwise analogous 730–749.
46 B.J. Weber, G.B. Chapman / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 97 (2005) 31–46

Chapman, G. B. (1996). Temporal discounting and utility for health Markowitz, H. (1952). The utility of wealth. Journal of Political Econ-
and money. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Mem- omy, 60(2), 151–158.
ory, and Cognition, 22, 771–791. Mellers, B., Schwartz, A., Ho, K., & Ritov, I. (1997). Decision aVect the-
Chapman, G. B., & Winquist, J. R. (1998). The magnitude eVect: Tem- ory: Emotional responses to the outcomes of risk gambles. Psycho-
poral discount rates and restaurant tips. Psychonomic Bulletin and logical Science, 8(8), 423–428.
Review, 5, 119–123. Mellers, B., Schwartz, A., & Ritov, I. (1999). Emotion-based choice.
Du, W., Green, L., & Myerson, J. (2002). Cross-cultural comparisons of Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 128(3), 332–345.
discounting delayed and probabilistic rewards. The Psychological Myerson, J., Green, L., Hanson, J., Holt, D., & Estle, S. (2003). Dis-
Record, 52, 479–492. counting delayed and probabilistic rewards: Processes and traits.
Gilovich, T., & Medvec, V. H. (1995). The experience of regret: What, Journal of Economic Psychology, 24, 619–635.
when, and why. Psychological Review, 102, 379–395. Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, L. (1991). Decision making over time and
Green, L., Myerson, J., & Ostaszewski, P. (1999). Amount of reward under uncertainty: A common approach. Management Science, 37,
has opposite eVects on the discounting of delayed and probabilistic 770–786.
outcomes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, Rachlin, H., Brown, J., & Cross, J. (2000). Discounting in judgments of
and Cognition, 25(2), 418–427. delay and probability. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 13,
Holt, D., Green, L., & Myerson, J. (2003). Is discounting impulsive? Evi- 145–159.
dence from temporal and probability discounting in gambling and Rachlin, H., Logue, A. W., Gibbon, J., & Frankel, M. (1986). Cognition
non-gambling college students. Behavioral Processes, 64, 355–367. and behavior in studies of choice. Psychological Review, 93(1), 33–
Hershey, J., & Schoemaker, P. (1980). Prospect Theory’s reXection 45.
hypothesis: A critical examination. Organizational Behavior and Rachlin, H., Raineri, A., & Cross, D. (1991). Subjective probability and
Human Performance, 25, 395–418. delay. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 55(2), 233–244.
Hogarth, R., & Einhorn, H. (1990). Venture Theory: A model of deci- Thaler, R. (1981). Some empirical evidence on dynamic inconsistency.
sion weights. Management Science, 36(7), 780–803. Economics Letters, 8, 201–207.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An analysis of Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in Prospect Theory:
decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291. Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and
Keren, G., & Roelofsma, P. (1995). Immediacy and certainty in inter- Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.
temporal choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Pro- Tversky, A., Sattath, S., & Slovic, P. (1988). Contingent weighting in
cesses, 63, 287–297. judgment and choice. Psychological Review, 95(3), 371–384.
Kühberger, A., Schulte-Mecklenbeck, M., & Perner, J. (1999). The van Dlijk, W., & van der Pligt, J. (1997). The impact of probability
eVects of framing, reXection, probability, and payoV on risk prefer- and magnitude of outcome on disappointment and elation. Orga-
ence in choice tasks. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision nizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 69(3), 277–
Processes, 78(3), 204–231. 284.
Lichtenstein, S., & Slovic, P. (1971). Reversals of preference between Zeelenberg, M. (1999). Anticipated regret, expected feedback, and
bids and choices in gambling decisions. Journal of Experimental behavioral decision making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Mak-
Psychology, 89(1), 46–55. ing, 12, 93–106.
Loomes, G., & Sudgen, R. (1982). Regret theory: An alternative of Zeelenberg, M., van Dijk, W., van der Pligt, J., Manstead, A., van
rational choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal, 92, 805–824. Empelen, P., & Reinderman, D. (1998). Emotional reactions and
Loomes, G., & Sudgen, R. (1986). Disappointment and dynamic con- the outcomes of decisions: The role of counterfactual thought in
sistency in choice under uncertainty. Review of Economic Studies, the experience of regret and disappointment. Organizational Behav-
53, 271–282. ior and Human Decision Processes, 75(2), 117–141.

You might also like