V 7 N1 Intro Origins BG

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 15

ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 27

Behaviorology, a comprehensive discipline


An Introduction to the with philosophical, experimental, analyti-
cal, and technological components, is the
Origins, Status, and natural, life science, emphasizing the causal
mechanism of selection, that discovers,
Mission of Behaviorology interprets, and applies the simple and
multiple variables that are in functional
relations with the simple and complex,
Stephen F. Ledoux overt and covert behaviors of individual
organisms (especially people) during their
SUNY–Canton lifetime (and beyond, with respect to cul-
tural practices), and that takes into account
[This paper began as part of an invited address to faculty socio–cultural and physical variables
and graduate students of the School of Management at from the environment as well as variables
Xi’an Jiaotong University (Xi’an, Shaanxi, People’s Re- from the biological history of the species.
public of China,  March ), as well as to other Chi- Here is a simpler way to present that full definition:
nese audiences, all of whom wanted a brief introduction The discipline of behaviorology,
to the concept of an independent natural–science disci-  being a comprehensive discipline with
pline of behaviorology, separate from any non–natural philosophical, experimental, analyti-
science discipline. As indicated by its title, it also serves as cal, and technological components,
the introduction to a larger work (i.e., Fraley & Ledoux,  is a natural, life science;
). This paper is included here to encourage contin-  emphasizes the causal mechanism
ued consideration—by older and newer audiences—of of selection;
the historical events and directions that it covers.—Ed.]  discovers, interprets, and applies the
simple and multiple variables that are

ehaviorology? What is that? Where does it come


in functional relations with the
simple and complex, overt and covert
from? How does it differ from other disciplines and fields behaviors of individual organisms
that evince some interest in why people do what they do? (especially people) during their life-
How is it related to other disciplines and fields? How time (and beyond, with respect to
much is encompassed by behaviorology, such as its con- cultural practices); and
tributions? Why should anyone learn anything about be-  takes into account socio–cultural and
haviorology? Questions such as these typically arise when physical variables from the environ-
people first come across the term behaviorology. This pa- ment as well as variables from the
per presents some initial answers to these questions by biological history of the species.
surveying an analyzed history of the origins of the disci-
pline of behaviorology and the behaviorology movement.
The survey includes some corroborative evidence from Where Does Behaviorology Come From?
the status of behaviorological science in China. (For
elaboration of the points introduced in this paper, see As a current discipline, behaviorology comes from the in-
Fraley & Ledoux, , and Ledoux, a, b, c.) teraction of the previously developed behaviorological
science and technology with the current behaviorology
movement. The conditions under which the original be-
What is Behaviorology? haviorological science and technology developed gave rise
to the current behaviorology movement, and that move-
Put too simply, behaviorology is the science and technology ment has enabled recognition of the current, indepen-
of behavior relations. This may appear similar to the way dent disciplinary status of behaviorology.
some other disciplines define themselves. A more elabo-
rate definition, an expansion of the definition written for Science and Technology Origins
the By–laws of , The International Behaviorology The science, and the technology originally developed
Association (an expansion undertaken when experience from the science, began about seventy years ago, early in
indicated some lingering confusion over the discipline’s the career of B.F. Skinner. Paradigmatically, Skinner
range and depth of coverage), should help discriminate never really was a psychologist in the sense of accepting
between behaviorology and those other disciplines: the transformation paradigm of psychology. Sometime
Page 28 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

during his work in the s, he began using the life–sci- common term, selection by consequences (see Ledoux,
ence selection paradigm, typical of the natural science of d, for more detailed terms).
biology, in the task of developing a natural science of be- The specifics of selection causality operate differently
havior, especially the behavior of people. Skinner was op- at other levels of life science (while the shared use of se-
erating within a department of psychology (a discipline lection causality attests to the interrelationships of the
with a fundamentally mystical philosophical core) at disciplines at all levels of life science). On the biological
Harvard University. However, he did much of his pre– level, selection causality affects species through natural se-
graduation work under W.J. Crozier, the head of the lection. On the level of cultures, selection causality in-
physiology branch of Harvard’s biology department volves selection of cultural practices. (Among natural
(Skinner, , p. ). Crozier had been a student of the sciences, a mechanical causal mode is emphasized in
biologist Jacques Loeb, and both Crozier and Loeb had physical sciences while the causal mode of selection is
emphasized the causal mechanism of selection in their emphasized in life sciences.) Behavior is functionally re-
natural science work. Skinner, perhaps without initially lated to many other variables as well, but the selection
realizing he was doing so, transferred the concept of se- mechanism is usually a necessary component of those re-
lection from biology to behavior relations. He thereby lations (e.g., stimulus control variables). The relation-
brought a particular, natural science paradigm to bear on ships found in nature between all these variables and
the questions of a scientific study of behavior. behavior are described by, and often as a group referred to
With respect to behavior, selection refers to the last- as, the natural laws, or nature’s laws, of behavior.
ing effects, on a person’s or other organism’s behavior, of In conjunction with the philosophy of science called
the consequences of that kind of behavior. For example, radical behaviorism, decades of research by Skinner and
a child who must ask (the response) loudly and repeat- those trained in this new approach followed Skinner’s use
edly for a cookie before receiving one (the consequence) of the paradigm of selection by consequences as the fun-
is a changed person. He or she is changed physically and damental component of studying behavior. (See Ledoux,
thus behaviorologically by the occurrence of the conse- a, for an introduction to some basic elements of
quence. The consequence alters the bodily structure in a radical behaviorist philosophy; the selection paradigm is
manner that can be observed at the physiological level not included as one of those elements even though, for
and at the behaviorological level. At the physiological behaviorologists, this philosophy and paradigm may have
level the alteration can be seen as nervous system changes become inseparable.) The efforts of Skinner and those
the specifics of which physiologists are making better other researchers produced discoveries of the elementary
known. At the behaviorological level it can be seen as a natural laws involving the behavior of organisms. By the
changed behavior repertoire in that, in the future, ask- s, those researchers were developing technologies to
ing–for–cookie responses will be even louder and more change accessible environmental variables and so produce
persistent. These inseparable effects occur because receiv- behavior change. Further, they were applying these tech-
ing that past cookie selected for loud and persistent ask- nologies to improve various aspects of the human condi-
ing. Selection causes physical changes now that are seen tion. These applications help people to do more, act
as altered behavior later. better, and behave more effectively in all facets of life, for
Behaviorologists address those altered behaviors by example, in child care, health care, education, daily liv-
referring to the probability of behavior and changes in that ing, work, leisure, art, entertainment, academic pursuits,
probability occasioned through selection by consequences; and even science itself.
consequences select behavior to occur more often or to Ever since those early discoveries and applications, new
occur less often. In selection causality on the behavior- generations of researchers have continued to make fur-
ological level, a response  is followed by (and usually has ther advances, discovering more complex principles and
actually produced) a consequence . The occurrence of  interactions and developing more complex technologies.
leads to responses of class  being more, or less, likely to The application of these technologies extends into ever
occur again in the future. That is, in the selection causal wider areas, continually improving personal and cultural
mode,  affects (class) . Selection is thus a type of causal practices. The term behavioral engineering provides a gen-
mode different from the more familiar mechanical causal eral description of these applications for it suggests both
mode where  leads to . In the mechanical mode, for ex- the technical process of changing the relevant environ-
ample, too high a temperature in cooking () burns the mental variables and the resulting changes in behavior.
food (), or, in reflexes, an increase in light (a stimulus, ) (This name, behavioral engineering, supersedes an earlier
elicits a decrease in pupil size (a response, ). With selec- name, behavior modification, partly because the older
tion causality, at the level of the behavior of organisms name is misleading. The older name implies that be-
during their lifetime, behavior is selected by its conse- haviorological practitioners directly manipulate behavior
quences to occur again or not; from this arises the more whereas they actually arrange—engineer—changes of the
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 29

particular environmental variables related to the behavior Behaviorological professionals found considering other
of concern, with the result that the behavior changes.) strategies difficult. Some of them finally did so however,
and thereby initiated the behaviorology movement.
Movement Origins Effects of incommensurability. By the s, be-
The behaviorology movement encompasses the haviorological professionals were experiencing the effects
efforts of behaviorologists in developing professional or- of the incommensurability of their science and psycholo-
ganizations and academic homes to preserve and extend gy. (By this time they were called behavior analysts, the
the behaviorology discipline and its contributions to hu- name still used by, among others, some professionals try-
manity. This movement arose from the conditions under ing to engage in behaviorological science, with its selection
which the original behaviorological science and technol- paradigm and radical behaviorist philosophy of natural
ogy developed. Those conditions involved incommensu- science, within the mystical discipline of psychology.)
rable differences between a discipline of behaviorology The effects of incommensurability are varied. Some con-
and the discipline of psychology, especially concerning cern the extent to which behaviorology can make its con-
their respective paradigms. Incommensurable differences tributions to the culture. Others concern employment
are differences that are incompatible, and that cannot be opportunities and the control of disciplinary infrastruc-
compared like those between apples and ghosts. tures. And still others exist also (Fraley & Ledoux, ).
Lett () explains paradigmatic incommensurabil- One effect of incommensurability was that within
ity as “the question of whether rival theories can be com- psychology the science of behavior was increasingly un-
pared and evaluated according to a standard measure” (p. derrepresented, underfunded, de–emphasized in most
). Lett also points out that alternative paradigms need departments, and simply dropped in others. As a result,
not be incommensurable: students were less and less able to receive training in the
If two paradigms agree about the nature of science of behavior. (Ledoux, b, provides a descrip-
the problem to be solved and about the ap- tion of some behaviorology curricula in higher education.
propriate means of solving that problem, The contents of these curricula reflect the depth and
they are commensurable. Furthermore, para- range of the behavior science training unavailable in psy-
digmatic commensurability is a relative mat- chology.) Students covered few courses related to the sci-
ter. Two paradigms may agree about the ence of behavior in their degree programs because few
problems to be investigated but disagree as to were offered by psychology departments. More likely, the
the means of solution. Scientific evolution student’s required exposure to the laws of behavior in-
and “scientific creationism,” for example, are volved a single chapter, or part of a chapter, from the
both concerned with the origins of the hu- twenty or so included in standard introductory psychol-
man species, but the two paradigms have ogy textbooks. And those chapters not only typically mis-
radically different epistemological principles. represented behavior science (e.g., the usual confusion
If one paradigm chooses to rely upon experi- between negative reinforcement and punishment) but
ence as its epistemological foundation, it can also they were increasingly out–of–date; researchers were
make no impact upon a paradigm that ap- reporting advances in behaviorological work mostly in
peals ultimately to revelation. (pp. –) journals outside those of the usual psychology literature
So, “if the participants in such a debate restrict them- perused by textbook authors.
selves to the terms and assumptions of their own para- With so little exposure, substantial interest in the sci-
digm, they can have nothing to say to one another” (Lett, ence developed in fewer students. Those who did become
, p. ). They are incommensurable (see Ulman, interested usually did so due to studying under a be-
, for elaboration). haviorologically oriented faculty member. But the oppor-
Behaviorological science had arisen and existed for some tunities to do that were also decreasing. After reducing
decades, mainly within the realm of psychology, before the number of behavior science courses, programs re-
the accumulating effects of incommensurable differences duced the number of behavior science faculty. So even in-
required independence–oriented actions. During this terested students could not easily be fully trained in the
time, behaviorological professionals had become accus- science of behavior and its applications; not enough
tomed to trying (and failing) to change psychology fully courses or teachers were accessible. But these students still
into a natural science of behavior. By the s the differ- had to take plenty of courses covering unparsimonious,
ences between the two became more openly incommen- non–natural science in their programs. As a consequence
surable. Events in later decades showed more and more these fewer, newer natural scientists of behavior were less
why the earlier strategy of trying to remake psychology trained in the available behaviorological science than they
was inappropriate (see Fraley & Ledoux, ). But the might have been (and perhaps less trained than the earlier
momentum of decades of that strategy was hard to break. generations of faculty and personnel whom they re-
Page 30 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

placed). So they were likely to be less effective than they use at their founding), did begin to reflect the indepen-
could have been as scientists, as teachers, and as behav- dent disciplinary status implied by the incommensurable
ioral engineers, and so were their students, and so on. differences with psychology.
If those effects of incommensurability were the only The effects and implications of incommensurability
ones, and no effective actions occurred to change that made the need for separation into independent disci-
trend, the long term result could have been the practical plines increasingly clear. Some behaviorological profes-
disappearance of an effective and advancing scientific and sionals finally began to take the necessary actions. They
systematic approach to people’s behavior and how to contributed to the academic debates (which began in ear-
change and improve it. Fortunately, positive effects of in- nest in ) in the behavior–analytic literature about an
commensurability were also detectable, along with ap- appropriate name and directions for the comprehensive
propriate and supportive actions to consolidate and natural science discipline concerned with behavior rela-
further advance the science. For instance, personnel in tions. In  they (a) formally recognized the separate
various cultural agencies were increasingly looking and independent status of that discipline, (b) accepted
specifically toward behaviorological science as the pro- behaviorology as the name denoting that discipline, and
vider of effective behavioral engineering, relevant to their (c) founded the scientific organization that came to be
concerns. To mention but a few, these personnel included called The International Behaviorology Association
(a) educators looking beyond the typical resources of () and is now called the International Society for Be-
their field, (b) workers and managers in business and in- haviorology (). By the end of , their organizational
dustry looking for ways to increase productivity and job efforts were reflected in (a) a continuing series of annual
satisfaction, etc., and (c) government units, especially at conventions with, as a sample, the second in Mexico at
state level, responsible for services to citizens with dis- the Los Horcones community in January , and the
abilities. (For example, in the s some California state fourth in New Orleans,  in January , (b) a news-
officials wanted to spot whether or not applicants for cer- letter, originally called the TIBA Newsletter, and now
tain jobs had specific training in behavior management. called Selections, (c) a carefully planned, comprehensively
To make this easier to do, Joseph Morrow, a behavior- peer–reviewed disciplinary journal to appear in ,
ological scientist at California State University, Sacra- called Behaviorology, (d) a non–copyright–retaining jour-
mento, arranged for students to receive a “Certificate in nal, with short–process peer reviewing, called Behavior-
Behavior Modification”—using the designation common ological Commentaries for articles that fall between the
at the time—if their studies included a particular pattern respective domains of the newsletter, Selections, and the
of courses that specifically expanded their skills in the journal, Behaviorology, and (e) the allocation of one–
area of behavioral engineering.) fourth of all dues explicitly for the support of behavior-
Early independence actions then the behaviorology ological research.
movement. From the s through the s, both posi-
tive and negative effects of incommensurability prodded
some initial actions, early moves towards independence. How Does Behaviorology Differ From
Behavior analysts founded numerous behavioral journals Other Disciplines and Fields?
and their own professional organizations. Most of these
were separate from psychology’s literature and organiza- The original question was longer: “How does behaviorology
tions. None of them, however, openly espoused the dis- differ from other disciplines and fields that evince some
ciplinary status implied by the incommensurable interest in why people do what they do?” An initial response
differences with psychology. Some behavior analysts and is that behaviorology is interested in more than this. It is
behaviorological professionals also founded academic also interested in what can be done about what people do.
programs (especially at the graduate training level). Many
of these programs were also organizationally independent
of psychology through their association with academic
departments representing various applied behavioral fields
which could be informed by various disciplines, includ-
ing behaviorological science (e.g., special education). A
few programs functioned with the status and structure of
a separate discipline by forming a natural science training
alternative in a distinct department separate from their
respective university’s psychology department. These de-
partments, typically describing themselves with the term
behavior analysis (the term behaviorology not yet being in
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 31

Encompassing this difference, and substantiated by other the availability of a more effective approach, especially
differences (in philosophy of science, subject matter, one with a different and incommensurable paradigm,
methodology, etc.), is the fundamental and incommensu- evoked little interest. Psychologists’ paradigm and eclec-
rable difference in paradigms between behaviorology and ticism remain thoroughly intertwined.
these other disciplines and fields. So most of this answer The fact that different schools and approaches di-
focuses on the paradigm difference. (See Vargas, , vided psychology merely masked its otherwise character-
whose names for the paradigms are used here; also see istic transformational paradigmatic unity. Psychologists’
Fraley & Ledoux, , for additional details, including stress on eclecticism focused on differences in emphases
consideration of the other differences as well.) and particulars of the various schools and approaches.
Consequently they have only gradually apprehended
Of Paradigms and Eclecticism their common transformation paradigm. Outside psych-
The two paradigms are the selection paradigm Skin- ology critics often complained about the apparent lack of
ner had adopted from biology and the transformation a unifying paradigm in psychology, thereby casting
paradigm of psychology and some other disciplines. Psy- doubts on the disciplinary status of that aggregate. The
chological subscribers to the transformation paradigm are critics also seemed influenced by the differences in em-
most interested in positing (with emphasis on a hypo- phases in the various psychological approaches. So they
thetical–deductive model) the causes of behavior chiefly too were distracted from apprehending the basic para-
in the transformations that they believe occur inside the digm. In defending against these criticisms, psychologists
person. These are the transformations that external vari- stressed their eclecticism since they had not yet clearly
ables (inputs, to use current cognitive terminology) seem recognized their paradigmatic unity. They stressed it to
to undergo before becoming apparent as behavior (out- the point that the previously pragmatic eclecticism be-
puts) in a basically mechanical causal mode. Since this came an inherent aspect of their self–description (as
paradigm does not support much interest in the inputs or passed on by countless repetitions throughout a psychol-
outputs for their own sake, the possibility of, and conse- ogy student’s training).
quently concern for, effective control is diminished. In Conveniently, however, the transformation paradigm
contrast, behaviorological subscribers to the selection not only encompasses the similarities of psychologists’
paradigm are most interested in discovering (with em- perspectives but also allows them their eclectic, even con-
phasis on an inductive model) the causes of behavior tradictory differences. Most psychologists, regardless of
chiefly in the genetically affected, potentially manipulable eclecticism or perspective, seem little interested in behavior
behavior–environment interactions, with selection by or the variables of which it is a function. They are little
consequences as the fundamental causal mode. Since this interested in inputs (the variables) and outputs (the be-
paradigm explicitly supports interest both in behavior for havior). They try to relate these mainly for other reasons,
its own sake and in the variables of which behavior is a and by adapting an older (and changing; see Chiesa,
function, the possibility of, and consequently concern ) natural–science–style x leads to y (or x is followed by y)
for, effective control is enhanced. type of mechanical causality. But psychologists cannot
Psychology’s transformation paradigm has played a easily relate a given input to a given output as cause. So
particular role regarding eclecticism. Psychologists have psychologists presume something must happen to the in-
generally considered their discipline as an eclectic aggre- puts before outputs occur. Somewhere and somehow the
gate. Their eclecticism seemed originally pragmatic. It al- inputs must be changed, transformed, into outputs. Those
lowed them to search along multiple paths for an effective changes, as they do not seem apparent elsewhere, must be
approach to the general question of “Why do people do happening inside the organism, possibly because of
what they do?” But could it allow them to find such an something the organism can be seen as doing. Psycholo-
approach? They were convinced that multiple, eclectic gists try to relate the inputs and outputs to learn some-
paths constituted the best course for them to follow. thing about what they presume is behind them.
However, their eclecticism had no built–in need for reso- Psychologists then undertake to tell the world, from their
lution. They could continue working under eclecticism various perspectives, all the things they assume are hap-
indefinitely (and have been doing so). Eclecticism actu- pening inside the organism, perhaps because of the organ-
ally does not require either ultimately adopting, or even ism. In placing their interests inside the organism, they
looking for, an effective approach. Indeed, the notion of keep to their familiar mechanical causality. Now, how-
an effective approach, as in a single, substantive, system- ever, this causality takes the form of x leads to  leads to y.
atic, comprehensive approach, seems to be anti–eclectic Here,  (for organism) represents the various transforma-
by definition. In addition, as psychologists were to dis- tions different psychologists believe occur inside the or-
cover, they already shared a paradigm, the transformation ganism as inputs are then said to become outputs.
paradigm, that allowed them their eclectic differences. So However, the transformation paradigm does not address
Page 32 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

the makeup of transformations; it addresses only their the inductive (observation– and measurement– and ac-
position between the inputs and outputs. Psychologists tion–based) approach to knowing. These Ionian roots are
hypothesize, from various perspectives, numerous types found to be ascendant or prevalent in societies during peri-
of transformations and these can be contradictory and ods of increasing social progress, for example, during the
even mutually exclusive. The result is the interplay be- time of the Ionian trading cities when “new societies of
tween the transformation paradigm and eclecticism. The traders, craftsmen, and freeholding peasants—the first lim-
paradigm supports transformations in general, whether ited attempts at democracies and republics” (Lerner, ,
agreeable or contradictory, while under eclecticism the p. ) were forming, as well as during the Renaissance
latter are automatically tolerated. and the nineteenth century (Lerner, , p. ) and to
Even though the many, specific psychological ap- some extent the present (e.g., in Japan around the s).
proaches differ among themselves, they all adhere to the In contrast, the characteristics of the transformation
transformation paradigm. Giving them a label like paradigm and psychology have their Western roots in the
“school” does not change this characteristic. None of them preferences of the dualist Greeks (e.g., Plato, circa 
adheres to the selection paradigm. At this level of analy- ..., and Aristotle, circa  ...). The dualist Greeks
sis, only the natural science of behavior founded by Skin- preferred the deductive method, its associated philo-
ner adheres to that paradigm (but see Ulman, , also). sophical approach known as idealism (which takes ideas,
And the selection paradigm is as different from the trans- thoughts, as primary, that is, reality does not exist apart
formation paradigm as evolution is from creationism. from what people think exists), and the hypothetical–de-
ductive (pure reason and less observation) approach to
The Skinnerian Alternative knowing. These dualist roots are found to be ascendant
Skinner was doing research in the s using the se- or prevalent in societies during periods of decreasing so-
lection paradigm; but he was operating within a unit of cial progress, for example, during Greek slave–holding
organized psychology. The location of this research may society, during the Western middle ages, and in many
simply be a product of what evolutionary biologists call ways during much of the s (see Sagan, ).
historical contingency (see Gould, ) since Skinner Both these roots and their differences have some im-
could, and under Crozier’s influence almost did, pursue pact on most disciplines. The branching of the psycholo-
his work officially from within a unit of organized biology. gy–behaviorology shared historical trunk is not an
Yet the venue of this research constitutes the beginning of isolated instance in academic history. It may be part of an
an historical trunk, shared by both behaviorology and psy- ongoing scientific revolution. For example, in his 
chology. This trunk lasted only for about three decades book The Big Bang Never Happened, Eric Lerner argues that
and has since divided, forming two distinct branches, these roots and differences are the basis of the competi-
each with its own continuing disciplinary history. tion between big bang cosmology and plasma cosmology.
The roots of this trunk are also as different as the two He argues that big bang proponents continue in the
paradigms and disciplines that shared the trunk before Plato–Aristotle tradition, and that observational evidence
diverging. The history of these roots traces back, in West- seems to show their position to be less parsimonious than
ern culture, to various early Greeks and their philoso- their competitor’s position. Plasma proponents, he argues,
phies and approaches, and the ideologies of those and continue in the Ionian tradition, and their position seems
other times. As Lerner () reports, the early Western to be more consistent with observations. Some parallels
versions of “The empirical and the deductive methods… with psychology and behaviorology, and their paradigm
both arose around  .. They emerged from a fierce clash, are evident. Even so, whether or not a Big Bang
social conflict to determine what sort of society would happened is irrelevant to any clash between psychology
succeed Bronze Age civilization—a society of free labor and behaviorology, and in any case is still unresolved.
or one of slave labor” (p. ). Sometimes in paradigm clashes, one position ultimately
The characteristics of the selection paradigm and be- eclipses or subsumes the other, as when quantum me-
haviorology have their Western roots in the preferences of chanics superseded Newtonian mechanics in physics. The
the Ionian Greeks (e.g., Thales, circa  ..., and positions co–exist for a time as one develops and advances
Anaxagoras, circa  ...). With navigation and other while the other declines. With other paradigm clashes, such
needs prompting developments in science and technology, as the one between behaviorology and psychology, the
the Ionians preferred the empirical method, its associated positions co–exist for a time, sharing their history. Then
philosophical approach known as materialism (which they branch off, going their separate disciplinary ways.
takes matter, nature, as primary, that is, reality exists Figure  illustrates the shared history, its roots, and its
whether or not people are around to think about it), and later branching for behaviorology and psychology:
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 33

day is—but a minor criterion for adopting explanations


Behaviorology Psychology (see Fraley & Ledoux, , Ch. ). As a result, the stage
was set for various substantial changes in the positions of
– 1960s both psychologists and radical behaviorists. The effects of
incommensurable paradigms were driving both the overt
Shared Trunk – paradigmatic differentiation and the subsequent historical
– 1930s separation into officially independent disciplines.

The Reaction for a


Ionian Roots Dualist Roots Non–Natural Science Tradition
Also during the s, psychology was undergoing
the “cognitive revolution” (or, depending on one’s per-
Figure 1. Branching disciplinary tree and philosophical roots. spective, “cognitive counterrevolution”). One aspect of
that development was psychologists’ increased acceptance
that they had little interest in behavior for its own sake or
Different kinds of reasons bring about those different in demonstrations of effective control. So they could not
paradigm–clash scenarios. Regarding behaviorology and convince themselves of much need to heed the concerns
psychology, how could the shared historical trunk come of radical behaviorists. But they were not unmoved by
about? How was Skinner’s beginning behaviorological those concerns. They were paying more and more atten-
science from within psychology possible, given the in- tion to the paradigmatic similarity among the various
commensurable differences between the paradigms? psychological approaches and less attention to their eclec-
Skinner’s doing such work from within psychology tic differences. They began to apprehend the role of their
was possible because the psychology of the time was paradigm in emphasizing their similarities without
much more sensitive to differences at the level of schools threatening their differences. As a consequence they be-
and approaches than to differences between paradigms. gan to disassociate from any group that did not share
Various schools of thought were already contending their transformation paradigm. This especially meant dis-
within psychology. All these shared the transformation association with radical behaviorism since several other
paradigm. But no school was able to demonstrate itself to forms of behaviorism do operate under the transforma-
be better than the other schools nor could they show that tion paradigm (including interbehaviorism, method-
other schools were inadequate. So they all had to tolerate ological behaviorism, paradigmatic behaviorism, and
each other and co–exist, which they did under the ratio- Watson’s original behaviorism).
nale of eclecticism. When Skinner originated the operant Radical behaviorists, after decades of a history shared
approach, it also could not be shown to be inadequate with psychology, experienced the disassociation as the
and so it also was tolerated. The fact that the operant ap- effects of the incommensurability of the respective para-
proach did not share the transformation paradigm with digms. Before the cognitive movement, psychology had
the psychological schools but was based in the selection tolerated and benefited from radical behaviorism. How-
paradigm did not originally occasion much comment. ever, since the cognitive movement began, psychologists
By the s, however, circumstances had changed. have labeled and treated as dead any non–transformational
Those who continued to advance the science and tech- positions regardless of the facts (see Wyatt, Hawkins, &
nology Skinner had originated had come to be known Davis, ). Radical behaviorism was a common target
first as operant behaviorists and then as behavior analysts of such unjustifiable slurs because its paradigm was fully
or radical behaviorists. (The latter was more concise since incommensurable. Consequently the demonstrated quality
usage of the other names had become blurred over time; and quantity of its research and applications were given
now, behaviorologists is the best descriptor, at least for those less and less consideration. Accumulated scientific evidence
who are part of the behaviorology movement.) By using for its more parsimonious and practical accounts of be-
the criterion of effectiveness in action regarding subject mat- havior no longer received the attention their effectiveness
ter, radical behaviorists were demonstrating the value of had earned. Instead, political and economic concerns
their science. That same evidence was also showing the prevailed, with programmatic emphases, funds, and other
various psychological approaches to be less effective and resources being more emphatically directed towards hy-
unparsimonious. Yet parsimony receives scant attention pothetical cognitive transformations. The result of these
in psychology, and effective action regarding subject matter developments was the objective, though not necessarily
was then—and still among psychological approaches to- immediately recognized, differentiation of the transfor-
Page 34 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

mation and selection paradigms. And this differentiation discipline: psychoanalytic (i.e., Freud), cognitive/mental-
provided the foundation for the separation of the inde- istic (e.g., Maslow and Piaget), and behavioral (i.e., the
pendent disciplines of psychology and behaviorology. science of behavior originated by Skinner).
Also, psychology is not entirely consistent in these The Chinese report a special preference for the Pav-
matters. It continues to claim that behaviorism is dead. lovian and Skinnerian work based on the natural science
However, this is only true within psychology and only in approach and experimental methods these two share. In
the sense that psychology all but ignores transformational part, this preference for Pavlov and Skinner may be due
behaviorisms while the work of radical behaviorists is no to a particular aspect of Chinese history. The Chinese
longer advancing in psychology (although this work does culture has been less burdened than Western culture has
continue to advance in behaviorology and in the efforts of been by philosophically idealist dualism, a dualism that
behaviorological scientists who remain employed in units pervades Western culture. So Chinese culture has suffered
of organized psychology). Yet psychology also claims that less from the unscientific separation of phenomena into
behaviorism still is part of psychology. This also is only the different realms of mental and physical (soul/body,
partly true in that various transformational behaviorisms spiritual/material, mind/reality) that results from philo-
continue to exist within psychology. Also, the principles sophical dualism. Western psychology traditionally pre-
and practices of the first few decades of radical behavior- fers the non–physical aspect. (The Chinese language,
ist research did occur mostly in units of organized psych- while it has a rich variety of terms for most of the West-
ology and so are a part of that historical time shared with ern usages of the term mind, actually lacks a direct trans-
psychology. Introductory psychology textbooks still faith- lation of mind as Western psychologists use that
fully report, usually as part of the chapter on learning, this term—as a dualistic, uncaused metaphysical cause. In-
outdated material, and little beyond it. While over thirty stead, for that usage, Chinese professionals generally use
years out of date, that material is presented as though it a word that, less appropriately, translates back into En-
were the latest material available, which it generally is— glish better as “brain.”)
in psychology. However, the years of advances since the However, in the s, Chinese behavior science pro-
paradigm differentiation of the s are arguably not fessionals lost contact with Western developments. They
part of psychology and are rarely covered in those text- spent the decade of the s trying to update, and
books (with rare exceptions such as the text by Poling, thought the update complete. But they were disturbed by
Schlinger, Starin, and Blakely, ). Again, the advances what they saw as very few advances in principles and
were generally reported in journals (beginning, for ex- practices, from those missing years, relevant to solving
ample, with the Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Be- practical, behavior–related problems.
havior) that, being independent of psychology’s principal In beginning to look elsewhere for solutions, they are
disciplinary literature, are seldom perused by most psych- discovering that their update is not complete. It involved
ology textbook authors. The benefits from those advances little beyond the traditional Western psychology sources
accrue mostly according to the extent to which one has (literature, texts, personnel) and these contain little of the
acquired and maintains a verbal and skill repertoire in be- substantial behaviorological–science advances from those
haviorology or, at least, in behaviorological science. years. The Chinese are discovering that they have over-
The experience in China. The situation of behavior looked virtually all the post–s advances in principles
science in the People’s Republic of China provides cor- and practices in the science originally founded by B.F.
roborative evidence for the separateness and indepen- Skinner. This occurred because at about the same time
dence of behaviorology and psychology. Chinese behavior that the Chinese lost contact, the greatest proportion of
science professionals in Xi’an, Shaanxi, provided com- those advances began to be, and have since been, increas-
mentary on the situation in China to the author while he ingly reported and supported outside psychology, greatly
was there, as part of a faculty exchange, teaching courses reducing access to them from within psychology. The
on Verbal Behavior, and Behaviorology and Education, Chinese are also considering the possible reasons for this
during the – academic year. situation, including the incommensurable paradigm
The discussions uncovered several points of mutual differences indicating and validating separate disciplines.
interest. The Chinese use a word they translate as psych- (See Ledoux, c, for a more complete discussion of
ology to encompass the three sources they currently see behaviorology in China.)
for their discipline: traditional Chinese views on why Transformations and eclecticism revisited. Are hy-
people do what they do, the views adopted from the dis- pothesized, internal transformations a reasonable alterna-
cipline in the Soviet Union (especially the work originat- tive to behavior–environment interactions? The variety of
ing with Pavlov on reflex/emotional, that is, respondent, psychology’s transformations may indeed be more ini-
behavior), and Western perspectives. The Chinese have tially captivating than the patient discovery and tested
included three parts in the Western component of their application of complex behavioral laws. Transformations
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 35

seem smoothly consistent with the philosophically dual- havior aspect. Exactly what is happening physiologically
ist cultural history that pervades the milieu of Western when behavior (overt or covert) occurs and when related
society. Are these a rationale for the many people at- variables occur (the particular conditions and particular
tracted to psychological theorizing? This attraction occurs consequences) are important questions to which the
in spite of the much greater difficulty in later making use natural science discipline of physiology can provide answers.
of theorized transformations to help solve society’s vari- Is psychology’s crossover to physiology an appropriate
ous general and personal problems, compared to the one? Psychologists who take this route show some prefer-
more technological applications of behavioral laws to ence for natural science, physiology in this case. How-
such concerns. Is this another example of being affected ever, psychologists may be the only ones viewing the
more by short–term variables (e.g., the fun of discussing crossover as a reasonable disciplinary activity. For the
competing transformational accounts) than by delayed crossover interrupts physiology’s mission and further
variables (e.g., the later, improved effectiveness, in help- compromises the status of psychologists’ own discipline
ing situations, after having studied behavior–environ- by shifting their subject matter into areas legitimately
ment interactions)? claimed already by a different discipline. Psychologists
In any case, some of these transformations are simply may find academic turf battles with physiology far more
mentalistic inventions that violate a basic premise of the common than with behaviorology.
natural sciences, namely respect for the continuity of As for eclecticism, observers can already note a de-
events in space and time that accumulates, link by related crease in its importance even in psychology. The shift in
link, in a researchable natural history. Hence the emphasis under the cognitive movement to stressing
scientific status of those transformations is questionable similarities (e.g., the transformation paradigm) seems to
and unparsimonious. The transformation paradigm al- have prompted the decrease in eclecticism which is evi-
lows and invites such untestable, metaphysical inventions dent in the relative coverage of the psychological perspec-
to enter the chain of space–time events, breaking and tives. Perusal of various psychology film series (e.g., the
thereby disrespecting the continuity of those events. Such Discovering Psychology series) and any number of intro-
transformations, their related paradigm, and disciplines ductory psychology textbooks shows the cognitive per-
or parts of disciplines supporting that paradigm have spective to be filling the stage. Next in coverage is
thus removed themselves from consideration as part of information derived from another discipline, physiology.
any natural science discipline or field. Other perspectives (e.g., psychoanalytic, humanistic, or
Many other transformations are not transforma- gestalt) often receive little more than lip service. Unfortu-
tions at all but rather are the physiological bases of be- nately, this waning of eclecticism has not paralleled any
havior, an appropriate subject matter for a natural commitment for changing toward an effective science
science such as physiology. For example, neurons firing concerned with why people do what they do and what
(in the central or peripheral nervous systems), in ways can be done about it. (The Poling, et al., , text is one
often but not necessarily connected to muscles contract- exception in that it provides some natural science stan-
ing or glands secreting, etc., are physiological aspects of dards with which to compare and evaluate the several al-
the same fact whose behaviorological aspects observers ternative perspectives it includes at appropriate points.)
might witness as, say, salivating or the movements of a
hand or of the vocal cords under particular conditions The Historical Division
and with particular consequences. Psychology’s increasing stress on similarities like the
Sometimes the physiological and behaviorological as- transformation paradigm had contributed substantially
pects cannot be separated, such as when the behavior is to the differentiation of the established disciplinary para-
covert. Muscles or glands may not even be involved. For digms. That differentiation, in the s, objectively cre-
example, due to having learned to observe and verbally ated two separate and independent disciplines out of the
report the occurrence of private responses (Skinner, , previous shared history. The historical trunk divided into
Ch. ), people may observe and report themselves seeing separate branches. These disciplines differ not only in
something, regardless of whether the thing seen is present paradigms but also, in associated ways, in subject matters,
to be seen or not; yet all that the properly instrumented philosophies, methodologies, etc. Not until the s,
physiologist observes about this seeing is neurons firing at though, did the resulting changes in contingencies (the
the back of the brain. These neurons firing (physiological effects of incommensurability) begin affecting people
level) and the behavior of seeing (behaviorological level) are enough for them to emit behavior consistent with the
inseparable aspects of the same fact, the same phenom- fact of different disciplines. Not until the s did they
enon. Neither overt nor covert behavior can occur with- begin to name and reorganize behaviorology.
out nervous system activity; but the nervous system activity
aspect may sometimes occur only along with a covert be-
Page 36 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

conclusions after following the same scientific proce-


dures. This is partly because natural scientists disallow
How is Behaviorology Related to the inclusion of metaphysical events in their explanatory
Other Disciplines and Fields? accounts, for such events are untestable. Natural sciences
respect the continuity of events in space and time that
The distinction between social science and natural science accumulate in a researchable natural history. These are
is relevant here because the interest behaviorologists have defining characteristics of natural science which behav-
in people is taken by some professionals as placing be- iorology shares. (A later, more refined view has natural
haviorology in the social science arena. However, social science opposing mysticism directly rather than by way of
sciences not only derive from an interest in people (an social science. See Ledoux, f or g, for details
interest shared by many natural sciences), but from an- and references.)
other commonly acknowledged characteristic as well; so- Among the natural sciences, behaviorology is one of
cial scientists easily reach contradictory conclusions after the foundation life sciences (along with biology) rather
following the same scientific procedures. This is partly than one of the foundation physical sciences (such as
because many social scientists allow metaphysical (mysti- physics or chemistry). Figure  illustrates behaviorology’s
cal) events to enter their explanatory accounts. In con- position along a life science continuum (see Fraley &
trast, natural scientists more easily reach consistent Ledoux, , about the term culturology).

Behaviorology
Biology Culturology

Micro Level Individual Level Macro Level


(sub–individual) (group/population)

Figure 2. Disciplinary coverage for the three main levels of analysis in the life sciences.

(The study of ecosystems, species evolution, and the


behavior of animals in groups by some animal biologists How Much is Encompassed by
implies that a disciplinary overlap also exists between bi- Behaviorology, Such as its Contributions?
ology and culturology. So Figure  might be redrawn as a
triangle with extended sides that cross each other. Each Plenty, but thorough coverage goes beyond the bounds of
side would represent one of these domains and its associ- this paper. The point of this paper was to introduce an
ated discipline. The areas where the lines cross would analyzed history of the emergence of the discipline of be-
then represent the overlap in the interests of the intersect- haviorology through the behaviorology movement. In
ing disciplines.) the process the status and mission of behaviorology were
As a basic science, behaviorology provides the foun- introduced as well. One must still address the basic and
dations that inform the considerations and technologies advanced natural laws involving behavior as discovered
of various applied behavioral fields (e.g., organizational by behaviorological scientists as well as behaviorology’s
behavior management) as they seek to fulfill their respective philosophy of science, interpretations, and analyses, plus
cultural missions (a field is where one applies a founda- its technologies and applications. All of these constitute
tion science discipline). Such fields range from advertising parts of behaviorology’s past, current, and potential cul-
to zoology, with many currently in a scientific limbo tural contributions.
without an appropriate basic science informing their For instance, here are some basic components of the
efforts. Fraley (), in a paper addressing the cultural radical behaviorist philosophy of science; these compo-
mission of behaviorology, stresses the role of behaviorol- nents have value beyond the boundaries of behaviorology it-
ogy as the appropriate science to inform these areas (also self, and some have been mentioned already: (a) Radical
see Fraley & Ledoux, ). behaviorists respect behavior as a natural phenomenon as
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 37

part of respecting the continuity of events in space and ther a general–behaviorology textbook (e.g., Fraley, )
time which accumulates as a natural history. (b) Radical or issues of the Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis can
behaviorists emphasize experimental control over depen- provide a starting point for reviewing the research on
dent variables and the application of that control in cul- many of these applications.
turally beneficial ways. (c) Radical behaviorists recognize
private events, such as thinking or emotions, as covert
behaviors involved in the same lawful relationships that Why Should Anyone Learn Anything
involve overt behavior. (d) Radical behaviorists ac- About Behaviorology?
knowledge that scientists are also behaving organisms
whose behavior, scientific or not, is affected by the same The laws of behavior (that is, the relations described by
variables that affect other behavior, and that those vari- those laws) do not always produce benefits; at least as of-
ables include scientists’ philosophy of science. (See ten as not, they may produce problems. For instance,
Ledoux, a, for some elaboration; see Chiesa, , many families fall victim to the accidental, unplanned
for extensive discussion.) conditioning of various undesired behaviors. Without
The laws involving behavior essentially reflect the contact with behaviorological science, parents may never
functional relations between behavior and the variables realize that yelling at or even spanking a child may actu-
inherent in an organism’s (a) species history, (b) personal ally strengthen the behavior they are trying to weaken,
history, (c) current situation and, for people, (d) cultural especially if that is the only or main kind of attention the
setting. These contain the variables a behaviorologist ad- child receives. Parents may never realize that the general
dresses when trying to analyze, understand, predict, con- rule to provide appropriate kinds of attention more when
trol, and interpret the behavior of organisms. A peek at children are behaving in the ways parents desire (i.e., to
some of the advances in researching and applying these “catch your children being good”; Christophersen, )
laws (advances arising since the paradigm differentiation is both more effective than just ignoring them, and more
in the s) would involve describing numerous topics: effective than just catching and punishing them when
(a) the distinction between event–shaped and verbally– they are bad. “Catching them being good” is more effec-
mediated behavior (Vargas, ), (b) the analysis of ver- tive in increasing desired behavior and thereby reducing
bal behavior (Skinner, ), (c) the recombination of the occasions for undesired behavior. (See Latham, ,
repertoires (Epstein, ), (d) establishing operations for details on this and other behaviorologically based,
(Michael, ), (e) multi–term (n–term) contingencies prevention oriented child–rearing practices.)
(Sidman, a, b), (f ) the function–altering effects As that example shows, the accidental or unplanned
of contingency–specifying stimuli (Schlinger & Blakely, operation of behavioral laws having undesirable effects on
), (g) stimulus equivalence relations (Sidman, ; behavior becomes a tyrant affecting people’s lives. Until
Stromer, ), (h) the general level of reinforcement after behaviorological research began in the s, few could
(Cautela, ), and (i) behavioral engineering and cultural do much to stop that tyranny for those laws were little un-
design (Skinner, ; Ulman, ; West & Hamerlynck, derstood. Today, through behaviorology, people can increas-
). These topics highlight some of the state–of–the– ingly replace that tyranny by designing and redesigning
art aspects, in the s, of the scientific comprehension the world in which they live. They can take the responsi-
and handling of complex human behavioral relations. bility to use the ongoing discoveries about those laws to
Other cultural contributions involve continuously improve the human condition (and even to evaluate
developing and extensively tested behavioral engineering scientifically what words like “improve” mean; see Krapfl &
technologies applicable to all facets of life, with particu- Vargas, ; Vargas, , ). These actions are possible
lar value in resolving both personal and cultural concerns. because one of the behaviors generated and maintained by
These range from preventative measures in child–rearing the operation of these laws is the behavior of people in gen-
practices, to making education effective (e.g., Johnson & eral taking control of themselves, and the environmental
Layng, ) including the critique of developmentalism, variables that affect them, in informed ways (which also
to enhancing business, industrial, and organizational enables them to countercontrol for potential misuses of
management, to the design and redesign of cultures and this science). The greatest initial significance of behaviorol-
cultural practices including those related to rescuing the ogy may not be in the management of day–to–day indi-
planetary environment and so helping restore the mutu- vidual affairs nor, perhaps, even in providing solutions to
ally beneficial balance between the Earth and its inhabit- large social problems (e.g., the crisis in American education).
ants (see Gore, ; also see the bibliography at the end Instead the greatest significance may be in providing some
of Ledoux, e, for references to other examples, as critically needed tools to help understand and deal with
well as to works covering more of the depth and range of the world–wide environmental and outer space concerns
the behaviorology discipline and its cultural utility). Ei- and crises facing the generations of today and tomorrow.
Page 38 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

The basic reason to study behaviorology, then, is to those laws or not), and (d) whether we “know” those laws
reduce the risks and derive more than the minimal, auto- or not (as in “can state and use them,” that is, whether
matic benefits from the way nature’s laws govern behav- our talk, or better, our talk and our use–skills, have both
ior. Studying behaviorology expands your repertoire of come effectively and explicitly under the control of state-
behavior with respect to those laws and their applica- ments of the relationships inherent in those laws or not).
tions. The more extensive your training in behaviorology In these levels, knowledge refers to the range and depth of
is, the greater can be your effectiveness, your success, with our behavior repertoires. To illustrate these levels of
its applications to human concerns. knowledge (repertoire), consider an example from the
How much behaviorological knowledge and skills is teaching profession.
right for you? Everyone should be as familiar with the Persons untrained in chemistry but trained in English
basics of behaviorology as they are with the basics of bi- literature (and even trained in teaching literature as well)
ology and physics and other standard natural sciences would be quite out of place conducting a chemistry class.
covered through primary and secondary education. Be- They do not know the names or properties of the chemi-
yond the basics, “How much is right?” depends on the cals under discussion in that class (i.e., their behavior rep-
complexity of the applications appropriate to your areas ertoire does not include responses appropriate to the
of concern. The more complex the applications are in a pertinent variables, such as the discriminative stimuli and
particular area, the greater is the amount of behaviorolo- consequences, present in that situation). Yet if they mix
gy study needed if you are to be effective in that area. For some of the chemicals before them, they will produce the
instance, look at some of the areas involving children, for same chemical reactions that their trained chemistry col-
these are typical of the complexity levels of most areas of leagues would have produced had those colleagues mixed
human concern. While a lack of study leaves anyone’s those same chemicals. The laws of chemistry are in force
potential for success to accident or chance, parents can, whether they like it or not, and whether they use them
by design, attain a quite reasonable level of informed (by mixing some of the chemicals before them) or not.
effectiveness in child–rearing practices with only a basic What about the trained chemistry colleagues? Are
amount of behaviorology study (the equivalent of one or they trained only in chemistry or are they also trained in
two courses in behaviorology; see Ledoux, b). Edu- teaching, and does that make any difference, especially to
cators, on the other hand, find that teaching effectively teaching? After accumulating, usually over years, certain
requires substantially more study. And working with au- kinds of experiences (which typically occur by accident or
tistic children requires even more. In each of the two lat- chance), the chemistry teachers who are trained only in
ter cases, the complexity of both the applications and the chemistry come to know about teaching. At least, you
relevant controlling variables increases (while gaining ac- would say they do so to the extent that they come to be
cess to those variables is often more difficult as well). effective in teaching, that is, in expanding the chemistry–
Such circumstances demand a more professional level of related repertoires of their students. Their teaching–re-
training (starting with a Bachelor’s degree in behaviorol- lated use–skills have come effectively under the control of
ogy) if practitioners are to be as effective as possible in ar- the laws involved in successful teaching. Yet even after de-
eas such as these. cades of teaching, they are unlikely to be able to describe,
in terms of nature’s complex laws relating to the expan-
A Matter of Epistemology Also sion of repertoires (i.e., the scientific foundations of
The “Why study behaviorology?” question need not teaching and learning), the reasons for their effectiveness.
be answered only with respect to complexity and They cannot tell another chemistry–trained person how to
effectiveness. Consider also this answer: “We should teach chemistry effectively. (They can, of course, make up
study behaviorology because we are affected by nature’s theories about their successes; but that is a different mat-
laws anyway; perhaps the more we know concerning ter entirely, and something to be avoided if teaching in
these laws, the better off we will be.” But what does general is to become effective.) While they can effectively
“know” mean? Let us take a little trek into a scientific teach chemistry, and can model doing so, they cannot
epistemology (the question of what knowing is) to help un- effectively teach teaching, even of chemistry. They do not
derstand this answer better, including how it relates to know teaching as they know chemistry.
the complexity and effectiveness answer. Effectively expanding the repertoires of students
Nature’s laws, the laws of the universe, affect us at through knowing teaching (an instructional design reper-
different levels of knowledge. They affect us (a) whether we toire), and effectively handling chemicals (a subject–mat-
like it this way or not, (b) whether we have used those ter repertoire), are very different behavior repertoires. The
laws or not, (c) whether we “know about” those laws or latter is informed by chemistry while the former is in-
not (as in “can use the laws effectively,” that is, whether formed by behaviorology. If the would–be teachers of
our use–skills have come effectively under the control of chemistry or any subject matter want to become effective
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 39

teachers, want to know teaching, want a comprehensive Our trek into epistemology helps put into perspective
repertoire of teaching skills, and want it by design in a the differences between just being affected by nature’s laws
shorter time rather than by chance over a longer time, (whether we like them or not, or use them or not), know-
then they must study the discipline that informs teach- ing about them, and knowing them, as these relate to in-
ing. To the extent that they learn both to teach a particu- creasing complexity requiring more comprehensive study
lar subject matter (i.e., to expand their students’ for effectiveness. This applies especially to behaviorology,
repertoires in that subject matter) and to explain accu- as the science of behavior relations, since so many areas of
rately and scientifically what it is that they are doing interest involve human behavior. The more extensive
which results in that expansion of repertoires, to that ex- your training in behaviorology, the more effective you can
tent you would say not only that they know their subject be in dealing with behavior in the contexts of concern to
matter but also that they know teaching as well. Their you. (For reasons of this sort,  included among its
talk and use–skills have both come effectively and explic- purposes support for a basic “behavior literacy” gradua-
itly under the control of statements of the relationships tion requirement of appropriate content and depth at all
described by the laws of behavior relevant to teaching. levels of education; at the college level, that would likely
(You might even say they know teaching even if only their involve a couple of courses. See Fraley & Ledoux, ,
talk has clearly come under that control.) And teaching is and Ledoux, b, f.)
but one example of the many human endeavors where
levels of knowledge/repertoire relate to effectiveness. A Matter of Hygiene Also
Vargas and Fraley (; also see Vargas, ) discuss Yet another answer to the “Why study behaviorology?”
some benefits of separating these two major repertoires in question is available. With so many human problems (and
education, the repertoires of subject–matter expertise and potential threats to survival itself), the importance of learn-
instructional design expertise. These repertoires might be ing and applying behaviorology today is akin to the impor-
too complex to expect most individuals to expend the effort tance of learning and applying the then new discoveries of
to master both thoroughly. However, two experts, each with biological science about  years ago. The discovery of
mastery of one of these repertoires, can combine their the relation between micro–organisms and disease formed
efforts and thereby achieve greater overall educational the basis, in the first half of the s, of today’s standards
effectiveness. Indeed, one design expert can combine for biological hygiene. (Biological hygiene is that vital
efforts with a dozen or more content experts to achieve ounce–of–prevention whose success, in reducing the fre-
such improvements. The subject–matter experts can con- quency of disease, we take for granted today, so many
centrate on the subject–matter content of the courses or years after the discovery of the relevant scientific facts.)
programs of study while the instructional design expert Learning and applying behaviorology could be called
concentrates on the instructional arrangements to teach a matter of behavioral hygiene, the next step, especially in
those contents with scientifically sound methods. problem prevention, after having successfully developed
The point Vargas and Fraley make is significant be- and adopted biological hygiene. We would not consider
cause the usual emphasis on subject–matter expertise risking hepatitis by eating without first cleaning our hands
generally leads to ignoring the complementary need for after using the toilet. Why should we then continue to
instructional design expertise. People presume, incor- risk, for example, low success rates (relative to potential)
rectly, that someone who is a subject–matter expert au- in education when we can, if appropriately trained, bring
tomatically has a thorough enough repertoire appropriate about consistently demonstrated high success rates in
for teaching that subject. Yet usually the teaching reper- both deportment/emotional and academic/intellectual
toire is minimal. That is especially common in post–sec- areas? (For elaboration, see Johnson & Layng, ;
ondary education. However, as our example with teaching Latham, ; Skinner, ; and West & Hamerlynck,
chemistry showed, early and long–sustained effectiveness .) Why should we take those risks when we can, in-
requires training in both expert repertoires. Vargas and stead, clean up our actions by applying some behavioral
Fraley refocus attention on the need for employing a sci- hygiene? How many years will pass before we achieve
entifically based instructional design repertoire if educa- today’s potential successes and take behavioral hygiene for
tional effectiveness is to improve. The question is, will granted? The sooner we become more informed by this
effectiveness arise by chance in the slow, lucky accumula- science, throughout society, the less time it will take.
tion of the necessary experiences, or will it accrue by de- Let us take the responsibility to learn and apply be-
sign through training and practice, especially in the haviorology’s discoveries about the laws of behavior at
so–far neglected arena of instructional design? Vargas and least for the sake of behavioral hygiene. Let us do so to
Vargas () extend the discussion to current instruc- improve the human condition, to take control of our in-
tional materials and programming. teractions with our environments, and to master control
of ourselves.
Page 40 (issn 1536–6669) ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004

Krapfl, J.E. & Vargas, E.A. (Eds.). (). Behaviorism


and Ethics. Kalamazoo, : Behaviordelia.
Endnotes Latham, G.I. (). The Power of Positive Parenting. Lo-
gan, : P&T ink.
From the original address prepared for Chinese and other Latham, G.I. (). Behind the Schoolhouse Door: Eight
audiences, this paper was revised for publication () in Skills Every Teacher Should Have. Logan, : P&T ink.
Behaviorological Commentaries, Serial No. , pp. –. Ledoux, S.F. (a). An introduction to the philosophy
Subsequently, it was the first—and principal—part of a called radical behaviorism. In S.F. Ledoux. Origins
presentation at the second Behavior Analysis Around the and Components of Behaviorology—Second Edition
World Conference, held in  at Keio University in To- (pp. –). Canton, : ABCs.
kyo, Japan (the other part of that presentation coming Ledoux, S.F. (b). Behaviorology curricula in higher
from Ledoux, c). With further minor revisions, it education. In S.F. Ledoux. Origins and Components
appeared in Origins and Components of Behaviorology of Behaviorology—Second Edition (pp. –).
(Ledoux, e, pp. –) under a longer title (“An intro- Canton, : ABCs.
duction to the orgins, status, and mission of behaviorol- Ledoux, S.F. (c). Behaviorology in China: A status
ogy: An established science with developed applications report. In S.F. Ledoux. Origins and Components of
and a new name”). In any case this paper presents only a Behaviorology—Second Edition (pp. –). Can-
starting point for further, more in–depth examinations of ton, : ABCs.
behaviorology to be found in other behaviorological–sci- Ledoux, S.F. (d). Increasing tact control and student
ence resources (such as Fraley & Ledoux, ). comprehension through such new postcedent terms
The author thanks those Chinese and Western col- as added and subtracted reinforcers and punishers. In
leagues, especially Shi Ming de, Guy Bruce, John S.F. Ledoux. Origins and Components of Behaviorolo-
Eshleman, and Lawrence Fraley, who provided many gy—Second Edition (pp. –). Canton, : ABCs.
helpful comments on various drafts of this material. Ad- Ledoux, S.F. (e). Origins and Components of Behav-
dress correspondence regarding this paper to the author iorology—Second Edition. Canton, : ABCs.
at –, Canton  – . Ledoux, S.F. (f ). Afterword. In S.F. Ledoux. Origins
and Components of Behaviorology—Second Edition
(pp. –). Canton, : ABCs.
References Ledoux, S.F. (g). Defining Natural Sciences. Behav-
iorology Today,  (), –.
Cautela, J.R. (). General level of reinforcement II: Lerner, E.J. (). The Big Bang Never Happened. New
Further elaborations. Behaviorology,  (), –. York: Times Books.
Chiesa, M. (). Radical Behaviorism: The Philosophy Lett, J. (). The Human Enterprise: A Critical Introduction
and the Science. Boston, : Authors Cooperative. to Anthropological Theory. Boulder, : Westview Press.
Christophersen, E.R. (). Little People, (Third Edi- Michael, J.L. (). Distinguishing between discrimina-
tion). Kansas City, : Westport Publishers. tive and motivational functions of stimuli. Journal of
Epstein, R. (). Of pigeons and people: A preliminary the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, , –.
look at the Columban simulation project. The Behav- Poling, A., Schlinger, H., Starin, S., & Blakely, E. ().
ior Analyst, , –. Psychology: A Behavioral Overview. New York: Plenum.
Fraley, L.E. (). The cultural mission of behaviorolo- Sagan, C. (). The Demon–Haunted World: Science as a
gy. The Behavior Analyst, , –. Candle in the Dark. New York: Random House.
Fraley, L.E. (). General Behaviorology: The Natural Sci- Schlinger, H. & Blakely, E. (). Function–altering
ence of Human Behavior. Morgantown, : Lawrence effects of contingency–specifying stimuli. The Behav-
E. Fraley (Rt.  Box , Reedsville   ). ior Analyst, , –.
Fraley, L.E. & Ledoux, S.F. (). Origins, status, and Sidman, M. (a). Functional analysis of emergent ver-
mission of behaviorology. In S.F. Ledoux. Origins and bal classes. In T. Thompson & M. Zeiler (Eds.).
Components of Behaviorology—Second Edition (pp. Analysis and Integration of Behavioral Units (pp. –
– [seven chapters]). Canton, : ABCs. ). Hillsdale, : Erlbaum.
Gore, A. (). Earth in the Balance. New York: Plume. Sidman, M. (b). The measurement of behavioral de-
Gould, S.J. (). Wonderful Life. New York: W.W. Norton. velopment. In N.A. Krasnegor, D.B. Gray, & T.
Johnson, K.R. & Layng, T.V.J. (). Breaking the Thompson (Eds.). Developmental Behavioral Pharma-
structuralist barrier: Literacy and numeracy with cology (pp. –). Hillsdale, : Erlbaum.
fluency. American Psychologist,  (), –. Sidman, M. (). Equivalence Relations and Behavior: A
Research Story. Boston, : Authors Cooperative.
ehaviorology oday  Volume 7, Number 1, Spring 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 41

Skinner, B.F. (). Science and Human Behavior. New


York: Macmillan.
Skinner, B.F. (). Verbal Behavior. New York: Apple-
ton–Century–Crofts. Reprinted, , Cambridge,
: The B.F. Skinner Foundation.
Skinner, B.F. (). Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New
York: Knopf.
Skinner, B.F. (). The Technology of Teaching. New
York: Appleton–Century–Crofts.
Skinner, B.F. (). The Shaping of a Behaviorist. New
York: Knopf.
Stromer, R. (). Stimulus equivalence: Implications
for teaching. In W. Ishaq (Ed.). Human Behavior in
Today’s World (pp. –). New York: Praeger.
Ulman, J.D. (). Toward a synthesis of Marx and
Skinner. Behavior and Social Issues,  (), –.
Ulman, J.D. (). Behaviorology and psychology are
incommensurable paradigms: A rejoinder to Staats.
Behaviorological Commentaries, Serial No. , –.
Vargas, E.A. (). Rights: A behavioristic analysis. Be-
haviorism,  (), –.
Vargas, E.A. (). Hume’s “ought” and “is” statement:
A radical behaviorist’s perspective. Behaviorism, 
(), –.
Vargas, E.A. (). Verbally–governed and event–governed
behavior. The Analysis of Verbal Behavior, , –.
Vargas, E.A. (). Behaviorology: Its paradigm. In W.
Ishaq (Ed.). Human Behavior in Today’s World (pp.
–). New York: Praeger.
Vargas, E.A. (). A university for the twenty–first cen-
tury. In J.R. Cautela & W. Ishaq (Eds.). Contempo-
rary Issues in Behavior Therapy: Improving the Human
Condition (pp. –). New York: Plenum.
Vargas, E.A. & Fraley, L.E. (). Progress and struc-
ture: Reorganizing the university for instructional
technology. Instructional Science, , –.
Vargas, E.A. & Vargas, J.S. (). Programmed instruc-
tion and teaching machines. In R.P. West & L.A.
Hamerlynck (Eds.). Designs for Excellence in Educa-
tion: The Legacy of B.F. Skinner (pp. –). Long-
mont, : Sopris West.
West, R.P. & Hamerlynck, L.A. (Eds.). (). Designs for
Excellence in Education: The Legacy of B.F. Skinner
(Limited Edition). Longmont, : Sopris West.
Wyatt, W.J., Hawkins, R.P., & Davis, P. (). Behavior-
ism: Are reports of its death exaggerated? The Behav-
ior Analyst, , –.

You might also like