Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 35

1 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Piaget’s Different Intelligence Test:


From IQ Tests to Operatory Intelligence

Richard F. Kitchener
Department of Philosophy
Colorado State University
For Collins, Colorado
USA

Running Head: Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Richard F Kitchener
Department of Philosophy
Colorado State University
Eddy Hall
Fort Collins, Colorado USA 80525
Telephone: 970 988 9438
E-mail: rkitch@colostate.edu
Word count: 8606
Keywords: Piaget, Binet, Burt, IQ Testing, Operatory Intelligence
2 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Abstract
A signature event in the history of psychology occurred in 1919 when Jean Piaget was asked to

standardize Cyril Burt’s tests of intelligence on Parisian children. Impressed by the errors

students made, Piaget studied the underlying reasoning process of these children. This led to

Piaget ‘s new méthode clinique for studying the intelligence of children and its development.

But why was there a need for such standardization? How did Burt’s intelligence test differ from

Binet’s version? How did Burt’s version pave the way for Piaget’s very different kind of

intelligence test—from I.Q. tests to tests of operatory intelligence?

I examine the history of this series of events pointing out the difference between Binet’s version

and Burt’s version, how they differed from Piaget’s similar questions and how the

standardization of Burt’s intelligence tests paved the way for Piaget’s different type of

intelligence test, a test of operatory intelligence.


3 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Introduction

Contemporary Piaget scholars have emphasized several crucial events in the intellectual life of

the well-known developmental psychologist and genetic epistemologist Jean Piaget: his

empirical work in naturalistic biology; his early philosophical career devoted to issues in

science, religion, and ethics; his encounter with the philosophical views of individuals such as

Henri Bergson, and so forth. In his autobiography (Piaget, forthcoming), Piaget mentions

another such signature event: his early empirical research with the intelligence testing movement

associated with Alfred Binet and Cyril Burt.

Sensing a need to learn more about psychology since it was to provide the link between biology

and epistemology, Piaget left for Zurich in 1919 to study psychology and psychoanalysis. After

a brief but unsatisfying period, Piaget then went to Paris to study logic, philosophy of science,

and more psychology (at the Sorbonne). While there, he was recommended to Theodore Simon

who was in charge of Alfred Binet’s laboratory at a local grade school. Dr. Simon, Piaget says,

“suggested that I should standardize Burt’s reasoning tests on the Parisian children.” Piaget

noted that although Burt’s tests had their diagnostic value, they were “based on the number of

successes and failures,” but he found “it was much more interesting to try to find the reasons for

the failures.” “Thus I engaged my subjects in conversations patterned after psychiatric

questioning, with the aim of discovering something about the reasoning process underlying their

right, but especially their wrong answers.” This was to become his famous méthode clinique.

What was remarkable to Piaget was that even the simplest tasks involving part-whole relations,

the coordination of relations, or the multiplication of classes proved to be difficult for children up

to 11 or 12.
4 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Piaget reports an incident with Théodore Simon which is not generally known. (This has been

questioned by Harris, 1997.) He was invited by Simon to give a lecture to the Société Alfred

Binet on “psychoanalysis and its relations with child psychology.” Psychoanalysis was not well-

known among pedagogues at that time and Simon’s invitation was accepted by Piaget. But

according to Piaget (1975), Simon “took revenge because of my independence” in doing

research on children instead of the assigned task of intelligence test standardization. Piaget’s

lecture was booed by the audience while Simon wore an imperturbable and continuous smile

(1975, p. 109). After a while, however, Simon rescued him from the crowd. This lecture was

one of the first publications coming out of his sojourn in Paris (Piaget, 1920).1

For two years (1919-1921), Piaget analyzed the verbal reasoning of children in response to a set

of intelligence test questions, publishing them in professional journals. “At last,” he concludes,

“I had found my field of research” and his career as a developmental psychologist was launched.

He was on his way to becoming the most celebrated developmental psychologist of the 20th

century.

Piaget had been searching for an area of empirical research that would allow him to pursue

answers to philosophical—notably epistemological—questions. Psychology was the right field,

he concluded, but how should he proceed to study the relevant psychological questions; indeed

what were they? Now he had an answer: he would study “the reasoning processes of children”—

their logic—and with this he would be studying the very development of reason. This would

involve the creation of a genetic (developmental) epistemology, not a traditional philosophical

epistemology, but one rooted in empirical scientific evidence.

1
Piaget wrote at least two other early articles on psychoanalysis, one in 1923 and one in 1933.
5 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

If we take Piaget at his word, this was a monumental event, a turning point in his career. But

how did it really differ from what had gone before him in the earlier work of Alfred Binet and

Cyril Burt? For that matter did Burt’s version differ from Binet’s in important respects? Both of

the intelligence testing procedures of Binet and Burt involved some cognitive activity similar

to what Piaget was to study. Was there really a difference between them? Why did Simon even

want Piaget to standardized Burt’s intelligence test questions on French students since he and

Binet had already spent years working out and refining their intelligence test—what would

become the famous Stanford-Binet intelligence test? What would be the point of standardizing

Burt’s apparently different intelligence test? For that matter, how did the format of the Binet-

Simon intelligence test differ from that of Burt’s intelligence test and how did both differ from

Piaget’s, which employed his méthode clinique? These are the questions I want to explore in the

present essay in part because I have not found a satisfactory answer to them.

Alfred Binet Intelligence Testing2

Alfred Binet’s intelligence test—the Binet-Simon Test—has a history that does not summarize

easily. The first installment was introduced in 1905 in the journal L’Année Psychologique:

“Upon the necessity of establishing a scientific diagnosis of inferior states of intelligence” (Binet

& Simon, 1905a). This was closely followed in the same year by “New methods for the

diagnosis of the intellectual level of subnormals” (Binet & Simon, 1905b) and “Application of

the new methods to the diagnosis of the intellectual level among normal and subnormal children

in institutions and in the primary school” (Binet & Simon, 1905c). These three were followed in

1908 by the normalizing scale for this intelligence test, ”The development of intelligence in

2
For discussion of the relevant views of Binet as they relate to Piaget, see Ducret, J.-J. (1984), Harris (1997), Huteau
(2006) , Wesley (1989). For Piaget’s views about Binet, see Piaget (1973, 1975)
6 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

the child”(Binet & Simon, 1908), with a slight revision, correction and application in 1911: in

“New investigations on the measurement of the intellectual level among school children”.

The first three 1905 essays are usually known as their test and the 1908 as the scale, which was

superseded by a somewhat different one in 1911 (Binet, 1911a). All five of these articles were

collected together and translated in 1916 as: The development of intelligence in children (the

Binet-Simon Scale (Binet & Simon, 1916).

A slightly different version of this 1911 scale was also published in the Bulletin de la société

libre pour l étude psychologie de l’enfant and also published in book form in 1911 (1911b),

which was translated into English and published as A method of measuring the development of

the intelligence of young children (1913). For English readers, therefore, there are two major

publications of the Binet-Simon intelligence test: 1913 and 1916 . But there are important

differences: the 1913 version is a kind of manual whereas the 1916 version contains a richer

theoretical presentation and justification.

Background

The immediate context surrounding the development of the Binet-Simon intelligence test

involved several factors. (For a historical overview of mental testing in this period, see e.g.,

Tuddenham, 1962; Young, 1923). In the first place, there was at a widespread interest in

understanding intelligence. To mention just two: Hyppolyte Taine wrote an entire book On

Intelligence (1870/1871), which was very influential and in England Charles Spearman’s (1904)

theory of intelligence, a hybrid account of general intelligence together with particular faculties

of intelligence, originally rivaled that of Binet’s as the most influential approach to studying

general intelligence for years.


7 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Of course this was not new since individuals had been philosophizing about intelligence and the

intellect since ancient times. “Intelligence” and “intellect” both derive from the Latin

“intelligere”, which is a translation of the Greek “noein” (to cognize), the activity of Nous—the

“Understanding.” Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics and others wrote about noesis, a special form of

cognition or “intellection,” and its relation to knowledge (episteme). In the modern period,

John Locke wrote about “ An essay on human understanding,” Baruch Spinoza’s entitled his

unfinished work: Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione translated as: On the Improvement of the

Intellect, and Gottfried Leibniz was after “the intellect itself” (intellectus ipse).

Although Taine did not distinguish intelligence from intellect, this began to occur as a result of

the Darwinian Revolution, which led to a re-evaluation of the question of intelligence in animals

(although reserving the notion of intellect for the alleged human form of intelligence). For these

thinkers, intelligence was located more in the interspace between organisms and their

environment, a notion stressed by individuals such as George Romanes in his book on Animal

Intelligence (1882). Pragmatists and functionalists such as Henri Bergson, John Dewey and

William James saw intelligence (at least partly) as a tool for coping with this world.

As a result there gradually emerged a distinction between intelligence and intellect, classically

expressed by Roback (1922), although how the two differ remains to be delineated even today.

This raised the question of what the then-current intelligence tests were testing intelligence,

intellect or both. At least one individual claimed: “…most of the modern mental tests are really

intellect tests, that is, tests of intellectual intelligence as distinguished from the motor or still

intelligence tests which are applied to animals.” As we will see Cyril Burt in his push for more

tests of higher reasoning seems to be advocating questions about intellect as distinguished from

general intelligence; one might make the same claim with respect to Piaget’s creation of his own
8 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

early version of intelligence tests—tests of intellect even though intellect is rooted in earlier

forms of intelligence.

Secondly, as a result of the movement of mandating public education for all its citizens, several

countries saw the need to identify those children whose native intelligence was such that they

were not benefitting from their education and hence required special classes. Consequently,

there was a pressing need to identify these “retarded” children by means of scientific testing

procedures. Recognized tests included a heterogeneous variety—sensory tests, behavioral tests,

physical measures (cephalic index, body type, graphology), etc. All of these indices were put to

work in the design of tests of intelligence. The result was a heterogeneous and by no means

coherent set of tests which, it was hoped, would enable scientists and educators to identify those

individuals requiring special education. In the process, individuals came to use such tests to

identify normal individuals and even those with superior intelligence.

Constructing such intelligence tests was thus originally designed to single out children of

significantly lower intelligence commonly designated by physicians at that time as idiots,

imbeciles, and morons (debilité).3 But such tests of abnormality presupposed some conception of

normal intelligence—what it was and how it developed from birth to adulthood. Such normal

intellectual development was clearly rooted in the child’s underlying biological nature displayed

over time and marked by their chronological ages. Hence for many individuals these new

3
Sometimes translated “feeble-minded.” Terms such as “retarded,” “feeble-minded,” along with the grades of
“idiot,” “imbecile,” and “moron” were employed to characterize these individuals until fairly recently. However,
becoming aware of the derogatory nature of these labels and given a changing theoretical conception of this malady,
professional organizations such as The American Psychiatric Association (in 2013) and the American Association
of Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities (in 2008) no longer use those terms and now employ the less
offensive one of “intellectual disability” or “intellectual and developmental disability.” As the AAIDD expresses it
“Intellectual disability is a disability characterized by significant limitations both in intellectual functioning and in
adaptive behavior as expressed in conceptual, social, and practical adaptive skills.” For a discussion of the reasons
for this change see Schalock, et al (2007). When I use these older and outmoded terms, it should be understood that
there is an implicitly understood “according to these thinkers” or “so-called.” I will use different terms to denote
this psychological syndrome.
9 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

intelligence tests of Binet and Burt constituted a way to measure not only debilitated

development but also normal and super-normal development. The intelligence tests in the hands

of Binet, Burt, Spearman, and others was thus the path to charting the entire trajectory of the

development of intelligence.

What do Intelligence Tests Measure?

Following the general assumptions of that period, Binet and Simon’s initial 1905 version of their

test consisted of a variety of quite heterogeneous items including tests of motor skill, perception,

memory, general knowledge, and several other items: personal cleanliness, speech, knowledge

of the body, ideas of place and time, reading and writing skills, etc. In their later 1908 and 1911

revisions, many of these same items were retained but items of a more “logical” nature were

added (See Table 1): explaining absurdities (e.g., “I have three brothers, Paul, Ernest and

myself”—one which Piaget used), giving abstract definitions (e.g., “charity,” “justice,”

“goodness”), rhyming, interpreting pictures (e.g., of an old couple on a park bench), giving the

meaning of facts involving “good sense,” and so forth. Clearly, the ability to answer such test

questions required different mental processes, processes of a more intellectual nature: to interpret

the meaning of a picture or an event—which involves what Binet called “good sense”—or to

explain what is absurd about myself being one of my brothers, to be able to distinguish the

difference between idleness and laziness, or to define “justice” seem still different abilities.

These tests of intellectual competence (s) seem different from tests involving a syllogism or a

quite different kind of test involving the conservation of liquid or a pendulum test.

Insert Table 1 about here


10 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

So even though Binet incorporated more intellectual type test questions, it remained an

open question whether these were tests of intellect or whether other type test questions were

needed, tests of a more logical nature. Indeed this motivated Cyril Burt to make substantial

revisions and/or additions to Binet’s intelligence test questions by adding tests of more

traditional logical reasoning.

The issue of the connection between intelligence and intellect (or rationality) and how

these relate to IQ tests were present from the very beginning and remains so today: Is

intelligence or intellect a unitary, global property of the mind, is it just the simple collection of

more particular cognitive faculties, or is it itself a particular discrete faculty? Etc. These are

questions about the nature of intelligence, questions Binet could hardly avoid.

Binet’s Theory of Intelligence

It is a widespread opinion that Binet had no clearly worked out theory of intelligence, that his

views about intelligence changed over the years and that he was groping towards a more

adequate account of intelligence (see e.g., Varson, 1936). Intelligence has two faces: one

involving a multiplicity of faculties, the other an underlying unity. Such a view can be found

perhaps in his most explicit view about intelligence appearing in one of his last books (1909)

where he wrote:

I have recently proposed with Dr. Simon. . . a synthetic theory of the functioning of the

mind, which…will show clearly that the mind is one, despite the multiplicity of its

Faculties; that it has one essential function to which all the others are subordinated. . .
11 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

In our opinion, intelligence, considered independently of phenomena of

sensibility, emotion , and will, is above all a faculty of knowing [connaissance], which is

directed toward the external world, and which labors to reconstruct it as a whole, by

means of the small fragments of it which are given to us. What we perceive of it is

element a, and all the very complicated work of our intelligence consists in uniting with

this first element a second element, the element b. All knowing [connaissance] is thus

essentially an addition, a continuation, a synthesis, whether the addition takes place

automatically as in external perception. . . or after a conscious search. . . But note well

that in this addition to the element a, there is already a host of faculties at work:

comprehension, memory, imagination, judgment, and above all, speech. Let us retain

only the most essential, and, since all this culminates in the invention of an element b, let

us call the operation an invention, which is executed after a comprehension. The

operation cannot be performed without our knowing what the question is, without our

adopting a certain line, from which we do not deviate, thus a direction is necessary . . The

ideas must be judged as fast as they ae produced and rejected if they do not fit the end

pursued; there must, thus be a censorship. Comprehension, invention, direction, and

censorship; intelligence is contained in these four words (1909, pp. 117-118; translation

from Varon, 1936, pp 46-47 modified)

A particular key faculty here is the notion of comprehension about which he wrote (1895) the

following:

There exists in us a faculty of comprehension, of grasping the meaning of a fact, object,

or idea, of a chain of reasoning. There are different names for the variants of this

complex faculty: it is the talent of observation thanks to which we distinguish reality


12 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

from appearances in what we perceive, the essential from the accessory, by means of

which we seize the relation of cause and effect—we analyze, synthesize, in a word we

comprehend. It is the espirit of finesse, intuitive rather than reasoned, thanks to which we

grasp puns or an intention, the imperceptible nuances of language or we give an account

of the motive of an action, of the character of an individual; it is the coup d’oeil, common

sense, judgment, the pragmatic sense which indicates the probable series of events, a

likely situation, the best solution, etc. One devises tests for these different aspects of

comprehension: thus, observation may be tested by asking for an explanation of the

movement of the parts of a machine which the subject observes in motion;

comprehension may be tested by definitions, differences between synonyms, criticisms of

inexact or incorrect sentences (p. 447).

Needless to say the relation of the faculty of comprehension to intelligence is opaque, for many

would say the faculty of comprehension is the faculty of intelligence. But Binet did say that he

had no (final) theory about the nature of intelligence and that he was more concerned with the

empirical tests for it. Subsequent thinks such as Spearman, Burt, and Piaget, who were equally

concerned with the question of the empirical tests of intelligence gave not only different accounts

of the nature of intelligence but also proposed quite different methods by means of which to test

it.

Cyril Burt’s Tests of Noetic Intelligence

Although Cyril Burt’s name is immersed in controversy, his contribution to intelligence testing,

although substantial, is less appreciated,4 and his influence on Piaget was significant (Riberio &

de Souza, 2020).

4
Burt (1914) is still among the best discussions of the conceptual problems surrounding intelligence testing.
13 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Burt began creating his own distinctive kind of intelligence test around 1908, utilizing the work

of earlier psychologists such as Spearman and Galton (although not Binet). This early program

was committed to the new correlational approach of British statisticians and psychologists

(Galton, Pearson, Spearman), later employing factor-analysis instead of what Burt called the

age-scale of Binet. Such an approach, with a variety of tests both similar to and different from

Binet, required standardization.

Burt’s intelligence testing did not center on mentally challenged students, as Binet’s tests did,

but on normal and gifted individuals (Burt, 1911, 1919), 5 although his most widely known work

(Burt, 1921) incorporated both kinds of tests. He incorporated items from the Binet-Simon tests

into his widely cited general work, this too required standardization on English students. Burt

was in communication with Binet (early on) and Simon, both of whom made suggestions for the

improvement of Burt’s tests. But Burt’s tests would need to be standardized not only on British

students but also on students from other countries, including French students.

Burt was especially concerned with the higher, more rational processes of children for several

reasons including identifying not only normal children but also super-normal, “gifted” subjects.

Becoming aware of Binet’s tests, he applied them, criticized them, and revised them. This

occurred over several years apparently with numerous interchanges with Binet and Simon, both

written and in person.

Unlike Binet, Burt’s fascination with the new statistical theories coming out of England led him

to argue for a factor-analytic approach to developmental cognition, opposing Binet’s more

eclectic and functional approach. His critical evaluation of Binet’s work was noted by Binet and

5
For example, he tested children in prep school at Oxford and Liverpool. The children there can hardly be taken as
average students. The same applies to the Isaacs who later tested children in the day care schools of Cambridge
(Kitchener, forthcoming).
14 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

appreciated somewhat, but this did not seem to result in any substantial changes in Binet’s

overall research program.

Like other psychologists of the period, was interested in general intelligence—an “inborn, all-

around mental efficiency,” “a single fundamental capacity,” “the higher, more rational, and

more complex mental processes”—what some call intellect. The current IQ tests, including

Binet’s, although perhaps adequate for measuring the intelligence of debilitated students were

not adequate to measure the general intelligence of the brighter students. Tests of reasoning

were therefore needed to test this “higher intelligence” and this would occur by studying their

correlation.

The main issue of the present essay centers not on Burt’s devotion to the new statistics coming

out of England but with the question of how Burt’s work on intelligence testing bears on

Piaget’s reported life-changing experience.6 Burt’s technical concern was with what he saw as

the less than adequate set of questions by Binet.

To create tests adequate for measuring this higher mental cognitive capacity Burt initially

(1911) used 14 tests but after running their correlations with intelligence, he concluded that only

5 had adequate correlations (the highest correlations were in the .70s). Although completion of

analogies was on the list, tests involving simple syllogisms were not—having the lowest

correlations of all—around .5. Still, he concluded that: “Of all the tests proposed, those

involving higher mental processes, such as Reasoning, vary most closely with Intelligence

(1911, p. 112). The main problem was the relation of tests of reasoning to intelligence. He

identified two types of cognitive activity belonging to this higher cognitive realm: logical

6
Burt (1919) and not Burt (1921) was the work Piaget explicitly addressed. As far as I can tell, Piaget was not
acquainted with his more hybrid account (Burt,1921). For this reason I will focus on Burt (1919). This is also the
sole reference to Burt in Inhelder’s work (1963/1968) on intelligence testing.
15 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

inference (reasoning) and what he termed apperception, “which depends upon a complex

synthetic activity, comparable to . . . intuition—the activity whereby we implicitly comprehend

the essential meaning or character of the whole, without explicitly analyzing it into its

component parts, or distinctly formulating their relations (1911, p. 103). This he labelled the

power of understanding— what the Greeks noesis—a concept to be found both in Spearman

(1905) and G. F. Stout, both of whom influenced Burt.

According to Stout (1909) for example:

By noetic synthesis I mean that union of presentational elements which is involved in

their reference to a single object; or, in other words, in their combination as specifying

constituents of the same thought. It is by noetic synthesis that those complex psychical

units come into being which we call percepts, ideas, and concepts. All these words imply

something which is perceived or conceived, or of which we have an idea; and it is this

objective reference which constitutes each of them a unit in mental process.” (p. 1).

Employing this notion, Burt concludes by saying: “. . . the development of reasoning appears to

consist essentially in an increase in the number, variety, originality, and compactness of the

relations which his mind can perceive and integrate into a coherent” (1914, p. 127). A view

similar to this was championed by Piaget reflecting the crucial role of relationalism in his

thinking.

In a subsequent work (1919), the center piece for our study about Piaget, Burt subjected

his earlier remarks to further empirical testing. He introduced “graded reasoning” where levels

of test difficulty—which might be thought to involve different mental levels—mapped onto ages

7 to 14. All of the test questions were questions of logic or logical reasoning in a broad sense.
16 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

They included analogies, deductive logic, inductive logic, informal fallacies and absurdities.7

The deductive logic questions, for example, involved classical Aristotelian logic involving

categorical, disjunctive, and hypothetical syllogisms. Although the correlations between answers

to syllogism tests and judgments of intelligence were not very impressive, often wavering around

.5, Burt continued to claim they were the best tests of intelligence.

Here are examples of some of the important test questions of Burt which Piaget’s found

particularly useful in studying higher intelligence.:

(7 Years) Jean says to his sister: “Part of [une partie de] my flowers are yellow.” Then

he asks them the color of his bouquet. Marie says: “All the flowers are yellow.” Simon

says: “Some of [quelques-unes de] of your flowers are yellow.” And Rose says:” “None

of your flowers are yellow” Which of them is right? (Piaget, 1921b, p. 438).

Another famous one extensively discussed by Piaget in several works (e.g., Piaget, 1924a) is:

(8 Years) Edith is fairer than Olive: but she is darker than Lily. Who is darker--Olive or

Lil.?

Finally:

(9 Years) If I have more than a shilling, I shall either go by taxi or by train If it rains I

shall either go by train or by bus. It is raining and I have half-a-crown. How do you think

I shall go?

7
Piaget did little explicit work on inductive logic, something his co-author Barbel Inhelder explicitly undertook.
Although is unclear what Piaget and Inhelder meant by induction and inductive logic, they assimilated it to the
hypothetico-deductive method and abductive inference, which are only two kinds of inductive logic (see Kitchener,
1999).
17 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

(12 Years) If the train is late he will miss his appointment: if the rain is not late he will

miss the rain. We do not know whether the train was late or not. Can we tell whether he

kept his appointment.

Burt calculated average test scores for each age thereby suggesting norms for each level and

proposing a developmental account of reasoning and intelligence (the correlation of reasoning

test scores and intelligence being 64 to .78).

Several points should be noted. First, Burt did not simply record the correct answers but asked

subjects why they gave the answer they did: the child gives his/her answer to the question “and

the child is asked to give his reason” (1919, p. 71). Burt stresses the importance of this: “In the

cross-examination lies the most valuable part of the test” (1919, p. 71), thus anticipating Piaget’s

major interest and his clinical method. But subjects’ protocols are not given by Burt. Instead an

additional numerical score is given to the correctness or adequacy of the reasons. There is no

real conversation between students and examiners, no Socratic dialogue occurring, a feature

Piaget and Inhelder stressed as crucial in their clinical method.

Secondly, Burt’s account of this process of the development of logical reasoning explicitly

rejects any notion of stages or qualitative structural change over time. “In the development of

the child’s capacity for formal reasoning no such distinct stages are discernible” (1919, p. 126).

Since the youngest age groups (7 years) can solve some syllogisms, this underlying logical

ability does not change over time although there is an increase in complexity of reasoning due to

subsequent acquisition of content obtained from the external world. “Logical form, therefore, is

of far less importance than either the amount or the kind of subject-matter” (1969,p. 126), which

presumably the child learns.


18 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Over the years Burt tested numerous British subjects on these questions. But obviously further

standardization was needed on children in other cultures, something both Binet and Simon were

aware of. But who could do this since Simon was absent from the laboratory school much of

the time. Voila! Jean Piaget was in need of psychological work. And so Piaget was given the

task of translating and standardizing Burt’s I.Q test questions.

Piaget’s Response

The Problem of Relations

Prior to Piaget’s first book, Le langage et la pensée chez l’enfant (1923), he reported several

experiments—both by himself working alone in Binet’s laboratory and then later in collaboration

of co-workers at the J. J. Rousseau institute in Geneva (Piaget, 1921a, 1921b, 1922a; Piaget &

Rossello, 1922b).8 These studies were the first ones issuing from Piaget’s prise de conscience

concerning his future field of research—the psychological processes underlying logical

operations and the possibility of a genetic epistemology. Several of these studies involved the

use of Burt’s tests or similar ones crafted by Piaget.

A central theme running throughout much of Piaget’s intellectual career was the logic of

relations. Early on as a youth he was concerned with holism, with the question of the nature of a

whole in relation to its parts (Kitchener, 1982, 1985). The parts of a whole and the whole itself

stand in a certain set of what we can call constituting relations. So to understand it you have to

understand three things: individual members (the parts of a whole), the whole itself, and their

constituting relations. A whole is more than a mere mathematical summation of its parts, but it

8
His very first article (Piaget, 1920) concerned his notorious lecture on psychoanalysis mentioned above. In
addition, a study of images (Piaget & Roselli, 1922), although different from the earlier studies, seem to be inspired
by several test items involving pictures. It was in this article that Piaget first explicitly introduced the notion of la
mèthode clinique (although without explication or elaboration). He explained this more fully in Piaget (1926). See
also Inhelder (1963/1968) who elaborated this notion.
19 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

is this collection plus all of the constituting relations. For example, society—a whole—is not

reducible to a collection of its individual members since it is the relations between members of

this society that makes it a society.

Piaget introduced an important distinction here between membership and other kinds of

relations. The individual parts of a whole can be members of the whole if they stand in a certain

kind of relation to it, e.g., I am a member of the human race. This is the part-whole connection

used in set theory and classical logic.

In addition, the parts of the whole can stand in a different kind of relation to each other, e.g., if I

have a brother, then there is a particular kind of relation between me and my brother: being the

brother of, which is a symmetrical relation.9 This is a part-part relation.

The central issue here concerned the nature of relations and the child’s becoming cognizant of

them. This is the source of the consequent problems children have in answering questions

about them. Piaget’s studies showed that young children lacked the ability to understand both

part-part relations and membership notions, a problem mastered by them only later. The

change from an earlier inept stage to a later competent stage came as a result of their

psychological construction of a set of structural relation, forming a logic of relations.

There were two types of questions about logical reasoning—reasoning involving relations—

emerging from Burt’s (1919) intelligence tests that Piaget addressed. First, there were 10

explicit test questions about part-whole relations Piaget took from Burt’s test questions. The

yellow bouquet question (see above) is one such example. Many 9–10-year-olds did not answer

9
Other important relations include transitivity and reflexivity. In formal group theory, a group consists of several
different relations, e.g., the INRC group of Inhelder and Piaget (1955/1958) .
20 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

the question correctly. They did not understand the relation between “part of ” and “some”—a

part-whole issue. They were still at a lower stage of cognitive reasoning.

Second, there were explicit questions about logical reasoning involving syllogisms, for example:

If this animal has long ears, it is a mule or an ass. If this animal has a big tail, it is a

horse or a mule. Now this animal has long ears and a big tail. What is it?

Here we have a logical problem involving relations—the intersection of classes—or logical

multiplication. Some children could understand logical addition (simple summation) but failed

to understand the class or set membership relation involved in logical multiplication. Only at a

later stage did they understand this. Both types of reasoning questions had their source in Burt’s

paper.

Piaget’s used the results of these studies to suggest why children made errors in answering

these questions, e.g., why they were inept at reasoning involving contradictions: they failed to

understand a contradiction because they were unable to hold two thoughts together at the same

time and to see their relationship. Psychological development could thus explain logical

ineptitude. In addition, children could not entertain the hypothetical nature of premises assumed

to be true—something necessary in logical reasoning. Here, then, was the beginning of Piaget’s

concern with the very nature of logical reasoning and its psychological underpinning.

All of this was tied to a developmental perspective involving stages or stage-like features and all

of this would become an important part of his genetic epistemology since in studying the

reasons children gave for their answers, they had to justify them during the course of their

conversation with the experimenters. So unlike studying children’s thinking as involving


21 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

answers plus their reasons, Piaget studied thinking as involving answers plus reasons together

with their justification of these reasons—a three-pronged approach.10

Genetic Epistemology

“When I arrived in Paris. . .” Piaget says, “ I already had the idea of doing epistemology, of

studying the formation of knowledge beginning with the psychology of the child” (Piaget,

forthcoming). In Binet’s laboratory, Piaget would discover how particular psychological

processes in the child would satisfy this epistemological interest—the intelligence tests of Burt

(and Binet)—and he would be able to set forth a more detailed conception of this new genetic

epistemology. This would necessitate an account not only of the psychogenesis of knowledge

but also of the nature of this developmental knowledge and the connection between the

psychology of the child and the development of knowledge. Prior to this he had the germinal

notion of such a genetic epistemology but what was needed was a more detailed and refined

account. This began to be sketched in the ‘20s with his studies of Leon Brunschwicg and

Arnold Reymond (1925), resulting in two early sketches of his genetic epistemology (Piaget,

1924b, 1925).11

As a result of the publication of his early experimental articles, Piaget was offered a position at

Geneva and while there he continued investigating the reasoning of the child, publishing the

ground-breaking works contained in Le langage et la pensée chez l’enfant (1923) and Le

jugement et le raisonnement chez l’enfant (1924a). These two works constituted an essential part

10
The introduction of the clinical method with its dialectical nature allowed one to study the child’s knowledge but
in addition it opened the way to studying the child’s incipient theory of this knowledge: from genetic knowledge of
the child to the genetic theory of knowledge of the child. Piaget never pursued this latter course in any systematic
way.

11
The first reference to genetic epistemology that I have found occurs in Piaget (1924b).
22 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

(along with other projected works) of what Piaget’s called “ Studies in Child Logic. “ This was

never completed. Piaget’s intellectual career subsequently changed in part as the result of what

can be called “the Isaacs Affair” (Kitchener, forthcoming)—his personal and scholarly

interchange with Susan Isaacs and Nathan Isaacs with a year spent in England. This was another

monumental event in the early life of Piaget. Although some individuals have noted this crucial

set of events, it remains a story yet to be told.

Operatory Intelligence

Although Piaget wrote little on intelligence testing after this period, he did explicitly write about

Binet at least twice; he wrote virtually nothing about Burt. He saw some value in the Binet-

Simon tests but the results of this I.Q. testing dealt only with the surface of things—the external

behavioral result—whereas he wanted to probe the underlying cognitive processes giving rise to

these results, namely, what he called operatory intelligence.

Intelligence, according to Piaget, consists of the ability to adapt to the environment via the

processes of assimilation-accommodation with the degree of adaptation being marked by varying

states of equilibrium characterized formally as a “groupings.” As he put it: “…the act of

intelligence consists essentially of ‘grouping’ operations according to certain definite structures. .

.intelligence is thus conceived as the form of equilibrium towards which all cognitive processes

tend… (Piaget, 1947/1950, p. v).

The central theoretical construct here is that of an operation. “We will call operations the

interiorized (or interiorizable), reversible actions … coordinated in structures, known as

operatory, which present laws of composition characterizing the structure in its totality as a

system” (1960/1973, p. 76). Operatory intelligence thus involves operations and an operatory
23 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

structure. Piaget’s alternative tests of intelligence involving the clinical method were thus

designed not to measure observable behavior but to get at this underlying operatory

intelligence.12

Conclusion

We are now ready to answer the questions originally posed. As we have seen, Burt’s intelligence

tests were sufficiently different from Binet’s that they needed standardization on French

children. The particular tests of Burt (1919) were ones in which the questions were aimed at

the “higher reasoning” of normal subjects not disabled individuals using syllogisms, analogies,

and fallacies—the heart of traditional logic. These were not the focus of the Binet-Simon tests

even though their tests contained questions requiring some abstract logical reasoning abilities or

general intelligence or intellect. When Piaget tested normal children on these Burt-type

questions, they made systematic errors in reasoning thus suggesting that since they were not

“retarded,” hence another explanation of their errors was needed. Piaget was acquainted with the

stage theory of individuals such as Pierre Janet, and perhaps Binet’s distinction between mental

ages and mental levels led him to suggest that these students were operating at a lower mental

level. His earlier thoughts about holism and the problem of relations led him to select test

questions concerning part-whole relations (and later symmetrical relations), set-theoretical

notions such as logical multiplication and logical addition, problems of classification, and the

development of formal reasoning. Being at a lower level, children did not understand such

12
Piaget’s research program was continued by Bärbel Inhelder and applied to diagnosing the mentally deficient by
means of conservation tests of weight, volume, etc. (1963/1968). The resulting alternative tests of mental
deficiency (and indirectly of normal intelligence) again employed the clinical method together with hands-on
activity involving problem-solving tasks with physical objects. According to Piaget, this was “the discovery of a
new criterion of mental deficiency” (Piaget, 1943/191963/1968, p. 11). Unfortunately it remains unclear how
Inhelder’s work can be used to diagnose mental disability. This work by Piaget and Inhelder has, however, been
used by subsequent researchers as indicators of mental deficiency of various kinds. (For reviews, see Dougherty &
Moran, 1983; Klein & Safford, 1977; Paour, 2011.)
24 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

concepts involving classes and relations; this required subsequent holistic construction in group-

like structures requiring passage to a later intellectual stage. This no doubt encouraged Piaget to

expand his stage-like thinking. These conceptions provided many of the details needed for his

life-long project of a genetic epistemology. Psychogenesis was the necessary link between his

biological theory and epistemology. Such an epistemology contained two aspects: the

historical development of knowledge in the sciences and the psychological development of

knowledge in the individual (Kitchener, 1986). His future path would thus involve empirical

work on the psychogenesis of logical operations coupled with his to be developed genetic

epistemology (Piaget, 1950). His life-long program of a genetic epistemology was thus launched.
25 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Acknowledgement

Special thanks to Anne Machin for reading and commenting on an earlier version of this paper.

Statement of Ethics

Not applicable

Conflict of Interest

Not applicable

Funding Sources

Not applicable

Author Contributions

Not applicable

Data Availability Statement

Not applicable
26 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

References

Binet, A. (1895). La psychologie individuelle. Année Psychologie, 2, 411-465.

Binet, A. (1909). Les idées modern sur les enfants. Paris: Flammarion.

Binet, A. & Th. Simon (1905a). Sur la nécessité d’etablir un diagnostic scientifique des états

inférieurs de l’intelligence. [On the necessity of establishing a scientific diagnosis of the

inferior states of intelligence]. Année Psychologique, 11, 163-190

Binet, A. & Th. Simon (1905b). Méthodes nouvelles pour le diagnostic du niveau intellectual des

anormaux [ New methods for diagnosing the intellectual level of subnormals]. Année

Psychologique, 11, 191-244.

Binet, A & Th. Simon (1905c) Application des méthodes nouvelles au diagnostic du niveau

intellectual chez des enfants normaux et anormaux d’hospice et école primaire

[Application of new methods to the diagnosis to the intellectual level of normal and

abnormal children in institutions and primary schools]. Année Psychologique, 11, 245-

336

Binet, A. & Th. Simon (1908). Le développement de l’intelligence chez les enfants [The

development of intelligence in children]. Année Psychologique, 14, 1-94.

Binet, A. & Th. Simon 1911a). Nouveau recherché sur la mesure du niveau intellectual chez les

enfants d’école [New studies on the measurement of the intellectual level of school

children]. Année Psychologique, 17, 145-201


27 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Binet, A.& Th. Simon (1911b). La mesure du développement de l’intelligence chez les jeunes

enfants [Measurement of the development of intelligence in young children].

(Publication de la Société Alfred Binet). Paris: Alcan.

Binet, A. & Th. Simon (1913). A method of measuring the development of the intelligence of

young children. (C. H. Town, Trans.). Chicago: Medical Book Co.

Binet, A. & Th. Simon (1916). The development of intelligence in children (the Binet-Simon

Scale) (E. Kite, Trans.; H. Goddard, Ed.). New Jersey: the Training School of the

Vineland Research

Burt, C. (1911). Experimental tests of higher mental processes and their relation to general

intelligence. Journal of Experimental Pedagogy and Training College Record, 1, 93-112.

Burt, C. (1914). The measurement of intelligence by Binet tests. The Eugenics Review, 6, 36-

50,140-152

Burt, C. (1919). The development of reasoning in school children. The Journal of Experimental

Pedagogical and Training College Record, 5, 68-77,121-127

Burt, C. (1921). Mental and scholastic tests. London: P. S. King

Dougherty, J. M. & Moran, J.D. (1983). The relationship of Piagetian stages to mental

retardation. Education and Training of Mentally Retarded, 18, 260-265.

Ducret, J.-J. (1984). Jean Piaget: Savant et philosophie. Les Années de formation, 1907-1924.

Etude sur la formation des connaissance et du sujet de la connaissance [Jean Piaget:

Scientist and Philosopher: The formative years, 1907-1924 . A study of the formation of

knowledge and the subject of knowledge] (Vol. II, pp. 546-568). Geneva: Libraire Droz.
28 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Harris, P. (1997). Piaget in Paris: From ‘autism’ to logic. Human Development, 40, 109-123

Huteau, Michel (2006). Alfred Binet et la psychology de l’intelligence [Alfred Binet and the

psychology of intelligence]. Le journal des psychologique, 234, 24-28.

Inhelder, B. (1963).Le Diagnostic du raisonnement chez les débiles mentaux (2nd Ed). Neuchâtel:

Delachaux & Niestlé (Translated by W. Stephens as The diagnosis of reasoning in the

mentally retarded. New York: John Day Co., 1968).

Inhelder, B. & Piaget, J. (1955). De la logique de l’enfant à la loqique de l’adolescent: essay sur

la construction des structures opératoires formeles. Paris: P.U.F. (Translated by A.

Parsons & S. Milgram as The growth of logical thinking from childhood to adolescence:

an essay on the construction of formal operational structures. London: Routledge &

Kegan Paul, 1958)

Kitchener, R. F. (1982). Holism and the organismic model in developmental psychology.

Human Development, 25 , 233-249.

Kitchener, R. F. (1985). Holistic structuralism, elementarism and Piaget’s theory of

relationalism. Human Development, 28, 281-294.

Kitchener. R. F. ( 1986). Jean Piaget’s theory of knowledge: Genetic epistemology and

scientific

reason. New Haven: Yale University press.

Kitchener, R. F. ( 1999). The conduct of inquiry: An introduction to logic and scientific method.
29 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

Kitchener, R. F. (forthcoming); Jean Piaget and the Isaacs affair..

Klein, N. K. & Safford, P L. (1977). Application of Piaget’s theory to the study of thinking of the

mentally retarded: A review of research. The Journal of Special Education, 11, 201-216.

Paour, J.-L. (2001). From structural diagnosis to functional diagnosing of reasoning: a dynamical

conception of mental retardation. In A. Tryphon & J. Vonèche (eds.)(2001). Working

with Piaget: Essays in honour of Bärbel Inhelder (pp. 13-38). Hove: Psychology Press.

Piaget, J. (1920). La psychoanalyse dans ses rapports avec la psychologie de l’enfant

[Psychoanalysis in its relations with the psychology of the child]. Bulletin

mensuel, Société Alfred Binet, 1, 18-34, 41-58.

Piaget, J. (1921a). Essai sur quelques aspects du développements de la notion de partie chez

l’enfant.[An essay on several aspects of the development of the notion of part in the

child] Journal de Psychologie Normale et Pathologique, 18, 449-480.

Piaget, J. (1921b). Une forme verbale de la comparaison chez l’enfant: un cas de transition entre

le judgment prédicatif et le jugement de relation [A verbal form of comparison in the

child: a case of the transition between predicative judgment and relational judgment] .

Archives de Psychologie, 18, 141-172.

Piaget, J. (1922a). Essai sur la multiplication logique et les débuts de la pensée formelle chez

l’enfan [An essay on logical multiplication and the beginnings of formal thought in the

child]. Journal de Psychologie Normale et Pathologique, 19, 222-261.


30 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Piaget, J. & P. Rossello. (1922). Note sur les types de description de images chez l’enfant [A

note on the types of description of images in the child]. Archives de Psychologique, 18,

208-234.

Piaget, J. (1923), Le langage et la pensée chez l’enfant. Neuchâtel/Paris: Delachaux et Niestlé

(Translated by M. & R. Gabain as The language and thought of the child. London:

Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1926).13

Piaget, J. (1924a). Le jugement et le raisonnement chez l’enfant. Neuchâtel/Paris: Delachaux et

Niestlé (Translated by M. Warden as Judgment and reasoning in the child). London:

Routledge & Kegan Paul 1928.14

Piaget, J. (1924b).” L’expérience humaine et la causalité physique” de L. Brunschvicg: étude

Critique [Critical Study of: “Human experience and physical causality” by Lèon

Brunschvicg]. Journal de psychologie normale et pathologique, 21, 586-607.

Piaget, J. (1925). Psychologie et critique de la connaissance [Psychology and the critique of

knowledge]. Archives de psychologie, 19, 193-210.

Piaget, J. (1943). Preface to the first edition. In B. Inhelder (1963).Le Diagnostic du

raisonnement chez les débiles mentaux (2nd Ed). Neuchâtel: Delachaux & Niestlé

(Translated by W. Stephens as The diagnosis of reasoning in the mentally retarded, pp.

9-12). New York: John Day Co., 1968).

13
The 2nd edition (1930) and 3rd edition (1948) of this are importantly different from the 1st edition, reflecting
Piaget’s response to the Isaacs criticism and important revisions in his thinking.
14
The 2nd and 3rd editions have new Prefaces.
31 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Piaget, J. (1947). La psychologie de l’intelligence. Paris:. A Colin. (Translated by M. Piercy &

D. Berlyne as The psychology of intelligence. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1950)

Piaget, J. (1950). Introduction à la épistémologie génétique [Introduction to genetic

epistemology] (3 vols.). Paris: P.U.F.

Piaget, J. (1960). Les praxies chez l’enfant (Translated by A. Rosin as “Child praxis” in The

child and reality. New York: Viking Press, 1973)

Piaget, J. (1973). Préface. In A. Binet, Les idées modernes sur les enfants [Modern ideas about

children] (pp. 5-10 ). Paris: Flammarion

Piaget, J. (1975). L’intelligence, selon Alfred Binet [Intelligence according to Alfred Binet] .

Bulletin de la Sociéte Alfred Binet et Théodore Binet, 75, 106-119\

Piaget, J. (forthcoming ). The complete autobiography (edited and partially translated by R.

Kitchener).

Ribeiro, A. E. M. & L. de Souza (2020). O encontro de Piaget como tests de intelligência de

Cyril Burt. Uma revisão narrative [Piaget’s meeting with Cyril Burt’s intelligence test: a

narrative review]. Psico. Of educ, San Paulo [on line], 51, 11-21.

Roback, A. A. (1922). Intelligence and intellect. The Journal of Philosophy, 19, 325-330.

Romanes, G. (1882). Animal intelligence. New York: Appleton.

Schalock, R. L., et al (2007). The renaming of mental retardation: Understanding the change to

the term intellectual disability. Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities, 45, 116-

124.
32 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Spearman, C. (1904). ‘ General intelligence,’ objectively determined and measured. The

American Journal of Psychology, 15, 201–293.

Stout, G. F. (1909). Noetic synthesis. In his Analytic Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 1-42). London:

Swan & Sonneschein.

Taine, H. (1870). De l’intelligence. Paris: Hachette (Translated by T. Haye as On intelligence.

London: Reeve, 1871).

Tuddenham, R. D. (1962). The nature and measurement of intelligence. In L. Postman (Ed.),

Psychology in the making: Histories of selected research problems (pp. 469-525). New

York: A. Knopf.

Varon, E. J. (1936). Alfred Binet’s concept of intelligence. Psychological Review, 43, 32-58.

Wesley, F. (1989). Developmental cognition before Piaget: Alfred Binet’s pioneering research.

Developmental Review, 9, 58-63.

White, S. H.( 2000). Conceptual foundations of IQ testing. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law,

6, 33- 43.

Young, K. (1923). The history of mental testing. The Pedagogical Seminary, 31, 1-48.
33 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Table 1

Chronological Tests

Six years
Distinguish morning and evening.
Define by use
Copy diamond
Count 13 pennies
Compare 2 pictures esthetically

Seven years
Right hand, left ear
Describe a picture .
Execute 3 commissions
Count 3 single and 3 double sous
Name 4 colors

Eight years
Compare 2 objects from memory
Count from 20 to 0
Indicate omission in pictures
Give the date
Repeat 5 digits

Nine years
Give change out of 20 coins
Definitions superior to use
Recognize the value of 9 pieces of
money
Name the months
Comprehend easy questions

Ten years
Copy a design from memory
Criticize absurd statements
Comprehend difficult questions
Place 3 words in 2 sentences
Twelve years
Resist the suggestion of lines
Place 3 words in 1 sentence
Give more than 60 words in 3 min
utes
Define 3 abstract words
34 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

Comprehend a disarranged sentence


Place 5 weights in order

Fifteen years
Repeat 7 figures
Find 3 rhymes
Repeat a sentence of 26 syllables
Interpret a picture
Solve a problem composed of several
facts

Adults
Comprehend a cut in a folded paper
Reverse a triangle
Answer the question about the Pres
ident
Distinguish abstract words
Give the sense of the quotation from
Hervieu
35 Piaget’s Intelligence Test

You might also like