Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

4.

2 Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility


HARRY FRANKFURT
Harry Frankfurt is Professor Emeritus at Princeton University. He has published several
important papers on the issues of free will.

A dominant role in nearly all recent inquiries into bringing the relevant moral phenomena into
the free-will problem has been played by a prin- sharper focus.
ciple which I shall call “the principle of alternate
possibilities.” This principle states that a person I
is morally responsible for what he has done only
if he could have done otherwise. Its exact mean- In seeking illustrations of the principle of alter-
ing is a subject of controversy, particularly con- nate possibilities, it is most natural to think of
cerning whether someone who accepts it is situations in which the same circumstances
thereby committed to believing that moral re- both bring it about that a person does something
sponsibility and determinism are incompatible. and make it impossible for him to avoid doing it.
Practically no one, however, seems inclined to These include, for example, situations in which a
deny or even to question that the principle of person is coerced into doing something, or in
alternate possibilities (construed in some way or which he is impelled to act by a hypnotic sugges-
other) is true. It has generally seemed so over- tion, or in which some inner compulsion drives
whelmingly plausible that some philosophers him to do what he does. In situations of these
have even characterized it as an a priori truth. kinds there are circumstances that make it im-
People whose accounts of free will or of moral possible for the person to do otherwise, and
responsibility are radically at odds evidently find these very circumstances also serve to bring it
in it a firm and convenient common ground about that he does whatever it is that he does.
upon which they can profitably take their oppos- However, there may be circumstances that
ing stands. constitute sufficient conditions for a certain ac-
But the principle of alternate possibilities is tion to be performed by someone and that there-
false. A person may well be morally responsible fore make it impossible for the person to do
for what he has done even though he could not otherwise, but that do not actually impel the per-
have done otherwise. The principle’s plausibility son to act or in any way produce his action. A
is an illusion, which can be made to vanish by person may do something in circumstances that

This paper first appeared in Journal of Philosophy vol. 66 (1969), pp. 829–839. Reprinted by permis-
sion of the publisher and author.
HARRY FRANKFURT • 4.2 Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility 529

leave him no alternative to doing it, without understood, in other words, as a particularized
these circumstances actually moving him or lead- version of the principle of alternate possibilities.
ing him to do it—without them playing any role, Let us suppose that someone is threatened
indeed, in bringing it about that he does what he convincingly with a penalty he finds unaccept-
does. able and that he then does what is required of
An examination of situations characterized him by the issuer of the threat. We can imagine
by circumstances of this sort casts doubt, I be- details that would make it reasonable for us to
lieve, on the relevance to questions of moral re- think that the person was coerced to perform the
sponsibility of the fact that a person who has action in question, that he could not have done
done something could not have done otherwise. otherwise, and that he bears no moral responsi-
I propose to develop some examples of this kind bility for having done what he did. But just what
in the context of a discussion of coercion and to is it about situations of this kind that warrants
suggest that our moral intuitions concerning the judgment that the threatened person is not
these examples tend to disconfirm the principle morally responsible for his act?
of alternate possibilities. Then I will discuss the This question may be approached by consid-
principle in more general terms, explain what I ering situations of the following kind. Jones de-
think is wrong with it, and describe briefly and cides for reasons of his own to do something,
without argument how it might appropriately be then someone threatens him with a very harsh
revised. penalty (so harsh that any reasonable person
would submit to the threat) unless he does pre-
cisely that, and Jones does it. Will we hold Jones
II morally responsible for what he has done? I think
It is generally agreed that a person who has been this will depend on the roles we think were
coerced to do something did not do it freely and played, in leading him to act, by his original de-
is not morally responsible for having done it. cision and by the threat.
Now the doctrine that coercion and moral re- One possibility is that Jones1 is not a reason-
sponsibility are mutually exclusive may appear able man: he is, rather, a man who does what he
to be no more than a somewhat particularized has once decided to do no matter what happens
version of the principle of alternate possibilities. next and no matter what the cost. In that case,
It is natural enough to say of a person who has the threat actually exerted no effective force
been coerced to do something that he could not upon him. He acted without any regard to it,
have done otherwise. And it may easily seem that very much as if he were not aware that it had
being coerced deprives a person of freedom and been made. If this is indeed the way it was, the
of moral responsibility simply because it is a spe- situation did not involve coercion at all. The
cial case of being unable to do otherwise. The threat did not lead Jones1 to do what he did.
principle of alternate possibilities may in this Nor was it in fact sufficient to have prevented
way derive some credibility from its association him from doing otherwise: if his earlier decision
with the very plausible proposition that moral had been to do something else, the threat would
responsibility is excluded by coercion. not have deterred him in the slightest. It seems
It is not right, however, that it should do so. evident that in these circumstances the fact that
The fact that a person was coerced to act as he Jones1 was threatened in no way reduces the
did may entail both that he could not have done moral responsibility he would otherwise bear
otherwise and that he bears no moral responsi- for his act. This example, however, is not a coun-
bility for his action. But his lack of moral respon- terexample either to the doctrine that coercion
sibility is not entailed by his having been unable excuses or to the principle of alternate possibili-
to do otherwise. The doctrine that coercion ties. For we have supposed that Jones1 is a man
excludes moral responsibility is not correctly upon whom the threat had no coercive effect
530 PART V • Determinism, Free Will, and Responsibility

and, hence, that it did not actually deprive him those which had already persuaded him to do so?
of alternatives to doing what he did. Or did he act on the basis of two motives, each of
Another possibility is that Jones2 was stam- which was sufficient for his action? It is not im-
peded by the threat. Given that threat, he would possible, however, that the situation should be
have performed that action regardless of what clearer than situations of this kind usually are.
decision he had already made. The threat upset And suppose it is apparent to us that Jones3 acted
him so profoundly, moreover, that he completely on the basis of his own decision and not because
forgot his own earlier decision and did what was of the threat. Then I think we would be justified
demanded of him entirely because he was terri- in regarding his moral responsibility for what
fied of the penalty with which he was threatened. he did as unaffected by the threat even though,
In this case, it is not relevant to his having per- since he would in any case have submitted to the
formed the action that he had already decided on threat, he could not have avoided doing what he
his own to perform it. When the chips were did. It would be entirely reasonable for us to
down he thought of nothing but the threat, make the same judgment concerning his moral
and fear alone led him to act. The fact that at responsibility that we would have made if we
an earlier time Jones2 had decided for his own had not known of the threat. For the threat did
reasons to act in just that way may be relevant to not in fact influence his performance of the ac-
an evaluation of his character; he may bear full tion. He did what he did just as if the threat
moral responsibility for having made that deci- had not been made at all.
sion. But he can hardly be said to be morally
responsible for his action. For he performed the
action simply as a result of the coercion to which
III
he was subjected. His earlier decision played no The case of Jones3 may appear at first glance to
role in bringing it about that he did what he did, combine coercion and moral responsibility, and
and it would therefore be gratuitous to assign it a thus to provide a counterexample to the doctrine
role in the moral evaluation of his action. that coercion excuses. It is not really so certain
Now consider a third possibility. Jones3 was that it does so, however, because it is unclear
neither stampeded by the threat nor indifferent whether the example constitutes a genuine in-
to it. The threat impressed him, as it would im- stance of coercion. Can we say of Jones3 that
press any reasonable man, and he would have he was coerced to do something, when he had
submitted to it wholeheartedly if he had not al- already decided on his own to do it and when he
ready made a decision that coincided with the did it entirely on the basis of that decision? Or
one demanded of him. In fact, however, he per- would it be more correct to say that Jones3 was
formed the action in question on the basis of the not coerced to do what he did, even though he
decision he had made before the threat was is- himself recognized that there was an irresistible
sued. When he acted, he was not actually moti- force at work in virtue of which he had to do it?
vated by the threat but solely by the My own linguistic intuitions lead me toward the
considerations that had originally commended second alternative, but they are somewhat equiv-
the action to him. It was not the threat that ocal. Perhaps we can say either of these things,
led him to act, though it would have done so if or perhaps we must add a qualifying explanation
he had not already provided himself with a suffi- to whichever of them we say.
cient motive for performing the action in This murkiness, however, does not interfere
question. with our drawing an important moral from an
No doubt it will be very difficult for anyone examination of the example. Suppose we decide
to know, in a case like this one, exactly what hap- to say that Jones3 was not coerced. Our basis for
pened. Did Jones3 perform the action because of saying this will clearly be that it is incorrect to
the threat, or were his reasons for acting simply regard a man as being coerced to do something
HARRY FRANKFURT • 4.2 Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility 531

unless he does it because of the coercive force to mean that he cannot but perform the action
exerted against him. The fact that an irresistible he performs. And yet the threat, since Jones3
threat is made will not, then, entail that the per- performs the action without regard to it, does
son who receives it is coerced to do what he not reduce his moral responsibility for what he
does. It will also be necessary that the threat is does.
what actually accounts for his doing it. On the The following objection will doubtless be
other hand, suppose we decide to say that Jones3 raised against the suggestion that the case of
was coerced. Then we will be bound to admit Jones3 is a counterexample to the principle of
that being coerced does not exclude being mor- alternate possibilities. There is perhaps a sense
ally responsible. And we will also surely be led to in which Jones3 cannot do otherwise than per-
the view that coercion affects the judgment of a form the action he performs, since he is a reason-
person’s moral responsibility only when the per- able man and the threat he encounters is
son acts as he does because he is coerced to do sufficient to move any reasonable man. But it is
so—i.e., when the fact that he is coerced is what not this sense that is germane to the principle of
accounts for his action. alternate possibilities. His knowledge that he
Whichever we decide to say, then, we will stands to suffer an intolerably harsh penalty
recognize that the doctrine that coercion ex- does not mean that Jones3, strictly speaking,
cludes moral responsibility is not a particularized cannot perform any action but the one he does
version of the principle of alternate possibilities. perform. After all it is still open to him, and this
Situations in which a person who does some- is crucial, to defy the threat if he wishes to do so
thing cannot do otherwise because he is subject and to accept the penalty his action would bring
to coercive power are either not instances of co- down upon him. In the sense in which the prin-
ercion at all, or they are situations in which the ciple of alternate possibilities employs the con-
person may still be morally responsible for what cept of “could have done otherwise,” Jones3’s
he does if it is not because of the coercion that inability to resist the threat does not mean that
he does it. When we excuse a person who has he cannot do otherwise than perform the action
been coerced, we do not excuse him because he performs. Hence the case of Jones3 does not
he was unable to do otherwise. Even though a constitute an instance contrary to the principle.
person is subject to a coercive force that pre- I do not propose to consider in what sense
cludes his performing any action but one, he the concept of “could have done otherwise” fig-
may nonetheless bear full moral responsibility ures in the principle of alternate possibilities, nor
for performing that action. will I attempt to measure the force of the objec-
tion I have just described.1 For I believe that
whatever force this objection may be thought
IV to have can be deflected by altering the example
To the extent that the principle of alternate pos- in the following way.2 Suppose someone—Black,
sibilities derives its plausibility from association let us say—wants Jones4 to perform a certain
with the doctrine that coercion excludes moral action. Black is prepared to go to considerable
responsibility, a clear understanding of the latter lengths to get his way, but he prefers to avoid
diminishes the appeal of the former. Indeed the showing his hand unnecessarily. So he waits until
case of Jones3 may appear to do more than illu- Jones4 is about to make up his mind what to do,
minate the relationship between the two doc- and he does nothing unless it is clear to him
trines. It may well seem to provide a decisive (Black is an excellent judge of such things) that
counterexample to the principle of alternate Jones4 is going to decide to do something other
possibilities and thus to show that this principle than what he wants him to do. If it does become
is false. For the irresistibility of the threat to clear that Jones4 is going to decide to do some-
which Jones3 is subjected might well be taken thing else, Black takes effective steps to ensure
532 PART V • Determinism, Free Will, and Responsibility

that Jones4 decides to do, and that he does do, had not been a fact. Indeed, everything hap-
what he wants him to do.3 Whatever Jones4’s pened just as it would have happened without
initial preferences and inclinations, then, Black Black’s presence in the situation and without
will have his way. his readiness to intrude into it.
What steps will Black take, if he believes he In this example there are sufficient condi-
must take steps, in order to ensure that Jones4 tions for Jones4’s performing the action in ques-
decides and acts as he wishes? Anyone with a tion. What action he performs is not up to him.
theory concerning what “could have done oth- Of course it is in a way up to him whether he
erwise” means may answer this question for him- acts on his own or as a result of Black’s interven-
self by describing whatever measures he would tion. That depends upon what action he himself
regard as sufficient to guarantee that, in the rel- is inclined to perform. But whether he finally
evant sense, Jones4 cannot do otherwise. Let acts on his own or as a result of Black’s interven-
Black pronounce a terrible threat, and in this tion, he performs the same action. He has no
way both force Jones4 to perform the desired alternative but to do what Black wants him to
action and prevent him from performing a for- do. If he does it on his own, however, his moral
bidden one. Let Black give Jones4 a potion, or responsibility for doing it is not affected by the
put him under hypnosis, and in some such way fact that Black was lurking in the background
as these generate in Jones4 an irresistible inner with sinister intent, since this intent never comes
compulsion to perform the act Black wants per- into play.
formed and to avoid others. Or let Black manip-
ulate the minute processes of Jones4’s brain and
nervous system in some more direct way, so that
V
causal forces running in and out of his synapses The fact that a person could not have avoided
and along the poor man’s nerves determine that doing something is a sufficient condition of his
he chooses to act and that he does act in the one having done it. But, as some of my examples
way and not in any other. Given any conditions show, this fact may play no role whatever in
under which it will be maintained that Jones4 the explanation of why he did it. It may not fig-
cannot do otherwise, in other words, let Black ure at all among the circumstances that actually
bring it about that those conditions prevail. brought it about that he did what he did, so that
The structure of the example is flexible enough, his action is to be accounted for on another basis
I think, to find a way around any charge of irrel- entirely. Even though the person was unable to
evance by accommodating the doctrine on do otherwise, that is to say, it may not be the
which the charge is based.4 case that he acted as he did because he could
Now suppose that Black never has to show not have done otherwise. Now if someone had
his hand because Jones4, for reasons of his own, no alternative to performing a certain action but
decides to perform and does perform the very did not perform it because he was unable to do
action Black wants him to perform. In that otherwise, then he would have performed ex-
case, it seems clear, Jones4 will bear precisely actly the same action even if he could have
the same moral responsibility for what he does done otherwise. The circumstances that made it
as he would have borne if Black had not been impossible for him to do otherwise could have
ready to take steps to ensure that he do it. It been subtracted from the situation without af-
would be quite unreasonable to excuse Jones4 fecting what happened or why it happened in
for his action, or to withhold the praise to which any way. Whatever it was that actually led the
it would normally entitle him, on the basis of the person to do what he did, or that made him do
fact that he could not have done otherwise. This it, would have led him to do it or made him do it
fact played no role at all in leading him to act as even if it had been possible for him to do some-
he did. He would have acted the same even if it thing else instead.
HARRY FRANKFURT • 4.2 Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility 533

Thus it would have made no difference, so far so as to assert that a person is not morally re-
as concerns his action or how he came to perform sponsible for what he has done if he did it be-
it, if the circumstances that made it impossible for cause he could not have done otherwise. It may
him to avoid performing it had not prevailed. The be noted that this revision of the principle does
fact that he could not have done otherwise clearly not seriously affect the arguments of those who
provides no basis for supposing that he might have relied on the original principle in their ef-
have done otherwise if he had been able to do forts to maintain that moral responsibility and
so. When a fact is in this way irrelevant to the determinism are incompatible. For if it was caus-
problem of accounting for a person’s action it ally determined that a person perform a certain
seems quite gratuitous to assign it any weight in action, then it will be true that the person per-
the assessment of his moral responsibility. Why formed it because of those causal determinants.
should the fact be considered in reaching a moral And if the fact that it was causally determined
judgment concerning the person when it does that a person perform a certain action means
not help in any way to understand either what that the person could not have done otherwise,
made him act as he did or what, in other circum- as philosophers who argue for the incompatibil-
stances, he might have done? ity thesis characteristically suppose, then the fact
This, then, is why the principle of alternate that it was causally determined that a person per-
possibilities is mistaken. It asserts that a person form a certain action will mean that the person
bears no moral responsibility—that is, he is to be performed it because he could not have done
excused—for having performed an action if there otherwise. The revised principle of alternate pos-
were circumstances that made it impossible for sibilities will entail, on this assumption concern-
him to avoid performing it. But there may be cir- ing the meaning of ‘could have done otherwise,’
cumstances that make it impossible for a person to that a person is not morally responsible for what
avoid performing some action without those cir- he has done if it was causally determined that he
cumstances in any way bringing it about that he do it. I do not believe, however, that this revi-
performs that action. It would surely be no good sion of the principle is acceptable.
for the person to refer to circumstances of this sort Suppose a person tells us that he did what he
in an effort to absolve himself of moral responsi- did because he was unable to do otherwise; or
bility for performing the action in question. For suppose he makes the similar statement that he
those circumstances, by hypothesis, actually had did what he did because he had to do it. We do
nothing to do with his having done what he did. often accept statements like these (if we believe
He would have done precisely the same thing, and them) as valid excuses, and such statements may
he would have been led or made in precisely the well seem at first glance to invoke the revised
same way to do it, even if they had not prevailed. principle of alternate possibilities. But I think
We often do, to be sure, excuse people for that when we accept such statements as valid
what they have done when they tell us (and we excuses it is because we assume that we are being
believe them) that they could not have done told more than the statements strictly and liter-
otherwise. But this is because we assume that ally convey. We understand the person who of-
what they tell us serves to explain why they did fers the excuse to mean that he did what he did
what they did. We take it for granted that they only because he was unable to do otherwise, or
are not being disingenuous, as a person would only because he had to do it. And we understand
be who cited as an excuse the fact that he could him to mean, more particularly, that when he
not have avoided doing what he did but who did what he did it was not because that was
knew full well that it was not at all because of what he really wanted to do. The principle of
this that he did it. alternate possibilities should thus be replaced,
What I have said may suggest that the prin- in my opinion, by the following principle: a per-
ciple of alternate possibilities should be revised son is not morally responsible for what he has
534 PART V • Determinism, Free Will, and Responsibility

done if he did it only because he could not have given several years ago, had formulated an exam-
done otherwise. This principle does not appear ple of the same general type and had proposed it
to conflict with the view that moral responsibility as a counterexample to the principle of alternate
is compatible with determinism. possibilities.
3. The assumption that Black can predict what
The following may all be true: there were
Jones4 will decide to do does not beg the ques-
circumstances that made it impossible for a per-
tion of determinism. We can imagine that Jones4
son to avoid doing something; these circum- has often confronted the alternatives—A and B—
stances actually played a role in bringing it that he now confronts, and that his face has in-
about that he did it, so that it is correct to say variably twitched when he was about to decide to
that he did it because he could not have done do A and never when he was about to decide to
otherwise; the person really wanted to do what do B. Knowing this, and observing the twitch,
he did; he did it because it was what he really Black would have a basis for prediction. This
wanted to do, so that it is not correct to say does, to be sure, suppose that there is some sort
that he did what he did only because he could of causal relation between Jones4’s state at the
not have done otherwise. Under these condi- time of the twitch and his subsequent states.
But any plausible view of decision or of action
tions, the person may well be morally responsible
will allow that reaching a decision and perform-
for what he has done. On the other hand, he will
ing an action both involve earlier and later
not be morally responsible for what he has done phases, with causal relations between them, and
if he did it only because he could not have done such that the earlier phases are not themselves
otherwise, even if what he did was something he part of the decision or of the action. The example
really wanted to do. does not require that these earlier phases be
deterministically related to still earlier events.
NOTES 4. The example is also flexible enough to allow for
1. The two main concepts employed in the principle the elimination of Black altogether. Anyone who
of alternate possibilities are “morally responsible” thinks that the effectiveness of the example is un-
and “could have done otherwise.” To discuss the dermined by its reliance on a human manipulator,
principle without analyzing either of these con- who imposes his will on Jones4, can substitute for
cepts may well seem like an attempt at piracy. Black a machine programmed to do what Black
The reader should take notice that my Jolly Ro- does. If this is still not good enough, forget both
ger is now unfurled. Black and the machine and suppose that their
2. After thinking up the example that I am about to role is played by natural forces involving no will
develop I learned that Robert Nozick, in lectures or design at all.

You might also like