Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 255

Contexts and Constructions

Constructional Approaches to Language


The series brings together research conducted within different constructional models and
makes them available to scholars and students working in this and other related fields.
The topics range from descriptions of grammatical phenomena in different languages
to theoretical issues concerning language acquisition, language change, and language use.
The foundation of constructional research is provided by the model known as Construction
Grammar (including Frame Semantics). The book series publishes studies in which this model
is developed in new directions and extended through alternative approaches. Such approaches
include cognitive linguistics, conceptual semantics, interaction and discourse, as well as
typologically motivated alternatives, with implications both for constructional theories and for
their applications in related fields such as communication studies, computational linguistics,
AI, neurology, psychology, sociology, and anthropology.
This peer reviewed series is committed to innovative research and will include
monographs, thematic collections of articles, and introductory textbooks.

Editors
Mirjam Fried Jan-Ola Östman
Institute for the Czech Language Department of Scandinavian Languages &
Czech Academy of Sciences Literature, University of Helsinki
Prague, Czech Republic Helsinki, Finland

Advisory Board
Peter Auer Seizi Iwata
University of Freiburg, Germany Osaka City University, Japan

Hans C. Boas Paul Kay


University of Texas at Austin, USA University of California, Berkeley, USA

William Croft Knud Lambrecht


University of New Mexico, USA University of Texas at Austin, USA

Charles J. Fillmore Michael Tomasello


Int. Computer Science Institute, Berkeley, Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology,
USA Germany

Adele E. Goldberg Arnold M. Zwicky


Princeton University, USA Stanford University, USA

Volume 9
Contexts and Constructions
Edited by Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald
Contexts and Constructions

Edited by

Alexander Bergs
Universität Osnabrück

Gabriele Diewald
Leibniz Universität Hannover

John Benjamins Publishing Company


Amsterdam / Philadelphia
TM
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of
8

American National Standard for Information Sciences – Permanence of


Paper for Printed Library Materials, ansi z39.48-1984.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Contexts and Constructions / edited by Alexander Bergs, Gabriele Diewald.


p. cm. (Constructional Approaches to Language, issn 1573-594X ; v. 9)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Pragmatics. 2. Grammar, Comparative and general--Syntax. I. Bergs, Alexander. II.
Diewald, Gabriele.
P99.4.P72C64   2009
306.44--dc22 2009033621
isbn 978 90 272 0431 8 (Hb ; alk. paper)
isbn 978 90 272 8878 3 (Eb)

© 2009 – John Benjamins B.V.


No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or any
other means, without written permission from the publisher.
John Benjamins Publishing Co. · P.O. Box 36224 · 1020 me Amsterdam · The Netherlands
John Benjamins North America · P.O. Box 27519 · Philadelphia pa 19118-0519 · usa
Table of contents

Contexts and constructions 1


Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

part 1. Context in construction grammar

On de-limiting context 17
Marina Terkourafi

Constructions and context: When a construction constructs the context 43


Henri-José Deulofeu & Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

Representing contextual factors in language change: Between frames


and constructions 63
Mirjam Fried

part 2. Interactional approaches

Grammatical constructions in dialogue 97


Per Linell

Interactional construction grammar: Contextual features of determination


in dialectal Swedish 111
Camilla Wide

part 3. Context and grammar

Contextual cues for particle placement: Multiplicity, motivation, modeling 145


Bert Cappelle

Conditionals and mental space set-up: Evidence from German word order 193
Ilona Vandergriff

Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar: The case of modal verbs 213
Ronny Boogaart

Index of Constructions 243

Subject index 245


Contexts and constructions

Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald


Universität Osnabrück, Universität Hannover

1. Introduction

The notion of “context” in grammar and discourse seems to be one of the most
important, most mentioned, and yet most poorly understood topics in linguistics.
Whenever we speak, our utterances are always situated in both a language-exter-
nal context and a language-internal co-text. Both context and co-text (which are
usually subsumed under one single label, i.e. ‘context’) may have some systematic
impact on the form and function of our utterances, not only just in terms of style,
but also with regard to systematic grammatical variability. One particularly inter-
esting notion in the investigation of co- and contextual factors is that of construc-
tions, both in a mostly pre-theoretical sense and in the technical framework of
Construction Grammar (CxG) ‘proper’. Here, the complex notion of ‘context’ has
surfaced repeatedly and scholars from a wide range of backgrounds have high-
lighted both the general importance of the concept and the regrettable neglect of
it in mainstream linguistics, i.e. in most linguistic theorizing outside of pragmatics
and discourse studies (cf. Diewald 2006; Heine 2002). Recently, studies on lan-
guage change in general and on grammaticalization in particular, which for long
have been struggling to come to grips with the impact of contextual factors in
linguistic change, have encompassed the constructional notions and combined
them with other existing concepts of contexts as “loci for change” (cf. Bergs &
Diewald, eds., 2008). This volume offers one of the first concerted attempts at in-
vestigating the role of context from a constructional point of view, with a focus on,
but no limitation to, Construction Grammar as one theoretical framework.

2. Construction grammar

Construction Grammar is a relatively recent and increasingly popular approach in


linguistic theory which postulates that language and knowledge of language con-
sist of conventionalized symbolic form-meaning pairings (“constructions”) at all
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

Syntactic properties
Construction
Morphological properties

Phonological properties Form

symbolic correspondence (link)

Semantic properties

Pragmatic properties (conventional) meaning


Discourse-functional properties

Figure 1. The symbolic structure of constructions (Croft & Cruse 2004: 258)

levels of linguistic structure: lexicon, morphology, syntax, possibly even phonol-


ogy, and discourse/text. Figure 1 illustrates one possible schematic representation
for a construction.
Constructions are often required to have some non-compositional aspect in
their meaning/function, although ‘sufficient frequency’ has recently also been ac-
knowledged as a criterion for construction status (Goldberg & Jackendoff
2004: 533, n.1; Goldberg 2006: 5). Constructions do not exist in isolation, but form
a structured inventory, e.g. through so-called inheritance relations and family re-
semblances (cf. Fried & Östman 2004). Another important, but mostly under-re-
searched tenet of construction grammar is that constructions incorporate seman-
tics, pragmatics, and discourse properties on their function, i.e. meaning side: “by
construction I intend a conventional association of any or all of the following kinds
of grammatical information: syntactic, semantic – including ‘pragmatic’, lexical
and phonological” (Kay 2002: 1). Goldberg is even more explicit on this point:
“Another notion rejected by Construction Grammar is that of a strict division be-
tween semantics and pragmatics. Information about focused constituents, topical-
ity, and register is presented in constructions alongside semantic information”.
(Goldberg 1995: 7). So far, many studies in construction grammar have focused on
(verb) semantic aspects. Although there are studies on constructions and speech
acts, i.e. illocutions (Lakoff 1987), on metalinguistic commentary (Kay 2004), on
speaker attitude (Lambrecht 1990; Kay and Fillmore 1999; Kay 2004: 16–19), and
on information structuring (Goldberg 1995; Michaelis and Lambrecht 1996;
Lambrecht & Lemoine 2005), most have treated pragmatics and discourse more or
less in passing, so that there is still no systematic survey of this domain (cf. Kay
2005). The present volume tries to fill this gap. The notion of context is located in
Contexts and constructions 

the overlapping area between pragmatics and discourse. The papers presented
here explore the possibilities and risks of integrating context into particular con-
structions and construction grammar in general. Topics range from particular
language and construction (grammar) specific problems to general technical anal-
yses and proposals, from the analysis of spoken language to diachronic aspects,
from questions of polysemy and semantic-pragmatic issues to syntactic and typo-
logical questions like sentence subordination and particle placement. The lan-
guages treated in the papers of this volume are Dutch, English, French, German,
Greek, Old Czech and Swedish. Most contributions make use of empirical corpus
data from genres as different as spoken every-day language and diachronic texts.

3. Co-text and context

Catford (1965: 31) introduced the distinction between context and co-text. Co-text
refers to language internal factors, such as the syntactic or textual environment of
a given element, context ‘proper’ refers to language external factors, such as time,
place, interlocutors and manner. While this distinction will be upheld in the fol-
lowing for sake of clarity of exposition, note that the difference is not undisputed.
Terkourafi (this volume) convincingly shows that there is strong interdependence
between the two, even to such an extent that co-text and context are in effect one
and the same. Co-textual factors play an important role from a constructional
point of view, but also in traditional approaches to grammar. The influence of
co-textual factors can be very obvious, for example in the well-established syntac-
tic principles of government and concord, which are direct outcomes of syntag-
matic, and hence, co-textual factors. In many languages verbs usually inherently
determine the number and the type of their complements. Similarly, subjects and
verbs usually agree in features such as person and number. These are some obvious
symptoms of co-textual effects, of how some linguistic element determines the
type and shape of another one in a given sentence.
Other co-textual influences can also be found. Studies in collocations and col-
lostructions (e.g. Stefanowitsch & Gries 2003, Hilpert 2008) have shown that cer-
tain elements and constructions exert more or less strong influence on the linguis-
tic company they keep. One of the most simple cases is the well-known
collostructional pattern of beautiful woman versus handsome man. Less well-known
perhaps is the case of the complex construction “N waiting to happen” as in (1):
(1) In short, she is a disaster waiting to happen when her father re-enters her life,
(1997–3–10, Time Corpus)
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

Stefanowitsch & Gries (2003) clearly show that there is a strong preference for ac-
cident to be used as head noun in the construction, followed by disaster. They even
go so far as to suggest that this clear correlation warrants a separate entry for ac-
cident waiting to happen in the dictionary. Note, however, that despite this strong
correlation, the partially filled complex concrete construction “N waiting to hap-
pen” itself does not carry any negative connotation and can also be used with pos-
itive head nouns and in utterances conveying neutral or even positive news. The
negative connotation is only added through co-textual occurrence of certain
nouns such as disaster or accident. Apart from traditional syntactic and more re-
cently collostructional factors, a third type of co-textual influence can be found. In
some other cases, co-textual influence can make itself felt even across clause and
sentence boundaries. In his discussion of the simple present in contemporary
English as a marker of futurity, Wekker (1976) mentions that
[t]he general principle that seems to hold here is that the simple present can be
used only if the temporal specifier is sufficiently near and explicit, so that it can
serve as a point of orientation. If there is a danger of ambiguity in using the simple
present for the future, the speaker will either have to repeat the temporal specifier,
or, as we saw in the longer passages, reintroduce will as a marker of futurity.
 (Wekker 1976: 81)

However, he also finds occurrences such as (2), in which the temporal specifier
next April is quite removed from the simple present form in question.
(2) Next April, for instance, you’ll see him […] in a six-part BBC serial ver-
sion of George Eliot’s ‘Daniel Deronda’. He plays the icecold aristocrat
Henry Grandcourt. (Wekker 1976: 81)
Even though the two elements are not grammatically related in any way – in fact,
they are not in the same clause, not even in the same sentence – the occurrence of
next April warrants the use of the simple present form he plays to refer to a future
event. Interestingly, will play would also be possible here, but was not used. Here in
this case we see co-textual influence at some distance, on a level that is actually
textual, beyond the single sentence (see Bergs, in prep.). Quite similarly, Linell
(this volume) discusses the form and function of constructions in dialogues and
shows how constructions are actually built to fit into particular slots in a given con-
versation. This, again, is a clear case of an interdependence of co-text and grammar,
which is rarely ever recognized by traditional grammatical models. Thus, bridges
and interesting connections become visible between construction grammar as one
grammatical model and domains from ‘applied linguistics’, such as discourse and
conversation analysis. Wide (this volume) discusses some concrete ways in which
Contexts and constructions 

the connection between conversation analysis and construction grammar can be


developed productively (cf. also the papers in Günthner and Imo 2006).
Contextual, i.e. extralinguistic factors in language use, are usually easy to see
but very hard to document. This means that their concrete influence is usually
very hard to pinpoint and to describe. Contextual factors include time and place
of the utterance, interlocutors, including their socio-cultural background, and
their world knowledge, among others. Hymes (1974: 53–62), for example, lists six-
teen factors which are involved in his s-p-e-a-k-i-n-g model: message form; mes-
sage content; setting; scene; speaker/sender; addressor; hearer/receiver/audience;
addressee; purposes (outcomes); purposes (goals); key; channels; forms of speech;
norms of interaction; norms of interpretation; and genres. This is not the place to
discuss the influence of each of these components. Suffice it to say that a fairly
large number of extra-linguistic, or at least semi-extra-linguistic factors, can be
identified which may be immensely important for successful (‘correct’) communi-
cation, though not necessarily for ‘grammaticality’ in the strict, traditional sense.
Fried (this volume) for example, discusses the role of communicative context in
relation to complementation patterns. Linell (this volume) focuses on the role and
function of discourse, i.e. multilogueal context. Deulofeu and Debaisieux (this
volume) argue that context – i.e. common ground – itself has to be treated as part
of the semantics of a construction.

4. Describing and analyzing co- and context in constructions

One of the most difficult problems in discussing context is the very “slippery”,
“volatile” nature of the object itself. Neither co- nor context, and their correspond-
ing effects, easily lend themselves to principled descriptions and analyses, as, for
example, attribute-value matrices (see Wide, this volume). This may be partly due
to the fact that traditionally contextual factors – often being deemed as random
and chaotic – have been largely ignored. The reason for their apparent random-
ness, however, appears to be something fundamentally ontological in this case.
Co- and context can be static and more or less permanent on the one hand, or
dynamic, flexible and rather volatile on the other. This partly resembles what has
been described as shared knowledge in functional approaches to grammar and
information structuring. Participants have some permanent knowledge base plus
some dynamic, active knowledge which is constantly updated and thus ever-
changing. Similarly, co- and contexts have both a permanent component and some
‘online’ part which is updated as we speak (see Linell and Terkourafi, this volume).
The latter is, of course, very hard to capture empirically. Describing context in the
narrow sense is also not without problems. Where, for example, should the line be
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

drawn? Traditional syntactic theories recognize certain strong contextual effects


within the sentence. But some cotextual effects in grammatical structure certainly
reach beyond the sentence. Approaches within the construction grammar frame-
work are currently trying to develop ways and means of capturing all these facts
and ideas. One of the most prominent is probably the notion of frames and frame
semantics (cf. Fried, this volume).
Frame semantics essentially links traditional semantic knowledge with ency-
clopaedic world knowledge. A given word (e.g. flu) activates one or more frames in
which it occurs and which provide encyclopaedic world knowledge associated
with that particular word (e.g. doctor, sneeze, fever, chicken soup and many more).
It is usually claimed that frames, which are based on recurring experiences, should
be regarded as gestalt based, i.e. in order to actually understand a given concept,
one needs to know essentially all concepts associated with that particular frame.
The result is a coherent network of concepts and frames which in turn forms our
world knowledge as such. It is not without good reason that frame semantics has
been called a ‘sister theory’ to construction grammar (Fried & Östman 2004: 5).
Both theories investigate meaning and cognition on the basis of empirical studies
of language use and see language rather as a network of concepts and constructions
than as organized on an item-plus-rule basis. Therefore, there have been growing
attempts to integrate frame semantics into construction grammar, and vice versa.

5. This volume

This volume presents eight original research papers which all deal with the ques-
tion of context and constructions. While some of them are explicitly couched in
construction grammar as such, others deal with the notion of grammatical con-
structions from a more pre-theoretical perspective. For coherence reasons, the
papers were organized in three different sections:
i. Context in construction grammar
ii. Interactional approaches
iii. Context and grammar
i. Context in construction grammar
Marina Terkourafi presents work “On De-Limiting Context”. She points out that
psycholinguistic findings have shown that pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s
utterance are in fact realized quite early on in utterance production and are not nec-
essarily the endpoint of any given process of speech production. Linguistic as well as
extralinguistic contexts seemingly play a crucial rule in this process. Linguistic con-
text in this case is treated in the same way as extra-linguistic contexts, since linguistic
Contexts and constructions 

context already ‘contains’, in a way, extra-linguistic context. In other words, Terkourafi


argues that there is no fundamental, systemic difference between the two.
This paper examines the extent to which results from the resolution of lexical
and syntactic ambiguities, reference assignment, and the processing of semantic
versus pragmatic anomaly, naturally extend to illocutionary force assignment, the
meaning component pertaining to understanding the pragmatic consequences of
the speaker’s utterance par excellence. It is proposed that illocutionary force is pro-
jected probabilistically from a limited set of contextual parameters pertaining to
who is talking to whom, when, and where. Subsequent linguistic and contextual
information serves to check this probabilistic prediction, either confirming it
(illocutionary assignment passing unnoticed), or revising it in the light of incom-
ing data. On the basis of detailed and comprehensive empirical data from spoken
dialogical Cypriot Greek, Terkourafi shows that different minimal contexts corre-
late positively with different linguistic constructions. This means that a limited set
of contextual parameters jointly considered can provide a pointer to the preferred
linguistic construction realizing a particular speech act, rendering reference to the
fully specified, nonce context of occurrence superfluous (at least at an initial stage).
The steady growth of interpretation suggests that interpretation begins as soon as
a speaker engages in speaking, and proceeds in parallel with the speaker’s utter-
ance, drawing on contextual information as and when this becomes available.
Contextual parameters that can be fixed early on during an exchange prime the
conventionally expected illocutionary force, thereby speeding up interpretation.
Through acculturation, these contextual parameters gain in salience: interlocutors
seek to settle these (if only by presumption) in order just to initiate interaction.
The contextual parameters jointly constituting a minimal context are motivated by
Gibsonian affordances applied to physical settings. In this way, a potentially un-
limited body of sociocultural knowledge is shaped into a limited set of contextual
parameters available for propositional manipulation. The resulting minimal con-
texts are neither impoverished with respect to the original input, nor reducible to
it. Furthermore, the contextual parameters jointly constituting a minimal context
cannot be broken down further into more abstract ones, such as relative status or
power, or social distance, but are rather mentally manipulated as primes.
The second paper in this section is by Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie
Debaisieux who investigate “Constructions and Context: When a construction
constructs the context” with the aim to explore the interrelations of a particular
syntactic pattern (various uses of parce que clauses in spoken French) with its com-
municative context. Taking Fillmore, Kay & O’Connor’s famous let alone study as
their starting point, they claim that there are constructions – not unlike let
alone – which bring in contextual background information to maximize the
“relevance” of the utterance they are added to by introducing contextually present
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

background information which the speaker assumes the addressee needs to know
in order to make most sense of the message. The underlying assumption is that
some pieces of utterances may not only be text, or parts of text, but actually more
like contextual background. The authors compare the status of these pieces to that
of footnotes in written language, i.e. they are, strictly speaking, marginal to the text
and nearer to context status than to plain text status. Their function is to shape the
relevant part of the context in a verbal construction. These subconstructions in-
serted in utterances have a special status that must be accounted for in linguistic
theory and in construction grammar. Their special status can be revealed in that
they show idiosyncratic formal as well as pragmatic properties. The exemplary
case study is on constructions which are introduced by subordinators and which
are thus formally similar to prototypical subordinated clauses. One of these can be
parce que. The authors show that some uses of parce que are quite specific. It has
neither the properties of subordinating parce que (focus of questions, of cleft sen-
tences, etc.), nor even of the parce que / cos’ introducing supplementive clauses.
The authors argue that this use of parce que forms a special construction which
they call the Context Focussing Parce que Construction (CFPC). This construction
inherits its formal properties both from “supplementive” constructions (resistance
against all prototypical adjuncts diagnostic tests) and from a general Parenthetical
Construction, the function of which is to insert extra material in a clause, as a side
remark. The function of this construction is to focus not on the truth conditions of
the main construction but on the “relevance” of this construction and to convey a
procedural meaning like: “take in consideration this specific piece of contextual
information to process the current utterance meaning and to achieve giving rele-
vance to it”. It is claimed that CFPCs are constructions in the true sense of the word
as they are specific combinations of form and meaning, whereby the meaning ex-
pressed by them transcends regular propositional meaning (or modification of
that meaning) as it belongs to the domain of information processing and the struc-
turing of common ground. The authors suggest extending the notion of linguistic
construction to encompass paralinguistic signs made use of in human communi-
cation, like gestures and other non-verbal communicative behavior.
Mirjam Fried is concerned with the specific question of frames and construc-
tions in her contribution with the title “Representing Contextual Factors in Lan-
guage Change”. In this corpus-based case study she explores the question of how
context enters conventional linguistic patterning and becomes part of the codified
relationship between meaning and form in a given expression. In particular, she
looks at the question of in which ways the complex interaction between traditional
semantic structure, thematic and cultural context, and systematic morphosyntactic
patterns can be captured and discussed within construction grammar. Her case
study deals with the semantic and morphosyntactic history of the Old Czech
Contexts and constructions 

(OCz) participial adjective (PA) věřící ‘(one) believing’, in relation to the verb věřiti
‘to believe’, which, because of its flexible nature, can be located somewhere be-
tween inflection and derivation. The OCz verb věřiti developed four senses
(roughly, belief, faith, credit, trust), each associated with a distinct comple-
mentation pattern and reflecting particular communicative context (e.g., Chris-
tian religion, commercial transactions, transfer of responsibility). Using an exten-
sive corpus from OCz texts containing a wide variety of genres, Fried show that
while the PA originates within the same semantic structure as part of the verbal
inflectional paradigm, its functional and semantic range became fixed differently
across the verb senses and different lexico-pragmatic properties correlate not only
with distinct thematic contexts but also with different syntactic preferences, all of
which contributes to fixing the functional status of the PA as a (quasi-actor) noun:
‘a Christian’; ‘a creditor’.
The development occurs along several dimensions: conceptual shifts vis-à-vis
textual distribution and contextual restrictions; the role of collocational patterns;
recurring syntactic patterning; chronological layering. The result is a complex pic-
ture of semantic, pragmatic, and grammatical factors that collectively motivate the
changes in the form’s usage and that must be part of any representation that aspires
to be descriptively accurate and to have an explanatory value. In that respect, the
present study makes a case for Frame Semantics (e.g. Fillmore 1982) and Con-
struction Grammar (Fillmore 1989; Fried & Östman 2004) as a particularly suit-
able model for representing lexico-grammatical networks in which the relative
stability of grammatical form does not conflict with the relative flexibility of mean-
ing or expressive richness, and vice versa. The paper thus establishes (i) the inter-
dependence of lexical meaning, the context in which the word is used, its illocu-
tionary force, and the morphosyntactic form that encodes these relationships; (ii)
how these factors figure in categorial shifts known as ‘transpositional morphology’,
and (iii) how the relevant generalizations about context in grammar can (or can-
not) be formally represented in terms of complex grammatical signs, through
frames and constructions.
ii. Interactional approaches
In the first paper of this section, Per Linell investigates “Constructions in Dia-
logue”. With reference to the notion of ‘constructional schema’, his contribution is
based on a distinctly ‘dialogical’, i.e. interactional and contextual, approach to lan-
guage in general and to grammatical constructions in particular. Some grammati-
cal constructions, e.g. cleft constructions and the so-called x-and-x construction
are analyzed in dialogical terms. The analyses give rise to the argument that the
opportunities for using a particular construction are largely built up dialogically
over sequences. Conversely, constructions often have properties that show how
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

they are built precisely to fit into sequences, with responsive properties (requiring
certain structures in prior co-text) and/or projective properties (setting up condi-
tions on possible next units). This suggests a way of developing the notion of ‘out-
er syntax’ in CxG. Simultaneously, the author also discusses some general ques-
tions of constructions and context, such as whether contexts should be described
in the same kinds of terms as constructions themselves or whether it is at all pos-
sible to formalize relevant contexts exhaustively.
In her contribution, Camilla Wide analyzes “Contextual Features from the
Point of View of CxG and Interaction”. One of her primary concerns in this paper
is how to formalize contextual features in terms of attributes and values. This pa-
per explores how contextual features can be described within the CxG framework
– without compromising the basic assumptions made within CA-inspired interac-
tional linguistics. In his early work on Construction Grammar, Fillmore stressed
the importance of considering communicative purposes and interactional features
when describing grammatical constructions. In recent years some versions of
Construction Grammar have become increasingly more formalistic and abstract;
this means, for Wide, that linguists from an interactional point of view have found
it increasingly difficult to relate to CxG approaches and ideas. In her contribution,
Wide analyzes the demonstrative pronoun den ‘the, that’ in Swedish from both a
Construction Grammar and an interactional point of view. Special attention is
paid to the use of den in Swedish dialects in Eastern Nyland in Finland where the
grammaticalization of den toward a definite article, supplementing the normal -(e)
n/-et definite article suffix, seems to have gone further than in standard varieties of
Swedish. In standard Swedish den is used as a definite article only in noun phrases
including modifiers, cf. bil-en ‘the car’ versus den röda bil-en ‘the red car-the’. Thus
the Eastern Nyland use of den in noun phrases without modifiers, as in den biln,
has traditionally been analyzed as a case of double definiteness. However, the use
of den in Eastern Nyland is closely connected to assumptions about common
ground of a certain kind. Since den is a deictic pronoun, contextual information
plays a crucial role in the use, interpretation and description of structures that
include den. When analyzed more closely, the Eastern Nyland structures with den
seem to be licensed by a construction which draws primarily on contextual infor-
mation. In order to formalize this construction, tools for describing various as-
pects of contextual information are needed. The paper suggests a solution in which
these tools are developed in terms of meaning potentials, in this case the potential
of den as a (discourse) focus marker and rhetorical device.
iii. Context and grammar
Bert Cappelle takes a fresh look at “Contextual Cues for Particle Placement” in his
contribution. This paper discusses some contextual factors that influence
Contexts and constructions 

constituent ordering in the English transitive verb-particle construction. Cappelle


not only recognizes and discusses traditional factors that seem to influence parti-
cle placement, such as discourse old versus discourse new information, he also
introduces a number of new contextual factors. One such factor is focality, i.e.
particular scenarios which put focus on one or more elements in the clause. Other
factors include syntactic priming, accessibility, and encyclopaedic world knowl-
edge. This paper thus adduces evidence that the choice of one word-order pattern
over another is prompted by more than just the assessment of the relative dis-
course-newness of the words (or their referents) involved. At least in the case of
particle placement, the selection of a particular ordering is cued by contextual
kinds of information that go far beyond what could be retrieved by an automatic
processor and that can only be gathered via a full linguistic and extra-linguistic
understanding of the situation referred to.
Ilona Vandergriff’s contribution focuses on “Conditionals and mental space
setup”. She analyzes the syntactic relation between the clauses and its role in con-
structing meaning. German syntax, unlike English, does not offer a marker in the
main clause which signals the dependency between clauses. Some spoken German
‘if ’-clauses, by contrast, are not syntactically integrated. Instead, the main clause
will have the verb position of an independent main clause. Suggesting an iconic
relationship between syntactic and conceptual dependency, content conditionals
with their real-world relationship between the clauses are generally described with
integrative word order, whereas speech-act conditionals are taken to signal their
looser conceptual dependency via non-integrative word order. These correlations
are relevant to research on conditionality beyond German because the different
orderings appear to provide a formal marker of the different cognitive domains in
which conditionals are interpreted. This paper considers clause integration as a
formal aspect of conditional sentences in German within the framework of Con-
struction Grammar. From this perspective, conditional sentences are examples of
a construction. Constructions may have predictable meanings, which are mapped
onto the formal and semantic parameters or their combinations. In order to see
when the variant orderings do and do not occur in speech act conditionality, this
paper analyzes authentic discourse data from the perspective of Mental Spaces
theory and proposes an account of the syntactic variation in speech-act condition-
als that is consistent with previous analyses of similar complex clause phenomena.
The findings show that clause integration has a predictable meaning but what is
being marked is not the cognitive domain in which the conditional is interpreted
but rather the mental space.
Ronny Boogart concludes the third section with his investigation of “Seman-
tics and Pragmatics in Construction Grammar”. He presents a case study on mo-
dal verbs in which he shows that the age-old debate concerning monosemous ver-
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

sus polysemous readings is marred with a number of theoretical problems and


obstacles which can be overcome within a construction grammar approach. With
the Dutch modal kunnen (‘can’), for example, it can be shown that in a network of
constructions, the property of complete inheritance takes care of the monosemy of
the construction. In other words, this reading forms the central, parental kunnen
construction which gives its basic meaning to all its linked subconstructions. At
the same time, certain other conventionalized uses, such as indirect speech acts,
form separate constructions in the network. The number of new constructions in
the network is restricted by the definition of constructions as such: conventional-
ized pairings of meaning and form. In other words, a supposedly new construc-
tion not only needs to show a new meaning, but also some new formal aspects. In
some cases, Boogart argues, these formal differences can only be found in the sur-
rounding discourse. For him, however, this also raises the important question of
where to stop with the inclusion of contextual information.

6. Outlook

This volume is one of the first to systematically investigate the interaction of co-
text, context and grammar. In particular, the contributions are concerned with the
notions of co- and context in general and especially in interaction, and how the
two can be integrated in the analysis of grammatical constructions and in con-
struction grammar. Needless to say, there are still a number of unresolved prob-
lems and open questions. While the contributions in this volume present excellent
case studies and many interesting points for departure for future analysis, three
important aspects will have to be discussed in the future. First, we need to look
some more into questions of formalizing co- and context in grammatical analyses.
The studies presented here point towards frame semantics as one possibility in this
regard. Second, we need to find better, i.e. clear and convincing dividing lines be-
tween ad hoc pragmatics and general common sense reasoning, both of which are
part of everyday interaction and crucial for successful communication, and se-
mantico-pragmatic factors, including co- and context as an important part of the
grammatical system, perhaps as conventionalized parts of grammatical construc-
tions. Third, there is a need for a model which, in a systematic way, describes the
processes and motives for the transition between cotext(s) and context(s) on the
one hand, and idiosyncratic, individual interpretive activity versus stereotypical,
i.e. conventionalized pragmatic factors on the other hand.
Contexts and constructions 

References

Bergs, Alexander. In prep. Expressions of futurity in contemporary English: A Construction


Grammar perspective.
Bergs, Alexander & Gabriele Diewald (Eds.). 2008. Constructions and language change. Berlin &
New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Catford, J. C. 1965. A linguistic theory of translation. London: Oxford University Press.
Croft, William. 2001. Radical Construction Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Croft, William & D. Alan Cruse. 2004. Cognitive Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Diewald, Gabriele. 2006. Context types in grammaticalization as constructions. In: D. Schönefeld
(Ed.), Constructions all over – case studies and theoretical implications. [Special Volume 1 of
Constructions]. Online publication at http://www.constructions-online.de/articles/specvol1/.
Fillmore, Charles. 1982. Frame Semantics. In: The Linguistic Society of Korea (Ed.), Linguistics
in the Morning Calm. (111–137). Seoul: Hanshin.
Fillmore, Charles. 1989. Grammatical Construction Theory and the familiar dichotomies. In: R.
Dietrich, & C.F. Graumann (Eds). Language processing in social context. (17–38). Amster-
dam: North Holland/Elsevier.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman. 2004. Construction Grammar: A thumbnail sketch. In: M.
Fried & J.-O. Östman (Eds), Construction Grammar in a cross-language perspective (11–86).
Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Goldberg, Adele. 1995. Constructions. A Construction Grammar approach to argument structure.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Goldberg, Adele. 2006. Constructions at work. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goldberg, Adele & Ray Jackendoff. 2004. The English resultative as a family of constructions.
Language 8(3): 532–567.
Günthner, Susanne & Wolfgang Imo (Eds). 2006. Konstruktionen in der Interaktion. Berlin &
New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Heine, Bernd. 2002. On the role of context in grammaticalization. In: I. Wischer & G. Diewald
(Eds.), New reflections on grammaticalization (83–101). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John
Benjamins.
Hilpert, Martin. 2008. New evidence against the modularity of grammar: Constructions, collo-
cations, and speech perception. Cognitive Linguistics 19(3): 391–411.
Hymes, Dell. 1974. Foundations in sociolinguistics: An ethnographic approach. Philadelphia: Uni-
versity of Pennsylvania Press.
Kay, Paul. 2002. English subjectless tagged sentences. Language 78(3): 453–481.
Kay, Paul. 2004. Pragmatic aspects of constructions. In: L. Horn & G. Ward, (Eds.), The Hand-
book of Pragmatics (675–700). Oxford: Blackwell.
Kay, Paul. 2005. Argument-structure constructions and the argument-adjunct distinction. In:
M. Fried & H. Boas, (Eds.), Grammatical constructions: Back to the roots (71–98).
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Kay, Paul & Charles Fillmore. 1999. Grammatical constructions and linguistic generalizations:
The What’s X doing Y? construction. Language 75(1): 1–33.
Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire, and dangerous things. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lambrecht, Knud. 1990. ‘What me worry?’ – Mad Magazine sentences revisited. BLS 6: 215–
228.
 Alexander Bergs and Gabriele Diewald

Lambrecht, Knud & L. Michaelis. 1996. Toward a construction-based theory of language func-
tion: The case of nominal extraposition. Language 72(2): 215–247.
Lambrecht, Knud & Kevin Lemoine. 2005. Definite null objects in (spoken) French. A Con-
struction-Grammar account. In: Mirjam Fried & Hans Boas (Eds.), Construction Gram-
mar: Back to the roots (13–55). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Stefanowitsch, Anatol and Stefan Th. Gries. 2003. Collostructions: Investigating the interaction
of words and constructions. International Journal of Corpus Linguistics 8(2): 209–243.
Wekker, Herman Chr. 1976. The expression of future time in contemporary British English.
Amsterdam: North Holland.
part 1

Context in construction grammar


On de-limiting context*

Marina Terkourafi
Assistant Professor, Department of Linguistics,
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

1. The sequentiality of linguistic analysis: A received view

There is a received view within the generative tradition in linguistics that levels of
analysis, starting with phonetics and ending with pragmatics, are sequentially or-
dered.1 Proposed if only as a methodological division — not necessarily a psycho-
logically defensible one — this view would run roughly as follows: phonetics fur-
nishes the input to phonology, phonology to syntax, syntax to semantics, and,
crucially for our purposes, semantics to pragmatics. That is, each of these levels
uses the output of the previous level and furnishes the input to the next. This is the
path followed during utterance interpretation. To reverse path is followed during
utterance production. The first part of this chain, up to and including semantics,
corresponds to the decoding phase and draws on our knowledge of language. The
tail of the chain, the passage from semantics to pragmatics, corresponds to the
inferential phase. During this last phase, we gradually expand the information we
take into account, to include, further to knowledge of language, other aspects of
world knowledge, such as who is talking to whom, at what time and place, within
which social framework, and so on.
The purpose of this process is to discover the speaker’s intended meaning. To do
this, we first need to find out what the sentence means (its truth-conditions),2 and,
based on that, to infer what the speaker meant by using it (presumably, so that we
may react accordingly). Of course, it has been known for some time now that to fix
the truth-conditions of a sentence we may actually have to go beyond semantics,
i.e. beyond knowledge of language, and into pragmatics, i.e. draw on the surrounding
context (see the discussion in Levinson 2000: 165ff. and the references therein). Some
classical cases are lexical or syntactic ambiguity resolution, and fixing the referents of
referring expressions, including indexicals. In all these cases, the truth-conditions of
the sentence cannot be fixed until context has been taken into account.
Context thus understood includes first and foremost the surrounding linguistic
context, i.e. the utterance as part of a larger discourse. Many ambiguities are
 Marina Terkourafi

routinely resolved with reference to linguistic context alone. The juxtaposition of


utterances can help resolve some cases of reference assignment, including anaphora
resolution. Even certain non truth-conditional aspects of meaning, such as illocu-
tionary force, can be determined by looking at the surrounding linguistic context,
as when an utterance is understood as an answer to a question in virtue of being
adjacent to it in the discourse. Yet other aspects of truth-conditional meaning can-
not be determined by looking at linguistic context alone. Determining the referents
of indexicals such as ‘this,’ or ‘that,’ ‘here,’ and ‘now’ requires a reference to the extra-
linguistic context of utterance. Similarly, an utterance such as di chi è il cane? (‘whose
is the dog?’) shouted by an exasperated male voice in Florence during the afternoon
siesta time, treated the referent of il cane as known — though there was no previous
discourse in which it could have been mentioned — in virtue of the perceptual sali-
ence of a barking dog in the surrounding extra-linguistic context.
We are then left with two solutions, as far as the relationship between seman-
tics and pragmatics goes.3 One is to consider that our semantics is underspecified;
that is, semantics narrows down the possibilities of interpretation to a set of alter-
natives, but does not pick one alternative.4 This is done by pragmatics, which is
now the level where truth-conditions are assigned. The second solution is to allow
for semantic and pragmatic processes to be interleaved, i.e. to run in parallel. This
solution essentially amounts to abandoning the strict sequentiality of levels as-
sumed at the outset. The constant to- and fro-ing between semantics and pragmat-
ics is, nevertheless, still regulated by semantics: pragmatic contributions to truth-
conditions are made only as and when triggered by semantics.5 This of course does
not include non truth-conditional aspects of meaning, such as illocutionary force
assignment or other (particularized) implicatures, which by definition require a
reference to the extra-linguistic context of utterance.
In sum, on the received view, language processing proceeds largely independ-
ently of context. Context is brought in during the final inferential phase, or, if need-
ed, a bit earlier, during the last stages of semantic analysis — but not before. Utter-
ances such as “water is H2O” or “carrots are good for health” are assigned
truth-conditions independently of contextual input. Other utterances, for instance
those containing ambiguous or referring expressions and many others too (for a list
of examples, see, e.g. the appendix in Bach 1994), need to refer to the context of ut-
terance, moving from its linguistic to extra-linguistic components, to fix their truth-
conditions. However, to receive a full interpretation, one that encompasses addi-
tional, non truth-conditional aspects of speaker’s meaning such as implicatures or
indirect speech acts, all utterances must refer to context, again starting from lin-
guistic context and only secondarily taking into account extra-linguistic context.
On de-limiting context 

2. An alternative: A constitutive role for context

Now consider an alternative to the received view. Assume that you are attending a
Pragmatics Conference in Northern Italy. You get up in the morning, have a show-
er, and go downstairs to have breakfast. There, you are asked by someone (whom
you take to be another guest, given that they are not wearing the hotel uniform
etc.) Scusi, sa dov’é il caffè? You don’t speak Italian, but you do recognize one word-
form from your interlocutor’s utterance: caffè. So you point them to the coffee pot.
Was that the correct response? It turns out it was.
How did you get there? Combining (at least) five pieces of information: a) a
similarity in phonological form between English /'kofi:/ and Italian /kaf ’fε/; b) a
perceptually given fact about the place of the exchange (the hotel’s breakfast
lounge); c) a perceptually given fact about the time of the exchange (morning); d)
a socio-culturally given piece of information that in the morning people have
breakfast; and e) a socio-culturally given piece of information that people in the
western world today often have coffee at breakfast. Only the first of these, (a),
draws on knowledge of language. The remaining four pieces of information draw
on knowledge of the world, specifically, on perceptually given (b, c) and socio-
cultural aspects (d, e) of the extra-linguistic context of utterance.
Had your interlocutor approached you at a different time and in a different
physical setting, say at the exit to one of the presentation rooms at the start of the
coffee break, this time you would be likely to point them to the area reserved for
coffee breaks. And you would not necessarily have assumed that they wanted to
drink coffee. ‘Coffee’ in this case could have been used loosely to refer to activities
that accompany the drinking of coffee (as when one is invited for “coffee”, but may
well drink tea). Yet on another occasion, if your interlocutor had approached you
in the middle of the street and asked the same question, you may not have under-
stood him or her at all. The linguistic information — the phonological similarity
between English /'kofi:/ and Italian /kaf 'fε/ — would have still been available. But
on its own it would have been hardly sufficient. Lacking a facilitating extra-lin-
guistic context, making any sense of your interlocutor’s question would have
seemed virtually impossible.
One may of course object that making any sense of any utterance in any unfa-
miliar language is pure guesswork, and that the processes involved are qualita-
tively very different from those involved in communicating in a familiar language,
not to mention one’s mother tongue. However this objection turns out to be un-
tenable for at least two reasons. The first has to do with the nature of the informa-
tion combined to respond to the Italian guest’s utterance. Predictably enough, this
includes information about the time and place of the exchange, and relevant piec-
es of sociocultural information activated by the former, perceptually-based data.
 Marina Terkourafi

The sheer fact that it is possible to enumerate in a principled manner the pieces of
information used shows that this process is not as random as it might appear at
first. Rather, what seem to be involved are successively structured layers of world
knowledge, much like, e.g., Schank and Abelson’s (1977) proposed continuum
from general to specific world knowledge.
According to Schank and Abelson, knowledge about the world ranges along a
continuum from general knowledge, that is, “knowledge [which] enables a person
to understand and interpret another person’s actions simply because the other per-
son is a human being with certain standard needs who lives in a world which has
certain standard methods of getting those needs fulfilled,” to specific knowledge,
that is, “knowledge [we use] to interpret and participate in events we have been
through many times” (1977: 37). In the example with the Italian hotel guest, deter-
mining the time of day as morning is achieved with reference to general world
knowledge (including perceptual data). This in turn activates the assumption that
breakfast is an activity that is relevant to the time of day. Other pieces of informa-
tion are a matter of knowledge that is increasingly specific. For instance, determin-
ing the location as a hotel breakfast lounge will depend not only on perceptual data
but also on one’s familiarity with hotels and the layout of rooms and furniture
therein. Relating the unfamiliar signifier /kaf 'fε/ to the familiar signified ‘coffee’
will probably be mediated by socioculturally specific knowledge that in today’s
western societies coffee is a staple part of breakfast (at least for many people). Since
other beverages may have been common in other parts of the world, or during dif-
ferent historical periods, to link the phonological form /kaf 'fε/ to its intended ref-
erent, both this piece of socioculturally specific knowledge, and the more general
information that Italy is a western country must be available to the understander.
In other words, the more similar the speakers’ backgrounds — i.e. the more similar
their knowledge hierarchies passing from general to specific world knowledge —
the more successful they will be at ‘guessing’ each other’s point.
The second reason why making sense of an utterance in an unfamiliar lan-
guage is not qualitatively unrelated to communicating in a familiar language is
that the type of informed ‘guesswork’ combining knowledge from different sourc-
es outlined above seems to be involved also in situations that are considered cen-
tral to linguistic theorizing, starting with language acquisition itself. In a series of
experiments pertaining to children’s early acquisition of verbs, Tomasello (1995)
showed that children rely crucially on what they take to be the adult’s intention in
the situation: “what the adult is doing in a given situation and why she is doing it”
(1995: 117). Children begin to develop social-intersubjective knowledge of this
kind around 9 months (Tomasello 1999: 61–77), so it is available to draw on when
acquiring language later on. A particularly frequent context for early verb acquisi-
tion is that of impending action by the infant: the majority of verb forms issued by
On de-limiting context 

mothers and correctly responded to by children were “anticipations of or requests


for child actions” (1995: 123). In this respect, both mothers and children seem to
be utilizing “attention as intentional perception” (1995: 136), that is, to be relying
on the fact that “organisms attend to things that are relevant to their current inten-
tional states” (ibid.), the former to guide children’s actions, and the latter to carve
out of mothers’ speech the intended referent actions of their verb forms (since,
unlike nouns, these cannot be ostensibly taught).6 Thus,
the bedrock on which the initial stages of language acquisition are built is chil-
dren’s understanding of the intentional actions of other persons, including their
understanding of adults’ social actions, such as making linguistic reference to
their shared world (1995: 140).

Similarly, Eve Clark observes,


by age two, children are already quite skilled at tracking the speaker’s intentions in
a variety of settings. These intentions may be obscured for young children by lan-
guage that is too complex, but in tasks where children are focused on the activity at
hand, they show good understanding of the pragmatic consequences of speaker
repairs [one aspect of speaker meaning: MT] (2004: 572; emphasis added).7

In other words, language acquisition draws more on informed ‘guesswork’ of a


pragmatic nature than on specifically linguistic, semantic decoding to start with
— and may even proceed along the lines of the former in spite of the latter!
All this suggests that, contrary to the received view, rather than constituting the
end-point of utterance interpretation, understanding the pragmatic consequences
of the speaker’s utterance is in fact achieved early on during this process drawing
on all available clues, including context. What is more, understanding these prag-
matic consequences and providing an appropriate response may well be the driving
force behind the acquisition of more abstract linguistic categories altogether. And,
to the extent that linguistic categories are “dynamic, context-sensitive (relational),
and therefore plastic [i.e., malleable; MT]” (Hawkins and Smith 2001: 27–30), their
formation does not stop after the normal period of language acquisition. In fact,
understanding the pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s utterance may well
drive the formation of linguistic categories throughout one’s life.
However, a skeptic may still wonder: can we say that when you responded cor-
rectly to your Italian interlocutor’s question in the breakfast room you knew the
meaning of the sentence uttered? Or that, when a two-year-old hears a familiar
expression among several new ones, and goes on to respond appropriately, he or
she knows the meaning of the sentence uttered? In short, is understanding the prag-
matic consequences of the speaker’s utterance the same thing as understanding the
meaning of their utterance?
 Marina Terkourafi

Practically, the two are indistinguishable. To the extent that knowledge of


meaning is in the head, it cannot be empirically observed. What can be observed
are its pragmatic consequences, and this is how knowledge of meaning is external-
ized. But when knowledge of meaning is externalized in this way, there are only
two possibilities: providing a pragmatically appropriate response, and providing a
pragmatically inappropriate response. These do not suffice to distinguish between
knowing the meaning of the sentence uttered and not knowing it (“what the world
would have to be like for the sentence to be true”), since, as we saw earlier, it is
possible in both cases to provide a pragmatically appropriate response. So, at a
practical level, there is no way to tell the difference between knowing the meaning
of an expression and responding appropriately to it. At this empirically observable
level, the two are equivalent.8
Yet, this could be merely a surface coincidence, obscuring fundamental differ-
ences in substance between the two. The earlier discussion of language acquisition
helps to lay such worries to rest, suggesting that the difference between knowing the
meaning of an expression and responding appropriately to it is more a matter of
degree and less one of substance. If, as Hawkins and Smith aptly put it, “denotative
meaning might lie at the intersection of all these variants on connotative meaning”
(2001: 41), knowing the meaning of an expression and providing a pragmatically
appropriate response cannot be radically different: the ‘generative’ relation between
them guarantees that they are made of the same ‘stuff ’, so to speak. Hence, if one
(providing a pragmatically appropriate response) is imbibed with context — as in
the cases of responding to an utterance in an unfamiliar language and in language
acquisition — so should the other (knowing the meaning of an expression).
Contrary to the received view, then, understanding the pragmatic consequenc-
es of the speaker’s utterance is in fact achieved early on during utterance interpre-
tation. Since understanding the pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s utterance
relies crucially on context, contextual input must be integrated into utterance in-
terpretation from the first. No hard and fast line can be drawn between linguistic
and extra-linguistic context in this respect. Because linguistic context is actually
nothing more than language already interpreted — if you prefer, ‘fixed­’ — with
respect to some extra-linguistic context, linguistic context already ‘contains’ extra-
linguistic context. In general, the more minimal (or, less explicit) the linguistic in-
put, the greater the contextual support needed (Hawkins & Smith 2001: 41). But no
matter how explicit linguistic input is, its interpretation is never context-free. The
received view, then, which treats context as a supportive element to be drawn on
solely as and when needed is a fiction of post facto analysis. For the language user,
who necessarily produces and understands language in specific contexts, language
understanding is a priori situated and inescapably contextualized.9
On de-limiting context 

3. Psycholinguistic insights

In support of the constitutive role of context in linguistic meaning advocated with-


in theoretical frameworks such as Frame Semantics and informally argued for in
the previous section, psycholinguistic studies have revealed the presence of con-
textual input during all stages of decoding, including phonological, syntactic and
semantic analysis. In this section, I review only a small sample of the related lit-
erature to showcase both the methodologies used, and the types of contextual
(perceptual as well as social stereotypical) information that have been shown to
affect linguistic decoding.
Johnson et al. (1999) studied the resolution of phonologically ambiguous pho-
netic stimuli. They found that information about the gender of the speaker affected
the way listeners resolved the ambiguity, revealing different category boundaries
for vowels for male and female speakers. These results persisted whether the infor-
mation about speaker gender was presented visually (a male or female face pic-
tured on screen uttering the ambiguous stimulus), or merely imagined (listeners
imagining a male or female speaker uttering the ambiguous stimulus). Regarding
their use of the term “gender,” Johnson et al. specify that they use this “to refer to
sex-based differences between people that are subjective in that “gender” refers to
a socio-cultural construct based in part on sex” (1999: 365 fn. 3). Moreover, they
draw a distinction between “talker” and “speaker”:
We are using “talker” to refer to the listener’s perceptual impression of a person’s
identity based on hearing or watching the person speak. This contrasts with our
use of “speaker” in a more generic sense which includes objective facts about a
person, such as vocal tract length. … Thus, when we call our theory “talker nor-
malization” as distinct from “speaker normalization” we mean to assert that
speech perception is influenced by socio-culturally based “gender” expectations.
(1999: 365 fn. 3)

Based on these results, Johnson et al. argue that “at least a part of the [vowel cate-
gory] boundary shift associated with “talker normalization” is due to expectations
regarding male and female voices that listeners bring to speech perception, quite
apart from the sensory information presented in the stimuli” (1999: 379). In other
words, it is the abstract social category of gender rather than assumptions about
physical attributes, such as vocal tract length, that drive the resolution of the pho-
nological ambiguity.
Spoken word recognition was also found to be mediated by context, including
both visual context and visually-induced information about social categories.
With respect to visual context, Tanenhaus et al. (1995) found that when temporary
ambiguities regarding word identity arose intra-lexically, as between “candle” and
 Marina Terkourafi

“candy,” subjects waited till the end of the word to identify the intended object
when both objects were available in the visual context. However, when no compet-
ing object was available, subjects identified the intended object before the end of
the corresponding word, suggesting that word recognition proceeds incrementally
beginning at word onset and is guided by visual context.
Visually-induced information about social categories, such as author profes-
sion, has also been shown to enhance word recognition. Fitneva and Spivey (2005)
showed subjects pictures of different professionals, and then presented them with
a lexical decision task asking them to imagine that the person previously pictured
was the speaker of the probe word. They found that words consistent with the
professional identity of the person pictured (e.g. “jury” for judge) were recognized
faster, suggesting that visually-prompted information about social categories fa-
cilitates lexical access. This experiment is of course one of many variants of the
semantic priming paradigm originally developed by Meyer and Schvaneveldt
(1971).10 Yet what is interesting about it is that the information facilitating lexical
access is now thoroughly social stereotypical in nature.
Other findings suggest that, like phonological and word processing, syntactic
processing is also mediated by context. Tanenhaus et al. (1995) studied the resolu-
tion of temporary syntactic ambiguities, as in “put the apple on the towel in the
box” using eye-tracking techniques. In this sentence, “on the towel” is temporarily
ambiguous between a destination and a modifier interpretation. Analyses priori-
tizing syntax claim that “on the towel” is interpreted as destination by default, and
then re-interpreted as modifier when the second PP “in the box” is heard. Con-
trary to these analyses, Tanenhaus et al. found that whether the first PP “on the
towel” is interpreted as destination or modifier depends on the visual context. If
there was an apple on a towel as well as a free towel that could serve as a destina-
tion, the ambiguity remained until the second PP “in the box” was heard. If, how-
ever, there were two apples, one on a towel and one not, the first PP “on the towel”
was immediately interpreted as a modifier, serving to disambiguate the intended
referent, i.e. no ambiguity arose as to its syntactic role. These results also show that,
similarly to what was argued earlier with respect to language acquisition, online
interpretation is goal-driven: “in natural contexts, people seek to establish refer-
ence with respect to their behavioural goals during the earliest moments of lin-
guistic processing” (Tanenhaus et al. 1995: 1634). There is no point wasting time
deriving syntactic structures that are not plausible given the visual context. In
other words, there is no point doing syntax independently of context.
Not only does visual context drive thematic role allocation to expressions as
soon as they are uttered, it also serves to pre-empt a thematic structure from only
partial linguistic information (e.g. hearing the words for agent and verb), and,
based on this, to identify the referents of the associated expressions before these
On de-limiting context 

have actually been uttered. Altmann and Kamide (1999) showed subjects visual
scenes representing potential semantic relationships between referents, e.g. a pic-
ture of a child and a cake, a toy train, a ball, and a toy truck. Subjects then heard
sentences such as “the boy will eat the cake” or “the boy will move the cake”. The
more constraining the selectional restrictions of the verb as to its object NP, the
faster subjects’ eye-movements settled on an intended referent (i.e. “cake” after
“eat”), even before the onset of the actual NP itself. This suggests that potentialities
of interaction between the objects pictured were latent in the visual context, and
activated by hearing the verb, already at verb onset. Similar results were obtained
when the sentences were heard after the visual stimulus had been removed, sug-
gesting that speakers build a mental representation of the stimulus and it is this
representation that they use in subsequent processing (Altmann 2004).
Finally, in a study investigating the effects of semantic and pragmatic anomaly
(violations of selectional restrictions vs. violations of world knowledge) using
electroencephalogram (EEG) and functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI)
data, Hagoort et al. (2004) found that both types of anomaly produce patterns of
brain activation that are identical in onset (i.e. they occur within the same time
frame) and latency, and very similar in amplitude and topographic distribution,
both engaging in activation of the left inferior pre-frontal cortex. This suggests
that semantic and world knowledge are drawn on in parallel during sentence
processing, dealing a direct blow to the presumed sequentiality of semantic and
pragmatic information. Differences in the processing of semantically and prag-
matically anomalous sentences emerge only later, suggesting that, although se-
mantic and world knowledge are drawn on in parallel, the mind does keep track of
the source of the anomaly. One might venture that this is because of the different
long-term consequences of each type of anomaly: semantic anomaly perhaps
ought to lead eventually to a revision of word meaning, whereas pragmatic anom-
alies of the type studied merely result in sentence falsity.
Taken together, the results of the psycholinguistic studies cited above give rise
to the following conclusions:
1. Interpretation does not begin after the end of the utterance, but starts at speech
onset and proceeds incrementally as the phonetic signal unfolds (Tanenhaus
et al. 1995; Altmann & Kamide 1999).
2. Interpretation aims to establish plausible ways of interacting with the world,
or, in other words, a pragmatically appropriate response; as such, it is driven
by the speaker’s goals (Tanenhaus et al. 1995; Altmann & Kamide 1999) in-
cluding the speaker’s projected goals when the speaker is different from the
self (Fitneva & Spivey 2005).
3. Linguistic and world knowledge are integrated from the earliest moments of
interpretation (Tanenhaus et al. 1995; Altmann & Kamide 1999).
 Marina Terkourafi

4. Linguistic and world knowledge are integrated in parallel rather than sequen-
tially (Tanenhaus et al. 1995; Altmann & Kamide 1999, Altmann 2004, Hagoort
et al. 2004).
5. Contextual input to interpretation includes both perceptually-given context
(Tanenhaus 1995; Altmann & Kamide 1999; Altmann 2004) and socio-cultur-
al expectations (Johnson et al. 1999; Fitneva & Spivey 2005).
6. Contextual input affects all levels of linguistic analysis.

4. Extending the scope of the phenomena: Illocutionary force resolution

The experimental studies cited above document input by both visual context and
socio-cultural expectations to interpretation from its earliest moments and at all
levels of linguistic analysis. The phenomena studied concern the resolution of lexi-
cal and syntactic ambiguities, reference assignment, and the processing of seman-
tic versus pragmatic anomaly, all phenomena falling squarely within the tradition
of truth-conditional semantic analysis (see Section 1). At the same time, these
studies document the influence of speaker goals on the determination of meaning,
supporting our earlier claim that knowing the meaning of an expression is not
radically different from understanding its pragmatic consequences (see Section 2).
If, as was argued earlier, knowing the meaning of an expression and understanding
its pragmatic consequences are indeed linked by a generative relationship in which
the former dynamically emerges from the latter, then the above results ought to
naturally extend into illocutionary force assignment, the meaning component per-
taining to understanding the pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s utterance
par excellence. In other words, if context contributes to truth-conditional aspects of
meaning in order to understand the pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s utter-
ance, could it also contribute to these pragmatic consequences directly? Indeed,
illocutionary force assignment itself may be viewed as a special case of contextual-
ly-driven pragmatic ambiguity resolution. This provides us with an extra reason to
suspect that, like with other types of ambiguity, context enters into illocutionary
force resolution from the first, i.e. as soon as contextual information is available.
My proposal is that illocutionary force is projected probabilistically from a
limited set of contextual parameters pertaining to who is talking to whom, when,
and where. Subsequent linguistic and contextual information serves to check this
probabilistic prediction, either confirming it (illocutionary assignment passing
unnoticed), or revising it in the light of incoming data. This section briefly outlines
the evidence for this proposal (cf. also Terkourafi 2002, 2005), while the following
two sections explore why this is a sensible view of how illocutionary force assign-
ment might proceed.
On de-limiting context 

4.1 Empirical motivation

The empirical findings motivating this proposal originate in spoken dialogical


corpus data from Cypriot Greek, tape-recorded in various settings and later tran-
scribed (approx. 60,000 words). Since conversations were recorded in the actual
settings where they occurred, several physical or otherwise extra-linguistic at-
tributes of the situation, such as the gender, age, social class of interlocutors, the
relationship between them, and the setting of the exchange were noted and later
fed into the analysis. During the analysis, utterances realizing offers or requests
were selected and classified as such depending on the addressee’s uptake
(Austin 1962). Then, the extra-linguistic attributes of the situation surrounding
each utterance, which had been noted during the collection of the data, served to
break down actual contexts of occurrence to schematic or otherwise ‘minimal’
contexts, consisting of the values of a limited set of contextual parameters (e.g., men,
aged 31–50, of middle class, addressing women, aged 31–50, of middle class, for
the first time, in a relationship of new customer to salesperson in a shop) but with
all other specificities removed.11
An investigation of the linguistic means used to perform offers or requests in
each such minimal context revealed that different minimal contexts correlated
positively with different linguistic constructions. In other words, out of a set of
semantically equivalent expressions conveying the same illocutionary force, a par-
ticular construction was preferred in a particular minimal context.12 The con-
structions that emerged from this analysis ranged from more to less abstract ones,
the most specific cases resembling Pawley and Syder’s (1983) “lexicalized sentence
stems.” In these, “the sentence structure is fully specified along with a nucleus of
lexical and grammatical morphemes which normally include the verb and certain
of its arguments; however, one or more structural elements is a class, represented
by a category symbol such as tense, np, or pro” (1983: 210). A default intonation
was also found to be part of the constructions analysed (cf. Cruttenden
1986/1997: 164).

4.2 An inheritance hierarchy of request constructions

Three types of constructions at different degrees of schematicity and context de-


pendence were revealed. At the most schematic level, requests over a large range of
minimal contexts were performed using a verb denoting a verbal or nonverbal act
in the second person singular imperative.13 The form of this construction may be
 Marina Terkourafi

specified as action.verb/speech.act.verb — imperative — 2ndsingular and


examples include:14
(1) [At home; Speaker: female, 18–30, working-class; Addressee: male, 18–30,
working-class; Relationship: family]
vasili ∫epase t∫e ton artemi
vassilis cover.imp.2sg and the artemis
‘Vassili, tuck in Artemis too.’
(2) [At work; Speaker: female, 31–50, middle-class; Addressee: female, 31–50,
working-class; Relationship: friends]
fkar’ ta friθca su.
pluck.imp.2sg the eyebrows your.2sg
‘Pluck your eyebrows.’
(3) [At work; Speaker: male, 31–50, middle-class; Addressee: male, 31–50,
middle-class; Relationship: old colleagues]
anikse tin porta re rikho
open.imp.2sg the door hey rikos
‘Hey Rick open the door’
(4) [At work; Speaker: female, 31–50, middle-class; Addressee: male, 31–50,
middle-class; Relationship: salesperson to old customer]
pien:e pano en’ o kostas.
go.imp.2sg up is the kostas.
‘Go upstairs, Kostas is {there}.’
(5) [At work; Speaker: female, 31–50, working-class; Addressee: male, 18–30,
working-class; Relationship: old customer to salesperson]
andoni (.) ela pjas’ ta misa
andonis (.) come.imp.2sg get.imp.2sg the half.
‘Andoni. Come and get half {of them}.’
(6) [At work; Speaker: male, over 51, middle-class; Addressee: female, over
51, middle-class; Relationship: employer to employee]
kane tilefonima esi marula mu
make.imp.2sg call you.2sg marula my
‘Make the call, Marula dear.’
(7) [At work; Speaker: female, 18–30, middle-class; Addressee: male, 31–50,
middle-class; Relationship: employee to employer]
var’ tes mes to folter su
put.imp.2sg them in the folder your.2sg
‘Put them {sheets of paper}in your folder’
On de-limiting context 

As can be seen from these examples, the construction action.verb/speech.act.


verb — imperative — 2ndsingular is used to perform requests across a wide
range of minimal contexts encompassing interlocutors of both genders, all age
groups, and both middle and working classes interacting in various roles, includ-
ing family, friends, old colleagues, salesperson and customer, and employee and
employer, at home and at work. This construction thus exhibits at once the least
degree of context-dependence, and the highest degree of schematicity, since lexical
items that can fill the verb slot are minimally constrained as to their semantics.
Contrary to the construction action.verb/speech.act.verb — imperative
— 2ndsingular which is characterized by a high degree of type frequency, three
tokens of this construction provide examples of high token frequency (Bybee 2006).
The expressions ase (leave — imperative — 2ndsingular = ‘let’), aku (listen
— imperative — 2ndsingular = ‘listen’), and el’a su po (come — imperative
— 2ndsingular to you i.tell =‘let me tell you’), although falling under the gen-
eral action.verb/ speech.act.verb — imperative — 2ndsingular construc-
tion, appear to constitute lexically-specific constructions with particular discourse
functions that override the request function of the more general construction.
In the data collected, their very high individual frequency goes hand in hand
with their being morphologically truncated (ase or ais < afise; aku < akuse; el’a su
po < ela na su po) and occurring utterance-initially, both of which provide struc-
tural indications that these forms are in fact frozen in Cypriot Greek. Indeed, when
these expressions are used, the act to be performed is typically expressed by a fur-
ther verb, such as na rotisumen in (8) (cf. Klamer 2000: 76).
(8) [At work; Speaker: male, aged 31–50, middle-class; Addressee: male, aged
31–50, middle-class; Relationship: salesperson to old customer]
endaksi. ase na rotisumen ton andrea
OK let.imp.2sg to ask.1pl the andreas
‘O.K. Let me ask Andreas.’
The way they combine with other elements in discourse provides further evidence
of their frozenness. Whereas el’a su po is literally a request, i.e. the first part of an
adjacency pair, the speaker seldom waits for the hearer’s uptake before continuing
(and one is hardly ever provided). Paralleling Klamer’s (2000: 76) hypothesis that
the absence of an intonational break after a report verb marks its function as a
complementizer, we can interpret a lack of speaker change at the end of this into-
national unit as signalling the non-requestive function of el’a su po. In the case of
aku and ase, it is their argument structure that has been affected: aku occurs with-
out a complement, whereas ase occurs with a clausal complement, and is conse-
quently not felt to have the full semantic content of ‘leaving (something)’, which it
has when followed by an NP. Both processes (loss of arguments and acquisition of
 Marina Terkourafi

new ones) have been associated with an expression’s becoming frozen/fixed as “the
result of frequently occurring in appropriate surface contexts” (Klamer 2000: 96).
Rather than requests, then, the three expressions ase, aku, and el’a su po appear to
function as ‘prefaces’ (Nofsinger 1991: 134–5): they serve to attract or ensure the
addressee’s continued attention, while contributing little, if anything, to the propo-
sition expressed by the utterance.
While the general action.verb/speech.act.verb — imperative — 2ndsin-
gular construction constitutes the most frequent realization for requests overall,
other lexically-specific constructions are preferred in specific minimal contexts.
Exchanges in shops and formal settings, such as public discussions and interviews
on the radio/TV, provide such minimal contexts. In the former, two constructions
involving the verb exo, ‘to have,’ take the lead, while in the latter, another construc-
tion, this time involving the verb θelo, ‘to want,’ prevails.
In requests exchanged between middle-class interlocutors in transactional
settings exete NP? (have — indicative.rising.intonation — 2ndplural = ‘do.
you-pl have NP?’) ranked first (Example 9).
(9) [At work; Speaker: male, 31–50, middle-class; Addressee: female, 18–30,
working-class; Relationship: new customer to salesperson]
eçete: phinats?
have.ind?.2pl peanuts?
‘Do you have some peanuts?’
On the other hand, in requests exchanged between working-class interlocutors in
the same settings exi NP? (have — indicative.rising.intonation — 3rdsingu-
lar = ‘is/are there NP?’) ranked first (Example 10).
(10) [At work; Speaker: female, 31–50, working-class; Addressee: male, 31–50,
working-class; Relationship: new customer to salesperson]
eçi mikres pu na min exun sçeδia pano? aspro
have.ind?,3sg small that subj neg have.ind.3pl patterns on? white
‘Are there any small plain {socks}? In white.’
In other words, exete NP? (have — indicative.rising.intonation — 2ndplural =
‘do.you-pl have NP?’) appears to be associated with the following minimal context:15
– Gender of speaker: {any}
– Age of speaker: {any}
– Social class of speaker: middle
– Gender of addressee: {any}
– Age of addressee: {any}
– Social class of addressee: middle, working
– Relationship: new customer to salesperson
On de-limiting context 

– Setting: at work
– Speech act occurs for the: 1st time
A slightly different minimal context is associated with use of exi NP? (have — in-
dicative.rising.intonation — 3rdsingular = ‘is/are.there NP?’).
– Gender of speaker: {any}
– Age of speaker: {any}
– Social class of speaker: working
– Gender of addressee: {any}
– Age of addressee: {any}
– Social class of addressee: working, middle
– Relationship: new customer to salesperson
– Setting: at work
– Speech act occurs for the: 1st time
Conversely, in addressing requests to interviewers in formal settings, women and
interviewees preferred yet a third construction, θa iθela VP (fut want — past
— 1stsingular = ‘I would.like VP’; Example 11).
(11) [On TV: Speaker: female, 31–50, middle-class; Addressee: male, 31–50,
middle-class; Relationship: interviewee to interviewer]
θa iθela na prosθeso kati eδo omos.
fut want.past.1sg subj add.1sg something here though.
‘I would like to add something here though.’
The relevant minimal context this time is:
– Gender of speaker: female, male
– Age of speaker: {any}
– Social class of speaker: (middle)
– Gender of addressee: {any}
– Age of addressee: {any}
– Social class of addressee: (middle)
– Relationship: interviewee to interviewer, interviewer to interviewee
– Setting: formal discussions
– Speech act occurs for the: 1st time
What is interesting when comparing the two exo/have-constructions with the
θelo/want-construction is that semantically there is nothing stopping θa iθela VP
(fut want — past — 1stsingular = ‘I would.like VP’) from performing a suc-
cessful request in transactional settings too. It constitutes an indirect request by
affirming the sincerity condition in much the same way as the two exo/have-con-
structions constitute indirect requests by questioning the preparatory condition
 Marina Terkourafi

concerning the existence of goods sought (Brown & Levinson 1987: 137). And
while affirming one’s desire for some thing should function equally well as a re-
quest as questioning its availability (compare English ‘Do you have NP?’ and ‘I’d
like NP’), the preferences in the Cypriot Greek data are clear-cut: out of 61 re-
quests by a new customer addressing a salesperson, only one (1.64%) was found
using θa iθela (and then, complemented by an NP). On the other hand, of 28 oc-
currences of θa iθela in the data, 26 are followed by a VP and 24 of these are in
formal settings. In other words, though they all fall under Brown and Levinson’s
strategy of negative politeness, these constructions are not interchangeable.
While the three token-frequency constructions analysed earlier are linked to
the more general action.verb/speech.act.verb — imperative — 2ndsingu-
lar construction in virtue of their form, the last three constructions are linked to
it in virtue of their function. In both cases, the additional degrees of lexical speci-
fication come with added pragmatic effects. In the case of the ase, aku and el’a su
po constructions, which are highly frequent across contexts, these added prag-
matic effects amount to overriding the requestive function of the general construc-
tion, which is now replaced by their function as prefaces. However, in the case of
the exete NP?, exi NP?, and θa iθela VP constructions, these further pragmatic ef-
fects seem to follow directly from the specific values of the associated minimal
contexts (italicised in the diagrammatic representations of these minimal contexts
above) that override the default (underspecified) context specifications of the more
general construction. These specific contextual values motivate assumptions about
additional (non-illocutionary) goals that participants may plausibly be pursuing in
these minimal contexts. The further pragmatic effects afforded by these lexically-
specific constructions, then, take the form of particular identity displays, above
and beyond the constructions’ illocutionary function as requests.16
The close association between minimal contexts and particular constructions
introduced at the beginning of this section is most clearly seen in constructions of
this last type and allows us to formulate the following hypothesis: as soon as a
construction is uttered in the minimal context with which it is associated, a par-
ticular illocutionary force — that of request, in the cases reviewed above — is
probabilistically assigned to it without further ado. This illocutionary force re-
mains operative until it is contradicted by incoming information. In other words,
a limited set of contextual parameters jointly provide a pointer to the intended il-
locutionary force, rendering reference to the fully specified, nonce context of oc-
currence superfluous — at least at an initial stage (see Section 5). Assuming this
hypothesis is in the right direction — subject to confirmation by future studies of
a similar design — two questions must be answered next. First, what is the advan-
tage of relying — at least at an initial stage — on a limited set of contextual
On de-limiting context 

parameters to infer illocutionary force? Second, why should precisely these con-
textual parameters be appealed to and no others?

5. Processing minimal contexts

In answer to the first question, the incrementality of interpretation provides some


clues. What the Cypriot Greek findings suggest is that the incrementality of inter-
pretation concerns not only the way in which linguistic input temporally unfolds
through time and is received and processed sequentially, but also the way in which
context is perceived and updated with new information. Information about the
gender, age, and social class of the speaker and addressee, the relationship between
them, the setting of the exchange, and the sequential order of realization of the
speech act is available at speech onset. In other words, it forms part of the inter-
locutors’ common ground up to and including the moment when the fact that an
utterance is being uttered is added to it, i.e. just before that utterance has been
evaluated (cf. Stalnaker 1999: 102). However, this is not the case with the sur-
rounding linguistic context (consider the first move in a dialogical game), paralin-
guistic and other idiosyncratic clues, which unfold in parallel with the utterance
(cf. Fitneva & Spivey 2005: 318).
As a result, these two sets of contextual information can take on different roles
during the interpretation process. Contextual information available at speech on-
set can begin to play a part before the contextual information unfolding in parallel
with the utterance even becomes available. In this way, it can serve to maximize
the speed of interpretation by channelling the interpretation process toward con-
ventionally expected outcomes, acting as a short-cut to the intended illocutionary
force. Contextual information becoming available as the utterance itself unfolds
checks the presumed illocutionary force and updates the context with the perlocu-
tionary effects actually achieved by the speaker’s utterance (this is one way in
which linguistic context, i.e. interpreted prior discourse, ‘contains’ extra-linguistic
context, as was claimed earlier).
The temporal priority of the first set of contextual parameters is due to the fact
that they are typically fixed on the basis of background knowledge or otherwise
perceptually (e.g. visually) available evidence. That is, they are largely settled auto-
matically, i.e. by reasoning pre-emptively on whatever data are available, even to
just initiate interaction. To see that this is so, consider the awkwardness of realiz-
ing that the person one is talking to on the phone is an elderly lady, not a young
child as one had originally surmised judging by the high pitched voice at the other
end of the line; or, of realizing that one’s addressee is a customer in a shop rather
than a salesperson only after making a goods-related query. The reason why these
 Marina Terkourafi

mundane situations typically prompt an apology is that settling these contextual


features one way biases the interpretation process in a certain direction. Once one
realizes one’s mistake, it is necessary not only to re-set the contextual parameters
to their correct values, but also to re-interpret previous discourse, withdrawing all
those inferences derived on mistaken premises. In other words, what such inci-
dents suggest is that we ‘hear’ different speakers differently, depending on default
assumptions that we have made about them.
Acknowledging the automaticity of assumptions about these contextual pa-
rameters is not to deny their socio-cultural basis. How individuals are assigned to
genders and age-groups, and even more so, to social classes and roles, how many
social classes, potential relationships between interlocutors, or interactional set-
tings are distinguished, are irreducibly social matters. As such, they rely on a proc-
ess of acculturation, akin to developing the set of “nonrepresentational mental
capacities that enable all representing to take place” which Searle refers to as “the
background” (1994: 143). In this sense, a minimal context comprising the gender,
age, social class of interlocutors, the relationship between them, and the setting of
the exchange constitutes convenient shorthand for an accumulated body of socio-
cultural knowledge.
The relationship between an utterance and its surrounding context has been
likened to that of figure and ground (Goodwin & Duranti 1992: 9). However, if the
above description of the relationship between a minimal context and the back-
ground is at all accurate, it seems more appropriate to conceive of this relationship
as a three-way one, between an utterance, a minimal context, and a background,
where continuous interaction occurs not just between utterance (figure) and min-
imal context (ground), but also between minimal context (ground) and back-
ground, the former simultaneously constrained and invested with meaning by the
latter. The background, in other words, will always ‘colour’ minimal context, and
similar minimal contexts will presuppose similar backgrounds.
Goodwin (1996) offers a case in point when he describes how what appears to
be “transparent vision,” i.e. obvious, unmediated understanding of scenes and
events, can actually go through several stages of “seeing,” all equally “thoroughly
social,” such that, in the end, “transparent vision is very much a crafted object”
(1996: 382). Barsalou (1999) outlines the cognitive underpinnings of this process,
whereby symbolic representations can emerge from perceptual input. As a result of
this process, frequently repeated patterns of interaction give rise to symbolic rep-
resentations available for propositional manipulation. Arising in this way, the con-
textual parameters discussed above are at once constructed and objective
(Sbisà 2002): they are not subjective individual mental constructs; rather, they both
arise with reference to perceptual data, and are constrained by social feedback.
On de-limiting context 

In answer, then, to the question of what is the advantage of relying (at least at
an initial stage) on a limited set of contextual parameters to infer illocutionary
force, the incrementality of interpretation suggests that interpretation begins as
soon as a speaker starts speaking, and proceeds in parallel with the speaker’s utter-
ance, drawing on contextual information as and when this becomes available.
Contextual parameters that can be fixed early on in an exchange prime the con-
ventionally expected illocutionary force, thereby speeding up interpretation.
Through acculturation, these contextual parameters gain in salience: interlocutors
seek to settle these — if only by presumption — in order just to initiate interaction.
It is telling in this respect that ambiguities concerning these contextual parameters
are rather badly tolerated — and, in some cultures at least, may actively deter one
from engaging in interaction until they are resolved.

6. Motivating minimal contexts

Let us come now to the second question posed at the end of Section 4: why should
precisely these contextual parameters be appealed to, and no others? The answer,
in a nutshell, is that the contextual parameters jointly constituting a minimal con-
text are motivated rather than arbitrary. Their jointly constituting a minimal con-
text can be predicted by the organization of human action.
Some useful insights into this organization are provided by Gibson’s (1977)
notion of ‘affordances’ of the physical environment, according to which the struc-
ture of an object embodies potentialities of interaction with this object
(cf. Mace 1977). Drawing a parallel between objects and physical settings, physical
settings may also be said to embody potentialities of interaction with them. The
physical layout of a shop is different to that of a bank, or to that of one’s living
room. The process by which physical settings afford us with specific potentialities
of interaction is best thought of as a discursive one, resulting from the mutual in-
teraction of an agent with his/her environment (cf. Mace 1977: 46). In this sense,
once again we are concerned with the kind of transparent vision mentioned ear-
lier. However, what is of interest now is that through such socio-culturally medi-
ated vision, mere perception of a certain physical layout can set in motion a whole
chain of inferences regarding the prototypical social roles of participants one may
expect to find therein, and prototypical individuals fulfilling these roles (for in-
stance, at a company’s reception desk (location), one might expect to find a secre-
tary (role) and she will stereotypically be female (gender)).17
Because human action exploits the affordances of physical settings, partici-
pants’ presence in a certain setting can act as a pointer to their behavioural goals
(Lindsay & Gorayska 1994: 37). This inference is clearly probabilistic and will vary
 Marina Terkourafi

for different goals. Some goals can be pursued in several different settings
(e.g. socializing with friends), while others cannot (e.g. trying a case in court). As
a result, different settings will constrain to different extents the sets of goals one
may plausibly pursue therein. This prediction is confirmed by the Cypriot Greek
corpus data. Preferences for lexicalized, as opposed to merely schematic, construc-
tions were revealed in those settings that most rigidly constrain the goals one may
plausibly pursue therein: when one enters a shop as a customer for the first time,
and during interviews on radio/TV (see Section 4).
The notion of the affordances of physical settings may thus provide the miss-
ing link between the limited set of contextual parameters we have been consider-
ing (interlocutors’ gender, age, and social class, the relationship between them,
and the setting of the exchange) and the kinds of goals that the speaker is pre-
sumed to be pursuing at any one time. By motivating the relationship between the
contextual parameters available since the early stages of the interpretation process,
affordances also limit their number. A potentially all-inclusive notion of context is
practically unmanageable and of little empirical usefulness. What is needed, in
this respect, is a notion of context that is bounded, i.e. that distinguishes context
from the totality of the interlocutors’ common ground.
The emergence of symbolically represented contextual parameters out of per-
ceptual input along the lines proposed by Barsalou (1999) shapes a potentially un-
limited body of socio-cultural knowledge into a limited set of contextual parame-
ters available for propositional manipulation. Because of this, the resulting minimal
contexts are neither impoverished with respect to the original input, nor reducible
to it. At the same time, the contextual parameters jointly constituting a minimal
context cannot be further broken down to more abstract ones, such as relative sta-
tus or power, or social distance. Rather, they are mentally manipulated as primes.
Interviews with informants suggest that, unlike the more abstract categories of
power and social distance, the contextual parameters proposed above are intui-
tively graspable and correspond to participants’ own internalized categories. The
primacy of the contextual parameters proposed above also receives support from
the literature on language acquisition, which shows that, by age four, children have
begun to pay attention to the categories of gender, age, and profession (the latter
being one determinant of social class), talking differently to mothers and fathers,
adults or peers and younger addressees, nurses and doctors (reported in E. Clark
2004: 573–576). That the proposed analysis uses the same categories internalized
by speakers satisfies not only Occam’s injunction not to multiply entities beyond
necessity, but also the ethnomethodological requirement to take “as a starting
point of departure for the analysis of context the perspective of the participant(s)
whose behaviour is being analyzed” (Goodwin & Duranti 1992: 4).
On de-limiting context 

7. Conclusion: Some consequences for grammar construction

My aim in this paper has been to advance a theoretically motivated and empiri-
cally backed argument for the context-dependent nature of linguistic interpreta-
tion at all levels of analysis. At a theoretical level, the argument is based on the
primacy of understanding the pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s utterance,
from which knowledge of meaning arises by a process of abstraction over time.
Examples of pragmatic understanding achieved with very little — or even in spite
of — linguistic input available go to show just how far interpretation can proceed
drawing on contextual information alone. In other words, context emerges as a
powerful resource that speakers interpreting language have at their disposal. Psy-
cholinguistic studies show that speakers systematically exploit this resource not
just to interpret linguistic input as this becomes perceptually available, but also to
anticipate future linguistic input before this has even materialized physically.
Based on these experimental results and on original corpus data from Cypriot
Greek, I further proposed that illocutionary force assignment as a central part of
understanding the pragmatic consequences of the speaker’s utterance begins from
the earliest moments of utterance interpretation and proceeds incrementally
alongside other aspects of linguistic analysis. Moreover, I suggested that speakers
exploit the sequential order in which contextual information becomes available.
Two types of contextual information may be distinguished in this respect. Infor-
mation pertaining to socio-cultural categories such as the gender, age, and social
class of interlocutors, the relationship between them and the setting of the ex-
change is available at speech onset, and serves to set up expectations about the
intended illocutionary force. Further paralinguistic and intonational cues become
available as the speech signal unfolds, and serve to confirm or revise the projected
illocutionary force. It is possible to project illocutionary force from this limited set
of contextual parameters, because human experience is structured by exploiting
the affordances of physical settings, making it possible to reason pre-emptively
from one’s presence in a physical setting to one’s goals.
This proposal remains to be experimentally assessed. One way of testing it is
measuring the speed of interpretation of linguistic stimuli containing, e.g., refer-
ring expressions, where reference assignment would vary according to illocution-
ary force assignment. In this way, it ought to be possible to establish with some
certainty how soon after speech onset illocutionary force is resolved, and, poten-
tially, by appropriately manipulating contextual variables, with respect to which
pieces of contextual information it is resolved.
While experimental confirmation of the present proposal must await future
research, there is enough in the available experimental and corpus results to sug-
gest that continuing to abide by grammatical frameworks that adopt an essentially
 Marina Terkourafi

sequential view of linguistic analysis is no longer viable. Especially if our criteria


for grammar evaluation include explanatory adequacy — paying particular atten-
tion to how linguistic knowledge is acquired by children rather than how it is actu-
ally processed by adults (cf. Chomsky 1995: 32) — it is clear that contextual input,
and, in particular, socially defined categories such as gender, age, and profession
which are interpreted as linguistically relevant by children at an early age, cannot
be excluded from our representations of grammar.
The closest parallel to the integration of phonological, syntactic, semantic and
pragmatic information revealed by the experimental studies is offered by sign-
based formalisms such as Construction Grammar, which allow the concurrent
specification of phonological, syntactic, semantic and pragmatic constraints on
the processing of linguistic constructions at various levels of abstraction. One ad-
vantage of Construction Grammar vis-á-vis related lexicalist formalisms is that it
allows for the specification of inheritance hierarchies of constructions, which ap-
pear to correlate with increasing levels of context specificity in the Cypriot Greek
corpus data (see Section 4.2). Working out how to incorporate pragmatic, and in
particular, extra-linguistic, considerations into our feature structures remains a
task for the future. At this stage, my aim has been simply to suggest the urgent need
for such an endeavour, by substantiating this both theoretically and empirically.

Notes

* I would like to thank Mirjam Fried, Roger Lindsay, and an anonymous reviewer for valua-
ble comments on a previous draft.
1. The strong sequentialist view outlined in this section is admittedly a straw-man put up for
the sake of argument for at least two reasons. First, it is presented in its simplest, bare-bones
form: more sophisticated versions of this view are also available. However, when considering
those more sophisticated versions, it is worth bearing in mind that the alternative view devel-
oped in this paper abandons not only the traditional sequentiality of levels of analysis but also
their informational encapsulation. As such, a more radical departure than merely admitting the
possibility of parallel distributed processing is required to accommodate this alternative view.
Second, the strong sequentialist view is contra-indicated by a mass of evidence from experimen-
tal psychology — only a fraction of which is reviewed in Section 3 below — and as such probably
no-one today would defend it as a psychologically plausible view of language understanding.
Nevertheless, as an idealised abstraction enabling theory development it underlies several dis-
tinctions, such as, e.g., between the lexicon and the grammar, or between the lexicon and the
encyclopaedia, which, in turn, often find their way into analyses of a more formalist persuasion.
As a result, although sequentiality as such may no longer be defensible or seriously defended, it
seems to be embedded deeply enough in our linguistic theorising to warrant presenting it as the
thesis against which to set up the antithesis argued for in this paper.
On de-limiting context 

2. It is an oft-neglected aspect of this truth-conditional stance that it brings into focus the re-
lationship of language to the world (recall the truth-conditional motto “to know the meaning of
a sentence is to know what the world would have to be like for the sentence to be true”). What
this essentially suggests is that there is no use (or: meaning) to language other than the informa-
tion that it conveys about the world (or: some world). In this sense, the ‘purpose’ of language is
to improve the alignment between what goes on inside our heads and what goes on outside of
them, so to speak; to give us a grasp onto the outside world; and, ultimately, to enhance our
performance as we act in this world. Seen from this perspective, the truth-conditional tradition
is not quite as antithetical to the ensuing language-as-action tradition started by ordinary lan-
guage philosophers as we may generally tend to believe.
3. Actually, these two solutions are not necessarily alternatives: one constitutes a point about
the informational role of semantic vs. pragmatic contributions, while the other relates to how
the computational processes employing this information are organized (I thank Roger Lindsay
for this observation). This is understandable given the different emphases of the respective fields
advocating them: on the informational import of linguistic expressions within semantics, and,
increasingly, on psychological plausibility within pragmatics.
4. This view is advocated within dynamic semantic theories such as Discourse Representation
Theory (Kamp & Reyle 1993) and Game-Theoretic Semantics (Hand 1999).
5. The latter solution is advocated within post-Gricean pragmatics including both Relevance
Theory and Neo-Gricean approaches.
6. Pre-empting these experimental results, Fillmore claimed that the labeling of whole scenes
or experiences precedes the labeling of individual, isolable parts of these, to finally produce “a
repertory of labels for schematic or abstract scenes and a repertory of labels for entities per-
ceived independently of the scenes in which they were first encountered” (1977: 62). To support
this last claim, he also presented preliminary psychological evidence of the greater cognitive
complexity of handling decontextualized behaviours and objects of perception (1976: 24).
7. The grounding of language acquisition in pragmatics, out of which, through successive
abstractions, semantics is built, is of course one of psychology’s earliest tenets (e.g., Vygotsky
1986[1934]) to have been confirmed by modern psycholinguistics (e.g., Maratsos 1977; Schank
& Abelson 1977: 222).
8. Such a verificationist view of meaning has previously been advocated by philosophers such
as Dummett or Brandom. I thank Michiel Leezenberg for this observation.
9. Those of a more cognitivist persuasion will be well acquainted with similar claims, most
notably through the work of Charles Fillmore on Frame Semantics (1976, 1977, 1982, 1984,
1986). Especially pertinent is his distinction between T-semantics (the semantics of truth) and
U-semantics (the semantics of understanding; Fillmore 1984, 1986), which parallels the distinc-
tion between the received view and the alternative view advocated in this paper. I thank Mirjam
Fried for bringing these works to my attention.
10. I thank Roger Lindsay for contributing this information.
11. For fuller description of the sampling and corpus collection and analysis procedures see
Terkourafi 2001, Chapter 2.
12. A theory such as Brown and Levinson’s (1978/1987) theory of politeness, which correlates
pragmatic strategies — rather than constructions — with underlying social variables such as
Power, Distance and Ranking of the imposition — rather than with directly observable attributes
 Marina Terkourafi

of interlocutors — fails to make this more finely grained prediction. The problem is that in their
theory, each pragmatic strategy can be realized by several linguistic expressions, whereas the
direct association between linguistic constructions and minimal contexts revealed by the analy-
sis of the Cypriot Greek data turned out to be conventional, i.e. not mediated by a general ra-
tionality principle such as Brown and Levinson’s Wx=D(S,H)+P(H,S)+Rx (1978/1987: 76).
13. There are several advantages to claiming that the relationship between imperatives and the
illocutionary force of request is conventionalized, i.e. defeasible, rather than a semantic,
encoded one, including the possibility to account more economically for imperatives perform-
ing offers, expletives, and instructions.
14. Cypriot Greek examples are rendered semi-phonologically in the IPA (post-lexical processes
are not represented), followed by a word-per-word translation, and an English gloss (‘ ’). Con-
structions discussed in the text are underlined in all three versions of the examples. Transcription
conventions and abbreviations used: 2sg=2nd person singular; IMP=imperative; FUT=future
particle; NEG=negative particle; SUBJ=subjunctive particle; CG=Cypriot Greek dialectal word-
form; (.) =brief pause; ? =rising intonation; , =flat intonation; . =falling intonation; : =elongated
sound (also used for Cypriot Greek geminates); { }=words added to improve translation.
15. Contextual parameters appearing as {any} had no significant impact on the use of the ex-
pression in the data. Values divided by commas appear in order of frequency. Values are indi-
cated in parenthesis when there was not enough evidence in the data to ascertain their impact
on use of the expression.
16. On the function of these constructions to assert a ‘middle-class customer’ identity desirable
in transactional settings, and a ‘familiar with an interviewing register’ identity desirable in for-
mal discussions, see Terkourafi (2002: 186–187 and 191–194 respectively).
17. The notion of affordances I am operating with in this section is clearly an extension of the
original Gibsonian term. Gibson specifically intended affordances as an alternative to cognitive
processes, arguing that “everything necessary to explain behaviour could be recovered from the
‘flux of information at the receptor surfaces’” instead (Roger Lindsay, personal communication).
A more appropriate term for the aspects of the physical environment I am interested in is per-
haps “plan enablement,” a term referring to “the subset of plans enabled by the fact that their
activation conditions are met by a particular physical setting” (Roger Lindsay, personal com-
munication). However, using the term ‘affordances’ brings with it some advantages that a shift
in terminology may not afford. These include recognizability of the general idea behind the term
— if not of its full complexity — across disciplinary boundaries, and most importantly the hand/
glove relationship of behaviour to the environment that prompted Gibson to coin the term af-
fordances in the first place, which provides an apt metaphor for the discursive relationship be-
tween an agent and his/her environment by which the affordances of physical settings emerge.
At the risk, then, of stretching this term beyond the dictates of scientific perspicacity, I continue
to refer to these visually grounded, socially-constructed (and hence distinctly cognitive) aspects
of physical settings as ‘affordances.’

References

Altmann, Gerry (2004). Language mediated eye-movements in the absence of a visual world:
The ‘blank screen paradigm’. Cognition, 93, B79–B87.
On de-limiting context 

Altmann, Gerry & Yuki Kamide (1999). Incremental interpretation at verbs: Restricting the
domain of subsequent reference. Cognition, 73, 247–264.
Austin, John (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bach, Kent (1994). Semantic slack: What is said and more. In S. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Foundations of
speech act theory: Philosophical and linguistic perspectives (267–291). London: Routledge.
Barsalou, Lawrence (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577–660.
Brown, Penelope & Stephen C. Levinson (1978/1987). Politeness: Some universals in language
usage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bybee, Joan (2006). From usage to grammar: The mind’s response to repetition. Language, 82,
711–733.
Chomsky, Noam (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
Clark, Eve (2004). Pragmatics and language acquisition. In L. Horn and G. Ward (Eds.), The
handbook of pragmatics (562–577). Oxford: Blackwell.
Cruttenden, Andrew (1986/1997). Intonation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fitneva, Stanka & Michael Spivey (2005). Context and language processing: The effect of author-
ship. In J. Trueswell & M. Tanenhaus (Eds.), Approaches to studying world-situated language
use: Bridging the language-as-product and language-as-action traditions (317–328).
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fillmore, Charles (1976/1981). Pragmatics and the description of discourse. In P. Cole (Ed.),
Radical pragmatics (143–166). New York: Academic Press.
Fillmore, Charles (1982). Frame Semantics. In The Linguistic Society of Korea (Eds.), Linguistics
in the Morning Calm (111–137). Seoul: Hanshin Publishing Company.
Fillmore, Charles (1984). Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica,
6, 222–254.
Fillmore, Charles (1986). U-semantics, second round. Quaderni di Semantica, 8, 49–58.
Gibson, James (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.) Perceiving, act-
ing and knowing (67–82). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Goodwin, Charles & Alessandro Duranti (1992). Rethinking context: Introduction. In A.
Duranti & C. Goodwin (Eds.), Rethinking context: Language as an interactive phenomenon
(1–42). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goodwin, Charles (1996). Transparent vision. In E. Ochs, E. Schegloff & S. Thompson (eds.),
Interaction and grammar (370–404). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hagoort, Peter, Lea Hald, Marcel Bastiaansen, & Karl Magnus Petersson (2004). Integration of
word meaning and world knowledge in language comprehension. Science, 304, 438–441.
Hand, Michael (1999). Semantics vs. pragmatics: ANY in game-theoretical semantics. In K.
Turner (Ed.), The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view (179–198).
Oxford: Elsevier Science.
Hawkins, Sarah & Rachel Smith (2001). Polysp: A polysystemic, phonetically-rich approach to
speech understanding. Rivista di Linguistica, 13, 99–188.
Johnson, Keith, Elisabeth Strand & Mariapaola D’Imperio (1999). Auditory-visual integration
of talker gender in vowel perception. Journal of Phonetics, 17, 359–384.
Kamp, Hans & Uwe Reyle (1993). From discourse to logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Klamer, Marian (2000). How report verbs become quote markers and complementizers. Lingua,
110, 69–98.
Lindsay, Roger & Barbara Gorayska (1994). Towards a general theory of cognition. MS. Oxford
Brookes University & City of Hong Kong Polytechnic.
 Marina Terkourafi

Mace, William (1977). James J. Gibson’s strategy for perceiving: Ask not what’s inside your head,
but what your head’s inside of. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.) Perceiving, acting and know-
ing (43–65). Hillsdale, NJ.: Erlbaum.
Maratsos, Michael (1977). Disorganization in thought and word. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford
(Eds.), Perceiving, acting and knowing (347–363). Hillsdale, NJ.: Erlbaum.
Meyer, David & Roger Schvaneveldt (1971). Facilitation in recognizing pairs of words: Evidence of
a dependence between retrieval operations. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 90, 227–234.
Nofsinger, Robert (1991). Everyday conversation. London: Sage.
Pawley, Andrew & Frances Syder (1983). Two puzzles for linguistic theory: nativelike selection
and nativelike fluency. In J.C. Richards & R.W. Schmidt (Eds.), Language and communica-
tion (191–226). London: Longman.
Sbisà, Marina (2002). Speech acts in context. Language and Communication, 22, 421–436.
Schank, Roger & Robert Abelson (1977). Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: An inquiry into
human knowledge structures. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Searle, John (1994). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Stalnaker, Robert (1999). On the representation of context. In R. Stalnaker (Ed.), Context and con-
tent: Essays on intentionality in speech and thought (96–113). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tanenhaus, Michael, Michael Spivey-Knowlton, Kathleen Eberhard, & Julie Sedivy (1995). Inte-
gration of visual and linguistic information in spoken language comprehension. Science,
268, 1632–1634.
Terkourafi, Marina (2001). Politeness in Cypriot Greek: A frame-based approach. PhD diss. Uni-
versity of Cambridge, Department of Linguistics.
Terkourafi, Marina (2002). Politeness and formulaicity: Evidence from Cypriot Greek. Journal of
Greek Linguistics, 3, 179–201.
Terkourafi, Marina (2005). Pragmatic correlates of frequency of use: The case for a notion of
‘minimal context’. In K. Nikiforidou, S. Marmaridou, & E. Antonopoulou (Eds.), Reviewing
linguistic thought: Converging trends for the 21st century (209–233). Berlin: de Gruyter.
Tomasello, Michael. (1995). Pragmatic contexts for early verb learning. In M. Tomasello & W. E.
Merriman (Eds.), Beyond names for things: Young children’s acquisition of verbs (115–146).
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Tomasello, Michael (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Vygotsky, Leo (1934/1986). Thought and language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Constructions and context
When a construction constructs the context*

Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

The role of context in construction grammar has been up to now viewed from a
restricted point of view. That is, context is used to help in analysing the meaning and
the pragmatic aspects of constructions, in keeping with the following assumption:
1. Context (common ground) forms part of the construction’s semantics
It has been observed that, in many cases, constructions have a non-compositional
meaning. A sub-class of semantically non-compositional constructions is charac-
terized by the fact that its interpretation involves the incorporation of pieces of
information derived by taking into account, broadly speaking, the context of the
utterance effected through the construction. The introduction of these contextual
pieces of information is achieved in most cases by means of lexemes carrying an
instructional meaning: “look at this aspect of context to process the meaning of
the construction.” This situation is best described by Kay:
A number of grammatical constructions have been described in which Part or all
of the meaning of the construction is […] a virtual instruction to the addressee to
examine the common ground of the conversation (along with the other interpre-
tive content of the sentence) to fill in some partially specified part of the intended
interpretation. An example involving the construction employing the expression
let alone is given in (a).

(a) Fred won’t order shrimp, let alone Louise, squid.

The addressee of an utterance of (a) can only interpret it successfully if he can find
in, or construct from, the conversational common ground a set of assumptions
according to which Louise’s willingness to order squid unilaterally entails Fred’s
willingness to order shrimp. (Kay 1997: 3)

In addition, (a) shows how such complex interpretational phenomena can be con-
ventionally associated with a particular morphosyntax, that is, they are encoded in
the construction via the expression let alone, serving as an instruction marker.
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

The aim of our paper is to address another case of a syntactic pattern involving
context, which can be summed up by assumption 2:
2. A construction provides pieces of context that the speaker considers to be nec-
essary for the addressee to get a relevant interpretation of the current utterance
We claim that alongside constructions, like the let alone one, which need context to
be interpreted, there exist constructions which bring in contextual background in-
formation to maximize the relevance of the utterance they are added to. This asser-
tion seems at the beginning of the sentence quite paradoxical. Any piece of an ut-
terance is usually regarded as text, not context. We would like to show that some
pieces of utterances are in fact not part of the ongoing text, but have some kind of
background status which makes them part of the context. At first glance, these piec-
es of utterances have, in the domain of speech, the same status as footnotes have in
written uses of language. They are, strictly speaking, marginal to the text and near-
er to context status than to plain text status. In any case, these subconstructs in-
serted in utterances have a special status that must be accounted for both in linguis-
tic theory and in construction grammar. Their special status can be revealed in the
fact that they show idiosyncratic formal as well as pragmatic properties.
In order to show this, we will focus on a subgroup of these constructions,
namely those which are introduced by grammatical devices (so-called subordina-
tors) and which appear as superficially synonymous with prototypical subordinate
clauses. Consider this example of a parce que clause in spoken French translated
with bold ‘cos (Debaisieux 2002):
(1) le roi parce que le roi est très aimé en Thaïlande je crois que j’en ai parlé
avant le roi est arrivé[…]... à leur faire comprendre que cette culture était
très en dent de scie (LOU. Cas.)
‘The king ‘cos the king is very much loved in Thailand – I think I have said
that before – the king succeeded in making them understand that this
culture was very uneven.’
The French version is perfectly acceptable. The parce que clause reintroduces a
piece of relevant common ground (as underlined by the speaker’s metacommuni-
cative comment I think I have said that before) by interrupting the processing of
the main line of discourse. We will show that this use of parce que is specific. It has
neither the properties of subordinating parce que, nor even exactly those of the
Constructions and context 

parce que / cos’ introducing “supplementive” clauses according to the terminology


of Huddleston & Pullum (2002) and evidenced in the well known examples:
(2) Jean est certainement à la Fac parce que j’ai vu qu’il avait laissé sa voiture
dans le parking
‘Sure John is at the University ‘cos I noticed that he left his car in the park-
ing lot ’
Parce que in (1) shares the non-subordinate status with parce que in (2), but it dif-
fers in many respects, as we will show later on. For instance it allows strict lexical
repetition (see bolded words in 1), which are very awkward in (3):
(3) Jean est certainement à la Fac parce que j’ai vu qu’ il (?? Jean) avait laissé
sa voiture dans le parking
‘Sure John is at the University ‘cos I noticed that he (?? John) left his car in
the parking lot’
Our claim is that the parce que construct in (1) belongs to a special type of syntac-
tic construction which we will call the context focussing parce que con-
struction (cfpc). The main goal of our paper is to provide a description of the
use of parce que, introducing cfpc based on syntactic contexts as well as prag-
matic functions. Besides this descriptive goal, we would like to address some theo-
retical issues. What is the exact status of this construction? In which kind of inher-
itance network is it involved?
The paper is organized in the following way: in Section 1, we investigate the
properties of cfpc, concluding that it is a specific syntactic pattern, in which the
parce que clause is not licensed by any grammatical category or construction1. In
Section 2, we distinguish two pragmatic subtypes of this pattern. In Section 3, we
show that this pattern is specific to spoken language in that it cannot be syntacti-
cally reduced to the insertion of a footnote, as found in written styles. We conclude
in Section 4 by addressing theoretical issues. This study is based on examples ex-
tracted from an authentic corpus of spoken French. The corpus consists of a
250,000 word transcription of recordings of spontaneous language in various nat-
ural environments (interviews, dialogs, narratives, etc.). More than 200 examples
of cfpc constructs have been extracted.
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

1. cfpc as a specific syntactic pattern

1.1 cfpc is an instance of non subordinate conjunction + clause

Let us consider as a prototypical example of CFPC the parce que clause in example
(1) repeated below as (4):
(4) le roi parce que le roi est très aimé en Thaïlande je crois que j’en ai parlé
avant le roi est arrivé[…]... à leur faire comprendre que cette culture était
très en dent de scie (Thailande)
As mentioned above, in this use, the parce que clause conveys backgrounded infor-
mation, out of the main line of the discourse, by means of which the speaker builds
a relevant “common ground” for the addressee. We can first show this CFPC as an
instance of non subordinate parce que clause. The non subordinative use of clauses
introduced by conjunctions has been observed in situations where the conjoined
clause follows the main clause:
(5) c’est une prof de SVT parce que l’an dernier j’ai fait un stage avec elle
‘She is a teacher of Natural science (I can assert that) ‘cos last year I had a
training session with her.’
In this pattern, the parce que clause does not express a cause of the fact asserted in
the main clause, but an argument in favor of the assertion made by the main clause.
One can verify that this construct has no properties characteristic of the subordi-
nate use, and thus cannot be analyzed as a syntactic adjunct in the main clause
(Debaisieux 2002).
a. This clause cannot be clefted:
(6) * c’est parce que l’an dernier j’ai fait un stage avec elle que c’est une prof de svt
b. It cannot be an answer to a why question:
(7) Pourquoi c’est une prof de svt? * parce que l’an dernier j’ai fait un stage
avec elle
c. It cannot be modified by a scope adverbial:
(8) * c’est une prof de svt surtout parce que l’an dernier j’ai fait un stage avec elle
d. It cannot be preposed to the main clause:
(9) * parce que l’an dernier j’ai fait un stage avec elle c’est une prof de svt
e. It cannot be conjoined with the main clause with anaphoric cela ‘that’:
(10) * c’est un prof de svt et cela parce que j’ai fait un stage avec elle
Constructions and context 

It is easy to check that the inserted parce que clause in (4) has the same behavior
and thus cannot be analyzed as an adjunct subordinate clause. But other proper-
ties show that the pattern is a special case of insubordinate parce que clause.

1.2 Specific properties of CFPC

1.2.1 Formal properties


a. Free insertion within the “main clause”
The non subordinate parce que clause generally follows the main clause. It is unu-
sual to find it inserted in the main clause:
(11) ??c’est une prof parce que l’an dernier j’ai fait un stage avec elle une prof de
svt
On the contrary, the backgrounded CFPC can be freely inserted in the main clause
(12), where the insertion occurs after a fragmented word:
(12) il a dit maintenant tu vas mettre la mitr- parce que tu sais c’est pas tout le
monde qui sait mettre une mitrailleuse en marche euh tu vas mettre la mi-
trailleuse là-bas (BIR. 7, 5)
‘He says now you are to set the mach- (ine gun) ‘cos you know not every-
body knows how to set up a machine gun hum you are to set the machine
gun over there.’
We know that “random” insertions of adverbial adjuncts functioning as epistemic
parentheticals or metalinguistic comments are also possible, but interestingly
enough, these insertions are not entirely free but grammatically constrained
(Espinal 1991; Marandin, 1999): they occur roughly at the boundary of any major
constituent. No such constraints govern our CFPC insertions. They occur as soon
as the speaker considers that they are pragmatically required for the processing of
the message.
b. Prosodic pattern
Martin (1978) and Morel & Danon-Boileau (1998) describe in detail the specific
prosodic contour which is observed in parenthetical constructs inserted in a
“main” construction, whether they are bare or introduced by a grammatical de-
vice. We should point out first that the parce que clause in (5) shows the regular
assertive contour of main clauses with Low F0 on the last accented syllable. On the
contrary, CFPC has a specific F0 high, spread over the structure (level 2 on a scale
of 4), and shows a flattened shape and fastened speech flow at the onset. All these
features iconically contribute a backgrounding effect. The CFPC in our examples
follows this general pattern. In cases where CFPC is postponed to and not inserted
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

in the main clause (see Example 16), it shows the same prosodic pattern, and the
effect will be one of afterthought.
c. Specific syntactic form
The iconic backgrounding effect of the prosodic pattern is reinforced in many
cases by other segmental iconic devices. We observe – in bold in examples (13)
and (14) – lexical reiterations with extra syntactic position in the main clause.
Within CFPC these elements are not perceived as disfluencies2: they help to estab-
lish a kind of natural bracketing of the parenthetical insertion. If we drop the in-
serted CFPC, as in (13′) or (14′), the repeated bold lexical items would appear as
mere performance phenomena without any structural function. As a consequence,
the syntactic form of the whole pattern is not exactly the sum of two well formed
sentences, one being inserted in the other.
(13) au moment où il arrive donc / ce qui est marrant bon le directeur / parce
que c’est le directeur qui fait passer tout ça c’est lui qui supervise tout / le
directeur il lui dit / vous êtes prêt (ALI. Cas.)
‘At the time he arrives thus what is funny (is that) well the director – ‘cos it
is the director who checks all this it is him who supervises everything –
the director says to him: are you ready?
(13′) ? bon le directeur le directeur il lui dit / vous êtes prêt
(14)
bien entendu dans son système il fallait que les masses jouissent d’avantages
qu’elles n’avaient pas eus auparavant/ donc le problème du logement /
parce que l’Empereur Napoléon III est un empereur de la vie quotidienne /
un homme qui s’intéresse de très près aux réalités de la vie de tous les jours/
ce problème donc il fallait qu’il le prenne à bras le corps (GUE. Cas.)
‘ Needless to say in his system the population had to benefit of privileges
which they didn’t have before so the issue of accommodation –‘cos the
Emperor Napoleon the IIId is an Emperor of everyday life a man who is
deeply concerned with true everyday life (problems) – this problem thus
he wanted to fix it
(14′) ? bien entendu dans son système il fallait que les masses jouissent d’avantages
qu’elles n’avaient pas eus auparavant/ donc le problème du logement ce
problème donc il fallait qu’il le prenne à bras le corps
d. Lack of isotopy constraints
The utterances forming the main line of a discourse are integrated in larger dis-
course units like narrative or argumentative patterns. Such discursive pragmatic
organizations can be considered as particular instances of a more general prag-
matic pattern: communicative action + possible continuation. The continuation
Constructions and context 

link has some formal counterparts in what can be called default discourse agree-
ment rules. Two well known instances of these rules are tense concord and default
pronominalisation in the case of coreference. The CFPC does not conform to these
tendencies: cases of free tense sequence (present tense sait inserted in a main line
pattern with past tense in [15]) or absence of default pronominalisation (repeti-
tion of le directeur in (13) or of problème in [14]) can be observed:
(15) donc en Allemagne j’ai rencontré des gens qui travaillaient pour les palé-
ontologues/ qui étaient des amateurs mais qui savaient très bien travailler/
parce que le paléontologue il sait très bien étudier une pièce mais il ne sait
pas l’extraire et la restaurer et la remettre sur gange si elle a été abîmée tout
ça / c’est comme ça que j’ai connu le gisement de X (PAUL. Cas.)
‘Thus in Germany I met some people who were working for paleontolo-
gists who where amateurs but who knew very well how to do the things
because the paleontologist he knows very well how to study a sample but he
doesn’t know how to extract it and to restore it if it has been damaged all that
it is like this that I got acquainted with the excavations of X.’
This situation is best understood if we assume that the parce que clause is not part
of the current discourse sequence and functions at another level that can be named
the regulative level. Utterances at this level have the function of regulating the
main organization of the ongoing discourse and not of pushing it up. Consequent-
ly, we can assume that the grounds for establishing reference are different at the
two levels. In (15), there is no possible coreference between the two occurrences of
the NP based on the lexical head paléontologue. The first occurrence refers to pale-
ontologists involved in the excavations which took place in Germany mentioned
in the narrative main line of discourse, whereas the second occurrence refers to
the general class of paleontologists and is used to provide encyclopedic informa-
tion at the regulative level.
e. Autonomous illocutionary force and specific groundedness of information
This difference of levels can be noticed in the enunciative domain as well as in the
discursive one. The main clause and the parce que clause belong to two distinct
enunciative grounds as exemplified in (16) below. The enunciator of the main
clause (elle disait…) is a character of the narrative (the grandmother), whereas the
enunciative ground of the inserted parce que clause is the speaker itself: the CFPC
provides a piece of cultural context ignored by the addressee and necessary for the
correct interpretation of the default invited inference of the question: the grand-
daughter is not a good pupil – as one could infer from “pass the examination at
twelve” – but a bad one (twelve was indeed the default age for the Certificate in
those times).
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

(16) alors ma grand mère elle allait voir l’institutrice et elle disait /est-ce que
vous pensez que elle pourra passer le certificat d’études à 12 ans/ parce que
c’était pas à 14 ans c’était à 12 ans et tous les soirs elle regardait tu as bien
fait tes devoirs tout (MICH. Cas.)
‘Then my grandma she went to see the school teacher and she said: do you
think she will be able to pass the Certificate at 12 ‘cos it was not at 14 (as
now) but at 12 and every evening she was checking: have you done your
homework everything?’
f. No grammatical relation nor category involved
All these formal properties could be summed up in saying that the CFPC is a clause
which is inserted in an utterance as an utterance on its own, with its specific illocu-
tionary force and communicative grounding, without any grammatical link or
constraint regarding the main utterance. Apparently there is a dependency relation
between the main and the inserted utterance, in the sense that the CFPC needs a
main structure to appear. But what is the exact nature of this dependency?
Consider for instance example (16). How is the CFPC licensed? If we take as
the main clause the first part of the utterance, all the syntactic tests used to dem-
onstrate syntactic dependency will fail. The only argument for making elle disait
the main clause is that, if we drop it, the sequence becomes unacceptable:
(17) ?? alors ma grand mère elle allait voir l’institutrice parce que c’était pas à 14 ans
c’était à 12 ans et tous les soirs elle regardait tu as bien fait tes devoirs tout
Does this test prove that the CFPC is syntactically licensed by the verb or the CP elle
disait…? In fact, there is an alternative way to describe the situation. We could say
that the CFPC is pragmatically or discursively licensed by the previous discourse.
CFPC is not dependent on the main clause as a grammatical structure, but as a
meaningful piece of discourse.
One could argue against this idea of “discourse dependency” by saying that in
all the examples above there are arguments in favour of grouping the parce que
clause with a specific utterance. For example, in (16), as the et prohibits the group-
ing of the parce que clause with the following one, it seems that the only possible
grouping is with elle disait est-ce que vous pensez qu’elle va pouvoir passer le certifi-
cat à 12 ans? Consequently, in such cases, the licensing pragmatic category would
not be a discourse pattern but a specific illocutionary act in this pattern. We as-
sume, nevertheless, that “discourse” licensing is the right analysis. There are in-
deed examples in which there is no mark of grouping with the preceding or the
following clause:
Constructions and context 

(18) S1 oui parce qu’il suffit qu’un bouton soit défectueux et puis ça marche pas
S2 oui tu peux avoir une panne d’électrique parce que tout est commandé
électriquement maintenant ou avec des motorisations des télécommandes
un tas de trucs il peut y avoir des systèmes qui fonctionnent pas
‘Yes you can have an electricity failure – ‘cos it is all electrically controlled
now or with additional engines or remote control a lot of devices – it can
happen that some systems do not operate
In such cases the CFPC should be analysed as floating above the whole discourse
and not attached to a specific utterance. Even pragmatically, the grouping appears
impossible: the content of the parce que clause provides a relevant background for
the first utterance as well as for the second one.
What CFPC needs in order to be licensed is the production of a piece of dis-
course, whatever its grammatical form, or even a mere communicative action on
the part of one participant in the interaction, for which it will provide, in a back-
grounded position, required contextual information. This communicative action
can be an illocutionary act conveyed by any kind of linguistic form or even a sig-
nificant communicative behavior accomplished by the participant. What licenses
CFPC is the discourse as a whole and not a grammatical category.
A good example for what we have called pragmatic or discursive dependency
can be given by an occurrence of CFPC without any possible grammatical basis of
insertion. The situation is an interaction between three speakers. L1 is the owner
of a farm who speaks only French. L2 and L3 are farm workers and native speakers
of Portuguese. L2 is almost bilingual, L3 almost monolingual. L1 explains the tasks
to be done in French to L2 and L3. L2, without having said anything in French to
L1 to confirm that he has understood his message, speaks in Portuguese to L3,
translating the message of L1, then he turns to L1 and utters:
(19) parce qu’en français il comprend encore pas tout
‘cos in French he still does not understand everything
The parce que clause inserted in the interaction cannot be related to any gram-
matical structure: it is inserted in the interaction and depends, as an explanatory
background, on the communicative behavior of translation.
This description allows for a coherent analysis of the formal properties of
CFPC: the lack of grammatical dependency explains the failure of syntactic de-
pendency tests, the pragmatic dependency implied by the foreground- back-
ground relationship explains the need for a previous piece of information for
CFPC to be licensed.
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

1.2.2 Pragmatic function


CFPC as a specific form of “discourse” dependent clause is associated with an in-
structional pragmatic function that can be informally phrased as this:
“Take into account preferably the piece of contextual information conveyed by
CFPC in computing the meaning of the main illocutionary act (or communicative
behavior) and in making the relevant discourse inferences.”

“Preferably” means that this piece of information is focused on within all the pos-
sible contextual information available to the addressee. In many cases, it appears
that CFPC provides a verbalization of missing contextual information, which is
often underlined by metacommunicative comments by the speaker (in bold)3:
(20) elle était venue donc au clavier parce qu’elle voulait chanter / parce que c’est
une fana du chant j’ai oublié de vous le dire / seulement le problème c’est
que c’est une fille qui a une voix un peu d’opéra (ALI. Cas.)
‘She turned to the piano because she wanted to sing ‘cos she is a fan of sing-
ing I forgot to tell you…’ but the problem is that she has a voice for opera.’
It is worth pointing out that the conventionalized semantic value of parce que as a lexi-
cal unit can be maintained in this use. We are not to consider that parce que has been
reanalyzed as a kind of discourse particle. The role of parce que as a link between main
and backgrounded utterances parallels its grammatical role relating two facts conveyed
respectively by a main and a subordinate clause as in the first occurrence of the parce
que clause in (20). The basic conventionalized meaning of the preposition par: à travers
‘through’ can be used to describe it in both cases. Informally, we can phrase it as: “The
speech (or communicative) action associated with the main utterance is fully un-
derstandable through (à travers) the speech act introduced by parce que.”
The causal value of subordinating parce que in [P (main clause) parce que Q
Clause] can in turn be obtained through the basic meaning, bearing in mind that
the effect of the subordinating relation is to restrict the semantic scope of the parce
que clause to the interpretation as a fact of the content of the main clause: P is a fact
through fact Q (= fact Q is the cause of fact P).
The à travers value is conventionally associated to parce que, as shown by the
fact that the CFPC introduced by other conjunctions has a different behavior. For
instance, bien que introduces a clause expressing a correction to a preceding asser-
tion as a backgrounded afterthought:
(21) j’étais pas trop j’ai jamais été trop système scolaire + euh bien que je j’aime
bien quand il y a des règles quand même hein – (BOR-R00PRI003)
‘I was not I never was too (favorable to) strict school regulations –well al-
though I like it when there are rules anyway.’
Constructions and context 

This mitigating function can be linked to the conventionalized meaning of the


conjunction bien que ‘in spite of ’ applied to the relationship between the two illo-
cutionary forces of the utterances, that is informally: je suis pas scolaire du tout is a
true assertion “in spite” of the truth of j’aime bien quand il y a des règles. As we may
expect, the formal properties confirm this pragmatic function. A parenthetic in-
sertion of this bien que clause sounds very strange:
(22) ? j’étais pas trop euh bien que je j’aime bien quand il y a des règles quand même
hein – j’ai jamais été trop système scolaire + je suis pas scolaire du tout +
On the contrary, a CFPC introduced by parce que would be perfectly possible in
this position:
(23) j’étais pas trop euh parce que je j’aime pas quand il y a trop de règles hein
– j’ai jamais été trop système scolaire +
There could be a pragmatic explanation for this distribution. In order to provide a
correction with bien que, the speaker needs the corrected assertion to be com-
pleted. On the other hand, contextual background information can be introduced
by parce que as soon as the ongoing communicative act has begun to be processed.
The conclusion is that, if the syntax of the pattern is kind of iconic, the morpho-
logical marking is achieved through lexemes with conventionalized meanings.

2. Pragmatic subtypes of CFPC

We can distinguish two main subtypes of CFPC according to their pragmatic function.
a. Regulation of the interaction by framing
The CFPC focuses or makes explicit some pieces of background information,
thanks to which the addressee will be able to make the required inferences to reach
a coherent interpretation of the whole message. In interactions about common-
place topics, the inserted piece is simply missing from the common ground. Con-
sider for instance (20) above, where the speaker explicitly points it out (‘I have
forgotten to tell you that’). In more technical discussions involving experts and
non-experts, the experts use CFPC in order to bring encyclopedic knowledge in the
common ground. For instance, in example (24), the expert must first emphasize
the status of patient for a person who has no sensation of pain, which is against the
audience’s commonsense expectations. Then, the use of pauvres ‘unfortunate’ to
qualify them is also justified by the medical pessimistic prognosis conveyed by the
second CFPC.
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

(24) il y a bon de très rares cas mais ça existe quand même de malades parce que
ce sont vraiment des malades qui n’ont dès la naissance aucune sensation de
douleur et ces pauvres enfin ces pauvres enfants souvent parce qu ‘ils ne viv-
ent pas très longtemps dans la plupart des cas sont complètement déformés
(PRIE.7, 5)
’Well there are very rare cases – but it happens anyway – of ill people – ‘cos
they are actually ill people – who from their birth on have no sensation of
pain and these unfortunate –well these unfortunate children –’cos they do
not live very long in most of the cases – are totally crippled.’
b. Regulation by reframing
In those cases, a coherent and apparently relevant interpretation can be reached by
the addressee within the frame of what he thinks is the current common ground.
But this is not the interpretation intended by the speaker, whose ground is differ-
ent. So, in order to guide the addressee to this interpretation, the speaker, aware of
the gap between the “grounds,” must block the undesirable inferences which could
lead to the wrong interpretation. The reframing is achieved by means of the CFPC,
which reestablishes a suitable common ground. This situation is found in (16)
above: the wrong default ground is that the examination is taken at age 14, the
reframed ground is that the examination is taken at age 12. In (25), the default
ground is that you do not buy a driving license but that you have to take (and pass)
a test to get your driving license. If the speaker wants to block the unintended in-
ference that the father acted against the law, he must reframe the narrative by add-
ing in the CFPC: “there (in that country) you do not pass the license, you buy it” to
get the proper ground.
(25) je pense que mon père a su me donner une certaine conscience ce qui fait
que dès que je suis retourné j’ai eu mon permis /enfin mon père m’a acheté
le permis / parce que là-bas tu passes pas le permis tu l’achètes / donc mon
père m’a acheté mon permis de voiture il m’a prêté une voiture (JAL. Cas.)
‘I think that my father succeeded in giving me moral concerns. It is the rea-
son why as soon as I went back home I got my driving license well my father
bought me the license –‘cos there you do not need to take a driving test you
just buy the licence so my father bought the license for me he lent me a car.’

3. CFPC does not have the structure of an inserted footnote

We said in the introduction that patterns like CFPC play the same role in spontane-
ous speech as footnotes in written text. This is roughly true but there are some
important differences between the two devices that are to be pointed out. Footnotes,
Constructions and context 

and even notes inserted in brackets or balloons in electronic texts, are autonomous
semantic and syntactic units inserted in the main text. The main text remains a se-
quence of well formed sentences if the notes are removed. From a semantic point of
view, the notes help to understand the main text, but even without the notes, it is a
coherent piece of discourse. The parenthetical oral structures we are studying con-
form in many cases to this pattern but they may also interact more closely with ei-
ther the syntax or the semantics of the main discourse, as already mentioned in
Section 1. We will address in this section further cases where the CFPC contributes
either to the syntactic cohesion or to the coherence of the utterance it is inserted in.
(26) below is perfectly acceptable as a discourse pattern. But if we remove the
inserted CFPC, as in (26′) it appears that the result is agrammatical, due to the pres-
ence of et alors. Whereas the whole discourse pattern is widely attested in sponta-
neous speech, the reduced one sounds very strange and unusual.
(26) les Espagnols alors quand on voulait les faire enrager parce qu’alors les
Espagnols eux ils étaient flegmatiques ils restaient des journées entières
allongés dans des salles de classes à rien faire et alors pour les faire en-
rager on leur disait Arriba España Viva Franco (RAIM. Cas.)
The Spanish then when we wanted to upset them –‘cos you know the
Spanish were very phlegmatic they stayed the whole day long lying in
classrooms, without doing anything – and then to upset them we said to
them: Arriba España, Viva Franco.’
(26′) ? les Espagnols alors quand on voulait les faire enrager et alors
pour les faire enrager on leur disait Arriba España Viva Franco
One way to describe this situation is to say that the alors and the et in (26) are not
licensed by any category in the construction underlying the main utterance, but by
the discourse CFPC pattern as a whole (the repeated alors function as iconic brack-
ets and the et (alors) marks the transition between the background and the main
line of the discourse). It is then expected that, in the absence of one essential part
of the pattern, those marks should be absent. We arrive at the conclusion that the
syntax of a discourse pattern may interact with the syntactic patterns or the con-
structions included in it to create new kinds of syntactic forms. These blended
structures are certainly ungrammatical as clause constructions but perfectly
acceptable and functional as discourse patterns. Another example of this phenom-
enon is provided by (27):
(27) en Algérie par exemple les panneaux publicitaires /rares panneaux parce
que c’est un pays où la publicité n’est pas aussi dominante qu’au Maroc mais
les rares panneaux publicitaires sont écrits en arabe (PHU. 8, 5)
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

‘In Algeria for example the very few advertisement posts very few ‘cos it is
a country where advertising is not so developed as in Morocco but the
very few ad posts are written in Arab.’
(27′) ? en Algérie par exemple les panneaux publicitaires rares panneaux mais les
rares panneaux publicitaires sont écrits en arabe (PHU. 8, 5)
Here the reduced version is also agrammatical. But its syntax can be explained at
the discourse pattern level in the full version. The lexical repetition of panneaux
marks the bracketing of the CFPC and the mais is licensed as a mark of a “rhetori-
cal” relation of contrast between the content of the parenthetical and an element
of the main line (there is less advertisement in Algeria than in Morocco but it is
more remarkable, because it is written in Arabic).
Example (28) shows a more complex case of interaction between background
and main line. The parenthetical contributes not only to the syntax of the whole
pattern, but also to its coherence. There is no means in the reduced version to reach
a coherent interpretation. In the full version it is clear that S1 wants to say that, for
the Mexicans, French people were perhaps not heroes, but at least much more pop-
ular than Americans. In the reduced version it is impossible to obtain this interpre-
tation, as the only possible coreference for the pronoun ils is with les français, (the
preposition vis a vis blocks the coreference with les americains). So we get the
wrong interpretation that in comparison with Americans, the French were not very
popular. What allows the correct interpretation in the full version is that ils can be
coreferent with les américains, introduced in rhematic position by the CFPC.
(28) S1 mais là vraiment les français pour les mexicains c’était
S2 hum des héros
S1 non peut-être pas jusque là mais bon / vis à vis des américains parce
qu’on avait les américains aussi ben ils ont pas ramassé un tel succès
‘but then frankly the French for the Mexicans they were… well heroes
… non I wont go so far but well compared to the Americans –‘cos we
had Americans also – well they didn’t get so much popularity
? S1 mais là vraiment les français pour les mexicains c’était
S2 hum des héros
S1 non peut-être pas jusque là mais bon / vis à vis des américains ben ils
ont pas ramassé un tel succès
Constructions and context 

4. The status of CFPC in the CG framework

Our description leads to the following conclusions:


a. CFPC is a construction in the broad sense, that is a conventional association of
form and meaning.
b. It appears to be licensed by a communicative pattern: foreground –background
as a whole. As it is impossible to predict the grammatical or even linguistic
composition of the foreground, which can be any kind of communicative be-
havior, we are led to the conclusion that CFPC is pragmatically licensed by the
communicative pattern, as a device allowing the speaker to focus on the con-
textual pieces of information he thinks the addressee needs to get the more
relevant interpretation of what is being communicated.
This leads us to address two questions: what is the exact nature of such a discourse
pattern and what kind of inheritance network is it involved in?
The basic components of the form of such patterns are not limited to linguistic
elements: categories or constructions, but extend to “communicative behavior”
recognized as such by the participants in the interaction (Berrendonner 2004).
This behavior may be performed through utterances or significant attitudes. The
utterances may be based on grammatical constructions or merely on paralinguis-
tic forms (interjections, discourse particles, onomatopoeia). The constructions
that put these forms in relation can be analyzed as functionally distinct groupings
of communicative or discourse units. The kind of grouping we have analyzed in
this paper can be labeled as a [discourse – background] pattern, or even more
generally [communicative behavior – background]. What should be pointed out is
that grammatical devices are used to specify the relationship between the back-
ground and the main line of discourse. These grammatical devices such as the
conjunction parce que are therefore multifunctional: on the one hand, they can be
involved in specifying grammatical relations in constructions headed by a gram-
matical category. For instance, parce que specifies a grammatical relation verb-
adjunct as a cause-consequence one. On the other hand, they specify, with the
same conventionalized meaning, the relation between two communicative behav-
iors in an interaction. As we have seen, parce que instructs the addressee to use the
information conveyed by the communicative unit it introduces as a “path” through
which the meaning of the “nucleus” communicative behavior is to be reached.
Such a situation can be generalized to many grammatical morphemes. Insights
in this direction can be found in the literature. CFPC recalls the discourse
patterns pointed out by Mithun (2005), rejoining observations by other linguists
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

(Goethals 2002; Miller 1998; Deulofeu 1999; Debaisieux 2004; Debaisieux &
Deulofeu 2004; Hopper 1988; Iwasaki & Ono 2002; Ono & Thompson 1995):
In a number of languages the prosodic, morphological, and semantic cues that
might characterize the sentence do not always converge. Dependent clause mark-
ers appear pervasively in what seem, on prosodic and semantic grounds, to be
independent sentences. A closer look shows that these markers are being used to
signal pragmatic dependency among larger elements in discourse. The markers of
dependency serve several recurring functions in discourse. The Yup’ik Participial
and Barbareno nominalized sentences contribute background, descriptive, sub-
sidiary, explanatory, or evaluative information, information that does not move
narrative forward. The Yup’ik Subordinative and the Hualapai switch-reference
markers signal textual cohesion, marking statements that together compose a
larger discourse unit. (Mithun 2005)

The common observation is that grammatical units can be involved in patterns


that go beyond the scope of sentence grammar. But the case of CFPC helps us to
generalize Mithun’s conclusions: not only discourse but interaction patterns are
involved in CFPC. Our conclusion will be that these constructs support the broad
conception of constructions currently assumed, that any kind of pairing between
form and meaning should be considered as a construction, even if the form re-
duces to a prosodic pattern and the meaning to a broad pragmatic function (Croft
2001). Our claim is that this comprehensive view of construction must even be
extended to non verbal communicative behavior if we want to encompass all the
possible forms of CFPC.
One strong result that emerges from these conclusions is that grammatical
signs like conjunctions are not only used to establish relationships between other
signs but between signs and indexical aspects of human communication: gestures,
inferences that are drawn from indexes. The challenge will be to find an adequate
formalism to integrate the grammar of indexes into the grammar of signs.
As for the inheritance networks, CFPC inherits its formal properties from two
more general patterns. First, as it responds negatively to all diagnostic tests which
could be used to show its syntactic integration within the main clause, it must be
analysed as an instance of “supplementive clause construction” and not as an in-
stance of Head-Adjunct pattern. Second, it also inherits properties from a more
general bare parenthesis construction (bpc), exemplified in the italics part of
the following utterance:
(29) et après tu ouvres les feuillets comme un livre et avec la lumière du soleil
il faut absolument qu’il y ait le soleil + il y a une ombre portée de la colonne
vertébrale qui te dit que là il y a un poisson ou autre chose
Constructions and context 

‘And after you open the layers like book pages and with (the help of) the
sun light –it is absolutely necessary that there be sun – there appears the
cast shadow of a spinal column, which tells you that there is a (fossil) fish
or something.’
CFPC seems to fulfill the same metacommunicative function as the bpc parentheti-
cal pattern in (29). Indeed a parce que could very well be inserted in (29). The main
difference is that what is achieved by means of the iconic device of mere insertion
of an independent utterance in another as in (29) is achieved in CFPC through a
conventionalized meaning of the morpheme parce que related to its canonical use
as a causal subordinator. As a consequence, the presence of parce que, as we have
seen above, narrows the scope of pragmatic functions that the bpc can fulfill.
The question remains whether cfpc could be put together with the large class
of parentheticals including epistemic parentheticals (Thompson & Mulac, 1991),
or apparent dependant clause constructions which acquire interpersonal meaning
(Traugott 1989). This important question goes beyond the scope of our paper but
we want to point out differences supporting the analysis of parentheticals and pa-
renthesis like constructions (CFPC and BPC) as distinct structures. As mentioned
above, on formal grounds, parentheticals are clearly related to a specific clause in
which they are inserted at a constituent boundary (Marandin 1999). CFPC and BPC
are inserted more freely inside an utterance, but cannot appear in front of it. On
semantic grounds, parentheticals elaborate the content of the proposition con-
veyed by the utterance, modifying its epistemic status or adding subjective values
to it. On the contrary, CFPC is totally external to this content. The CFPC of example
(15) is a good case in point. It doesn’t modify in any way the semantics of the ut-
terance it is inserted in, but contributes to providing the common ground with
which the addressee can elaborate an appropriate contextual interpretation of it
and specially of the word travailler: it helps anticipate a request of clarification
from the addressee about the exact role of the paleontologist “assistants” (des gens
qui travaillaient pour les paléontologues). The distinction between parentheticals
and parenthesis insertions, of which CFPC is an instance, seems descriptively justi-
fied, even if the line between the discourse and metadiscourse levels is not always
easy to draw.

Notes

* We are very grateful to the anonymous reviewer whose comments helped us to improve a
first version of this paper.
 Henri-José Deulofeu and Jeanne-Marie Debaisieux

1. On the contrary, the internal shape of the parce que clause is more grammatically con-
strained. Even if we can find more complex patterns than in adjunct parce que clauses, they are
all based on a tensed clause. In (13) and (14) for instance, the CFPC is composed of a juxtaposi-
tion of IPs, instead of the coordination of CPs found in subordinate parce que clauses. We will
not address the analysis of the internal structure of the parce que clause (Debaisieux 2002).
2. The same kind of pattern has been found in other languages. For example in spoken Ger-
man (Stoltenburg 2003) or Finnish (Duvallon 2006).
3. Notice that in this piece of discourse a parenthetical parce que clause is combined with a
preceeding subordinate adjunct parce que clause (parce qu’elle voulait chanter).

References

Berrendonner, Alain (2004). Grammaire de l’écrit vs Grammaire de l’oral: le jeu des composantes
micro- et macro-syntaxiques. In A. Rabatel, (Ed.) Interactions orales en contexte didactique
(249–264). Lyon: Presses universitaires de Lyon.
Croft, William (2001). Radical Construction Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Debaisieux, Jeanne-Marie (2002). Le fonctionnement de parce que en français contemporain:
étude quantitative. In C. Pusch & W. Raible (Eds.), Romanistische Korpuslinguistik – Ro-
mance Corpus linguistics, (349–362). Tübingen: Gunter Narr Verlag.
Debaisieux, Jeanne-Marie (2004). Les conjonctions de subordination: mots de grammaire ou mots
du discours? Le cas de parce que. Revue de Sémantique et de Pragmatique, 15/16, 51–67.
Debaisieux, Jeanne-Marie & José Deulofeu (2004). Fonctionnement microsyntaxique de modi-
fieur et fonctionnement macrosyntaxique en parataxe des constructions introduites par
que et parce que en français parlé, avec extension au cas de perché et che en italien parlé. In
F. Leoni, F. Cutugno, M. Pettorino, & R. Savy (Eds.), Parlato Italiano in cd-rom, Atti del
Convegno nazionale di Napoli, 13–15 febbraio 2003, CD multimediale (isbn 88–7092–
238–3). Napoli: M. D’Auria Editore.
Deulofeu, José (1999). Questions de méthode dans la description morphosyntaxique de l’élément
que en français contemporain. Recherches sur le français parlé, 15, 77–101.
Espinal, Teresa (1991). The representation of disjunct constituents. Language, 67–4, 726–762.
Goethals, Pierre (2002). Las conjunciones causales explicativas españolas como, ya que, pues, y
porque. Un estudio semiótico-linguístico. Paris & Leuven: Peeters.
Hopper, Paul (1988). Emergent Grammar and the a Priori Grammar Postulate. In Deborah Tan-
nen (Ed.), Linguistics in context: Connecting observation and understanding (117–134).
Norwood NJ: Ablex.
Huddleston, Rodney &. Geoffrey K. Pullum (2002). The Cambridge Grammar of the English
Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Iwasaki, Shoichi & Tsuyoshi Ono (2001). Sentence in Spontaneous Spoken Japanese Language.
In J. Bybee & M. Noonan (Eds.), Complex sentences in Grammar and Discourse (176–202).
Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Kay, Paul (1997). Pragmatic Aspects of Grammatical Constructions. Online: http://www.icsi.ber-
keley.edu/~kay/cg.prag.pdf, p. 3.
Marandin, Jean-Marie (1998). Grammaire de l’incidence. Online: http://www.llf.cnrs.fr/Gens/
Marandin/GrammaireDeL_incidence.htm.
Constructions and context 

Martin, Philippe (1978). Questions de phonosyntaxe et de phonosémantique en français. Lin-


guisticae investigationes, 2:1, 93–126. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Miller, Jim & Regina Weinert (1998). Spontaneous spoken language: syntax and discourse. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Mithun, Marianne (2005). On the assumption of the sentence as the basic unit of syntactic
structure, Linguistic diversity and language theories. Unpublished manuscript.
Morel, Mary-Annick & Laurent Danon-Boileau (1998). Grammaire de l’intonation, Paris-Gap:
Ophrys.
Ono, Tsuyoshi & Sandra A. Thompson (1995). What can conversation tell us about syntax? In Philip
W. Davis (Ed.), Alternative linguistics (213–272). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: Benjamins.
Stoltenburg, Benjamin (2003). Parenthesen im gesprochenen Deutsch. InList, 34. Online: http://
www.unipotsdam.de/u/inlist/issues/34/index.htm.
Thompson, Sandra & Anthony Mullac (1991). A quantitative perspective on the grammaticali-
zation of Epistemic Parentheticals in English. In E. Traugott & B. Heine (Eds.), Approaches
to grammaticalization, Vol. II, (313–329). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Traugott, Elisabeth & Bernd Heine (Eds.) (1991). Approaches to grammaticalization, Vol. II.
Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Representing contextual factors
in language change
Between frames and constructions

Mirjam Fried
Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague

1. Introduction

It is accepted both within cognitively based approaches to semantic structure


(e.g. Fillmore 1982, 1984, 1986; Geeraerts 1992, 1993; Cuyckens, Dirven & Taylor
2003) and within dialogical approaches to language analysis (e.g. Linell 1998) that
speakers’ expressive needs, together with general cultural understanding and spe-
cific contextual clues, participate in negotiating the meaning of a given piece of
discourse. The dynamic character of language use also presents this question nec-
essarily as one of variation and change; this dimension has been explored in a
particular strand of grammaticalization studies that focus on various aspects of
the interaction between codified semantic structure (‘lexical meaning’), broad
thematic and cultural context, and recurring morphosyntactic patterns as giving
shape, collectively, to a newly emerging grammatical structure (e.g. Bybee, Perkins
& Pagliuca 1994; Bisang 1998; Hopper 1998; Traugott 2003, 2008; Harris 2003;
Wiemer 2004; Wiemer & Bisang 2004).
A question that is yet to be taken up concerns the way(s) in which those com-
plex interactions and their dynamic nature can be systematically captured and fur-
ther illuminated by applying a particular grammatical model. With this general
goal in mind, I will present a small-scale corpus-based case study of a lexico-gram-
matical change that will illustrate what types of context may enter conventional
linguistic patterning. By examining specific aspects of language change, my focus
will be on representing a shift in speakers’ grammatical knowledge, its relationship
to recurring semantic and pragmatic constraints and their gradual reorganization.
On the surface, this seems to be a straightforward enough goal: in function-
ally oriented approaches, it is taken as self-evident that linguistic expressions are
used in ‘context’ and that certain aspects of the ‘context’ may find their way into
 Mirjam Fried

the grammatical properties of a linguistic expression. The task for a grammarian,


then, is to articulate such a connection precisely and explicitly. Upon further re-
flection, though, it becomes far from clear what exactly we may mean by ‘context’
and what exactly it is we can or ought to be explicit about. A glance at the rich lit-
erature on pragmatics in general (traditionally a primary domain of addressing
contextual issues) and on the connection between pragmatics and grammar sug-
gests that there are several ways in which the notion of context is understood and
incorporated in linguistic analysis.
One set of contextual factors revolves around issues of usage, i.e. the broadly
conceived pragmatic conditions, including the question of textual distribution, so-
cio-cultural grounding, genres, etc. This understanding of context is traditionally
associated with the field of pragmatics and usually has paid little attention to gram-
matical structure. For grammarians, on the other hand, reference to context has
typically meant concerns with managing information flow and the configuration of
discourse participants, whether within a clause or within a larger stretch of utter-
ances. Contextual issues are thus discussed in terms of regular correlations between
grammatical structure and information structure, the latter articulated in terms of
specific discourse roles. More recently, though, the notion of context has also been
used to mean the grammatical environment in which a given word or expression
occurs, either preferentially or exclusively. This concept of linguistic ‘context’ goes
back to Fillmore’s observations about the combinatorial restrictions on individual
lexical items when they enter syntactic phrases and sentences (Fillmore 1982, 1989;
Fillmore, Kay & O’Connor 1988) and has been also the cornerstone of Croft’s ap-
proach to defining grammatical categories (Croft 1991, 2001).
Since the present study takes the grammarian’s perspective, the point of depar-
ture will be the syntagmatic context. However, it will quickly become apparent that
other contextual factors must be worked in as well, echoing Fillmore’s early argu-
ments for incorporating discourse-based descriptions in our generalizations about
individual lexico-grammatical patterns (Fillmore 1974/1981, 1982). I will docu-
ment and argue that all three types of context enumerated above must be taken
into account if we wish to provide an adequate representation of linguistic struc-
ture and its changes over time. Following the general strategy proposed by Östman
(2005), I will suggest a way of incorporating the general insights found in the ex-
tensive research on genres and text typology (Werlich 1976; Biber & Finegan 1989;
Swales 1990; Bhatia 1993; Biber 1994; Halmari & Virtanen 2005; Bergs 2005a,
among many others). Specifically, Östman’s (2005: 130) notion of “discourse pat-
tern” will provide the necessary starting point for formalizing the textually moti-
vated constraints on grammatical structure, as they emerge from the data under
discussion. This general approach will lead to more comprehensive conclusions
Representing contextual factors in language change 

about how the different types of context may become distributed over different
parts of language structure over time.
The main questions motivating this study are thus the following: how do con-
textual and grammatical factors interact in language variation and change, to what
extent may their interaction become conventionalized, and can any general ten-
dencies be detected in the conventionalization process? In answering these ques-
tions, the paper also touches on the elusive nature of lexicalization as a distinct
diachronic process. While it is not my goal in this study to address the lexicaliza-
tion puzzle directly, the analysis will lead to some observations about the promise
of a constructional approach for illuminating the complexities involved in solving
the lexicalization problem.

1.1 Case study

The material for the case study comes from a particular set of expressions in Old
Czech (OCz). I will trace the development of the word form věřící ‘(one) believing’,
which in many ways illustrates the rich semantic and morphosyntactic history of
the so-called ‘long’ present active participles, a special participial form character-
istic of Slavic and Baltic languages (with some parallels in German as well). I will
refer to this form as ‘participial adjective’ (PA), which is misleading in terms of the
form’s functions, but it reflects its morphologically mixed-category status: an ad-
jectival inflectional case/number/gender suffix is attached to a verbal stem,
turning the result into a morphologically non-verbal entity. A preliminary illustra-
tion of this morphosemantic structure is in (1). The label part stands for ‘present
active participle’, which is formed by the -nt- suffix (the -nt- label indicates the
participle’s relationship to its Latin cognate).
(1) [[Vroot – theme – NT ]part – c/n/g]PA
[[ věř – í – c ]part – í ]PA ‘(the one) believing’
The shift in lexical category places the PA in the gray area between inflection and
derivation, which alone poses a challenge for linguistic theory. Moreover, we will
see that the functional and categorical status of the c/n/g suffix is distributed be-
tween nominal and adjectival properties and, therefore, cannot by itself fix the
category for the whole word form, thus contradicting the received view that parti-
ciples turn into adjectives (Haspelmath 1996; Schenker 1995: 106 on Slavic; Short
1993: 487 specifically on Czech). As a result, the PA provides a particularly illus-
trative case for studying the relationship between meaning, form, and context,
since the way in which the competition between its verbal, nominal, and adjectival
potential was resolved cannot be adequately described without considering the
ways in which this form was used in actual discourse.
 Mirjam Fried

To start with, we need to capture the fact that the PA věřící developed from a
functionally unspecified, fully context-dependent, and morphosemantically trans-
parent form that was part of the regular verbal inflectional paradigm and that oc-
curred in all major syntactic functions (reference, modification, and predication),
into primarily an actor noun meaning ‘practicing Christian’ and marginally a qua-
si-adjectival modifier with the same meaning, while also maintaining its fully in-
flectional and compositional status that can be glossed as ‘[who] believes sth. to be
true’. Furthermore, the form is simultaneously attested in a number of other inter-
pretations (‘believable’, ‘pious’, ‘creditor’, ‘trustworthy’, ‘authorizing’, etc.) that se-
mantically correspond to the polysemous structure of the verb root věř- ‘believe’
and that were present throughout the OCz period. Sweeping generalizations con-
cerning just the word form itself are thus impossible even on lexical semantic
grounds, let alone in its syntactic behavior.
Since the case study focuses on a single word only, it would perhaps be attrac-
tive to consider its diachronic development a case of lexicalization (to the extent
that there even is any consensus about what we mean by lexicalization processes,
cf. recent debates in Wischer 2000; Himmelmann 2004; Traugott 2008; Haas 2005).
I will suggest that such a treatment would be too simplistic; it would render the
change as essentially random and unrelated to the fact that the same kind of change
concerns a whole class of word forms, not just this one item. Before we can attach
any classification to the type of change involved (say, V → N or V → Adj), we must
consider all the relevant details of the gradual (re)shaping of multiple associations
between form and function, which in this case show great interdependence be-
tween verb meaning, context in which the word form is used, and the morphose-
mantic structure that mediates this relationship. The analysis will demonstrate
that specific lexico-pragmatic properties correlate with different functional out-
comes that are not predictable simply on the basis of assigning lexical categories in
the abstract but, rather, depend to a great extent on different syntagmatic prefer-
ences. The development thus will be analyzed along several dimensions: semantic
shifts vis-à-vis textual distribution and contextual preferences (in the sense of con-
ditions on usage); role of collocational patterns (syntagmatic context); potential
categorial status (N, Adj, V) vis-à-vis syntactic behavior; and chronological order.
The result is a complex picture of all the factors that collectively motivate the
changes in the form’s usage and that must be part of any representation that aspires
to be descriptively accurate and to offer an explanatory value.
The examples I use are based on an extensive corpus of excerpts from OCz
texts; the corpus contains a wide variety of genres and spans the period of about
250 years.1 This chronological stretch allows us to see both the synchronic varia-
tion for any given generation of speakers and the gradual conventionalization of
specific patterns, i.e., the resulting change.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

1.2 Theoretical background

Given the central role of syntagmatic context in the present study, it is only natural
to carry out the analysis within the theoretical apparatus of Construction Gram-
mar (Fillmore 1988, 1989; Fillmore, Kay & O’Connor 1988; Croft 2001; Fried &
Östman 2004) and Frame Semantics (Fillmore 1982; Fillmore & Atkins 1992;
Atkins 1994; Atkins et al. 2003; Fillmore et al. 2003; Fried & Östman 2003; Fried
2004, 2005), which together offer a particularly attractive model for representing
lexico-grammatical networks in which the relative stability of grammatical form
does not conflict with the relative flexibility of meaning and expressive richness,
and vice versa.
Construction Grammar (CxG) does not make a sharp distinction between
grammar and lexicon, thus allowing for systematic incorporation of gradient phe-
nomena, such as is inherent in mixed-category morphology. The model’s funda-
mental assumption that the basic unit of grammatical structure is a construction,
i.e. a conventional function-form pairing, naturally sets up grammatical construc-
tions as the domain of language change, which is also the view increasingly argued
for in grammaticalization research. Finally, both of these features ensure that we can
capture the gradualness characteristic of the slow process of losing internal struc-
ture and compositional meaning, resulting in new linguistic patterns with non-
compositional properties. In fact, it is one of the defining features of grammatical
constructions that they are never just the sum of their parts; mixed-category mor-
phology thus constitutes a prime candidate for testing a constructional approach.
The framework known as Frame Semantics is concerned with the ‘semantics
of understanding’ as the appropriate model of linguistic semantics. Linguistically
relevant semantic information is organized and structured in “interpretive frames”
(Fillmore 1982: 124), which represent the complete background scene associated
with a given linguistic expression: the scene’s participants, settings, and any other
unique semantic features (collectively referred to as ‘frame elements’) that are nec-
essary for speakers’ native understanding of what the lexical item means and how
it can be used in context. A single linguistic expression may be (and often is) as-
sociated with multiple frames and, conversely, a single frame may be shared by
multiple expressions; each such expression, then, represents a particular concep-
tualization of certain parts of the larger background scene. In the case of predi-
cates, i.e. argument-taking lexemes, the frame also carries information about the
conventional expression of the syntactically relevant participants as they manifest
themselves in the syntactic organization of sentences. This is a unique feature of
Frame Semantics as a lexical semantic model: the built-in connection between
lexical meaning of an item and the canonical morphosyntactic expression of its
frame elements. The connection, which also plays a prominent role in the present
 Mirjam Fried

analysis, is expressed in the form of a valence, which thus functions as an explicit


link between meaning and form in the domain of argument expression.
The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 introduces the morphosemantic
structure of the PA, identifying the (potential) syntactic and semantic contribution
of the PA’s components. Section 3 is devoted to the details of the diachronic develop-
ment of the form věřící, identifying the factors that were instrumental in the gradu-
al reorganization of the PA’s morphosemantic structure due to specific contextual
pressures. Section 4 addresses the representational issues concerning the gradual
loss of compositionality and proposes ways of capturing contextual effects in frames
and constructions. Section 5 offers general conclusions about contextual representa-
tion in Construction Grammar and some questions left for future research.

2. Morphosemantic structure of věřící

Before we can address the form věřící itself, we must consider the semantic struc-
ture of the verb root věř- from which the PA is derived. For the purposes of this
study, it is sufficient to present a brief overview, which is based on a more detailed
analysis of the verb semantics in Fried (2008a). The OCz verb věřiti ‘to believe’ is
attested in at least four major senses (roughly, belief, faith, credit, trust); each
is associated with a distinct complementation pattern and some senses reflect a
particular communicative context (e.g., religious faith, various types of commer-
cial transactions, transfer of legal responsibility). The overall structure is presented
in the frame-based semantic network in Diagram 1.
The rectangles represent the frames, each of which corresponds to a distinct
sense within the prototype structure. For now, the valence information is repre-
sented in a much abbreviated, simplified format: in each frame, the list on the left
represents the linguistically required frame elements and the list on the right gives
the corresponding morphological expressions as they conventionally occur in ac-
tive sentences. Maintaining the same indices (#1–3) across the frames is intended
to capture the fact that the same set of event participants, common to the shared
background scene of believing, takes on different frame-specific roles in the indi-
vidual senses, each of which corresponds to a distinct conceptualization of hold-
ing a belief. (A more precise formalism will be used in Section 4, when we try to
capture the PA’s place in this semantic network.)
In Diagram 1, the conceptually simplest sense is in the frame labeled belief,
meaning roughly ‘believe that [what somebody says] is true’ (literally, ‘believe
somebody in some matter’), and as such it can be posited as the prototype sense
(indicated by the thick-line rectangle). We also note that this sense requires mini-
mally three participant roles, labeled Believer, Recipient of Trust, and Content.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

BELIEF (content of thought) context: religious faith


#1 Believer – NOM
FAITH (content of thought)
#2 Recip. of Trust – DAT
#1 Believer – NOM
#3 Content – v LOC
#2 Deity – (v) ACC
before 1350
before 1350
TRUST (expectation) context: commercial transaction
#1 Dependent – NOM CREDIT (expectation) before 1350
#2 Caretaker – DAT
Frame: TRANSFER
#3 Valued Entity – GEN
#1 Creditor – NOM #1 Giver
around 1410 #2 Recip.
#2 Debtor – DAT
#3 Valued En. – ACC #3 Gift

Frame: COMMERCIAL
TRANSACTION
FEs: Buyer, Seller, Goods,
Cost, Tender,...

Diagram 1. (Partial) frame-based semantic network of the OCz verb věřiti

The faith sense can be seen as a narrower reading of belief, motivated by the
common usage of this verb in the context of religious faith. This sense has only two
participants expressed in syntax: a Believer and a Deity; the latter perhaps fuses
the Recipient of Trust and the Content elements of the prototype. Both belief and
faith also share the basic semantic feature of relating to the content of someone’s
thought.
Of about the same age is also the sense credit, in which the act of believing is
cast in the context of a commercial transaction, thus sharing also the semantics
(and complementation pattern) with verbs of commercial transaction (buy-
ing, selling, paying, etc.) and of transfer (giving, taking) in general; these con-
nections are indicated by the rounded rectangles representing these additional
frames, which are inherently unrelated to verbs of believing but overlap with one
of the senses. The meaning of this usage is literally ‘believe something to some-
body’, where ‘something’ is a Valued Entity (as a special interpretation of the Con-
tent role in the prototype) and ‘somebody’ is the buyer (Debtor), corresponding to
the Recipient of Trust in the prototype. Idiomatically, the meaning can be glossed
 Mirjam Fried

as ‘sell something to somebody on credit (i.e., on the belief that the buyer will pay
later)’, illustrated in (2):
{jal se předivně kupčiti, bera draze na úvěrky...}
(2)
což kto jedno chtěl věřiti
what.acc who.nom one want.ppl.sg.m credit.inf3
{všecko pobral}
‘{he traded in the strangest way, taking [things] on expensive credit},whatever
who[ever] wanted to offer on credit {he [=king] took it all}’
[Budyš 63; 1420; social satire]2
Note that this sense is not about the content of someone’s thought, but expresses an
expectation with respect to a particular behavior. This semantic feature is shared also
by the youngest sense, trust, which means ‘believe that a (protective) action will be
taken’ or, more literally, ‘believe someonei with respect to doingi X’. The trust sense
is attested only marginally and will not be relevant to the issues discussed in this study
since there is no attestation of a corresponding PA. Nor will I be concerned with the
belief sense, whose PA did not develop into an actor noun (cf. Fried 2008a).
The PA form věřící originated within the same semantic structure, as part of
the verbal inflectional paradigm. However, it developed differently within indi-
vidual senses and also added meanings that are not attested with other forms of
the verb, including the ‘short’ participle that forms the PA’s stem. It is therefore
necessary to examine more closely the morphosemantic structure of the PA itself.
In addition to the lexical meaning and the valence structure contributed by the
verb root, we have to consider the remaining formatives and their own contribu-
tion to the meaning of the PA as a whole.
As already mentioned, the PA is derived from the present active participle
(the ‘short’ form, sometimes also called, misleadingly, ‘gerund’), which was used
primarily as a non-finite predicate expressing various dependent adverbial clauses,
such as is shown in (3); the participle is underlined. (Throughout the paper, I will use
curly brackets {} to enclose additional context surrounding the token in question.)
{přidávám … múdré a opatrné lidi}
(3)
věřě jim mimo všecky přátely
believe.nt.sg m 3pl.dat besides all.acc.pl friend.acc.pl
‘{I’m sending … [these] wise and cautious people}, because I trust them
more than any of [my] other friends’
[ArchČ 15, 551; 1455; correspondence]
The PA’s participial stem marks explicitly several verbal categories. Present tense
(interpreted as contemporaneousness, as is typical of present-tense depictive sec-
ondary predicates, cf. Schultze-Berndt & Himmelmann 2004: 102) is a property
Representing contextual factors in language change 

of the present stem from which the participle is derived (in contrast to a distinct
past-tense stem). Active voice or ‘orientation’ (Haspelmath 1994: 153) is associ-
ated with the participial suffix -c- itself (in contrast to other types of participles,
such as past or passive). Finally, the root brings along a valence and the participle
normally expresses, through verbal government, the non-agent arguments in that
valence (i.e. those arguments that would not be linked to the subject function in
an active sentence). This feature follows the behavior of other non-finite verb
forms (infinitive, gerund, active participles) and in (3) is illustrated by the dative
jim ‘to them’ (= Recipient of Trust). All of this constitutes the internal morphose-
mantic structure of the PA and represents the PA’s verbal potential, predisposing
it, at least in principle, toward uses expressing secondary predication, comparable
to the short participle in (3). And indeed, such examples are attested, as we shall
see shortly.
The verbal potential conflicts with the external c/n/g suffix, which is clearly
non-verbal. Its categorial status, however, is open: it is adjectival in its morpho-
logical form, but referential in its function; the suffix is etymologically a demon-
strative pronoun and its contrastive function was not yet fully neutralized in early
OCz (Kurz 1958). The development of the PA reflects these open-ended func-
tional possibilities. Throughout OCz, the PA věřící is attested in all three syntactic
functions – reference, modification, and predication – that are a priori available.
In fact, it is often difficult and sometimes impossible to determine unambiguously
the function of a given token. For the purpose of illustration, a straightforward
and uncontroversial example of each function is given in (4): an actor noun in
(4a), which reinforces the referential potential of the external morphology (‘the one
believing’); an adnominal modifier in (4b), which capitalizes on the adjectival
form of the c/n/g suffix (‘which/that believes’); and a predicate heading a non-fi-
nite adverbial clause (here in the form of a genitive absolute) in (4c), which builds
on the verbal potential of the internal morphology (‘[while] not believing’) in spite
of the external suffix. The relevant phrases are enclosed in brackets <> for easier
identification.
(4) a. Kristusi Ducha Svatého dává v
Christ.nom Spirit.acc Holy.acc gives.pres.3sg in
nich < svými věřícím>
3pl.loc his.dat.pl believe.pa.dat.pl
‘Christi gives in them [=his gifts] the Holy Spirit to <hisi believers>’
[ŠtítVyš 84b2; 1396; religious tract]
 Mirjam Fried

b. lid < v  buoh věřící >


people.nom.sgm in god.acc.sg believe.pa.nom.sg
spasen byl
save.pass.sg m be.ppl.sg.m
‘the people < that believed in God > were saved’
[PasMuzA 488a; mid 14th cent.; legend]
c. < ješče jich nevěřících >... vece jim
still 3pl.gen neg.believe.pa.gen.pl say.pres.3sg 3pl.dat
‘< as/because they still don’t believe [him] >…, he says to them’
[EvZimn L 24,41, late 14th cent.; biblical]
The fluid functional distribution gradually gave way to the more restricted distri-
bution we know from ModCz, as described in Section 1.1. In the rest of the paper,
I will examine the contextual details that led to fixing the actor noun status in
particular. I will take a close look at how this form was used, in what kinds of con-
text (syntagmatic, pragmatic, semantic), and how the usage affected the function-
al outcome.

3. Factors in fixing the noun potential of věřící

As a syntactic noun, the PA is attested in only two senses of the verb meaning:
faith and credit. I will turn to the faith sense first.

3.1 věřící in the sense of faith

This PA usage appears early (by 1350 in my corpus), together with the finite forms
of the verb, and it is attested in all kinds of texts. It is mostly accompanied by its
non-subject argument (i.e., the Deity participant), which always retains the same
form it would have in a finite clause: the accusative-marked NP, in older examples
as a plain accusative, later on with the preposition v ‘in’; this is also the diachronic
pattern we find with the finite forms. The verbal properties of the PA are thus pre-
served in terms of its internal syntax and also in its active orientation: the PA’s
referent is the one who believes.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

At the same time, the syntactically verbal character is undermined in several


ways. Consider the set of examples in (5):
(5) a. bieše anděl zemský … všech
be.pst.3sg angel.nom.sg.m earthly.nom.sg m all.gen.pl
< v buoh věřících > chvála
in God.acc.sg believe.pa.gen.pl praise.nom.sg.f
‘[St. Paul] was an angel on earth…, the praise of all those <believing in God>’
[PasMuzA 303a; late 1300s; legend]
b. {Jezukriste,...jsi…}
všech < v  tě věřících > útěcha
all.gen.pl in 2sg.acc believe.pa.gen.pl solace.nom.sg.f
‘{Jesus Christ, you are} … the solace of all those <believing in you>’
[LegKat 65a; late 14th cent.; spiritual poetry]
c. {boha jezukristai jenž všudy}
pomáhá < v  sěi věřícím >
help.pres.3sg in self.acc believe.pa.dat.pl
‘{of God Jesus Christi who in all places} helps those <believing in himi>’
[OtcB 196b; late 14th cent.; legend]
First off, the syntactically present Deity argument does not provide a highly in-
formative or novel contribution: the referent is always God/Christ, expressed
sometimes directly (5a) but most often by a pronoun, either personal (5b) or re-
flexive (5c), that invariably refers to Christian God or Christ. The pattern suggests
pragmatic ‘emptying’ of the complement, whose presence serves merely as a place-
holder in the syntactic valence of the stem, not as an expression identifying a prag-
matically unpredictable participant in the reported event. In fact, there are texts
(e.g. VýklŠal from early 15th century, which is a religious tract interpreting the
Song of Songs as a simile for proper Christian faith and the love of Christ) in
which the bare form věřící consistently alternates with the phrase věřící v Krista
‘believer in Christ’, with no detectable difference in meaning or communicative
effect. In both this and other texts, the phrase was clearly used as a fixed colloca-
tion that was not intended to deliver any novel content. It must also be noted that
casting the religious faith in terms of Christian faith in particular is a feature spe-
cific to the PA, not carried over from the verb semantics. There the Deity truly can
be any object of worship, such as modly ‘pagan idols’ or gods of other religions
(cf. Fried 2008a), both in OCz and ModCz. The PA thus narrows down the seman-
tic range of the verb root and this is corroborated by the fact that the noun křest’an
‘Christian’ is sometimes used explicitly as this PA’s synonym (e.g. HusBlud 293).
 Mirjam Fried

The low informativeness of the complement necessarily weakens the verbal


potential of the PA, despite the full expression of the root’s valence. By mid-15th
century, we indeed see the crystallization of the PA’s meaning into denoting ‘a
Christian’, i.e. a member of a particular social and religious group rather than the
more literal ‘one who believes in God/Christ’. Put differently, the compositional
meaning provided by the morphosemantic structure is replaced by a more special-
ized meaning that is not directly predictable from the PA’s morphology, including
its tense marking: having an identity based on a particular trait (here, Christian
faith) obliterates the contemporaneousness that the internal morphology suggests.
Moreover, once the atemporal usage based on group-identity is well established,
we can expect additional semantic shifts that can only be motivated by their rela-
tionship to a semantically true noun, not by any relationship to the verb. And in-
deed, we find examples such as (6), where the meaning of věřící is generalized to
refer to church members, both alive and dead. Evidently, group membership is the
salient feature here, no just the individually assigned property of believing in
something, since the act of believing presupposes a conscious mind, while being
counted as a member of a class of individuals need not. Notice that the PA in (6)
does not (indeed, cannot) have any complement.
{žádajíc...spasení duše své a svejch starších a předchůdcích}
(6)
...i <jiných všech mrtvých
also other.gen.pl.m all.gen.pl.m dead.gen.pl.m
věřících > {voltář ke cti svaté Dorotě...založil a nadal}
believe.pa.gen.pl
‘{desiring…the salvation of his own soul and [the souls] of his elders and
predecessors…} and also of all other deceased members of his
congregation,{he founded and endowed an altar to honor Saint Dorothea}’
[ArchČ 9, 243; 1400; admin. record of dedicating a new altar]
However, complete absence of the complement is not always a measure of a non-
verbal interpretation of the PA either, as demonstrated by the example in (7). This
is one of the functionally ambiguous cases, where the PA can be either interpreted
as a fully compositional usage that is externally nominal but preserves all the in-
ternally marked verbal categories, including relative tense (as a temporal or condi-
tional circumstantial clause), or it can be interpreted as referring to a member of a
particular class of people:
(7) {Apolonius…nauči jej nasledovati přiebytka věčného a trpělivě hledati
božieho milosrdie... řka jemu}
že sě muož všecko dokonati < věříciemu >
that rf can.pres.3sg everything.nom.sg.n complete.inf believe.pa.dat.sg
Representing contextual factors in language change 

‘{Apolonius…taught him to aim for the eternal dwelling and patiently


seek God’s mercy…, telling him} that everything is possible <if one be-
lieves/for a believer>’ [OtcB 19a; late 14th cent.; legend]
The example is taken from a popular historical narrative reporting a sequence of
events and their consequences for the protagonist. This would support the predi-
cative, event-reporting interpretation, still expressing relative tense, along the lines
of ‘when/if you have faith, everything is possible’, since such usage is generally
well-documented in event-reporting narratives (chronicles, exempla, legends,
personal stories, etc.). At the same time, the religious framing of this particular
narrative – the text is a compendium of the lives of Saints – equally invites the
referential interpretation of ‘believers [in God]’, i.e. people who are defined by this
property independently of the events in the immediate context of the story. The
potential for ambiguity with respect to the relative strength of the verbal character
persists through the first part of the 15th century, and not just as a special feature
of this particular PA but as a general feature of OCz PAs (Fried 2003).
What is thus perhaps more important than internal syntax in the shift toward
a full noun status is the collocational pattern associated with this PA usage. It is
conspicuous that the PA frequently co-occurs with a universal quantifier, such as
všichni ‘all’, shown in (5a-b, 6) or každý ‘every’, regardless of complementation.
Semantically, this reinforces the generic, class-membership interpretation of věřící,
at the expense of a temporally restricted reading that applies only at a given mo-
ment. Put differently, in these quantified phrases, ‘having Christian faith’ can eas-
ily be understood not as a temporally grounded eventuality ascribed to an indi-
vidual entity (the non-restrictive relative clause interpretation) but as a classification
that is independent of the event expressed by the main predicate. The referential
potential is simultaneously strengthened by the external syntax, by giving it the
status of a head in a noun phrase. We may futher note that the quantifier slot
gradually expands to other types of modifiers, including possessives and adjec-
tives, such as we see in (4a), where the verbal government ‘believe(r) in him(self)’
is completely replaced by a nominal pattern ‘his believer’ and the Deity referent is
now indicated by the NP-internal possessive modifier.
When we organize the attested patterning chronologically, as in Diagram 2, it
becomes evident that the syntagmatic environment, i.e. the collocational prefer-
ence, plays a significant role in fixing the actor noun status.4 The external syntax
(noun slots and nominal government) together with the external and internal se-
mantics (quantification, predictable valence content) were only gradually, though
steadily, followed by internal syntax (complete valence suppression). The arrows
indicate persistence into Modern Czech and the dotted lines reflect relatively low-
er or sporadic incidence of a given feature.
 Mirjam Fried

1350 1380 1410 1450 1500 ... ModCz


INTERNAL:
complementation (v ACC)
fixed reference for
Deity complement
EXTERNAL:
modifiers
quantifiers
other
meaning believer in God

Christian
church member

Diagram 2. Chronology of the noun věřící in the faith sense

To summarize, this PA underwent a shift from a relatively transparent pattern re-


sembling a headless relative clause (predominantly non-restrictive) with a compo-
sitional semantic structure, to a full actor noun without any temporal grounding:
from ‘(the) one who believes in God/Christ’ to ‘Christian/man of the one-and-
only-presupposed-as-culturally-acceptable religion’ and eventually to ‘church
member’. This shift is due to several types of contextual factors. A broad commu-
nicative context is relevant and perhaps decisive in interpreting the older exam-
ples: as we see in (7), it is possible to interpret the form in an atemporal sense as
well as in temporally grounded predicative function, regardless of the externally
non-verbal syntax. In other words, nothing in that narrative (and other cases like
these) forces a particular inference and instead, it is left to the reader/hearer to
work out a plausible understanding. Gradually, though, the usage clearly consoli-
dates the referential potential of the PA suffix, highlighting the actor of the event
denoted by the root, rather than the event itself; the latter would be expected in a
true participle. And this is facilitated by, or at least correlates with, two contextual
factors. One is the low pragmatic and semantic salience of the referent expressed
by the non-subject complement, thus futher ‘demoting’ the verbal properties of
the form. The other is the syntagmatic context in which this PA is used: in syntac-
tically nominal slots which increasingly take on overt features of a clear noun
phrase structure and semantics.
In Section 4, we shall return to the question of how these different contextual fac-
tors entered the conventional understanding of the PA in its fixed categorial status.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

3.2 Věřící in the sense of credit

The PA used in the credit sense presents a distinctly different picture, although
the differences are consistent with the general tendencies displayed in the faith
sense as well as in all other cases of PAs that turned into actor nouns. To begin
with, the corpus does not contain any examples of credit-based PAs until the
early 1400s, even though the corresponding verb was commonly used in this
meaning as early as the faith sense (mid 1300s). Moreover, the verb occurs in all
kinds of genres (poetry, popular stories, legal documents, religious tracts, legends,
etc.), while its PA is attested exclusively in administrative and legal texts. This dis-
tribution suggests that věřící in the credit sense, unlike its faith counterpart,
developed as a technical term and was not part of the common vocabulary. The
oldest example in the corpus is shown in (8) and can be taken as fully representa-
tive of this usage.
(8) {Pakli bychom toho neučinili… mámy … odtud nikam nevyjéžděti tak
dlúho, až}
bychom < našim věřícím > svrchupsané
cond.1pl our.dat.pl believe.pa.dat.pl above.written.acc.sg.f
penieze úplně zaplatili
money.acc.pl entirely pay.ppl.pl
‘{If we didn’t do that… we have no permission … to leave this town} until
we’ve paid <our creditors> the above mentioned money in full’
[ArchČ 6,459; 1410; private record of a financial obligation]
Two syntactic features stand out prominently. One concerns the internal syntax of
the participial stem: without exception, this PA always appears bare, that is with-
out showing any verbal government for expressing the non-subject arguments
(potentially two – the Debtor and the Valued Entity) contained in the root’s va-
lence. Related to this fact is the other striking feature, namely, the syntagmatic
patterning. With the exception of one token (out of 20 in the corpus), to be com-
mented on shortly, this PA is always accompanied by a possessive modifier, which
is to say, it always occurs in a noun phrase. And as is also illustrated in (8), the
possessive invariably refers to the first person of either number, which means that
the referent of the PA věřící is always the speaker’s negotiating partner. Thus in
pragmatic terms, the possessive modifier actually instantiates one of the valence
participants (Debtor), but using purely nominal, rather than verbal syntax, and its
referent is highly restricted, as it can only be the speaker; this constraint certainly
does not follow from the meaning of the root or from any pragmatic condition
associated with its use.
 Mirjam Fried

All these features strongly favor nominal interpretation, in which the PA de-
notes a person that plays a particular role in a commercial transaction; in (8), it is
the role of the Creditor, the party that expects a mutually agreed-upon payment
from the Debtor-speaker. Such an interpretation is further corroborated by later
texts, in which the PA věřící is often used (especially in the late 1400s) interchange-
ably with the morphologically true actor noun, věřitel ‘creditor’ (-tel corresponds
to the English actor noun suffix –er). An illustration is in (9); the noun věřitel and
its corresponding translation are underlined.
(9) {a tak vždy máme vydávati na každý rok věřitelóm našim…, dokudž by-
chom svrchupsaných zlatých jistinných i s úrokem}
< našim věřícím > svrchupsaným nedali
our.dat.pl believe.pa.dat.pl above.written.dat.pl neg.give.ppl.pl
{a nezaplatili úplně}
‘{and so we must pay each year to our creditors...until we might give and
pay in its entirety the above mentioned principal and interest} <to our
above mentioned creditorsPA>’ [ArchČ 9, 294; 1451; a loan contract]
We could thus summarize that in contrast to the faith PA, this usage was from the
very beginning dedicated to its potential as an actor noun, which is unambigu-
ously signaled by its syntax, both external and internal: no verbal government,
consistently a full NP structure, and consequently we can also infer a weak sense
of temporal grounding. On the one hand, it is true that the attested data are most-
ly records of specific eventualities, in which the roles within a debt-paying transac-
tion are assigned within a particular, sometimes explicitly established time frame.
In that sense, the assignation of being a věřící need not be taken as indicating an
atemporal interpretation that defines a type of participant based on general class
membership. At the same time, the semantic overlap with the true, atemporal ac-
tor noun věřitel was clearly salient enough in the minds of the speakers if the forms
were so easily used as synonyms. This relationship, together with the syntactic pat-
terning, invites a shift toward an atemporal understanding, with the PA then de-
noting a conventional role in a particular type of business relations.
This conclusion is consistent with the one exception to the preferred syntactic
pattern just described, certainly so on pragmatic grounds. The one instance of the
PA without a modifier is not a record of an actual contract in which the speaker
enumerates his or her obligation toward a concrete partner. Instead, the example
in (10), chronologically relatively late, comes from a manual for composing con-
tracts and other official documents, where there is no need to be explicit about the
remaining participants; it only offers a general advice on what conventionally ac-
cepted options a creditor has toward his or her negotiating partner(s). No
Representing contextual factors in language change 

temporally restricted reading is even possible here, the PA can only be understood
as a classificatory label.
(10) na vuoli < věřícieho > jest
on will.loc.sg.f believe.pa.gen.sg aux.3sg
{diel od jednoho spolurukojmí vzieti}
‘it is [left] to the discretion of <the/a creditor> {to take a down payment from
one of the guarantors} [ProkArs 168; late 1400s; manual for legal writing]
Thus in the credit PA, the only verbal feature left appears to be the PA’s active
orientation: it is an actor noun, after all. This conclusion, however, requires some
elaboration; it still remains to be determined what exactly this PA meant, particu-
larly with respect to the general question that frames this study: how can we best
capture the PA’s conventional meaning and which, if any, interpretations have to
be left to broader thematic context, which is to say, to speakers’ understanding of
the situation at hand vis-à-vis the morphosemantic structure of the form.
The reason for posing this question are examples such as in (11) below, which
present an interesting twist on how the valence of the root may be manipulated in
different situational contexts. So far, all the uses have involved the most transparent
distribution of roles as it follows from the semantic structure of the verb root organ-
ized around the prototype. Recall the relationship between the participants across
different senses and particularly the correspondence between belief and credit,
the latter also with the overlapping frame of commercial transaction (ct), re-
peated in Diagram 3. For reasons that will become clear shortly, the ct frame is
presented in one of its particular subframes, which can be labeled as selling.
The distribution depicted in Diagram 3 is reflected in (8–10). The ‘believer’ in
those examples is a seller or money lender, i.e. the person who believes that the
buyer or borrower will pay his/her debt. The contexts all involve paying a debt and

frame [BELIEF ] frame [CREDIT] frame [SELLINGCT]


#1 Believer #1 Creditor #1 Seller
#2 Recip. of Trust #2 Debtor #2 Buyer
#3 Content #3 Valued Entity #3 Valued Entity
frame [TRANSFER]
#1 Giver
#2 Recipient
#3 Gift

Diagram 3. Věřící as a trusting seller/lender


 Mirjam Fried

the referent of věřící is cast in the Creditor role. But the examples in (11) are differ-
ent; the parentheses in (11a) reflect the actual orthography:
(11) a. {pakli bychom...zbožie... v zemské dsky...nemohli vložiti..., tehdy}
slibujeme... < našim věřícím > (straně
promise.pres.1pl our believe.pa.dat.pl (party.dat.sg
kupující) ... napředpsanú jistinu
buy.pa.dat.sg) above.written.acc.sg.f capital.acc.sg.f
{peněz a k tomu třetinu výše}
‘{should we fail to enter the [transfer of the] estate into the land regis-
ter, we hereby} promise [to pay] <our partner> (the buying party) the
abovementioned capital {and one third of its value on top of that}
[ProkArs 156b; late 1400s; legal writing manual]
b. {Pakli bychom toho všeho neučinili, tehdá }
< náš věřící > moci bude nám láti
our believe.pa.nom.sg can.inf be.fut.3sg 1pl.dat rail.inf
‘{Should we fail to do all that, then} our trusting [buyer] will be al-
lowed to rail at us’[ArchČ 15, 305; 1455; record of the sale of a village]
In (11a) the role of the PA’s referent is explicitly identified as ‘the buyer’, while in (11b)
that same role follows from the context: the speaker is the one selling the village and
he is laying down the conditions of a successful sale, which includes his writing the
deed into the land records. Evidently, the ‘believer’ need not always be the one who
is giving anything on credit (lending money or selling property), but can be also the
one who is buying on the belief that the goods (Valued Entity) are truly available or
have the promised value. In (11), the distribution of roles thus reflects a shift in per-
spective from which the transaction is viewed: while in (8–10) the usage takes the
perspective of the seller (hence the overlap with the selling subframe of the ct
scene), in (11) the buyer’s perspective is taken, which means a different conceptuali-
zation of the CT background frame, namely, buying. This switch, in turn, yields a
slightly different interpretation of the roles involved in the act of believing: instead of
the correspondences in Diagram 3, we get the configuration in Diagram 4.
To be sure, the context in (11) is still a commercial transaction and the issue at
hand is to ensure that the buyer and the seller do not cheat each other, but the status
of being the one who ‘believes’ is attached to the buyer rather than seller. The mean-
ing of věřící in these cases is thus more accurately paraphrased as ‘the one who be-
lieves [the integrity and honesty of] the seller’, not as ‘the one who sells X to the
buyer on credit’, as would be expected in an actor noun derived from the credit
sense of the verb věřiti. The latter interpretation is provided explicitly in (11a), also
through the use of the parenthetical clarification strana kupující ‘the buying party’.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

frame [BELIEF ] frame [CREDIT] frame [BUYINGCT]


#1 Believer #1 Beneficiary #1 Buyer
#2 Recip. of Trust #2 Guarantor #2 Seller
#3 Content #3 Valued Entity #3 Valued Entity
frame [TRANSFER]
#1 Recipient
#2 Giver
#3 Gift

Diagram 4. Věřící as the a trusting buyer

While examples such as (11) are very infrequent and seem to appear only in the
later chronological layers of my corpus, they cannot be simply dismissed as errors
or an individual peculiarity of a single writer; they come from different sources
and it is also significant that the buyer’s interpretation is specifically noted in some
of them. Instead, the ‘fuzziness’ only underscores the fluid interaction between
different frames that are evoked by a single word and whose activation may not be
a priori restricted to a specific type of context. It seems that the exact interpreta-
tion of the PA in the credit sense was shaped by two different thematic contexts:
one involving pure money transfer (as in lending, dowry payments, or any trans-
action treated simply as a debt of one party toward another), illustrated in (8–10),
and the other involving the purchase of a property. At the same time, the fact that
an author felt the need to explicate what he means by věřící (11a) in a context in
which the expected reading could be ‘creditor’ suggests that particular frames are
preferentially evoked in particular contexts (or, that there are certain convention-
ally expected associations between a type of cultural context and a particular se-
mantic frame) and while such associations can be violated, the unexpected fram-
ing may have to be signaled explicitly. It is also important to add that I have not
found any attestation of other forms of the verb věřiti (finite or non-finite) where
its subject would be interpreted as a ‘beneficiary/buyer’; it seems to be only the PA
form that developed this additional interpretation. A chronological summary is in
Diagram 5, where we can see that syntactically, both internally and externally, this
PA usage was purely and consistently nominal from the start; note also that it did
not survive into ModCz (nor did this verb sense as a whole).
To conclude, the conventionally expected meaning of věřící in the credit
sense seems to have been ‘one believing in his commercial partner’s honesty’. The
prototype structure associated with the meaning of the verb root motivates the
transparent interpretation of věřící as ‘trusting seller/lender‘, i.e. ‘creditor’, which is
indeed found in all kinds of contexts. However, in the context of property buying,
as a specific type of transaction, we find, at least marginally, a switch to the
 Mirjam Fried

1350 1380 1410 1450 1500 ... MCz


INTERNAL:
no complementation
EXTERNAL:
modifiers: 1st pers. possess.
meaning creditor

trusting buyer

Diagram 5. Chronology of the noun věřící in the credit sense

perspective of the buyer, yielding the interpretation of věřící as ‘trusting buyer‘, in


a shift away from the prototypical distribution of the roles maintained by the rest
of the verbal paradigm.

4. Context and grammar in a network model of language change

The discussion in the preceding sections makes several things evident. First off, it
would be an oversimplification and misrepresentation of historical reality if we
limited ourselves to noting that the form věřící turned (among other things) into
actor nouns. At a minimum, it did not turn into such nouns across the full seman-
tic spectrum provided by the meaning of the root. Furthermore, the factors that
were instrumental in developing the actor noun conventionalization were not
quite uniform across the relevant semantic subdomains (faith vs. credit). And
finally, a sweeping generalization that does not go beyond the level of lexical cat-
egories (a V → N change, or even if seen as a Participle → N change) misses any
kind of insight into the cognitive and communicative mechanisms that are in-
volved in grammatical reorganization and that can advance our understanding of
the incremental nature of such changes in general, not just in this particular case.
In order to understand the gradual shift in the conventional interpretations of
the form in question, we must first consider the PA’s place in the semantic network
provided by the root from which the form is derived. Without this connection, we
could at best provide a disjointed list of uses without any apparent motivation. Yet,
we can see that the different senses and uses of věřící form coherent sub-networks
within the semantic space associated with the verb. These sub-networks, in turn,
represent different clusters of essentially the same syntactic, functional, and prag-
matic properties and, crucially, the clustering is not necessarily predictable from
anything in the morphosemantic structure per se. In fact, the overall shift can be
best described as a gradual erosion of compositional structure. This means that the
Representing contextual factors in language change 

PA goes from being a transparent sum of its parts (with all the attendant flexibility
in use and functional status in larger context, due to the indeterminate nature of
the external c/n/g suffix) to a functionally fixed category with a meaning that is no
longer fully derivable from the form’s morphological make-up.
The task that remains, then, is to capture this shift in a way that properly in-
cludes the systematic participation of the relevant contextual factors and that also
allows us to make generalizations about the role different types of context played
in the process. Diagram 7 shows a frame-semantic/constructional network in
which all the semantic, syntactic, and contextual properties can be organized.
First, however, a few notes on the formalism; a slightly simplified notational
practice is shown in the generic constructional representation in Diagram 6
(the interested reader is invited to consult Fried & Östman 2004 for all the techni-
cal details, none of which are crucial to the concerns of this paper).
The nested boxes reflect constituent structure, but also allow us to make a
principled and systematic distinction between two domains of representation: the
‘external’ properties of a construction in the outside box (e.g. the c/n/g suffix that
forms the PA) and its ‘internal’, constituent-level properties (e.g. the participial
stem) in the inside box. This distinction is essential for capturing the fact that a
complex expression (morphological or syntactic) as a whole may have its own idi-
osyncratic features that do not follow from the internal composition. Individual
features are represented as attribute-value pairs, in Diagram 6 labeled only as attr
followed by a variable (x, y, etc.). Notice that the internal and external levels may
share certain attributes (co-indexed) and/or values, but need not share all of them;
hence the non-compositionality effects.
Turning now to the representations of the PAs, we start by noting that the frames
presented in Diagram 1 above correspond to those boxes in Diagram 7 below that
contain the attribute frame in them, followed by the name of the appropriate seman-
tic frame (belief, credit, etc.). Notice that most of these frames are now inside
other boxes, indicating the fact that the frame information, along with various oth-
er features, is contributed by the PA’s stem, which, in turn, is a constituent of an-
other form, namely, the PA itself (labeled as lform); this arrangement reflects the

attri x
attrj yy
attrk z
attri x
attrj y

Diagram 6. CxG formalism in the abstract


 Mirjam Fried

hierarchical morphological structure introduced in (1), although the representa-


tion in Diagram 7 ignores other structural details that are not crucial to the present
purposes. In an example of the external/internal distinction, the features listed at
the top of the outer box of the faith PA represent the constructional properties of
this use of věřící that do not simply follow from adding up the properties of its
constituent morphemes. (A bit more will have to be said about the representation
of the credit PA.) For easier orientation, all the features that are not predictable
from the morphosemantic structure of the PA are in italicized boldface.
The attribute-value formalism can be quite elaborate and detailed, but I prefer
to simplify the notation somewhat, in the interest of general accessibility. For our
purposes, we only need to register several such attributes; some are self-explanato-
ry, such as cat(egory), sem(antics), (discourse) role, modality, val(ence), while oth-
ers may require a brief commentary: dp is an abbreviation for ‘discourse pattern’,
which I use for marking textual/stylistic constraints (to be discussed in more detail
shortly), lform indicates a specific, physical word-form, while lxm stands for ‘lex-
eme’; FE stands for ‘frame element’.
The picture summarizes our observations about the faith and credit PAs,
also in relation to the general background frame belief, to which they still belong.
The path of the faith usage is relatively straightforward. This PA maintained the
more or less transparent structure of an inflectional form and only very slowly
shifted toward becoming a full-fledged actor noun. In particular, the valence of the
root, represented by the val statement inside the stem box, remained a property of
the PA as well: the val statement at the external level specifies that the non-subject
dependent can be expressed by the PA, albeit only optionally, as indicated by the
parentheses. The rest of the external properties, however, are idiosyncratic to the
PA: its external syntax is unambiguously that of a noun (in spite of the adjectival
morphology of the c/n/g suffix, not explicitly included in Diagram 7) and its mean-
ing is ‘Christian’, which follows from the narrowing of the referential potential of
the FE Deity (recall Diagram 1) to Christ. As the chronological summary in Dia-
gram 2 above shows, it took at least two generations of speakers before the internal
structure was sufficiently eroded and the atemporal interpretation became fully es-
tablished and the only one available. It was only when this shift was fully in place
that the ‘church member’ reading could arise, as an extension of the PA, without
any direct relationship to the verbal origin. Notice the complete absence of any va-
lence or, for that matter, any other reference to the participial stem in its representa-
tion; there is no motivation for positing any derivational link between the two.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

cat n lform věřící


sem ['Christian']
val {(#2 [Acc(v)])}

cat vNT-part lxm věř--


cat n lform věřící
sem ['church member'] Frame FAITH
FEs: #1 Believer
#2 Christ

Frame BELIEF val {#1 [Nom], #2 [Acc(v)]}


(content of thought)
FEs ...
COMMERCIAL TRANSACTION

context: property buying


context: money lending
cat n inherit Modification
dp admin./legal
genre binding contract
modality obligation
#2 cat poss. cat n lform věřící
role Speaker sem ['creditor']
cat vNT-part lxm věř-

Frame CREDIT
FEs: #1 Creditor
#2 Debtor
#3 Valued-Entity

val {#1 [Nom], #2 [Dat], #3 [Acc]}

Diagram 7. Frame-semantic/constructional network of OCz věřící as a noun

As we already mentioned, the crucial factor in the shift appears to be the syntag-
matic context, i.e. the collocational pattern [Quant + PA] in which this form rou-
tinely occurred; the collocational preference itself, though, did not become con-
ventionalized as such, it only facilitated the fixing of the PA’s categorial status. On
the other hand, the communicative context kept reinforcing certain interpretive
clues about the meaning of věřící that gradually did become part of the PA’s con-
ventional meaning. Specific contextual features, namely, promotion of Christian
faith, strongly favored a particular interpretation of the PA’s referent, which re-
sulted both in the semantic specialization of the PA (Christian faith) as compared
 Mirjam Fried

to the verb itself (religious faith) and in the PA’s functional specialization
(identification of group membership based on certain properties), yielding a se-
mantic and syntactic (though not morphological) noun.
In contrast, the case of the credit PA is more involved, its departure from its
inflectional origin much more complete and seemingly abrupt. The effects of the
syntagmatic context were directly and visibly incorporated in the conventional us-
age from the start. For one thing, the verbal potential was completely suppressed,
even beyond the issue of valence expression; this ‘fading away’ of the internal
structure is indicated by the gray color in the diagram: the participial properties of
the stem, the valence requirement of the root, and even the conventional configu-
ration of the frame participants associated with the verbal usage clearly lost their
significance. At the same time, the PA typically occurs in a modification structure
[Poss + PA], i.e., as the head of a phrasal construction that can be generalized as
[Modifier + N]. This fact is captured by enclosing the PA together with its posses-
sive modifier in a larger box, representing them as a single, conventional phrasal
unit. The features listed in the left-daughter box express the constraints associated
with the modifier and the right-daughter box represents the PA, as the head of the
whole Modification construction. This [Poss + PA] unit also carries all the proper-
ties of other modification patterns (such as case/number/gender agreement be-
tween the constituents, the distributional properties of the whole phrase in sen-
tences, etc.) and this relationship needs to be captured as well, through the inherit
statement at the external level.
However, we know that other types of contextual factors also played a role and
that those must be reflected in the representation as well. First of all, the PA was
restricted to a specific textual/stylistic context, in Diagram 7 indicated by the dp
(Östman’s 2005 “discourse pattern”) attribute: this PA only appears in a formulaic
administrative usage and was most likely coined specifically as a ‘technical’ term.
We can think of the notion of discourse patterns as conventional schematizations of
the speakers’ knowledge about distinct discourse situations, which may impose spe-
cific constraints on grammatical patterning. In the case of our [Poss + PA] colloca-
tion, the relevant discourse pattern can be conceptualized as a type of legal and ad-
ministrative discourse, which came in various subtypes (e.g. summonses, sentencing,
contracts, testaments, etc.). I label these provisionally as genres but the meaning and
use of these categories clearly need additional study. The attributes dp and genre
thus serve to invoke a general frame of understanding of a discourse situation in
which this PA naturally fits. Notice also that no such reference is necessary in repre-
senting the faith PA since its textual distribution remains unconstrained.
Second, the communicative context in which this PA was used seems to be
restricted to a particular modality: with the one motivated exception shown in
(11), the context always involves an expression of obligation with respect to
Representing contextual factors in language change 

maintaining trust between commercial partners. The modality is often expressed


directly by a verb of obligation, such as mít ‘ought to’ in (8–9), but can be also more
subtle, as in (11). Again, this restriction is not a property of the verb itself, nor the
participial stem but, rather, correlates with the kind of discourse it occurs in
(a binding contract).5
And finally, full understanding of the conventional meaning of this PA must
include reference to discourse roles: one of the participants provided by the verb
root is necessarily the speaker. This is consistent with the performative flavor of
the situation in which this PA was used: declaring contractual obligation between
the speaker and his/her contractual partner. All of these context-sensitive features
became part of the conventional meaning of the credit PA, turning it into an ac-
tor noun distinct from what the verbal paradigm would predict, including the fact
that it prototypically occurs only as the head of a modification construction.
The representation also leaves room for the development of the emerging
polysemy documented in (11). The possibility of reconfiguring the participant roles
indicates that the credit PA’s link to the verb’s semantic structure had been suffi-
ciently loose by the late 1400s (represented by the gray color for the indices #1–2 in
Diagram 7), thereby inviting an alternative perspective, which results in a different
hierarchical organization of the roles. At the same time, it is interesting to note that
this shift is found always in the same semantic context (property buying). This may
mean nothing, of course, since we are dealing with an incomplete record, but it may
also be indicative of the tendency toward isomorphism as a powerful motivating
force in balancing the tension between the need to express new meanings (polysemy)
and maintaining relative clarity through one-to-one mappings. However, we do not
have strong evidence for concluding that this marginal, though motivated, expan-
sion ever became a conventionally established distinction. The attestations suggest
the potential for such a development and our representation captures where and
why this kind of ‘stretching’ of the conventional pattern can occur, but the sporadic
record does not justify positing a distinct construction or a frame.
To summarize, once we attempt to formulate explicit generalizations about the
relevant empirical observations, at least two broad conclusions become apparent.
One concerns the level of descriptive detail. Although on the surface the PA devel-
opment may seem primarily an issue of morphology (generating a hybrid mor-
phological form within an inflectional paradigm), in reality it involves a number
of additional dimensions that have to be integrated in the analysis if we are to ar-
rive at an accurate picture of these forms and the changes in their use and catego-
rial status over time. The frame- and construction-based approach provides useful
tools for incorporating all the necessary detail in a principled and systematic way.
Second, the network in Diagram 7 embodies the gradient nature of the distinc-
tion between lexicon and grammar. Frames are a tool for structuring lexical
 Mirjam Fried

meaning (in the sense of speakers’ conventional understanding), but an accurate


representation of the meaning and usage of a lexeme or its word-forms may involve
a lot more than just an inventory of frames or, for that matter, a list of single words
associated with that frame. As we see with the credit PA, certain generalizations
about the properties of a single word (form) can easily go beyond the domain of a
word and instead take the form of a phrasal construction. This particular construc-
tion has fully transparent syntactic structure and yet, in order to articulate the
shifts in the speakers’ understanding of this PA, we cannot keep the external syntax
separate from the semantic and pragmatic constraints, all of which incorporate
various kinds of contextual clues. That is, the phrasal construction constitutes one
segment of the lexico-grammatical network associated with the noun věřící, thus
blurring the imaginary boundary between grammar and lexicon.

5. Conclusions

The main goal of this study was to examine the ways in which different kinds of
contextual information may play a role in the reorganization of specific form-
meaning associations, and how this reorganization can be represented by the tools
of a synchronic model of language that tries to give a cognitively plausible repre-
sentation of speakers’ linguistic knowledge. I approached the problem from a dia-
chronic perspective, studying the interaction between context and grammar as it
is reflected in the incremental accumulation of the features that collectively amount
to an observable shift in a form’s usage. Overall, the change under investigation
can be best described as a gradual conventionalization of a pattern of understand-
ing, in which lexical meaning, syntactic function, and communicative function
form an integrated whole.
The choice of the OCz PA as illustrative material is motivated by the fact that
the PA is a categorially hybrid form that developed in several different directions
(functionally and categorially, cf. also Fried 2003, 2008b, and in press), each direc-
tion correlating with a distinct cluster of various contextual factors. The PA’s struc-
ture and the patterns of its usage speak to many issues – semantic, syntactic, mor-
phological – and pose challenges both for accurate analysis and, perhaps even
more so, for finding an adequate way of representing the generalizations that can
be made about them.
The way different contextual factors entered the conventional understanding
of the PA věřící as an actor noun can be summarized as follows. (i) To the extent
that semantic/pragmatic context (i.e. the cultural grounding of speakers’ under-
standing) gets incorporated into the lexico-grammatical make-up of the PA, it af-
fects the frame structure, i.e. the lexical meaning (cf. the narrowing of the faith
Representing contextual factors in language change 

sense or the emerging split in the credit sense). (ii) The syntagmatic context indi-
cates structural and functional preferences of the item in question and if incorpo-
rated into the conventionalization of an expression, it may give rise either to new
grammatical constructions (e.g. the PA itself, as a morphological construction
whose internal structure became more opaque) or to a fixed phrasal expression
based on an independently existing grammatical construction (cf. the credit PA’s
modificational pattern). (iii) Finally, the fixing of a form’s usage may arise in par-
ticular textual settings, and such constraints again become part of the construc-
tional specifications (cf. the stylistic restrictions on the credit pa).
The syntagmatic context has turned out to be particularly relevant in shaping
the PA’s development, whether the patterning became part of the conventional
expression (credit) or just facilitated the gradual fixing of the categorial status
(faith). This observation underscores two things. One is the mutually reinforcing
effect of form and meaning/function: neither dimension can be strictly predicted
from the other, but each influences the speaker’s understanding and interpreta-
tion. Related to this is the importance of tracking collocational patterns and deal-
ing with them in a systematic manner, so that we can capture what is stable and
predictable about them without having to deny their idiosyncratic properties. The
collocations that played a role in the development of the PAs all share regular,
productive features with various general syntagmatic patterns (such as the gram-
matical properties of the abstract modification construction), but they are much
less transparent with respect to other types of context: textual, pragmatic, and se-
mantic. These features are unpredictable and must be ‘known by native speakers
outright’, i.e., must be specified explicitly in the representation, since they cannot
follow automatically from the knowledge of other linguistic patterns (cf. Goldberg’s
2002 notion of “surface generalizations”, which applies here as well).
In order to establish shifts within the lexico-grammatical network associated
with the PA, we have to first study the details of how the network’s (potential)
members are used in context and what are the factors that contribute to the sharp-
ening of the PA’s inherently available but vaguely delimited and initially context-
dependent syntactic function. One has to consider the way semantic space is di-
vided between different uses in different contexts, even within the same potential
category (in our case, nouns). We have seen that different senses within a polysemy
network shape the superficially identical form quite differently. Consequently, the
process of incorporating contextual information into grammatical structure re-
quires a network-based model of language that allows multidimensional represen-
tations of the interdependencies between lexical meaning, morphosyntactic struc-
ture, and pragmatic constraints both within and across individual constructions.
With respect to the representational potential of CxG vis-à-vis ‘context’, it is
clear that the model is equipped, conceptually, to accommodate the pragmatic and
 Mirjam Fried

general socio-cultural dimension of grammatical patterns, when needed. What


remains to be worked out more carefully, though, is a consistent set of relevant
categories and the notational convention for the contextual dimension. The present
analysis has taken a rather brute-force approach by simply invoking attributes that
were necessary for addressing the data at hand (dp, genre, modality, etc.). It is pos-
sible and, perhaps, desirable to treat the contextual issues as a distinctly recogniz-
able layer within constructional representations, along the lines of several recent
proposals (Östman 2000, 2005, Fried & Östman 2005, Bergs 2005b) which call for
organizing the contextual features and categories into coherent representational
domains, akin to the notion of frame as used and applied in Frame Semantics.
Finally, as suggested in the introduction, the analysis has consequences for
addressing the grammaticalization/lexicalization dilemma and the PAs provide
material for further exploration of this actively debated question. One possibility
in addressing the PA’s conventionalization patterns is to emphasize the observa-
tion that the development may be lexically restricted (different verbs or verb sens-
es predispose their PAs toward different contextual and structural preferences), in
which case we could simply approach them one at a time, as independent cases of
lexicalization in the sense of turning an inflectional word form into an independ-
ent lexeme. At the same time, all the tokens share the same morphosemantic
structure and differ only in selecting which particular subsets of those initially
provided features will become highlighted, or obscured, in their use. It thus fol-
lows, that the development bears signs of grammaticalization as well, through the
generalization of certain semantic features and through the gradual enlisting of
the new usage (motivated by various contextual factors) for different syntactic
functions, in the sense of Traugott’s metonymy-based definition of grammaticali-
zation (Traugott 1992; Traugott & Dasher 2002). The constructional approach
seems to offer a way of reconciling the two sides of the problem, minimally by al-
lowing us to frame the distinction and its manifestations as a continuum, rather
than a strict opposition.

Notes

1. The genre selection includes historical, biblical, administrative, expository, and didactic
texts, legal documents, poetry (both spiritual and secular), popular entertainment, correspond-
ence, drama, instruction manuals, etc. The chronology covers the full OCz period, from the first
attestations well before 1300 until the early 1500s. The corpus contains over 1200 tokens of the
PA form, which represents more than 240 distinct verb roots. The form věřící is commonly at-
tested throughout the OCz period and its relatively high frequency across all kinds of texts can
be taken as evidence that the form was well entrenched, including in the genres that are known
to reflect spoken language fairly closely.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

2. The OCz texts are identified by the abbreviations established in the Old Czech Dictionary
(Staročeský slovník 1968).
3. Abbreviations in the glosses: NOM ‘nominative’, GEN ‘genitive’, ACC ‘accusative’, DAT ‘da-
tive’, INS ‘instrumental’, M/F/N ‘masculine/feminine/neuter’, SG/PL ‘singular/plural’, PA ‘parti-
cipial adjective’, PRES ‘present tense’, PST ‘past’, FUT ‘future’, NT ‘pres. active participle, PPL
‘past participle’, PASS ‘passive participle’, INF ‘infinitive’, RF ‘reflexive particle’, NEG ‘negative’,
AUX ‘auxiliary’, COND ‘conditional’.
4. While many of the manuscripts in the corpus can be dated quite precisely, many others can
only be placed within an estimated time period (a decade or more). For the present purposes, it
is sufficient to follow the practice established by the Old Czech Dictionary (Staročeský slovník
1968), which recognizes six chronological layers, each identified by reference to its upper bound-
ary ([up until] 1300, [up until] 1350, and so on).
5. The semantically unrestricted distribution of the verb correlates with the fact that it was
used in all kinds of genres, not just a particular type of administrative texts. Recall the example
in (2), which illustrates the contextually neutral nature of the verb.

References

Atkins, B..T. S. (1994). Analyzing the verbs of seeing: a frame semantics approach to corpus
lexicography. Berkeley Linguistic Society, 20, 42–56.
Atkins, Sue, Charles J. Fillmore, & Christopher R. Johnson (2003). ‘Lexicographic relevance:
selecting information from corpus evidence.’ International Journal of Lexicography, 16,
251–280.
Bergs, Alexander (2005a). Social networks and historical sociolinguistics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Bergs, Alexander (2005b). The future in context: a constructional approach. Paper presented in
The 9th International Pragmatics Conference, Riva del Garda, Italy.
Bhatia, Vijay K. (1993). Analyzing genre: language use in professional settings. London: Longman.
Biber, Douglas (1994). Dimensions of register variation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Biber, Douglas & Edward Finegan (1989). Drift and the evolution of English style: a history of
three genres. Language, 65, 487–517.
Bisang, Walter (1998). Grammaticalization and language contact, constructions, and positions.
In A. Giacalone Ramat & P. Hopper (Eds.), The limits of grammaticalization (13–58).
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Bybee, Joan, Rever Perkins & William Pagliuca (1994). The evolution of grammar: Tense, aspect
and modality in the languages of the world. Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press.
Croft, William (1991). Syntactic Categories and Grammatical relations. Chicago: The University
of Chicago Press.
Croft, William (2001). Radical Construction Grammar: Syntactic theory in typological perspec-
tive. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cuyckens, Hubert, René Dirven & John R. Taylor (Eds.) (2003). Cognitive approaches to lexical
semantics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1974/1981). Pragmatics and the description of discourse. In Ch. J. Fillmore,
G. Lakoff, & R. Lakoff (Eds.), Berkeley studies in syntax and semantics I (Chapter V). Dept.
 Mirjam Fried

of Linguistics, UC Berkeley. [(1981) In P. Cole (Ed.) Radical pragmatics (143–166). New


York: Academic Press.]
Fillmore, Charles J. (1982). Frame Semantics. In The Linguistic Society of Korea (Eds.), Linguis-
tics in the Morning Calm (111–137). Seoul: Hanshin Publishing Company.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1984). Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica,
6, 222–254.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1986). U-semantics, second round. Quaderni di Semantica, 8, 49–58.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1988). The mechanisms of ‘Construction Grammar’. Berkeley Linguistic So-
ciety, 14, 35–55.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1989). Grammatical Construction theory and the familiar dichotomies. In
R. Dietrich & C. F. Graumann (Eds.), Language processing in social context (17–38).
Amsterdam: North-Holland/Elsevier.
Fillmore, Charles J. & B.T.S. Atkins (1992). Toward a frame-based lexicon: The semantics of RISK
and its neighbors. In A. Lehrer & E. Feder Kittay (Eds.), Frames, fields, and contrasts: New essays
in semantic and lexical organization (75–102). Rahway, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Fillmore, Charles J., Paul Kay, & Mary Catherine O’Connor (1988). Regularity and idiomaticity
in grammatical constructions. Language, 64, 501–538.
Fillmore, Charles J., Miriam R. L. Petruck, Josef Ruppenhofer, & Abby Wright (2003). Frame
Net in action: The case of attaching. International Journal of Lexicography, 16, 297–332.
Fried, Mirjam (2003). Dimensions of syntactic change: Evidence from the long -nt- participle in
Old Czech texts. In R.A. Maguire & A. Timberlake (Eds.), American Contributions to the
13th International Congress of Slavists in Ljubljana (79–92). Slavica.
Fried, Mirjam (2004). Predicate semantics and event construal in Czech case marking. In M.
Fried & J-O. Östman (Eds.), Construction Grammar in a cross-language perspective (87–120).
Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Fried, Mirjam (2005). A frame-based approach to case alternations: The swarm-class verbs in
Czech. Cognitive Linguistics, 16, 475–512.
Fried, Mirjam (2008a). A Frame Semantic account of morphosemantic change: the case of Old
Czech věřící. In D. Divjak & A. Kochanska (Eds.), Cognitive paths into the Slavic domain
(283–315). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Fried, Mirjam (2008b). Constructions and constructs: Mapping a shift between predication and
attribution. In A. Bergs & G. Diewald (Eds.), Constructions and language change (47–79).
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Fried, Mirjam (In press). Grammaticalization and lexicalization effects in participial morphol-
ogy: A Construction Grammar approach to language change. In H. Cuyckens, K. Davidse,
& J-Ch. Verstraete (Eds.), Grammaticalization and grammar. Amsterdam & Philadelphia:
John Benjamins.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman (2003). The explicit and the implicit in the Suasion Frame. In
E. Hajičová, A. Kotěšovcová & Jiří Mírovský (Eds.), Proceedings of CIL 17, 1–22, CD-ROM.
Prague: Matfyzpress.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman (2004). Construction Grammar: A thumbnail sketch. In M.
Fried & J-O. Östman (Eds.), Construction Grammar in a cross-language perspective (11–86).
Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman (2005). Construction Grammar and spoken language: The
case of pragmatic particles. Journal of Pragmatics, 37, 1752–1778.
Representing contextual factors in language change 

Geeraerts, Dirk (1992). The return of hermeneutics to lexical semantics. In M. Putz (Ed.), Thir-
ty years of linguistic evolution: Studies in honor of René Dirven (257–282). Amsterdan &
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Geeraerts, Dirk (1993). Vagueness’s puzzles, polysemy’s vagaries. Cognitive Linguistics, 4, 223–
272.
Goldberg, Adele E. (2002). Surface generalizations: An alternative to alternations. Cognitive Lin-
guistics, 13, 327–356.
Haas, Florian (2005). The development of English each other – grammaticalization, lexicalisa-
tion, or both? Paper presented at the conference From Ideational to Interpersonal: Perspec-
tives from Grammaticalization, Leuven, Belgium.
Halmari, Helena & Tuija Virtanen (Eds.) (2005). Persuasion across genres. Amsterdam & Phila-
delphia: John Benjamins.
Harris, Alice C. (2003). Cross-linguistic perspectives on syntactic change. In B.D. Joseph & R.D.
Janda (Eds.), The handbook of historical linguistics (529–551). Blackwell.
Haspelmath, Martin (1994). Passive participles across languages. In B. Fox & P. J. Hopper (Eds.),
Voice: Form and function (151–177). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Haspelmath, Martin (1996). Word-class-changing inflection and morphological theory. In G. Booij
& J. van Marle (Eds.), Yearbook of Morphology 1995 (43–66). Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Himmelmann, Nikolaus P. (2004). Lexicalization and grammaticization: Opposite or orthogo-
nal? In B. Wiemer & W. Bisang (Eds.). What makes grammaticalization? (21–42). Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Hopper, Paul J. (1998). Emergent grammar. In M. Tomasello (Ed.), The New Psychology of Lan-
guage (155–175). New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum associates.
Kurz, Josef (1958). K otázce doby vzniku slovanských adjektiv složených a jejich původního
významu. In Studie ze slovanské jazykovědy, sborník k 70. narozeninám akademika Fr.
Trávníčka (211–219). Praha: SPN.
Linell, Per (1998). Approaching dialogue. Talk, interaction and contexts in dialogical perspectives.
Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Östman, Jan-Ola (2000). On the outskirts of ‘the periphery’: Construction Grammar meets the
Postcard Frame. Paper presented at the The 7th International Pragmatics Conference,
Budapest, Hungary.
Schenker, Alexander M. (1995). The Dawn of Slavic: An introduction to Slavic philology.
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Schultze-Berndt, Eva & Nikolaus P. Himmelmann (2004). Depictive secondary predicates in
crosslinguistic perspective. Linguistic Typology, 8, 59–131.
Short, David (1993). Czech. In B. Comrie & G.G. Corbett (Eds.) The Slavonic languages
(455–532). London & New York: Routledge.
Staročeský slovník [Old Czech Dictionary] (1968). Praha: Academia.
Swales, John (1990). Genre analysis: English in academic and research settings. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Traugott, Elizabeth Closs (1992). From less to more situated in language: The unidirectionality
of semantic change. In M. Kefer & J. van der Auwera (Eds.), Meaning and grammar: Cross-
linguistic perspectives (497–517). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Traugott, Elizabeth Closs (2003). Constructions in grammaticalization. In B.D. Joseph & R.D.
Janda (Eds.), The handbook of historical linguistics (624–647). Oxford: Blackwell.
Traugott, Elizabeth Closs (2008). The gammaticalization of N.P. of NP patterns. In A. Bergs & G.
Diewald (Eds.) Constructions and language change (23–45). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
 Mirjam Fried

Traugott, Elizabeth Closs & Richard B. Dasher (2002). Regularity in semantic change. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Wiemer, Björn (2004). The evolution of passives as grammatical constructions in Northern
Slavic and Baltic languages. In B. Wiemer & W. Bisang (Eds.). What makes grammaticaliza-
tion? (271–331). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Wiemer, Björn & Walter Bisang (2004). What makes grammaticalization? An appraisal of its
components and its fringes. In B. Wiemer & W. Bisang (Eds.). What makes grammaticaliza-
tion? (3–20). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Wischer, Ilse (2000). Grammaticalization versus lexicalization: ‘Methinks’ there is some confu-
sion. In O. Fischer, A. Rosenbach, & D. Stein (Eds.), In pathways of change: grammaticaliza-
tion in English (355–370). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
part 2

Interactional approaches
Grammatical constructions in dialogue

Per Linell
Department of Culture and Communication, Linköping University

1. Introduction1

Construction grammars take many shapes, from more formalistic ones to more
cognitive ones (Goldberg 1995; Fried & Östman, 2005; Croft & Cruse 2004). This
paper takes its point of departure in the analysis of talk-in-interaction and in dia-
logical theory. Such a theoretical framework will still share many assumptions
with Construction Grammar (CxG; Fried & Östman 2005), including of course
the insistence that a theory of grammar must be usage-based. Yet it is undeniable
that many variants of CxG suffer from an interactional deficit. I will therefore ar-
gue for a dialogical – a more interactional and contextual – theory and interpreta-
tion of grammatical constructions and lexical resources (Linell 2006a, 2009).

2. A dialogical conception of grammatical constructions

I take dialogical theory (or ‘dialogism’) (Linell 1998, 2009, and references there) to
be a general theoretical framework for the description and explanation of most
kinds of human action, cognition, communication and semiotic practices. It
stresses the dynamic use of linguistic resources in the construal of meaning in in-
teraction and contexts, whether the medium is spoken, written or electronic. That
is, the terms ‘dialogue’ and ‘dialogical’ are not used here exclusively with reference
to direct interactions between two or more mutually co-present individuals or
communicative systems, e.g. face-to-face interactions based on spoken language.
On the other hand, this is not to deny the significance of the metaphor of conver-
sation within many applications of dialogical theory. And indeed, I shall deal in
this paper with linguistic resources as used in talk-in-interaction.
One of the credos of dialogical theory is that, as regards language and lan-
guage use, we should always prefer explanations in terms of cognitive processing
and/or social action and interaction (e.g. constraints on turn design conditioned
by sequential contexts), and let purely structural (language-internal) accounts
 Per Linell

only stand proxy for such explanations. As applied to grammatical constructions,


this view is more in line with the interactional variant of cognitive grammar of
Ono & Thompson (1995), following Langacker (1987), than with formal CxG.
Ono & Thompson (1995) introduce the notion of ‘constructional schema’. Be-
low, I summarise their most important points:
1. Language users’ grammatical knowledge is organised in terms of ‘construc-
tional schemas’ that are relatively stable and have emerged from language us-
ers’ cumulative experiences of utterances. They are “schematizations over sets
of expressions parallel in formation, which are their instantiations” (p. 220).
2. Having once emerged in some form, a schema constitutes a pattern, according
to which speakers configure linguistic elements when they are faced with the
task of having to solve a particular communicative problem in a new situation.
3. Schemas are abstract prototypes (p. 217) with fuzzy boundaries (p. 220);
“[they] do not form a finite set, but are best understood as a dynamic and
constantly changing inventory” (p. 220).
4. From a formal point of view, constructional schemas can be phrases, clauses,
or multi-clause structures (p. 220). Schemas can be combined, linked to and
embedded within each other in different ways (p. 220).
5. The structure of each single schema is linked to principles such as “one clause
at a time” (Pawley & Syder, 1977) and “one new idea per intonation unit”
(Chafe, 1994).
6. Instantiations of schemas are negotiated locally, and are strongly influenced by
cognitive constraints, and by social constraints that emerge in and through the
situated interaction (p. 217).
Another interactionist account of constructions is that of Anward (1999). Anward
formulates nine theses, which I here collapse into five: Constructions are (i) utter-
ance types, i.e. abstractions from concrete utterances, or aspects of networks of re-
lated such utterances, but (ii) they are also lexicalised items with variable parts, (iii)
which are open and dynamic, both paradigmatically and syntagmatically. (iv) They
(or their instantiations/PL) are context-dependent as well as context-inducing, but
(v) at the same time, they have also been abstracted, “torn from contexts”, i.e. large-
ly decontextualised, although they still bring with them some residue of their former
contextual embeddedness when they become employed in new usage events.
Anward’s and Ono & Thompson’s points are obviously very closely related. In
principle, I would endorse all of them, but I will proceed beyond them in some
Grammatical constructions in dialogue 

respects, in particular in developing aspects of the external (or outer) syntax of


constructions, with three subaspects:
a. what conditions on prior sequences does (the occurrence of) a specific gram-
matical construction set up (these conditions being either specific require-
ments or merely preferences),
b. what conditions on subsequent sequences does it set up,
c. what are its preferred co-occurring resources?
This implies that we will be concerned with some aspects of sequential context(s)
when we consider grammatical constructions (cf. Anward’s point (iv)). I will argue
that some conditions of the kinds suggested by (a–c) can be part of the language
user’s knowledge of each and every grammatical construction.
Language users also have pragma-semantic knowledge linked to specific
grammatical constructions. At some level, they ‘know’ a great deal about what
kinds of meanings and functions constructions have and what sorts of pragmatic
effects one can achieve with them. Accordingly, this theory assumes that construc-
tional schemas, alias grammatical constructions, have integral meaning potentials
tied to themselves. Neither situated interpretations of utterances nor the meaning
potentials of the resources of language can be fully compositionally derived from
their constituent elements.
The central idea behind the notion of meaning potential is that no word or
grammatical construction has a completely fixed meaning (or function) that is
actualised in all its usage events, but instead, the meaning potential is a (structured)
set of affordances2 for sense-making that combines with contextual factors to yield
situated meanings in different ways in different situations (Norén & Linell 2007). I
shall use the term ‘functional potential’ for the meaning potential of a grammatical
construction (as opposed to a lexical item).

3. X-och-x – a responsive construction in Swedish

Research in interactional linguistics has demonstrated that talk in real interaction


is incrementally produced and in various senses co-constructed by several par-
ticipants (e.g. Auer 2007; Lindström 2006). Utterances are often co-constructed,
and they are always dependent on sequential links within connected discourse.
These links are either backward-pointing (‘responsive’) or forward-pointing
(‘projective’) (or both). If the concrete constructs, i.e. the situated utterances, have
these properties, then it seems reasonable to assume that at least some of the more
abstract constructions (schemas) used, i.e. the resources of language, have been
designed to be used in interaction and that they too include responsive and
 Per Linell

projective properties. The definition of such a ‘responsive construction’ is that its


linguistic form encodes (local) responsivity. This means that one can tell from the
morpho-syntactic (and prosodic) form of any instantiation that it cannot be the
first contribution in the discursive sequence (episode) where it occurs; instead, it
is responsive to some prior contribution, and sometimes, this prior contribution
too must exhibit a particular form.
Many constructions, and some of their instantiations, are of course not re-
sponsive in this narrow sense. For example, an utterance like It’s raining can occur
as the first (and even only) contribution to a conversational episode. On the other
hand, there are also many other responsive constructions in various (and arguably
all) languages. Some English examples are:
– various elliptical constructions,
– many question types (responsive questions), such as echo-questions: “am I sure?”
“do I read?”, and wh-questions with declarative word order: “you live where?”,
– the “incredulity response construction” (Lambrecht, 1990): “(what?) him wear
a tuxedo?”,
– more well-known constructions, such as the it-cleft,
– various contribution types (with a grammatical side), many of which have
been explored in Conversation Analysis, for example, and-prefaced questions
(Heritage & Sorjonen 1994) and so-initiated formulations (Drew 1998).
Yet, explicitly dialogical analyses of grammatical constructions have seldom been
made, but Wide (2002) provides one devoted to the responsive construction vera
búinn aδ in Icelandic.
For reasons of space, I shall focus on only one grammatical construction here,
that of x-och-x (i.e. ‘x-and-x’) in Swedish. This construction belongs to a subcate-
gory of responsive constructions that we may call ‘reactive’ constructions. In using
x-och-x, the speaker reacts to (or against) the use of a word or expression x occur-
ring in a prior utterance, and by repeating it (in this case: twice, with an interjacent
och ‘and’) in the beginning of his/her response, he or she reaccentuates it, negotiat-
ing and respecifying its situated meaning. Let us cite an example before going into
further details.3
(1) FLYTTA Å FLYTTA (sam:V1: 989ff) (there is ongoing talk in a dinner-
table conversation about a German family that was forced to leave Finland
after WW II)
1. G: sen så beslagtos huse å (0.5) dom flytta tilbaka
2. ti (0.7) ti Hamburg (å)
3. M: nå flytta å flytta men ja menar va (.) fan kan du
4. göra
Grammatical constructions in dialogue 

G: “then the house was confiscated and (0.5) they moved back to
(0.7) to Hamburg (and)”
M: “well (nå), moved and moved but I mean what (.) the hell can you do”
The speaker uses the x-och-x construction to comment on the situated use of a
particular expression x, suggesting that x is not quite situationally appropriate, al-
though not completely misplaced either. In (1), x is flytta ‘move (house)’, and
speaker M seems to cancel the sense aspect of ‘moving voluntarily’, whereas he
might still endorse another aspect, such as the more neutral semantic aspect of
‘changing one’s dwelling-place’.
In the terminology of Fillmore et al. (1988), x-och-x is a formal idiom. A better
term might be ‘schematic idiom’ (Croft & Cruse 2004: 234). The x-och-x segment
itself appears as a syntactically non-integrated element in the ‘pre-front field’
(cf. Auer 1996) of a turn or turn constructional unit (TCU). However, it is usually
prosodically integrated, rather than marked off (separated) (in the terms of Selting
2005: 21) with the following clausal segment. It contains two copies of an expres-
sion x (a morphological form of a lexeme) that has occurred in a prior utterance.
These two x’s are conjoined by och ‘and’, in conversational language almost always
in the phonological form /o/, usually rendered as å in spelling.
What the speaker does with x-och-x is to take an expression x from an imme-
diately prior utterance, place a reduplicated copy of it (x och x) in the pre-front
field of a new turn or turn-constructional unit, and follow this up with an utter-
ance in which the situated appropriacy of x in relation to the current topic is nego-
tiated. Thus, the construction has a semantic-pragmatic function, or rather func-
tional potential that cannot be entirely derived from its constituents, i.e. ‘x’ and
‘and’, and their meanings. I shall go into more pragmatic-semantic details below.
X-och-x occurs mainly in conversational language, that is, in actual talk-in-
interaction as well as in certain written and electronic genres (e.g. chat, weblogs)
in Swedish, and similarly at least in Danish, Norwegian, and Finnish. There is no
direct counterpart of x-och-x in English; in our example (1), we could render the
meaning of “moved and moved” approximately as “moved?, it depends on what
you mean by that”. In German, you may compare the formal idiom Was heisst
schon x? (or x oder nicht x).
The source of x is usually in the interlocutor’s prior contribution, as in (1), but
it can also occur in the speaker’s own utterance. There are many similarities be-
tween the other-responsive and self-responsive uses, but also some formal and
pragma-semantic differences (for details, see Lindström & Linell 2007). Here, I
shall cite one more other-responsive example (2), and then provide a self-respon-
sive example (3).4
 Per Linell

(2) MÅNGA Å MÅNGA (TemaK:B9:4:6) (from the very start of a talk at a


maternity clinic between a doctor (D) and a pregnant woman (W);
D wonders if W is used to being tape-recorded in connection with her
visits to the clinic)
1. D: jaha du e van vi de här å-eh (.) bli inspelade¿
2. W: ja=
3. D: =du har (.) haft många inspelade samtal eller¿
4. W: ja-eh (.) många å många men de e nåra stycken
5. så de--
D: “okay (jaha), you are used to this ah (.) being tape-recorded?”
W: “yeah”
D: “you have (.) had many conversations recorded, or...¿”
W: “well (ja-eh) (.), many and many, but there are quite a few, so it’s --”
In (2), the speaker objects to the use of många ‘many’, without downright denying
its relevance. X-och-x accomplishes some kind of devaluation or downgrading of
x, that is, from, say, ‘a large number’ to ‘some’ or ‘quite a few’.
(3) NORMAL Å NORMAL (Swedish Radio; a H(istorian) is being interviewed
by an I(interviewer) on the topic of elite schools, so-called Napola schools,
in Nazi Germany and their possible role in promoting Aryan elitism)
1. H: […] eh (.) °ja° de va (.) delvis normal skolgång
2. men-eh (.) eller ja, normal å normal °men° (.)
3. man ägnade mycke tid åt fysisk fostran å gymnastik
4. å sedan så småningom också (.) militära övningar.
5. I: så man höll på å kasta handgranater å skjuta me
6. gevär?
H: “ah (.) well (ja) it was (.) a partly normal schooling but ah or well
(ja), normal and normal (.) but one devoted much time to phys-
ical education and exercises and then gradually also (.) to mili-
tary practices.”
I: “so one was busy throwing hand-grenades and shooting with rifles?”
What the speaker does in (3) is to question in retrospect his own use of the term
‘normal’ (in line 1). However, he does not take it back completely. Rather he seems
to suggest that some military education was ‘normal’ in the specific historical con-
text, but that military exercises would not be considered ‘normal’ in today’s com-
prehensive schools. One may perhaps see this as a downgrading on a scale of ‘nor-
mality’. When x-och-x is self-responsive, it is partly reminiscent of what
Couper-Kuhlen & Thompson (2005) have descibed as ‘concessive repair’ in English
Grammatical constructions in dialogue 

data. An example would be the following (2005: 263): a school teacher has com-
plained about the unruliness of the children in class, saying that she needs to get it
all off her mind, and then mentions that she will have an in-service training the
day after: so I can switch off. well, not really switch off but you know, relax. This
concessive repair involves a response to a prior description (here: “switch off ”),
treating it as “partially unjustified”, as an “overstatement” (she did not mean “re-
ally switch off ”), and then following it up with a “revised statement”, which does
not, however, imply a complete “backing down” (“you know: relax”). In contrast to
x-och-x, however, ‘concessive repair’ is always self-responsive, and is not as tightly
grammaticalised. While concessive repair is a conversational practice, x-och-x is
clearly a grammatical construction. Furthermore, x-och-x is probably less of a re-
pair; it treats the deployment of the expression x as in fact partially justified in the
context at hand.

4. Conditions on x-och-x as a construction

Space restrictions exclude both further examples and a detailed analysis of, for in-
stance, conversational (impromptu) vs. written (and therefore sometimes edited)
usages. (Lindström & Linell (2007) provide a comprehensive analysis.). Instead, I
will consider here what properties of x-och-x one might want to specify in a more
precise dialogical analysis of the construction. I shall distinguish between formal-
grammatical and semantic-pragmatic aspects. Among the former, I shall talk about
conditions of internal structure, and conditions on ‘outer syntax’ (co-text) of three
kinds: conditions on antecedent segments (i.e. on prior contributions to the local
sequence), subsequent segments, and co-occurring linguistic resources.

4.1 Formal-grammatical aspects

The primary condition on antecedent strings is of course the following:


i. If an expression x (a morphological form of a lexical item x) occurs in the
preceding turn constructional unit (TCU) or turn, x-och-x may be used.
This rule articulates a necessary condition in the sense that x-och-x is an option if
and only if x does occur in the prior discourse. This is also what makes x-och-x
into a responsive (and reactive) construction. (In very exceptional cases, this rule
can be flouted when a speaker begins a new communicative episode with an in-
stance of x-och-x. But then, a prior occurrence of x will be tacitly inferred and
imagined by the hearer.) However, (i) is not a sufficient condition (nor are the
 Per Linell

other conditions below sufficient conditions); if an expression x occurs in an utter-


ance, it is of course not necessary to follow it up with x-och-x.
Other, non-obligatory but enabling conditions are: X-och-x is more probable,
ii. if x is focally stressed in the prior (source) utterance,
iii. if x is rhematic in that utterance, and
iv. if the source utterance is interrogative (this applies only when x-och-x is other-
responsive).
The interpretation of each such condition is that if the condition is satisfied, the
probability that x-och-x will be used in the following utterance is increased
(presupposing of course that condition (i) is satisfied in the first place). In our ex-
ample (1), (ii) and (iii) are satisfied, but not (iv). In (2), (iv) too is partially satisfied.
As we have seen (cf. also condition (x) below), the speaker of x-och-x questions the
situational appropriacy of x. If the source x is already placed in an interrogative
utterance (condition (iv)), we can, in some instances, talk about a collaborative
construction of uncertainty and its elimination (example (2)).
As regards the internal structure of the x-och-x segment itself, we might posit
the following obligatory conditions:
v. x-och-x occurs in the ‘pre-front field’ of a new turn or TCU,
vi. x in x-och-x is repeated (twice) in the same morphological form as in the
source utterance,5
vii. both x’s (or at least the second one) are focally stressed,
viii. the x-och-x segment itself is prosodically (but not syntactically!) integrated
with the subsequent utterance.
Co-occurring constructions are other linguistic devices and constructions that
speakers tend to ‘co-select’. In traditional terms, x-och-x is preferably “constructed
with” certain other resources. Thus, the following condition is optional:
ix. x-och-x often co-occurs with distancing responsive particles (in the examples
here: nå, ja, ja-eh) and concessive markers, especially in self-responsive cases
(eller ‘or’ (cf. example (3): line 2), i alla fall ‘anyway’, etc.).
In coherent discourse, especially within the bounds of local contributions, speak-
ers routinely make semantic specifications that involve the use of several (usually
convergent) semiotic resources (Deppermann 2005: ‘co-selection’). Co-selected
resources “reciprocally constrain and specify each other’s local interpretation”
(Deppermann, 2005: 306). Therefore, such resources often become associated with
each other. In this case, the lexicalised grammatical construction x-och-x is (para-
digmatically and syntagmatically) associated with distancing particles and conces-
sive markers, as a sedimented result of speakers’ co-selection routines.
Grammatical constructions in dialogue 

Finally, moving on to the subsequent contribution, we find:


x. after the x-och-x segment, it is obligatory to proceed with an utterance that –
for current communicative purposes – confirms (or foregrounds) some as-
pects and simultaneously cancels (or backgrounds) other aspects of x’s mean-
ing potential.
Note that unlike the antecedent condition, this subsequent part is necessarily present:
x-och-x does not occur without this kind of continuation.6 This fact (together with
condition (viii)) may be taken as an argument for regarding this subsequent seg-
ment as part of (the internal structure of) the grammatical construction itself.

4.2 Semantic-pragmatic aspects

The subsequent segment is closely related to the semantic-pragmatic functions of


x-och-x. As we have seen, what the x-och-x construction does is usually to prob-
lematise one (central) sub-sense of the meaning of x, and to enhance another as
situationally appropriate. One might say that the construction is a grammatical-
ised method of initiating a local meta-linguistic discussion and semantic analysis
of the situated use of x, and this deliberation necessarily involves consideration of
x’s lexical meaning. That is, in using the construction, the speaker exploits the
meaning potential of x as a communicative resource. In fact, precisely this – nego-
tiating which semantic aspects of x will apply – can be seen as the core of the
construction’s own functional potential. This amounts to another argument for in-
cluding (what I just called) the subsequent segment (cf. condition (x)) within the
grammatical construction itself. In our example (1), as we noted, what is ques-
tioned is the appropriacy of using flytta ‘move (house)’ in a situation in which the
people moving had no other choice; it seems that flytta is often taken to mean
‘move voluntarily’, and this is the aspect of the meaning potential that is being
cancelled here. At the same time, other aspects of the meaning potential are pos-
sibly supported in (1), such as ‘changing one’s dwelling place’.
The analysis of x-och-x usage events involving different lexemes can be used as
an illuminating case of probing the interaction between grammar and lexis in au-
thentic language use. Accordingly, Norén & Linell (2007) analyse the interaction
of x-och-x with different kinds of lexemes, and demonstrate that the construction
has somewhat different semantic-pragmatic effects depending on the meaning po-
tential of the lexical item (x) with which it interacts. X-och-x is often applied to
items with a quantitative or scalar semantics, and it downgrades or contextualises
the situated value of x. In this respect, a quantifier like många ‘many’ in (2) clearly
belongs to another semantic category than flytta ‘move’ in (1). A word like normal
‘normal’ is not unambiguously scalar in its semantics, but Norén & Linell (2007)
 Per Linell

argue that the construction may sometimes foreground or actually construct a


scale-dependent interpretation of x. In (3), the military exercises were ‘normal’
only in the particular socio-historical environment talked about, that is, the con-
versationalists construe it as a case placed somewhere towards the lower end of a
scale of (general) ‘normality’.

5. General conclusions: Constructions in dialogue

My topic in this paper is not x-och-x per se (see Lindström & Linell 2007), nor
dialogical linguistics in general (see Linell 2006a, 2009). Rather, I am interested in
what the study of responsive constructions can teach us, when it comes to remedy
the interactional deficit in Construction Grammar. By way of summary, I shall
draw attention to three or four points in a dialogical (contextual, interactional)
conception of a grammatical construction.
Contexts, including linguistic co-texts, sanction specific linguistic resources,
and at the same time, contexts are themselves evoked or made relevant by the lat-
ter (Anward; see above). The first point is therefore that the situated occurrrences
and interpretations of particular utterances involve sequential dependencies; ut-
terances have backward-pointing (‘responsive’) and forward-pointing (‘projective’)
properties. In other words, grammatical constructions are made to fit into se-
quences of real coherent sequences of sense-making in talk (or text). Some con-
structions have actually encoded such relations. X-och-x is such a responsive con-
struction; language users’ knowledge about this linguistic resource includes
knowledge about antecedent and subsequent strings, as well as about co-occurring
resources. Accordingly, such constructions do not only have an internal structure;
they also have an external syntax with (at most) three parts: antecedent segments,
subsequent segments, and co-occurring resources.
Secondly, grammatical constructions are concerned with actions and doings;
they should be thought of in terms of methods, procedures or operations. Com-
municatively, they make a change, a ‘difference that makes a difference’, to the
micro-situations in which they occur. The use of x-och-x changes, however little,
the understanding of the current situation and its discoursal topic. Linguistically,
constructions are operations on form and meaning, operating on some linguistic
material and returning something else. On the structural, product-oriented side,
they are oriented to the (speaker’s) design and production of utterances or utter-
ance parts with a particular linguistic structure. In CxG jargon, the abstract ‘con-
struction’ licenses or authorises the ‘construct’ instantiated.
Within an overall dialogical framework, we would like to capture methods,
procedures and operations, and more generally: actions and processes. If, then, we
Grammatical constructions in dialogue 

try to account formally for grammatical constructions, this is not exclusively a mat-
ter of dealing with constituent structure, as in most grammatical theories, includ-
ing CxG (despite its basis in e.g. Fillmore’s semantics of understanding), but with
methods used by the parties to the interaction. Furthermore, while syntacticians
(and compositionalists in semantics) usually deal only with the internal structure,
a dialogical linguistics must also take external syntax into consideration.
The third point, too, is related to the preceding considerations. A grammatical
construction has pragma-semantic properties that cannot be exhaustively derived
from its constituent parts. We must assume, of course, that some loose form of
compositionality is needed for assigning interpretations to new complex expres-
sions, but strict compositionality is impossible. First, we can of course not compute
interpretations of situated utterance tokens without contextual information
(and relevant contexts cannot be specified in advance). Secondly, as several schol-
ars in cognitive linguistics and construction grammar (e.g. Goldberg 1995: 13ff.)
have argued, strict compositionality does not hold on an abstract ‘structural’ level
either; specific constructions have semantic properties that cannot be composi-
tionally derived. A grammatical construction involves a specific semantic operation
that is tied to the construction as a whole. In the case of x-och-x, the construction is
mainly reactive: it negotiates the meaning of an expression x occurring in the prior
discourse, and modifies or revises the interpretation to be accepted locally.
This in turn implies that the grammar as a whole will register similar informa-
tion at many places. Such a ‘maximalistic’ assumption, which is opposed to the
dominant minimalism of many models of theoretical linguistics (Cappelen &
Lepore 2005), is nowadays commonplace in both usage-based approaches, such as
construction grammar (Fried & Östman 2005), and in some more theoretical ap-
proaches to semantics (Recanati 2004). Specific constructions may inherit proper-
ties from more abstract constructions. For example, x-och-x undoubtedly belongs
to a family of reactive constructions with several properties in common (Lind-
ström & Linell 2007). Certain linguistic resources are frequently co-selected (see
above), and such resources are arguably associated with similar information at
several places in the language user’s knowledge of his or her language.
Fourth, I have been reasonably specific about various conditions associated
with x-och-x in this paper. Such constraints on the use of x-och-x could arguably
be formalised in a suitable notation. However, we must be aware that a complete
formalisation is not necessarily the ultimate goal. This is argued in Linell (2006b)
with particular reference to x-och-x. Formalisation is not a neutral or “innocent”
meta-linguistic description, but it transforms its own subject matter. If we think of
the subject matter as the dynamic practices of sense-making, and the resources
used in these practices, formal accounts tend to respecify these in terms of static
semantic frames and syntactic structures that are assumed to exist somehow
 Per Linell

abstracted from language use. If we think of language dialogically, as involving ac-


tions in situations in the world, we can not simply equate situated meanings with
tokens of abstract fixed types. While I would definitely insist that grammatical
constructions and meaning potentials do exist as such, in addition to and in one
sense partly independently on the situated usage events, as accumulated resources
in the situation-transcending practices of language use; these resources are, after
all, only made manifest, actualised, in these real usage events.

Notes

1. This paper builds upon joint work with Jan Lindström (Helsinki) and Kerstin Norén
(Karlstad). The paper was first read in a workshop on “Context in Construction Grammar”
organised by Jan-Ola Östman and Mirjam Fried at IPrA IX, Riva del Garda, Italy, July 14, 2005.
I am grateful to all these colleagues, as well as to other participants in the workshop. My own
work was supported by a grant from the Swedish Research Council (No. 421–2004–1087). The
author can be contacted at the following e-mail address: Per.Linell@liu.se
2. The notion of affordance comes from Gibson’s (1979) theory of perception. For the applica-
tion to language, see e.g. Thibault (2005).
3. The examples used here are drawn from a corpus of tape-recorded cases (Lindström &
Linell 2007). Here I have simplified transcripts. The particular x-och-x segment and its source in
a prior utterance are given in bold-face. In this paper, each example is followed by an approxi-
mate rendition in English, in which the x-och-x phrase has been translated word-by-word de-
spite the fact that it lacks an idiomatic English counterpart.
4. (.) marks a micro-pause. Underlining (of a syllable nucleus, i.e. a vowel sign) indicates
focal stress.
5. There are some (non-random) exceptions to this. See Lindström & Linell (2007).
6. Just like in the case of the necessary condition (i), condition (x) can occasionally be flouted,
with particular rhetorical effects.

References

Anward, Jan (1999). Constructing an interactionist account of constructions. Paper presented at


Workshop on Construction and Interaction, Helsinki, September 1999.
Auer, Peter (1996). The pre-front field in spoken German and its relevance as a grammaticaliza-
tion position. Pragmatics, 6(3), 295–322.
Auer, Peter (2007). Syntax als Prozess. In H. Hausendorf (Ed.), Gespräch als Prozess. Tübingen:
Narr.
Cappelen, Herman & Ernie Lepore (2005). Insensitive semantics. A defense of semantic minimal-
ism and speech act pluralism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Chafe, Wallace (1994). Discourse, consciousness and time. Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press.
Grammatical constructions in dialogue 

Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth & Sandra A. Thompson (2005). A linguistic practice for retracting
overstatements: ‘Concessive repair’. In A. Hakulinen & M. Selting (Eds.), Syntax and lexis in
conversation (257–288). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Croft, William & D. Alan Cruse (2004). Cognitive linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Deppermann, Arnulf (2005). Conversational interpretation of lexical items and conversational
contrasting. In A. Hakulinen & M. Selting (Eds.), Syntax and lexis in conversation (289–317).
Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Drew, Paul (1998). An exercise in the comparative analysis of talk-in-interaction in different
(institutional) settings: the case of ‘formulations’. In H. Lehti-Eklund (Ed.). Samtalsstudier
[‘Conversational studies’] (29–42). Helsinki: Department of Scandinavian Languages and
Literature.
Fillmore, Charles, Paul Kay & Mary K. O’Connor (1988). Regularity and idiomaticity in gram-
matical constructions: the case of let alone. Language, 64, 501–538.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman (2005). Construction Grammar: A thumbnail sketch. In
M. Fried & J.-O. Östman (Eds.), Construction Grammar in a cross-language perspective
(11–86). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Gibson, James (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.
Goldberg, Adele (1995). Constructions: A Construction Grammar approach to argument struc-
ture. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Heritage, John & Marja-Leena Sorjonen (1994). Constituting and maintaining activities across
sequences: and-prefacing as a feature of question-design. Language in Society, 23, 1–29.
Lambrecht, Knud (1990). What, me worry: Mad Magazine sentences revisited. In D. J. Costa
(Ed.), Proceedings from the Sixteenth Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistic Society
(215–228). Berkeley, CA.: Berkeley Linguistic Society.
Langacker, Ronald (1987). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, Vol. 1: Theoretical prerequisites.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Lindström, Jan (2006). Interactional linguistics. In J.-O. Östman & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Hand-
book of Pragmatics 2006. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Lindström, Jan & Per Linell (2007). X-och-x som samtalspraktik och grammatisk konstruktion.
[‘X-och-x as a conversational practice and grammatical construction’]. In E. Engdahl &
A.-M. Londen (Eds.), Interaktion och kontext (19–89). Lund: Studentlitteratur.
Linell, Per (1998). Approaching dialogue: Talk, interaction and contexts in dialogical perspectives.
Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Linell, Per (2006a). Towards a dialogical linguistics. In M. Lähteenmäki, H. Dufva, S. Leppänen,
& P. Varis (Eds.), The XIIth International Bakhtin Conference: Proceedings (152–167).
Jyväskylä, Finland: Department of Languages.
Linell, Per (2006b). Can we formalise the linguistic resources of interactional language? In M.
Suominen et al. (Eds.), A Man of Measure: Festschrift in Honour of Fred Karlsson on his
60th Birthday. Special Supplement to SKY Journal of Linguistics, 19, 56–65. Turku: The
Linguistic Association of Finland.
Linell, Per (2009). Rethinking language, mind and world dialogically: Interactional and contex-
tual theories of human sense-making. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
Norén, Kerstin & Per Linell (2007). Meaning potentials and the interaction between lexis and
grammar: Some empirical substantiations. Pragmatics, 17, 387–416.
 Per Linell

Ono, Tsuyoshi & Sandra A. Thompson (1995). What can conversation tell us about syntax? In
Ph. Davis (Ed.), Descriptive and theoretical modes in alternative linguistics (213–271).
Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Pawley, Andrew & Frances Syder (1977). The one clause at a time hypothesis. Unpublished
manuscript.
Recanati, François (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Selting, Margret (2005). Syntax and prosody as methods for the construction and identification
of turn-constructional units in conversation. In A. Hakulinen & M. Selting (Eds.), Syntax
and lexis in conversation (17–44). Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Thibault, Paul (2005). The interpersonal gateway to the meaning of mind: the inter- and intraor-
ganism perspective on language. In R. Hasan, C. Matthiessen & J. Webster (Eds.), Continu-
ing discourse on language: A functional perspective (117–156). London: Equinox.
Wide, Camilla (2002). Perfect in dialogue: Form and functional potential of the vera búinn a∂ +
inf. construction in contemporary Icelandic (PIC Monographs, 3). Helsinki: Department of
Scandinavian Languages and Literature.
Interactional Construction Grammar
Contextual features of determination
in dialectal Swedish

Camilla Wide

1. Introduction1

This paper discusses the role of context in Construction Grammar (CxG) and the
question of how contextual features can and should be included in the Construc-
tion Grammar formalism. I will show that certain contextual features need to be
included in the formalism if we want to describe spoken language constructions
properly. More specifically, I will suggest a solution that builds upon a combina-
tion of Construction Grammar with Interactional Linguistics (IL), which is an
interdisciplinary and a cross-linguistic approach to language. The methodological
foundation of IL is Conversation Analysis (CA). The other disciplines that have
contributed to IL are discourse-functional linguistics and linguistic anthropology
(see Schegloff, Ochs & Thompson 1996; Couper-Kuhlen & Selting 2001).
As Fillmore points out (1988: 35), the framework of Construction Grammar is
a moving target. There are thus several ‘construction grammars’ available (cf. Östman
& Fried 2005). When I talk about Construction Grammar (CxG) in this paper, I
refer to the original approach initiated by Charles J. Fillmore (e.g. 1988, 1989) and
further developed by, among others, Fried and Östman (e.g. 2004).
The pragmatic dimension has always played an important role in CxG (see in
particular Fillmore 1996). Fillmore (1989: 32) stresses the role of interaction and
points out that in CxG “numerous grammatical constructions are described as
instruments of interaction”. However, in practice, interactional features have not
been described or investigated to any greater extent in work within CxG. Fried &
Östman (2004: 24) point out that CxG until very recently has had a fairly narrow
view of pragmatics: “pragmatic force and effect have been recognized primarily as
conveyed through conventions of language, not in terms of conversational reason-
ing or socio-cultural constraints and possibilities”. In addition to this, spoken
 Camilla Wide

language has, according to Fried & Östman (2005: 1753), played a fairly modest
role within CxG:
the bulk of constructional research has not been particularly concerned with ana-
lyzing spoken data beyond noting, occasionally, that a specific syntactic pattern
may have different manifestations in spoken language from what it has in ‘stand-
ard’ grammar [...].

The purpose of this paper is to contribute to some of these less investigated areas
of CxG, specifically spoken language and interaction. In addition to this, my study2
deals with another aspect of language that has traditionally not been in the center
of grammatical investigation: grammatical constructions in regional non-standard
dialects. In the empirical part of the article, I will discuss an adnominal demon-
strative construction in the Swedish dialects of eastern Nyland in Finland (the area
to the east of the capital Helsinki). An instantiation of the construction is shown
in (1) below.
(1) va må de ‘klåkka-n ska vara?
what may that/the clock [=time]-the shall be
‘what time is it?’ (Natural observation, 2004)
The construction, which consists of the pronoun de(n) ‘that’ and a noun with a
suffix of definiteness (de ‘klåkka-n ‘that/the clock-the’), has syntactic parallels but
no direct communicative-functional parallels in the standard Swedish language.
As indicated in the glosses to example (1), the form de (also pronounced te) could
be interpreted as the preposed definite article den ‘the’, which in standard Swedish
is only used in front of modified nouns (cf. bil-en ‘car-the’ vs. den röda bil-en ‘the
red car-the’). Forms with the demonstrative pronoun den ‘that’ do occur in front
of nouns that are not modified in standard Swedish. However, in these cases the
function is to point out a referent or underline a contrast (cf. Ge mig boken ‘Give
me the book’ vs. Ge mig den boken ‘Give me that book’), which is obviously not the
case in example (1). In order to describe the function of the eastern Nyland con-
struction from a CxG point of view it is thus necessary to capture the contextual
features of the construction in an adequate way.
The paper is organized as follows. In the next section, I will compare the no-
tions of ‘construction’ in CxG and in IL. Sections 3–5 present my empirical analy-
sis of the eastern Nyland construction and make a comparison with other con-
structions in the eastern Nyland dialects as well as in standard Swedish. In Section
6, the results of the empirical analysis are discussed from a theoretical point of
view in terms of how the contextual constraints on the eastern Nyland construc-
tion can be described using CxG formalism, without contradicting the findings
about spoken language and interaction arrived at through IL.
Interactional construction grammar 

2. The notion of ‘construction’

In their comparison of Construction Grammar and Interactional Linguistics Fried


& Östman (2005) stress the similarities between the two approaches, for example,
the fact that both approaches take all ‘chunks’ of language as equally important for
analysis and description. Furthermore, Fried & Östman conclude that among dia-
logical approaches to language (see Linell 1998), Conversation Analysis (CA)
“– and especially its further development of Interactional Linguistics – is the clos-
est to CxG in its interactional objectives and interests” (2005: 1754). This closeness
is also reflected in works on Interactional Linguistics, among others, Ono &
Thompson (1995) and Linell (2004, 2005, this volume), who refer explicitly to
Construction Grammar (see also Günthner & Imo 2006, Imo 2007). However,
Fried & Östman (2005: 1756) point out some differences between the approaches,
such as the focus on the outcome in CxG vs. on process in CA, and suggest that a
fertile starting point is to “accept that CxG and CA are compatible approaches that
do different things and aspire to do different things, but they accomplish their
goals in a complementary manner”.
Both CxG and IL are usage-based approaches. One of the main points made
about IL is that it takes non-experimental, everyday performance as the basis for
linguistic description (Steensig 2001: 12, see also Couper-Kuhlen & Selting
2001: 4–5). In contrast to many paradigms within generative linguistics (the
Chomskyan paradigm in particular) linguistic performance plays an important
role also in CxG since grammatical constructions should be cognitively and com-
municatively plausible per se (cf. Fillmore 1989; Fried & Östman 2004: 76). How-
ever, the use of data has different implications for the analyses conducted in IL and
CxG respectively. In IL, the data consist of recorded and transcribed naturally-oc-
curring conversations. The goal of the analysis is to capture what patterns the par-
ticipants of the conversation orient towards and how they make this orientation
explicit. Special attention is paid to factors like sequentiality, co-construction and
act-activity interdependence (Linell 2004: 8). These factors are analyzed in depth
by reference to often rather long extracts. By contrast, in CxG, the data generally
consist of isolated sentences, which provide a limited amount of contextual infor-
mation (for some noteworthy exceptions, see Fujii 2004; Fried & Östman 2005).
In CxG a construction is an abstract representational entity, that is, “a conven-
tional pattern of linguistic structure that provides a general blueprint for licensing
well-formed linguistic expressions” (Fried & Östman 2004: 18). Actually occurring
linguistic expressions are not called constructions but rather constructs. Ono &
Thompson (1995) and Linell (2004, 2005) also point out that grammatical patterns
are to be seen as schematic rather than specific. According to Ono & Thompson,
constructions consist of “schematizations over sets of expressions parallel in forma-
 Camilla Wide

tion, which are their instantiations” (1995: 220). A ‘constructional schema’, which is
the term Ono & Thompson use (following the cognitive grammar tradition, see
Langacker 2008: 215–227), thus serves as a template for analogous expressions.
A major tenet of CxG is that form and meaning (or function) form an inte-
grated whole in grammatical constructions (Fillmore 1989: 19, Kay 1995: 171,
Fried & Östman 2004: 12). This goes well with an interactional perspective of lan-
guage, where linguistic forms are seen primarily in the light of what function they
have or acquire in interaction (cf. Couper-Kuhlen & Selting 2001: 6–7). However,
although construction grammarians like Fillmore (1989: 32) stress the role of in-
teraction, concepts such as ‘meaning’, ‘function’ and ‘interaction’ are applied in dif-
ferent ways in CxG and IL. In IL taking interactional features into account means
showing and describing explicitly how participants in a conversation use linguistic
resources or patterns in order to do things in the interaction. Meaning and func-
tion are treated as conventionalized but partly open and negotiable aspects of lin-
guistic items, that is, as potentials rather than as fixed values (see Norén & Linell
2007). As Linell (1998: 113) points out, these potentials, however, “are never suffi-
cient for determining communicative meaning”. Thus, even though constructions
are based on speakers’ and listeners’ earlier experiences of situations and contexts
they can be locally managed, negotiated and adapted to new situations. It is there-
fore not possible to predict exactly what function a specific construct will acquire
in situated use. In addition to this, speakers and listeners, as Ono & Thompson
(1995: 217) point out, seem to be “highly tolerant of utterances which, because of
such phenomena as reformulations and repetitions, only roughly approximate any
‘constructional schema’, or which blend more than one schema”.
Treating meaning and function as potentialities requires contextual features to be
accounted for in descriptions – and formalizations – of constructions. This is in the-
ory not a problem for CxG. Fillmore (1989: 33) explicitly stresses the role of context:
the abstraction of linguistic knowledge away from context is rejected outright in
the constructionist view, since a part of the understanding of grammatical con-
structions is knowing, one at a time, what they are for and what principles guide
their choice.

Fried & Östman (2005) even mention that constructions can be seen as potenti-
alities. However, contextual features are included to a very limited extent in the
actual formalization of constructions in CxG studies. When they are formalized,
the features are analyzed in different terms than in IL. For example, the concept of
the speech act, which is one of the pragmatic attributes Fried & Östman (2005)
use, is considered problematic in IL since it has traditionally been used to analyze
sentences in isolation (see Linell 1998: 208–212). This reflects a more general
difference between CxG and IL. Whereas studies on IL argue that language is
Interactional construction grammar 

dynamic and has to be treated as such, studies on CxG stress the fact that all parts
of language, including contextual and interactional features, can be described in
terms of discrete feature structures (cf. Fried & Östman 2004: 30). Anward (1999),
however, points out that constructions should be seen as types that originally
emerged out of typified utterances (see also Linell, this volume). Constructions are
thus affected by cognitive and social constraints arising from interaction (Ono &
Thompson 1995: 217) and should be analyzed and explained in relation to the
situated discursive and interpretive activities themselves. Linell (2005: 281) points
out that certain constructions may be restricted to or at least overrepresented in
certain activities or communicative genres. Furthermore, many constructions
have responsive or projective features (cf. Wide 2002), which may constrain the
preceding and following turns, that is, the ‘external context’ in a wider sense than
what is usually accounted for with the concept in CxG (cf. Fillmore 1988: 36).
In the following sections, I will illustrate empirically the relevance of account-
ing for contextual and interactional features in a dynamic way when describing
spoken language constructions. I start with a presentation of the demonstrative
construction in eastern Nyland, and a discussion of why the construction is inter-
esting from the point of view of Swedish grammar and CxG. After that, I present
the major functions of the construction in authentic conversation. The empirical
part of the study ends with a formalization of the construction in which contextual
and interactional features are taken into account. My argument for why a formali-
zation should be done is the following. If contextual and interactional features are,
as I argue, part of constructions, such features should also be shown as explicitly as
possible; and the most explicit way of accounting for features is to suggest a for-
malization in terms of attribute-value matrices. If such an attempt is not made, we
cannot be sure that CxG gives an adequate picture of language and language use.

3. Structural aspects of the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction

The demonstrative construction in eastern Nyland contains the following


components:
(2) den/det (sg.), de (pl.) + noun + suffix of definiteness
‘the/that’ ‘the/those’ ‘the’
In (2), the construction is presented in standard (written) Swedish, as opposed to
the eastern Nyland dialect in which den would be te/de. In the remainder of the
paper, I will use the conventions of written Swedish only when I discuss examples
from standard Swedish.3 In examples from eastern Nyland dialects, I use the
Swedish alphabet to represent the eastern Nyland pronunciation. Thus, long
 Camilla Wide

sounds are marked with double vowels or consonants (e.g. frååga ‘ask’). Further-
more, the quality of vowels and consonants is spelled as pronounced. Thus, the
plural form [tom] ‘they’, for example, is spelled tåm/dåm (not tom/dom) since the
representation of [o] in Swedish is generally å (cf. example (9) below).
As examples (3)–(4) below show, the pronoun/article den ‘that, the’ is un-
stressed and pronounced [te] or [de] in the singular in the eastern Nyland dialects.
The variation between the t- and d-forms is related to dialect leveling; t-forms oc-
cur in rural dialects and d-forms are used in town dialects. Both forms are used
with all types of nouns. The eastern Nyland dialects thus do not make the standard
Swedish gender distinction between den – det for singular non-neuter and neuter
words, respectively. (Cf. standard Swedish den klocka-n ‘that clock-the’ (non-neu-
ter) and det jordbruk-et ‘that farm-the’ (neuter) with de klåkka-n ‘that clock-the’
and te joordbruuk-i ‘the farm-the’ in examples (3) and (4)).
(3) Så möött an ein bisi. Te ‘bisi-n frååga [...]
then met he a man that/the man-the asked
Så gav te ‘bisi-n åt ånån ein tjepp.
then gave that/the man-the to him a stick
‘Then he met a man. The man asked... Then the man gave him a stick.’
(NFOS 1896: 17)
(4) va må de ‘klåkka-n ska vara?
what may that/the clock [=time]-the shall be
‘what time is it?’ (Natural observation, 2004)
In example (3) and example (4), which is identical to example (1), a bare noun in
the definite form (gubb-en ‘man-the’, klock-an ‘clock-the’) would be used in stand-
ard Swedish, since the referent is unique and the noun is syntactically unmodified.
As example (5) shows, the suffix of definiteness is not present in constructs where
the noun is a proper name.
(5) Men te ‘Alda-Ø, hon va så skåjjigär, hon
but that/the Alda she was so funny she
vild bara fråån te ‘joordbruuk-i.
wanted only from that/the farm-the
‘But Alda, she was so funny, she just wanted to get away from the farm.’
(Lundström 1939: 146)
The different forms of the eastern Nyland construction in the singular and plural
are summarized in Table 1.
Interactional construction grammar 

Table 1. Forms of the eastern Nyland construction in the singular and plural

Singular, non-neuter Singular, neuter Plural

tåm/dåm noun-na
te/de noun-(i/e)n te/de noun-e/i ‘those/the noun-the’
‘that/the noun-the’ ‘that/the noun-the’ tåm/dåm noun-en(a)
‘those/the noun-the’
te/de proper name-Ø
‘that/the proper name’

In example (5) above the proper name Alda would either be used alone or to-
gether with the demonstrative pronoun den där ‘that’ (den där Alda ‘that Alda’) in
standard Swedish. The standard Swedish equivalent of the second occurrence of
the eastern Nyland construction in example (5), the expression te joordbruuki ‘the
farm’, would be det där jordbruket ‘that farm’. From a standard Swedish perspec-
tive, the use of the pattern [te/de ‘that/the’ + noun + suffix of definiteness] in ex-
amples (3)–(5) is thus unexpected for two reasons: a) den seems to be used as a
definite article in contexts where it cannot be used in standard varieties (i.e., with
nouns without premodifiers) and b) den is used as a demonstrative pronoun in
contexts where another demonstrative pronoun, for example den där ‘that’, would
be used. I will therefore argue that the eastern Nyland pattern with te/de and un-
modified nouns in the definite form should be analyzed as a construction of its
own, which lacks direct parallels in standard Swedish.

4. Comparison with standard Swedish

The premodifying demonstrative pronoun in the eastern Nyland construction has


sometimes been analyzed in the literature as a definite article (Dictionary of Swed-
ish Dialects in Finland (FO), den 8, Reinhammar 1975: 79). This suggests that the
preposed definite article could have been grammaticalized further in the eastern
Nyland dialects than in standard Swedish. As Table 2 shows, the preposed definite
article den is not used together with non-modified nouns in the definite form in
standard Swedish. The preposed and postposed articles occur together only when
nouns are premodified, for example with an adjective.4
As in many other languages (cf. Diessel 1999: 128–132), the definite article den in
Swedish has developed from a demonstrative pronoun, the pronoun den (the Swed-
ish Academy Ordbok (SAOB), den XIV.4). At the same time, den has retained some of
its older functions and is still also used as a demonstrative pronoun. In present-day
standard Swedish there are four demonstrative pronouns, the simple forms
 Camilla Wide

Table 2. Indefinite and definite articles in standard Swedish

Singular, non-neuter Singular, neuter Plural

indefinite forms en bok ‘a book’ ett hus ‘a house’ böcker ‘books’


hus ‘houses’
definite forms, bok-en ‘book-the’ hus-et ‘house-the’ böcker-na ‘books-the’
unmodified nouns hus-en ‘houses-the’
de fina böcker-na
definite forms, den fina bok-en det stora hus-et ‘the nice book-the’
modified nouns ‘the nice books-the’ ‘the big house-the’ de stora hus-en
‘the big houses-the’

denna ‘this’ and den ‘that’ and the compound forms den här ‘this’ and den där ‘that’.
Except for the pronoun denna ‘this’ all the demonstrative pronouns in standard
Swedish combine with nouns in the definite form, that is, they are used together
with the suffix of definiteness, corresponding roughly to the use of the eastern
Nyland te/de ‘that/the’. Table 3 shows an overview of the adnominal demonstrative
pronouns in standard Swedish.
The simple forms denna ‘this’ and den ‘that’ are older than the combined forms
den här lit. ‘that here’ and den där lit. ‘that there’, which have been attested in written
Swedish since the 16th century (Hirvonen 1987: 412–419). In writing, den and

Table 3. Adnominal demonstrative pronouns in standard Swedish

Sing., non-neuter Sing., neuter Plural

denna/detta ‘this’ denna bok detta hus dessa böcker


dessa ‘these’ ‘this book’ ‘this house’ ‘these books’
dessa hus
‘these houses’
den/det ‘that’ den bok-en det hus-et de böcker-na
de ‘those’ ‘that book-the’ ‘that house-the’ ‘those books-the’
de hus-en
‘those houses-the’
den/det här ‘this’ den här bok-en det här hus-et de här böcker-na,
de här ‘these’ ‘this book-the’ ‘this house-the’ ‘these books-the
de här hus-en
‘these houses-the’
den/det där ‘that’ den där bok-en det där hus-et de där böcker-na,
de här ‘those’ ‘that book-the’ ‘that house-the’ ‘those books-the’
de där hus-en
‘those houses-the’
Interactional construction grammar 

especially denna are still preferred (Fraurud 2000: 10–11, Lindström 2000: 109). In
many varieties of spoken language, however, den här and den där are highly gram-
maticalized and seem to gain ground at the expense of the older forms denna and
den5. In most varieties of Finland Swedish, the simple form denna is hardly used at
all. In eastern Nyland dialects denna is used to some extent but is losing ground to
the combined form den här. Both the simple form den and the combined form den
där, however, are used frequently in the eastern Nyland dialects (for a quantitative
comparison of different forms, see Wide 2008a).
The pronoun den, which is prosodically more stressed than the definite article
den, has lost most of its original dimension of distality in standard Swedish
(Lindström 2000: 108; however, cf. the Swedish Academy Grammar (SAG) 2: 324).
The compound pronoun den där is used almost exclusively for referring to entities
further away from the speaker in a physical or psychological sense. While the form
den has become highly grammaticalized as a definite article, it has at the same time
lost ground as a demonstrative pronoun. This is the case in adnominal contexts in
particular. Den can still be used deictically in similar contexts as the pronoun den
där, e.g. Hela 'den (≈ den där) 'tunnan är 'tom ‘That whole barrel is empty’ (SAG 2:
322). However, when den is used for pointing out referents some kind of comparison
is usually included, such as in example (6) below. In (6a) where the speaker refers to
a referent in the physical surrounding by using a noun in the definite form (gård-en
‘farm-the’) only one referent of the kind is available. By contrast, in (6b) where the
speaker refers to a referent by using den and a noun in the definite form (den gård-en
‘that farm-the’), there are several referents of the same kind to choose from.
(6) a. Det var 'gården hon ville köpa.
it was farm-the she wanted buy
‘It was the farm she wanted to buy.’
b. Det var 'den 'gården hon ville köpa.
it was that farm-the she wanted buy
‘It was that farm she wanted to buy.’ (SAG 2: 323)
In standard Swedish adnominal den typically occurs in anaphoric contexts when
the referent has been mentioned explicitly or implicitly in the immediately preced-
ing context. An example of the latter case when the noun phrase with den is used
discourse-deictically to refer to an event is given in (7) below.
(7) Han gick till Canossa. Den vandringen tog två veckor.
he walked to Canossa that hike took two weeks
‘He walked to Canossa. That walking tour took two weeks.’ (SAG 2: 325)
 Camilla Wide

In examples (6)–(7), the pronoun den is stressed along with the noun. Similar occur-
rences of the eastern Nyland pronoun te/de can also be found. However, in expres-
sions such as the ones shown in (3)–(5) above te/de is not stressed (de ‘bisin ‘that/the
‘man’, te ‘Alda ‘that/the ‘Alda’, te ‘joordbruuki ‘that/the farm’). Prosodically, the con-
structs of the eastern Nyland construction thus differ from syntactically similar
structures with the pronoun den in standard Swedish. In the following section, I will
show that this difference in form is also accompanied by a difference in function.
To summarize, the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction differs from
standard Swedish in the following ways. The pronoun te/de is unstressed, which
makes it prosodically reminiscent of the preposed definite article den in standard
varieties. Furthermore, te/de is used with bare nouns in the definite form, which
suggests that the preposed article has grammaticalized further in the eastern
Nyland dialects than in standard Swedish. In examples such (3) and (4), only a
noun in the definite form would be used in standard varieties. However, the east-
ern Nyland construction is also used in contexts, such as in example (5), where
structures with other demonstrative pronouns, for example den där ‘that’, would
be used in standard Swedish. The construction can therefore not be explained
merely as a further development of the definiteness marking system.

5. Functions in interaction

The main purpose of the examples I have discussed so far has been to show that
the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction is used in contexts where the pro-
noun/article den is not used in standard Swedish. In this section I will focus on
describing the construction from an “inside” perspective, that is, on how it is used
by native speakers in authentic extracts from spoken language. I will argue that the
use of the construction is highly dependent on shared knowledge. This knowledge
makes it possible to use the construction in contexts that appear strange from a
standard Swedish perspective.
My main data consist of three everyday conversations, one institutional con-
versation and four dialect recordings (in total 5 hours of transcribed data, for de-
tails see Wide 2008a). In addition to this, I have also collected some examples by
natural observation (cf. example (4) above) and analyzed examples presented in
older literature (cf. examples (3) and (5) above). The dialect recordings in my main
data are not “authentic” in the sense that they would have taken place irrespective
of whether the recording was made or not. Two of the dialect recordings are rem-
iniscent of conversations; the interviewer holds a low profile and the informants
talk primarily to each other about their everyday life and old times. The other two
recordings are more interview-like since the informants are, among other things,
Interactional construction grammar 

asked to talk about a film they have seen. Nonetheless, both of these recordings are
comparatively informal and do not follow an explicit agenda.
My method of analysis is Conversation Analysis. I have analyzed a large
number of examples qualitatively in order to find typical uses of the eastern Nyland
construction. Due to limited space as well as the scope of this paper, it is not pos-
sible to present as many examples as is usually done in CA studies. Hence, I will
show only a few examples of the typical features I have found among the totally
155 examples of the eastern Nyland construction in my main data. In line with the
theoretical and methodological background assumptions of CA I will not present
any quantitative evidence for my generalizations about the construction. Exten-
sive qualitative evidence for the generalizations presented in this paper can be
found in Wide (2008a, 2008b).
In order to describe and characterize the situations where the eastern Nyland
construction is used, it is necessary to consider more context in the examples than
was done in (3)–(5) above. Let us start by looking at example (8) from a dialect in-
terview. The speaker in the extract is talking about a film she has seen. In this
7-minute long film (A strawberry-shaped day, Kangas et al. 2003; Östman 2008), a
person is biking in the countryside in Finland and various incidents connected to
strawberries take place. During the extract, the speaker refers to the bike in the film
four times: with the expression me velå ‘by bike’ in line 1, with the expression me sen
velå ‘with her bike’ in line 8, with the expression umpå velån ‘on bicycle-the’ in line
13 and with the expression te velån ‘that/the bike-the’ in line 16. (In order to shorten
the extract I have left out the backchanneling signals uttered by the researcher.)
(8) A strawberry-shaped day (Dialect recording, Liljendal, 2003)
1 I: så foor hon ti postlåådån me velå å (.) å så fick
then went she to mail-box-the by bike and and then got
2 hon någa koort å he va antaagligen någa såm
she some card and it was likely something which
3 hon tykkt att va roolit för hon såå nu uut
she thought that was funny because she looked prt out
4 (å tykk åm de nu sku ha vari) ((laughs)) å så
to like if it prt should have been and then
5 när hon tåå trampa viidare (.) från påstlåådån
when she then peddled further from mail-box-the
((4 lines omitted))
6 så va däär een.ssh- ja kåmmär ihååg en väägsjylt
then was there a s- I remember a road sign
7 me en stoorer joordgubb *å så* (.) å så (.) pajna
with a big strawberry and then and then went
 Camilla Wide

8 hon ivääg ååt te hålle me sen velå å så va


she off to that way-the with her bike and then was
9 däär enn (.) kaar elär påjtji kva man nu ska sej
there a man or boy what one prt shall say
10 såm rusta til ett stånd.hh (.) å- men så å
who prepared to a stand and but then and
11 sku sälj joordgubbar
intended sell strawberries
((2 lines omitted))
12 en låådo me joordgubbar såm hon ladd i [...] kårjen
a box with strawberries which she put in basket-the
13 umpå velån å så hadd ja no ett liitet avbrått
on bike-the and then had I prt a little break
14 imilan att tankana måst no ha vandra
between that thougths-the must prt have wandered
15 för att ja så hadd ja *så ja kåmär ihåg* så va
cause that I then had I as I remember then was
16 att te velån låå ikull å å joordgubbana [...]
that that/the bike-the lay over and and strawberries-the
‘then she went to the mail box by bike and then she got a card or
something and it was probably something she thought was funny
because she seemed to like it, if it would have been, and then she
drove away from the mail box... then there was a, I remember a sign
with a big strawberry, and then and then she drove in that direction
with her bike and then there was a man or boy, or whatever you
should say, who was putting up a stand, but then, and was about to
sell strawberries... a box with strawberries which she put in... the
basket on her bike, and then I had a break, my thoughts must have
wandered because then I had, as I remember, that the bike was on
the ground and the strawberries...’
The extract shown in (8) can be characterized as a narrative. In the sequence fol-
lowing the extract, the speaker finishes her story about the film by telling the in-
terviewer about a little strawberry-shaped fan that the main character in the film
picks up from a small box. The construct of the eastern Nyland construction, te
velån ‘that/the bike-the’, thus occurs towards the end of a narrative. When the
speaker says that the bike had fallen on the ground in line 16, she has already
talked about the bike three times. The bike is hence an activated referent that has
received a certain position in the common ground built up by the speaker and the
listener. In this particular example, the bike has been mentioned explicitly. The
Interactional construction grammar 

reference could thus be characterized as anaphoric. However, when the special


demonstrative construction occurs the bike has not been mentioned for a while in
the narrative. In standard Swedish, neither a noun in the definite form (cykeln
‘bike-the’) nor an expression with the demonstrative pronoun den (den cykeln ‘that
bike-the’) would therefore be used here. (In standard Swedish, the pronoun den is
typically used to refer to entities or events mentioned in the immediately preced-
ing context. See example (7) above.) An expression with the pronoun den där
would be used instead, since this demonstrative pronoun is typically used in stand-
ard Swedish to reactivate referents that have not been mentioned for a while
(Lindström 2000: 117–119; SAG 2: 321)).
One of the main characteristics of the eastern Nyland demonstrative construc-
tion in narratives seems to be that it refers to entities that have already received a
certain status in the common ground of the speakers and listeners. At the same
time, the referents in question are clearly prominent in the narratives. The bike in
extract (8) is shown in almost all scenes of the film. It is the bike that takes the
main character through the main plot of the film. Hence, the bike plays a fore-
grounded role. In the particular scene that the speaker describes in line 16 in ex-
tract (8), the bike has turned over and the strawberries that were in a basket on the
bike are smashed on the ground. The speaker describes this scene as a climax in
the film; she directs attention to and focuses on the accident with the strawberries.
Rather than just referring to it as a chronological event in the narrative, she “slows
down” her story and points out that the event is special. As seen in the extract, the
narrative line has broken down just before the event with the strawberries on the
ground is presented; in lines 13–15, the speaker makes several meta-comments
about how her thoughts must have wandered when she was watching the film.
In extract (8) the eastern Nyland te/de is thus not merely used as a pleonastic
definite article in order to add an (unspecified) emphatic sense to the event described,
as sometimes suggested in the literature (cf. Reinhammar 1975: 79). Neither is it
used to point out a bike in a contrastive sense, as a structure with den would do in
standard Swedish. Rather, it is used in order to refer to an entity that has been made
prominent in the discourse and in order to bring a dramatic climax into focus.
In narratives, constructs of the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction
tend to be found towards the end when a dramatic climax is being described or
built up, such as in example (8) (for further examples, see Wide 2008b). However,
instances licensed by the construction can also be found in the beginnings of sto-
ries when a referent from the preceding discourse is being reintroduced. In exam-
ple (9), two informants are talking about cats in their vicinity. This topic has been
introduced by M earlier in the conversation. In the sequence shown in (9), K is
talking about how she lets the cats eat the remains when she is gutting herring
(lines 4–8). She then starts to talk about how the waste disposal is taken care of in
 Camilla Wide

the area where she and M live (lines 10–14). However, M wants to continue to talk
about cats and reintroduces the topic in line 15 by using, among other things, the
eastern Nyland demonstrative construction: men just täär ennu åm- åm dåm kat-
tåna just ‘but still about about those cats’.
(9) About cats (Dialect recording, Pernå, 2003)
1 K: fast vi int sjölv haar någå kattår så vi haar
though we not ourselves have any cats then we have
2 åtta kattår i kring ås såm all andra haar
eigth cats in around us like all others have
3 M: jåo (0.4) ºjåoº
yes yes
4 K: at så täär när ja (0.4) rensar strömingana (.) [...]
that so there when I gut herrings-the
((three lines omitted))
5 så leggär ja uut täär å (0.4) så fåår dåm då it e
then put I out there and then may they then eat it
6 iblaand it(är) åm de int rååkar kåm någån
sometimes eat(s) if it not happens come any
7 kattå så (0.9) så fåår tåh (0.4) sjååråna (.) *åm int
cat then then may then magpies-the if not
8 aadär (.) it opp tåm rääså[na*
others eat up those rests-the
9 M: [men (---) ]
but (---)
10 K: så bihööv(är) man]
then needs one
11 int sjikk dåm ti Bårgå e de int [ti Bårgå]
not send them to Borgå is it not to Borgå
12 M: [jåo ]
yes
13 K: vi sjikkar (0.5) aavfalle våårt nu (0.6)
we send waste-the ours now
14 e de int så
is it not so
((four turns about waste disposal omitted))
15 M: men just täär ennu åm- åm dåm kattåna
but just there still about about those/the cats-the
16 just de här me våår eh Fäärdinand (.) den (1.1)
precisely this with our Ferdinand it
Interactional construction grammar 

17 när vi far i- (0.6) i bastån så e an diit å


when we go i- in sauna-the then is he there and
18 (.) så näär [...]
then when
‘K: even though we do not have any cats ourselves we have eight cats
around us as everybody else has
M: yes yes
K: so when I gut herrings... I put out [the remains] and then they may
eat it, sometimes they [the remains] are eaten, if there is no cat
around, the magpies, if there is no one else, may eat those remains
M: but (unhearable, overlapping speech)
K: so one does not need to send them to Borgå, is it not to Borgå
M: yes
M: we send our waste these days? is it not so?
M: but still about those cats, precisely this with our Ferdinand, it,
when we go to the sauna, he is there, and then when...’
In standard Swedish, structures with the pronoun den där ‘that’ (or den här ‘this’)
are used in contexts where a topic is reintroduced (Lindström 2000: 117). As we
have seen, structures with the pronoun den ‘that’, by contrast, are used to refer to
referents in the immediately preceding context, not to activate referents that are
more distant. In the eastern Nyland dialects, structures with te/de ‘that’ as well as
structures with de där/te tär lit. ‘that there’ can be used to activate distant referents
(see Wide 2008a). Whereas structures with de där/te tär may be used to activate
referents that are potentially not salient in the situation in a similar way to struc-
tures with den där in standard Swedish (cf. SAG 2: 321), structures with te/de
specifically re-activate referents that are salient, such as in extract (9). In other
words, when structures such as dåm kattåna ‘those/the cats-the’ are used to acti-
vate referents, these referents have already been discussed to some extent or are
otherwise well known to the participants in the conversation.
In examples (8) and (9), constructs of the eastern Nyland construction are
used in anaphoric contexts to direct the focus to familiar or special entities that
have been mentioned explicitly in the preceding context. In everyday conversa-
tions among people who know each other well, instantiations of the construction
can often be found in first mentions, that is, when the referents have not been
mentioned or discussed earlier in the conversation. This is the case in line 5 in
extract (10) below, which is from a dinner conversation. E talks about a car that he
and his son (speaker L) have been working on together. Before the sequence in the
extract starts, the participants of the conversation have been discussing whether E,
who is fatally ill, should travel abroad to visit his sister during his son’s winter
 Camilla Wide

holidays. E, however, also wants to finish the car for his son L. When he suggests,
in lines 4–6, that he and L would use L’s vacation for working on the car instead, he
is directing the attention to something that needs to be solved or taken care of, that
is, a “problem”. Even though he has said in the context preceding the sequence
shown in the extract that he would really like to visit his sister abroad, he seems
unsure of whether he has time to do it because of the car.
(10) Fixing the car (Dinner conversation, Lovisa, 2004)
1 E: de lååtär braa
it sounds good
2 (0.9)
3 E: ja saa noo ååt mamma häär redan een aftå att
I said prt to mum here already one evening that
4 (0.7) åm man i stelle sku åfra de vekkån
if one in stead would sacrifice the week-the
5 Lasse e leedi så sku man laag de biiln
Lasse is on vacation then would one fix that/the car-the
6 i sjikk hit å [(---) ]
in order here and
7 M: [nå nää] nu ska [ni fa ti Irland]
prt no prt shall you go to Ireland
8 L: [men ja haar ]
but I have
9 tvåå vekkår (0.4) leedit sidu (0.4) ja e- ja kan
two weeks free prt I am I can
10 [taa de (andra vekkan)]
take the other week-the
11 M: [nää nu e de ] väärt å faar(a) ti Irland=
no prt is it worth to go to Ireland
12 E: =joo [joo e så ]
yes yes is so
13 L: [(---) ja tyk]kär de å (.) åm du årkkar bara
(---) I think it also if you are able prt
‘E: that sounds good
E: I said to mum here one evening that what if one would sacrifice
the week Lasse is on vacation instead, then we could fix that car
here and (---)
L: but no you should go to Ireland
E: but I am on vacation two weeks, I can use the other week
L: no it is worth it to go to Ireland
Interactional construction grammar 

E: yes, yes it is
L: I think so, too, if you just have the strength to do it’
The sequence shown in extract (10) can be described as a negotiation. E puts forth
a competing solution to how he and L should spend L’s winter holidays. As seen in
lines 7–13, however, his son L and M, who is his daughter-in-law, reject this solu-
tion. When E refers to the car in line 5 in extract (10), it is the first time it is men-
tioned in the conversation. He is not pointing out a car that can be seen from the
dinner table. Neither is he contrasting the car to any other cars. Yet, it is com-
pletely evident to all the participants in the conversation what car E is talking
about. E and his son have been working on an old Volvo for quite a while and are
occupied with doing this on the weekend when the conversation takes place. The
car in question is thus highly salient in the situation, the main object of an ongoing
activity that not only E and L, but also M are involved in. When E mentions the car
in line 5, he thus brings into focus an entity that is already activated, even though
it has not been mentioned in the preceding conversation. Rather than bringing
into focus a distant referent, he thus connects the ongoing discussion to an ongo-
ing activity in a wider context (cf. Lindström 2000: 113).
In the sequence following extract (10), the car is not discussed further. Hence,
the car does not become topicalized in the same way as the cats in extract (9). During
the following three minutes when the participants continue to talk about the trip to
Ireland and then move on to discuss coffee making, two additional comments are
made about the car. In both cases the speakers, L and E, respectively, refer to the car
by using the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction. As in example (10), these
comments are neither preceded nor followed by any longer discussion about the car.
The main function of the eastern Nyland construction in example (10) thus seems to
be to relate the ongoing discussion to a wider context that the participants share.
This function is typical of the construction more generally (for further examples, see
Wide 2008a, 2008b). However, the context in question must either be common to
the participants of the conversation due to some shared activities or experience, as in
(10), or made common to the participants through the conversation itself as in (8).
In extracts (8)–(10), instances of the eastern Nyland construction appear in
contexts where structures with the distal demonstrative pronoun den där ‘that’
would be used in standard Swedish. However, constructs of the construction may
also occur in contexts where the proximal pronoun den här ‘this’ would be used.
When the construct shown in example (11), de tyyge ‘that/the material’, was ut-
tered, the speaker was holding up the sleeve of his jacket to the listener. Before he
made the utterance, he had been talking about the new jacket he was wearing and
telling the listener how fantastic it was. The jacket had in other words been made
known and prominent in the preceding context.
 Camilla Wide

(11) The fantastic jacket (Natural observation, 2005)


de e så starkt de tyyge
it is so strong that/the material-the
‘this material is so strong’
Constructs of the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction hence show simi-
larities to structures with both the pronouns den där ‘that’ and den här ‘this’ in
standard Swedish. The constructs are used for focusing on known or prominent
referents in the communicative situation. This suggests that the te/de element in
the construction is not to be analyzed as a definite article but rather as a demon-
strative pronoun. Let us therefore now shortly return to examples (3) and (4),
where instantiations of the construction occur in contexts that are typical of struc-
tures with definite articles rather than structures with demonstrative pronouns.
In both examples (3) and (4), the referent is unique. In example (3), which is
from a folk tale, the referent bisin ‘the man’ is introduced with a noun in the in-
definite form (ein bisi ‘a man’) and then referred to twice with a construct of the
eastern Nyland construction (te bisin ‘that/the man’). Example (4) thus resembles
schoolbook examples of how the definite form of nouns is used in Swedish: first,
you introduce a referent with a noun in the indefinite form and then you refer
anaphorically to this referent with the noun in the definite form. This suggests that
the te/de element in example (3) could be seen as a definite article rather than as a
demonstrative pronoun. However, in the folk tale in question, not all referents are
talked about in this way. As in the other examples discussed, the eastern Nyland
construction is used to focus or point out a referent which is special or prominent,
that is, plays an important or major role in the situation, in this case a narrative.
In example (4), the referent is unique in a broader sense. The speaker uses the
expression de klåkkan lit. ‘that/the clock-the’ to ask what time is it. This could be
seen as a case of larger situation use, which is a typical use of definite articles rath-
er than demonstrative pronouns (Hawkins 1978: 115–123; Himmelmann
1996: 210). However, the expression was uttered in a situation when a clock that
had been turned off during the night needed to be set. The speaker was standing
next to the clock and addressed the other persons present in the situation (his fam-
ily). He was facing a problem that needed to be solved: the clock had to be set and
he did not know the exact time. As the speaker in example (10), who talks about
the car that needs to be fixed, the speaker in example (11) was thus directing the
listeners’ attention to something that needed to be taken care of, a problem.
Thus, if examples (3) and (4) are analyzed in isolation, it is possible to catego-
rize the te/de element as a definite article. When these examples are investigated in
a wider context, however, it turns out that the structures with te/de are used in
order to perform specific discourse functions. They direct the attention to a refer-
Interactional construction grammar 

ent which is (made) prominent in the situation. I therefore see no reason to draw
a distinction between occurrences such as examples (3)–(4) and (8)–(10) as re-
gards the te/de element. Based on the communicative functions that the structures
with te/de and a noun in the definite form acquire in their contexts, it is thus pos-
sible to conclude that te/de functions as a demonstrative pronoun rather than as a
definite article. Primarily, however, te/de is part of the particular syntactic pattern
that I have called the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction. It is the combi-
nation of te/de with a noun in the definite form with certain types of contextual
features that creates the special meaning and function of the construction.
To summarize the discussion in this section, the entities referred to with the
eastern Nyland construction have to be part of the shared knowledge of the par-
ticipants of the conversation. Either the entities must have been made known and
prominent through a narrative or story as in example (8) or through an ongoing
activity as in examples (4) and (10). Alternatively, the entities are prominent in
discourse on a more global scale than the ongoing conversation or in some non-
verbal activity that the participants of the conversation are involved in. Further-
more, the entities referred to are unique or self-evident either in the situation, as
in example (10), or more generally, as in example (4); no aspect of contrast as in
the use of den in standard Swedish (cf. example (6) above) can be discerned. The
function of the eastern Nyland construction on a global level seems to be to acti-
vate referents from larger contexts, that is, to anchor the ongoing conversation to
discussions or activities outside the conversation. On a more local level the con-
struction tends to occur either in situations where a point is being made or pre-
pared for, or in situations where tasks need to be checked or performed. In the
following section, I will discuss how these features can be included in a formaliza-
tion of the construction. As I have pointed out above, I find it necessary to include
interactional and contextual features in the formalization of constructions in or-
der to present an adequate picture of language and language use in CxG.

6. Formalization

The CxG notation is based on boxes-within-boxes diagrams that show the con-
stituent structure. Within the boxes, detailed grammatical information is provided
in terms of feature structures, and co-indexication is used to mark the unification
principles, that is, to show how constructions and specifications ‘fit together’ in a
non-derivational fashion (see e.g., Michaelis & Lambrecht 1996: 225–228; Fried &
Östman 2004: 25–29). The eastern Nyland construction is a phrasal construction,
and its constituents may be represented with a box diagram as shown in Figure 1.
 Camilla Wide

The eastern Nyland demonstrative construction

#1 #2
role p-determiner role head role s-determiner
lfm te/de/tåm/dåm cat noun cat [suffix of
stress null val {#1, #2} definitiness]
stress primary

Figure 1. The constituents of the eastern Nyland construction

In the diagram in Figure 1, the noun is marked as the head of the construction.
The obligatory complements of the noun are represented with valence relations.
The unification indices #1 and #2 show that the noun is necessarily modified by a
preposed (p-) determiner and a suffixed (s-) determiner (the omission of the s-
determiner with proper names is licensed by a special lexical construction for
proper names). The p-determiner is specified in terms of lexical forms (lfm) since
it is represented by a special set of demonstrative pronouns that are included in the
construction. The suffixed determiner, by contrast, is specified as a category (cat)
since it relates to a more general pattern in Swedish nominal inflection. Finally, the
values ‘null’ and ‘primary’ of the prosodic attribute stress for the p-determiner
and noun, respectively, mark that the forms te/de/tåm/dåm are unstressed in the
construction and the main prosodic stress is on the noun.
The formalization shown in Figure 1 specifies the syntactic form of the eastern
Nyland construction. However, it tells us nothing about the meaning or function
of the construction. Since constructions are constellations of form and meaning/
function, this side of the construction ought by default to be taken into account in
the formalization. As discussed in Sections 3–5, the eastern Nyland construction
performs communicative tasks taken care of by several different constructions in
standard Swedish. Hence, the functional side of the construction cannot be left to
implicit shared knowledge about standard language use. When faced with the con-
struction as a non-native speaker of eastern Nyland dialects, one typically tries to
define the construction in terms of standard Swedish distinctions. However, dia-
lects form language systems of their own and should not be described in terms of
other varieties which might have a prestige status for political or socio-historical
reasons. Similar syntactic forms in different varieties may have different functions
and thus represent different types of constructions. Hence, in order for us to be
able to explain the eastern Nyland construction properly, the communicative
function of it has to be explicated and included in the formalization.
However, grammatical constructions do not usually have just one single com-
municative function. As discussed in Section 2, they rather have a functional
Interactional construction grammar 

potential, which specifies how they can be used in order to perform communica-
tive tasks (Wide 2002; Linell 2004, 2005). Since grammatical constructions get
their final meaning or function in situated interaction, it is often difficult to ana-
lyze and pinpoint exactly how they perform certain communicative tasks. Formal-
izing communicative and interactional features in a neat and concise way is thus
in many ways problematic (cf. Linell 2006, this volume).
In order to explore the communicative-functional aspects of grammatical
constructions more thoroughly than has been done so far, it is necessary to begin
with tentative solutions. In Figure 2 below, I present a solution for how the eastern
Nyland construction can be represented (cf. Auer 2006; Imo 2006 on the formali-
zation of interactional features). To start with, the functional aspects are repre-
sented in the outermost box, which means that they are features of the construc-
tion as a whole. In order to capture the special combination of functional features
that the eastern Nyland construction represents, I have used the attributes se-
quential position, reference, activity, coherence and functional po-
tential. Since my analysis is preliminary and has to be worked out in more detail,
the values of the features are presented as text within square brackets and single
quotes (cf. Fried & Östman 2004: 30).
The attribute sequential position is presented first in the formalization. As
discussed, sequentiality plays an important role in IL. My analysis of the eastern
Nyland construction so far has shown that the construction tends to occur at the
boundaries of episodes, for example, at the beginnings and ends of narratives.

The eastern Nyland demonstrative construction


sequential position [‘beginning/end of episodes, inserted comments’]
reference [‘shared, specific knowledge, non-contrastiveness,
discourse focus’]
activity [‘narrative, global on-going discourse, talk about
shared non-linguistic activity’]
coherence [‘anchoring to larger (on-going) context’]
functional potential [‘creates focus on a familiar prominent referent to
make a point in a narrative, check or solve a
task in the situation, remind listeners of or bring
into focus larger contexts’]

#1 #2
role p-determiner role head role s-determiner
lfm te/de/tåm/dåm cat noun cat [suffix of
stress null val {#1, #2} definitiness]
stress primary

Figure 2. The form and communicative function of the eastern Nyland construction
 Camilla Wide

In addition to this, the construction occurs in isolated comments referring to larg-


er discourses than the ongoing conversation (cf. example (10) above); in order to
capture this feature of the construction I have included the value ‘inserted com-
ments’ in the sequential position attribute.
In the remainder of this section, I will discuss the other communicative-func-
tional attributes included in Figure 2 in more detail. I will start by comparing my
set of attributes to some concepts of nominal reference used in earlier studies on
CxG, specifically the concepts ‘topic’/‘focus’ and ‘active’/ ‘semi-active’/‘inactive’.
Michaelis & Lambrecht (1996: 226–227) introduce two pragmatic values into
the CxG formalization: act (activation) and prag (pragmatic role). They state
that the attribute act “in those boxes which represent referential arguments de-
notes the activation status of the NP referent, that is the assumed status of this
referent in the consciousness of the addressee at the time of utterance”. Thus, act
can take two other attributes as its value, active and accessible. Accessible ref-
erents are those which are identifiable but not fully active, and yet recoverable
from context. An active referent, by contrast, is “also necessarily an accessible ref-
erent, one that is currently ‘lit up’ in the shared consciousness of the speaker and
addressee”. Michaelis & Lambrecht point out that the activation attribute should
be distinguished from the pragmatic role attribute, which has two possible ter-
minal values, ‘topic’ and ‘focus’. A constituent is a topic expression, according to
Lambrecht (1994: 131), if “the proposition expressed by the clause with which it is
associated is pragmatically construed as being about the referent of this constitu-
ent”. Focus, on the other hand, is “the semantic component of a pragmatically
structured proposition whereby the assertion differs from the presupposition”
(Lambrecht 1994: 213; see also Lambrecht 2004: 162–164).
The attributes active and accessible discussed by Michaelis & Lambrecht
(1996) are largely based on Wallace Chafe’s studies on the activation state of con-
cepts. According to Chafe (1987), particular concepts at particular times may be in
one of three different states: ‘active’, ‘semi-active’ or ‘inactive’. Chafe’s definition of
an active concept is basically the same as Michaelis and Lambrecht’s definition of
active referents, i.e. “a person’s focus of consciousness”. A semi-active concept is
“one that is in a person’s peripheral consciousness, a concept of which a person has
a background awareness, but which is not being directly focused on” and an inac-
tive concept is “one that is currently in a person’s long-term memory, neither fo-
cally nor peripherally active” (Chafe 1987: 25). Active concepts have been men-
tioned in the previous context or have a naturally given status in the
conversational context, such as ‘I’ and ‘you’. Hence, they correspond roughly to
‘given information’ and are typically spoken with attenuated pronunciation. Semi-
active concepts, in turn, correspond to ‘accessible information’ (p. 26–28). Chafe
(p. 29) points out that concepts do not remain active very long unless their
Interactional construction grammar 

activation is refreshed. Nonetheless, concepts do not become fully inactive imme-


diately, rather they “may remain in the semi-active state for some time”.
Could the eastern Nyland construction be described or explained in terms of
the features ‘topic’/‘focus’ and ‘active’/‘semi-active’/‘inactive’? To start with, these
concepts are problematic per se since they focus on rather small units of language.
Michaelis & Lambrecht (1996) analyze sentences and Chafe (1987) investigates
the representation of information in narratives from an intonation unit perspec-
tive. The values ‘topic’ and ‘focus’ are especially difficult to apply in my analysis,
which aims at combining CxG with IL without sacrificing any important tenets of
IL. In some of the examples presented in sections 3–5, such as (3) and (8), the in-
stantiations of the eastern Nyland construction do refer to someone or something
being talked about, that is, they have the function of being a topical expression.
However, this most likely is a general feature of demonstrative constructions; they
explicitly pick out referents to be discussed. In examples such as (5) and (10), the
situation is not as straightforward. The first occurrence of the eastern Nyland con-
struction in example (5) occurs in a left-dislocation, and could indeed be described
as a topical expression (cf. Lambrecht 1994: 181–183). The second occurrence,
however, can be found to the far right in the sentence, that is, in the position where
new information is typically presented in Swedish. This occurrence of the con-
struction is thus focal rather than topical. What unites the uses of the two expres-
sions in (5) is not focality or topicality in Lambrecht’s sense. Neither can the use of
the construction be explained with reference to the notion of ‘discourse topic’,
which Ochs, Keenan & Schieffelin (1976: 338) define as “the proposition (or sets
of propositions) about which the speaker is either providing or requesting new
information”. As example (5) shows, the eastern Nyland construction can be used
both for referring to propositions (the person Alda) and the information provided
(‘wanted [to go] away from the farm’). What unites the two expressions in (5) is
that they refer to and bring into focus shared background knowledge of the speak-
er and addressee. This is also the case in example (10). Here the car, which is being
referred to by the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction, is introduced with-
out having been mentioned previously. It is thus difficult to see how the car could
be topical on the sentence level. As the expression te ‘joordbruuki ‘that farm-the’ in
example (5), the expression de ‘biiln ‘that car-the’ in example (10) occurs to the far
right, rather than to the left in the sentence. It thereby introduces new information
both on the discourse and on the sentence level and is focal rather than topi-
cal. However, as discussed in Section 5, the car is part of a common activity of the
speakers and listeners in example (10). Thus, the car could be seen as a given refer-
ent from a broader discourse point of view. By focusing on the car, the speaker
directs the attention of the listeners to a problem which everybody knows that
needs to be fixed.
 Camilla Wide

Investigating the topical and focal features of the eastern Nyland construction
on a sentence or intonation unit level in more detail would be most interesting.
However, my analysis of the construction so far indicates that the special use of the
construction is not explainable on this level of language. Rather, the construction
must be investigated in broader contexts, including contexts outside the ongoing
conversation. As shown in examples (8)–(10), instantiations of the construction
are used in interaction in order to direct the listeners’ attention to certain refer-
ents. In some cases, such as in example (9) about the cats, these referents are clear-
ly topical. However, in examples such as (8) about the bike, the use of the construc-
tion does not refer to the topic of the narrative, but rather to an important
“contracting party”. Furthermore, one of the main purposes of the construction
seems to be to anchor an ongoing discussion to a broader context, such as in ex-
ample (10) about the car. In order to capture the information structure features of
the eastern Nyland construction it is thus necessary to use concepts such as ac-
tivity and coherence in the formalization. By ‘activity’ I refer to all types of
social activities, that is, what Couch (1986: 113) describes with the following
words: “Human beings routinely contact, interact with and leave each other’s pres-
ence; in the process they initiate, construct and terminate various forms of social
activity”. Following Levinson (1979) who uses the term ‘activity type’ to refer to
any culturally recognized activity, I thus include both linguistic and non-linguistic
activities in the concept. For the concept of coherence, on the other hand, I rely on
the hermeneutic view as expressed for example by Bublitz (1998):
Coherence is the outcome of the language user’s gestalt creating power. People are
driven by a strong desire to identify forms, relations, connections which they can
maximize in order to turn fragments into whole gestalts, i.e. to ‘see’ coherence in
strings of utterances. Coherence is also a cooperative achievement (in ongoing
discourse more than in ‘petrified’ text) because it depends on both the speaker’s/
writer’s and the hearer’s/reader’s willingness to negotiate coherence. Mutual un-
derstanding not only rests on the participants sharing the same socio-cultural
background, the same range of knowledge and communicative assumptions, but
also on their ability to figure out unshared experience, i.e. to adjust their own
world-view to that of their interlocutors’. Hearers/readers are constantly engaged
in trying to re-create coherence as an equivalent of the speaker’s/writer’s coher-
ence, but despite their efforts they can never succeed in coming up with an exact
copy. Coherence is only approximate and a matter of degree and best described as
a scalar notion. Any interpretation of coherence is restricted and, accordingly,
partial to different degrees.

In Figure 2 above, I have given the eastern Nyland construction the coherence
value ‘anchor to larger (ongoing) context’. The activity value is stated as ‘narrative,
global ongoing discourse, talk about shared non-linguistic activity’. The purpose of
Interactional construction grammar 

both values is to pinpoint the function of the eastern Nyland construction as ex-
plicitly as possible. However, the values differ from the values presented in most
CxG studies since they are not seen in relation to a fixed set of values. Due to the
IL perspective of my study, I find it necessary to treat the list of values as open (cf.
the discussion in Section 2).
Let us now turn to the attribute reference. As shown in Figure 2 I have given
the eastern Nyland construction the reference value ‘shared, specific knowledge,
non-contrastiveness, discourse focus6’. These values are based on the results of the
empirical analysis presented in Sections 3–5. Would it have been possible to use
the concepts of ‘active’, ‘semi-active’ and ‘in-active’ here instead?
As I have shown, the pronoun den ‘that’ is unstressed in the eastern Nyland
construction. The prosody of the demonstrative element of the construction thus
corresponds to Chafe’s (1987) characterization of active referents. The noun in the
construction, by contrast, is stressed, which indicates that the construction does
not refer to active referents. Furthermore, since the construction contains a de-
monstrative pronoun and a noun, it is not an entity which is typically used for re-
ferring to active referents (this is usually done with pronouns and similar expres-
sions, cf. Chafe 1987: 26–28). As discussed, a general feature of the eastern Nyland
construction is that it refers to ongoing activities of different kinds. Thus, the con-
struction can hardly be seen as referring to inactive referents. What remains is the
value ‘semi-active’, which refers to accessible information. Expressions with de-
monstrative pronouns fit nicely into this category because they are often used to
activate referents that are known but have not been discussed for a while. Accord-
ing to Chafe (1987: 29), concepts become semi-active in two ways: by not having
been talked about for a while and by having been implicitly introduced through a
narrative schema. Thus, expressions used for semi-active concepts cover a great
variety of different constructions, such as nouns in the definite or indefinite form,
possessive constructions and demonstrative constructions. As regards the eastern
Nyland dialects, this means that ‘semi-active’ is a feature not only of the demon-
strative construction discussed in this study but also of other demonstrative con-
structions. My argument is therefore that concepts such as ‘active’ and ‘accessible’
have to broken down into more specific features.
By using the attributes activity, reference and coherence it is possible to
pinpoint the special characteristics of the eastern Nyland construction in a more
precise way than by using concepts such as ‘topicality’ and ‘activation’, which were
originally developed for purposes other than for describing demonstrative con-
structions per se. The values I have presented in Figure 2 above can be seen as
contextual constraints on the eastern Nyland construction. However, in order to
bring together these communicative-functional features of the construction, the
functional potential of the construction needs to be explicated. In Figure 2, I
 Camilla Wide

have specified this potential as follows: ‘creates a focus on a familiar prominent


referent to make a point in a narrative, check or solve a task in the situation, re-
mind the listeners of or bring into focus larger contexts’. As with the other features
presented in Figure 2, the value is tentative. It will probably be possible to describe
it in more detail when the communicative-functional aspects of demonstrative and
other determination constructions have been worked out more generally for east-
ern Nyland dialects, Swedish and other languages. Even then, the value will prob-
ably have to be stated as a rather free textual description rather than as a selection
from a limited set of possibilities. As discussed in Section 2, the functional poten-
tial of grammatical constructions specifies in what way the constructions can be
used for performing communicative tasks. The concept of potentiality in itself im-
plies that the functional contents cannot be described with a finite set of values.
To summarize, in this section I have presented a tentative solution for how the
contextual features of the eastern Nyland demonstrative construction can be for-
malized in a CxG fashion. In my solution, I have followed the basic principles of
the CxG notation. However, due to my aim to combine CxG with Interactional
Linguistics, I have introduced some new concepts to the notations. These concepts
of sequential position, reference, activity, coherence and functional potential do not
just differ from pragmatic concepts used in previous studies on CxG. They also
differ in the way they are treated in the formalism, that is, as features which partly
overlap with each other.

7. Conclusion

The purpose of this paper has been to discuss a demonstrative construction in a


variety of spoken Swedish (eastern Nyland dialects in Finland) in order to explore
how Construction Grammar could be combined with Interactional Linguistics.
My main aim of the study has been to show that it is possible to combine these
frameworks. However, when communicative-functional aspects are added to CxG
formalizations, this has to be done in accordance with the findings and principles
of IL. Hence, I have introduced some concepts that are used in interactionally
oriented studies (sequential position, reference, activity, coherence, functional po-
tential) to describe the eastern Nyland construction. Some of these concepts over-
lap each other and they generally cannot be presented in binary or explicit terms
in the way syntactic features of constructions are typically presented. Nonetheless,
these features describe the eastern Nyland construction in a more precise way
than concepts such as ‘topic’/‘focus’ and ‘active’/‘semi-active’/‘non-active’, which
do not distinguish the construction sufficiently from other determinative con-
structions. Even though the concepts I have used and the way they are presented
Interactional construction grammar 

in the formalism obviously have to be studied and refined further, they open up
new possibilities to explore the functional sides of demonstrative constructions in
a more detailed way.

Notes

1 This article is based on a paper presented at IPrA, Riva del Garda, Italy, in July 2005. For
valuable comments on earlier drafts of the article, I thank Jan-Ola Östman, Mona Forsskåhl,
Benjamin Lyngfelt, Diana ben-Aaron and the anonymous referees.
2 The study is a contribution to the project Svenskan i Finland. Syntaktiska drag i ett jämförande
perspektiv ‘Swedish in Finland. Syntactic features in a comparative perspective’ at the Society for
Swedish literature in Finland 2003–2006 (see Lindström et. al. 2002; Wide & Lyngfelt 2009).
3 The main differences between spoken and written standard Swedish in the use of definite
articles and suffixes are the following. The neuter singular form det is generally pronounced [de]
and the plural forms de (nom.) and dem (obl.) are pronounced [dom] (or in some varieties [di]
in the nominative case and [dem] in the oblique case).
4 Standard Swedish allows double definiteness marking in noun phrases where a modifier
(consisting of a subordinate clause) does not precede but rather follows the noun, e.g., det (vikti-
ga) villkoret att räntan skulle vara betald före årsskiftet ‘the (important) condition-the that inter-
est-the should be paid before year turn-the’, den tunnan som står i garaget ‘the barrel-the that is
in garage-the’ (the Swedish Academy Grammar (SAG) 2: 301, 303). This is also the case in east-
ern Nyland dialects.
5 However, denna is used commonly in spoken language in southern and south-western
Sweden; in contrast to what is the case in standard Swedish the pronoun is here also combined
with nouns in the definite form (denna bok-en ‘this book-the’).
6 With ‘discourse focus’ I do not mean that the information is new. Rather, the term describes
that the speaker “zooms” in on the referent in question (cf. Lindström 2000: 119) in order to
structure the discourse and create coherence between different layers of contextual knowledge.

References:

Anward, Jan (1999). Interaction and Constructions. Paper presented at workshop in Helsinki,
September 1999. Revised version to appear in J.-O. Östman & M. Fried (Eds.), The Socio-
Pragmatics of Frame Semantics and Construction Grammar. Amsterdam & Philadelphia,
PA: John Benjamins.
Auer, Peter (2006). Construction Grammar meets Conversation: Einige Überlegungen am Beispiel
von „so“-Konstruktionen. In S. Günthner & W. Imo (Eds.), Konstruktionen in der Interak-
tion (291–314). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Bublitz, Wolfram (1998). Cohesion and Coherence. In J. Verschueren, J.-O. Östman, J. Blom-
maert & C. Bulcaen (Eds), Handbook of Pragmatics 1998 (1–15). Amsterdam & Philadel-
phia, PA: John Benjamins.
 Camilla Wide

Chafe, Wallace (1987). Cognitive constraints on information flow. In R.S. Tomlin (Ed.), Coher-
ence and Grounding in Discourse (21–51). Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Couch, Carl (1986). Elementary forms of social activity. In C. Couch, S. Saxton & M. Katovich
(Eds.), Studies in Symbolic Interaction: The Iowa School. Parts A and B (113–129). Green-
wich: JAI Press.
Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth & Margret Selting (2001). Introducing Interactional Linguistics. In
M. Selting & E. Couper-Kuhlen (Eds.), Studies in Interactional Linguistics (1–21). Amster-
dam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Diessel, Holger (1999). Demonstratives: Form, Function, and Grammaticalization. Amsterdam &
Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1988). The Mechanisms of “Construction Grammar”. BLS, 14, 35–55.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1989). Grammatical Construction Theory and the Familiar Dichotomies.
In R. Dietrich & C.F. Graumann (Eds.), Language Processing in Social Context (17–38).
Amsterdam: North-Holland/Elsevier.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1996). The pragmatics of constructions. In D.I. Slobin, J. Gerhardt, A.
Kyratzis & J. Guo (Eds.), Social Interaction, Social Context, and Language. Essays in Honor
of Susan Ervin-Tripp (53–69). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
FO = Ordbok över Finlands svenska folkmål. 1976–. Helsingfors: Forskningscentralen för de in-
hemska språken.
Fraurud, Kari (2000). Demonstrativer i svensk sakprosa. In DENNA – DEN HÄR – DEN DÄR.
Om demonstrativer i tvärspråklig belysning. En minnesskrift till Elsie Wijk-Andersson [ASLA
INFORMATION, 26:2 2000] (5–28). Uppsala: Universitetstryckeriet.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman (2004). Construction Grammar: A thumbnail sketch. In M.
Fried & J.-O. Östman (Eds.), Construction Grammar in a Cross-Language Perspective (11–
86). Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Fried, Mirjam & Jan-Ola Östman (2005). Construction Grammar and spoken language: The
case of pragmatic particles. Journal of Pragmatics, 37, 1752–1778.
Fujii, Seiko (2004). Lexically (un)filled constructional schemes and construction types: The case
of Japanese modal conditional constructions. In M. Fried & J.-O. Östman (Eds.), Construc-
tion Grammar in a Cross-Language Perspective (121–155). Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA:
John Benjamins.
Günthner, Susanne & Wolfgang Imo (Eds.) (2006). Konstruktionen in der Interaktion. Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Hawkins, John A. (1978). Definiteness and Indefiniteness: A Study in Reference and Grammatical-
ity Prediction. London: Croom Helm.
Himmelmann, Nikolaus P. (1996). Demonstratives in Narrative Discourse: A Taxonomy of Uni-
versal Uses. In B. Fox (Ed.), Studies in Anaphora (205–254). Amsterdam & Philadelphia,
PA: John Benjamins.
Hirvonen, Ilkka (1987). Konstruktionstyperna denne man och denne mannen i svenskan: En
språkhistorisk undersökning. Helsingfors: Svenska litteratursällskapet i Finland.
Imo, Wolfgang (2006). „Da hat des kleine glaub irgendwas angestellt“ – ein construct ohne con-
struction? In S. Günthner & W. Imo (Eds.), Konstruktionen in der Interaktion (263–290).
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Imo, Wolfgang (2007). Construction Grammar und Gesprochene-Sprache-Forschung: Konstruk-
tionen mit zehn matrixsatzfähigen Verben im gesprochenen Deutsch. Tübingen: Max Nie-
meyer.
Interactional construction grammar 

Kangas, Kea, Jan-Ola Östman, Leila Mattfolk & Åsa Mickwitz (2003). A strawberry-shaped day.
Paper presented at The 8th International Pragmatics Conference (IPrA), Toronto, 2003.
Kay, Paul (1995). Construction Grammar. In J. Verschueren, J.-O. Östman & J. Blommaert
(Eds.), Handbook of Pragmatics. Manual (171–177). Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John
Benjamins.
Lambrecht, Knud (1994). Information structure and sentence form. Topic, focus and the mental
representations of discourse referents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lambrecht, Knud (2004). On the interaction of information structure and formal structure in
constructions: The case of French right-detached comme-N. In M. Fried & J.-O. Östman
(Eds.), Construction Grammar in a Cross-Language Perspective (157–199). Amsterdam &
Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Langacker, Ronald W. (2008). Cognitive Grammar. A Basic Introduction. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Levinson, Stephen C. (1979). Activity types and language. Linguistics, 17–5/6 [219/220], 365–399.
Lindström, Eva (2000). Some uses of demonstratives in spoken Swedish. In S.P. Botley & T.
McEnery (Eds.), Corpus-based and Computational Approaches to Discourse Anaphora
(107–128). Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Lindström, Jan, Anne-Marie Londen, Marianne Nordman, Marketta Sundman & Jan-Ola Öst-
man (2002). Svenskan i Finland. Syntaktiska drag i ett jämförande perspektiv. Project plan.
Helsingfors: Svenska litteratursällskapet i Finland.
Linell, Per (1998). Approaching Dialogue: Talk, interaction and contexts in dialogical perspectives.
Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Linell, Per (2004). On Some Principles of a Dialogical Grammar. In K. Aijmer (Ed.), Dialogue
Analysis VIII: Understanding and Misunderstanding in Dialogue. Selected Papers from the
8th IADA Conference. Göteborg 2001 (7–23). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
Linell, Per (2005). En dialogisk grammatik? In J. Anward & B. Nordberg (Eds.), Samtal och
grammatik: Studier i svenskt samtalsspråk (231–328). Lund: Studentlitteratur.
Linell, Per (2006). Can We Formalise the Linguistic Resources of Interactional Language? In M.
Suominen, A. Arppe, A. Airola, O. Heinämäki, M. Miestamo, U. Määttä, J. Niemi, K.K.
Pitkänen & K. Sinnemäki (Eds.), A Man of Measure: Festschrift in Honour of Fred Karlsson
on his 60th Birthday. SKY Journal of Linguistics, 19, Special Supplement, 56–65.
Lundström, Gudrun (1939). Studier i nyländsk syntax. Stockholm: Norstedt.
Michaelis, Laura A. & Knud Lambrecht (1996). Toward a construction-based theory of language
function: the case of nominal extraposition. Language, 72, 215–247.
NFOS = Nyländska folksagor och -sägner, Vol. VI, 1896. Ordnade av A. Allardt & S. Perklén.
Helsingfors: Tidnings- och tryckeriaktiebolagets tryckeri.
Norén, Kerstin & Per Linell (2007). Meaning potentials and the interaction between lexis and
contexts: An empirical substantiation. Pragmatics, 17, 387–416.
Ochs Keenan, Elinor & Bambi B. Schieffelin (1976). Topic as a discourse notion: a study of
topic in the conversations of children and adults. In C.N. Li (Ed.), Subject and topic (335–
384). New York: Academic Press.
Östman, Jan-Ola (2008). Expedition Liljendal. In H. Palmén, C. Sandström & J.-O. Östman
(Eds.), Dialekt i östra Nyland: Fältarbete i Liljendal med omnejd [Nordica Helsingiensia]
(9–25). University of Helsinki: Department of Scandinavian Languages and Literature.
Östman, Jan-Ola & Mirjam Fried (Eds.) (2005). Construction Grammars. Cognitive grounding
and theoretical extensions. Amsterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
 Camilla Wide

Ono Tsuyoshi & Sandra A. Thompson (1995). What can conversation tell us about syntax? In
P.W. Davis (Ed.), Alternative Linguistics. Descriptive and Theoretical Modes (213–271). Am-
sterdam & Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.
Reinhammar, Vidar (1975). Pronomenstudier. Uppsala: Almqvist & Wiksell.
SAG = Svenska Akademiens grammatik. Ulf Teleman, Staffan Hellberg & Erik Andersson, 1999.
Stockholm: Svenska Akademien (Norstedts distr.).
SAOB = Ordbok över svenska språket, utg. av Svenska Akademien. 1893–. Lund. (Available at
http://g3.spraakdata.gu.se/saob/.)
Schegloff, Emanuel A., Elinor Ochs & Sandra A. Thompson (1996). Introduction. In E. Ochs, E.A.
Schegloff & S.A. Thompson (Eds.), Interaction and grammar (1–51). Cambridge, New York
& Melbourne: Cambridge University Press.
Steensig, Jakob (2001). Sprog i virkeligheden: Bidrag til en interaktionel lingvistik. Århus:
Aarhus Universitetsforlag.
Wide, Camilla (2002). Perfect in Dialogue. Form and functional potential of the vera búinn að +
inf. construction in contemporary Icelandic [PIC Monographs, 3]. University of Helsinki:
Department of Scandinavian Languages and Literature.
Wide, Camilla (2008a). Bruket av demonstrativa pronomen och bestämd form i östnyländska
samtal och intervjuer. In J. Lindström (Ed.), Språk och interaktion 1 [Nordica Helsingiensia 10]
(107–149). University of Helsinki: Department of Scandinavian Languages and Literature.
Wide, Camilla (2008b). En diskursfokuskonstruktion i östnyländska. In H. Palmén, C. Sand-
ström & J.-O. Östman (Eds.), Dialekt i östra Nyland Fältarbete i Liljendal med omnejd [Nor-
dica Helsingiensia 14] (53–109). University of Helsinki: Department of Scandinavian Lan-
guages and Literature.
Wide, Camilla & Benjamin Lyngfelt (Eds.) (2009). Konstruktioner i finlandssvensk syntax: Skrift-
språk, samtal och dialekter [Skrifter utgivna av Svenska litteratursällskapet i Finland, 716].
Helsingfors: Svenska litteratursällskapet i Finland.

Transcription conventions

word expression discussed in the analysis


word emphasis
*word* laughter in speaker’s voice
ºwordº soft voice
.word word uttered on inbreath
wor- speaker interrupts himself
[ overlapping speech starts
] overlapping speech ends
= turns are latched
.hh audible inbreath
(.) short pause
(0.9) timed pause (seconds)
(word) speech which is difficult to decipher
Interactional construction grammar 

(---) inaudible speech


[...] speech omitted
((laughs)) transcriber’s comments
prt discourse particle
part 3

Context and grammar


Contextual cues for particle placement
Multiplicity, motivation, modeling

Bert Cappelle

This chapter looks into a variety of contextual factors that play a role in a well-de-
scribed case of grammatical variation: the particle placement alternation in transi-
tive phrasal verbs (e.g., to pick up the book / to pick the book up). Most of the factors
that linguists have argued to be of relevance to this alternation are phonological,
morpho-syntactic, semantic or discourse-functional in nature (cf. Gries 2003). I
am not concerned here with re-investigating all known factors. Rather, what I in-
tend to do is (i) to single out those factors, both familiar and less familiar ones, that
can be construed as involving, one way or another, the context in which the phras-
al verb occurs, (ii) to formulate the further motivation(s) behind these factors, and
(iii) to briefly consider how these factors might be integrated into a constructionist
model of the variation. The main emphasis lies on my first aim.
The text is organized as follows. In Section 1, I introduce the ordering alterna-
tion at hand, as well as two important (and related) conditions on the morpho-
syntactic form which the direct object noun phrase (NP) should take for the alter-
nation to be possible: the object should not be an unaccented pronoun nor should
it be syntactically heavy – in sum, it should have moderate weight. Section 2 links
these two related constraints to a first, often-mentioned contextual factor, namely
the discourse-familiarity of the object NP, which has to do with whether that ob-
ject refers to something that has already been mentioned or evoked in the preced-
ing linguistic context (in which case that object will often be realized as an unac-
cented pronoun) or whether it introduces a new referent (in which case its
identification may require lengthy and complex modifications of the noun).
The subsequent sections deal with other, less well studied or less obviously
context-related factors. In Section 3, I will deal with a factor that could easily be
(and often has been) confused with discourse-familiarity, namely focus struc-
ture. This factor is concerned, simply put, with whether or not a clause element
provides prominent information, where ‘prominent’ can only be evaluated, of
course, in terms of contextual relevance and importance. Section 4 presents a
 Bert Cappelle

recently-discovered contextual factor: the presence of an instance of the transi-


tive verb-particle construction in one ordering or the other in the immediately
preceding linguistic context and its persistence effect on the word order of a sub-
sequent occurrence of that construction. Section 5 looks into linguistic context in
its widest sense: the impact of register and region. Section 6 is devoted to cues for
particle placement coming from the context taken in a more extra-linguistic sense:
here we look at how the choice for one or the other constructional alternative may
be influenced by whether or not the referent of the direct object NP and the ac-
tion it undergoes are ‘expected’, given certain frame-based knowledge. Sections 7
and 8, then, deal with factors that might not seem to be related to the notion of
context in any straightforward way: whether or not the verb-particle construction
is stative, and the degree to which the verb-particle combination is semantically
compositional, respectively. I will ask (and answer) the question how viable it is to
reformulate these factors as contextual ones.
Section 9 provides some explanation of why the factors exert the influence that
they do. Section 10, finally, reflects on how the impact of these contextual factors on
the particle placement variation can be modeled in a constructionist framework.

1. Particle placement: The phenomenon

1.1 One alternation, two conditions

The particle of a transitive phrasal verb can occur on either side of the object noun
phrase. The examples given in (1) illustrate this placement variation:
(1) a. They messed up the show. (‘joined’ ordering)
b. They messed the show up. (‘split’ ordering)
This variation is constrained by two conditions on the object NP, namely, (i) that it
not be an unaccented pronoun and (ii) that it not be too heavy. If the object NP is
an unaccented personal pronoun, the particle has to follow it; if it is decidedly
heavy (more on which below), the particle has to precede it:
(2) a. *They messed up it.
b. They messed it up.
c. They messed up everything we had all worked towards these last few
months.
d. *They messed everything we had all worked towards these last few
months up.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

Whether a pronoun is accented or not is easy enough to ascertain in any given


context, even when the mode of communication is written rather than spoken. In
written discourse, different readers will normally reach a consensus as to whether
the pronoun receives a “silent” accent. The pronoun only receives an accent if it is
focused on, but this is a rather exceptional case for pronominal objects. Also, there
is no gradience in ‘accentedness’ of an object pronoun. Either the pronominal ob-
ject is accented (i.e. is focused on) or it is not (i.e. is not focused on). There are no
in-between cases.1 In the rare case that a pronominal object receives an accent, it
can follow the particle (e.g. Bolinger 1971: 39–40; Fraser 1976: 17; Aarts 1989: 286),
but it does not have to, as we will see in Section 3.2. In the much more common
case that the pronominal object is unaccented, it obligatorily has to precede the
particle. There simply is no other option.
By contrast, the end-placement of heavy objects is not a categorical constraint
but a tendency. That is, the requirement that particles precede heavy object NPs
can only be expressed as a statistical generalization, not as an absolute rule, because
there is only an increasing preference for end-placement of the object NP as its
weight increases. Since the weight of the object NP (unlike the presence or absence
of focal accent) is a matter of degree, we can only try to determine what can count
as a sufficiently heavy NP for us to predict with a reasonable degree of confidence
that the split ordering will be ruled out. Moreover, it is not immediately clear how
we should define ‘weight’. Do we have to look at crude factors like number of words
or syllables (i.e. length) or is weight to be defined relative to the internal constitu-
ency of the NP (i.e. complexity)? Or is there even another parameter that should be
taken into account if we talk about the weight of a constituent?

1.2 Weight: A matter of length or a matter of complexity?

The earliest known formulation of the general principle of end-weight (Quirk et al.
1972) probably dates back to Otto Behaghel’s (1909/1910) “Gesetz der Wachsend-
en Glieder” (‘law of increasing elements’), of which he later gave the following
concise formulation:
Von zwei Gliedern von verschiedenem Umfang steht das umfangreichere nach.
(Behaghel 1930, cited in Arnold et al. 2000: 29)
(‘Of two constituents of different size, the larger one follows [the smaller one].’)

Interestingly, Dik (1997 [1978]: 404) mentions Behaghels law of increasing ele-
ments as the first statement of his own “principle of increasing complexity”, not-
withstanding that Behaghel’s law clearly refers to size (i.e. length) and not to con-
stituent-internal syntactic complexity. This goes to show that length and
complexity are often treated as interchangeable parameters (cf. Wasow 1997 for
 Bert Cappelle

disciussions of this point). There can be no misunderstanding, though, that length


and complexity constitute different definitions of the concept ‘weight’. So, the
question is: Which parameter defines weight best – length (i.e. number of, say,
words) or complexity (i.e. internal syntactic intricacy of the NP caused by the
presence of, e.g., a postmodifier)?
Length apparently does play a role in constituent ordering. Charting the choice
of particle-final placement against length of the object NP (measured in words) in
a large set of corpus examples, Lohse et al. (2004: 243) observe a first marked drop
in the choice of this ordering (from 40% to 18%) if the NP-length increases from
two to three words, and a second marked drop (to a negligible 3%) if the NP-length
reaches 5 words or over.2 Yet, as Lohse et al. further point out, these marked drops
may in fact also correlate with increasing internal complexity of the object NP,
since NPs of length three have more chance of containing a modifying adjective
(besides a determiner) and since NPs of length five or over have more chance of
containing postnominal modifiers like prepositional phrases or relative clauses.
The idea that what actually determines particle placement is not so much the
length of the object NP as its phrase-structural complexity has been suggested by
various scholars, including Chomsky (1964 [1961]; 1975), Fraser (1966), and Ross
(1986 [1967]).3 Complexity is usually taken to involve the presence of an embed-
ded clause. Thus, while the object NP in (3a) is longer – both in number of words
and in number of syllables – than the object NP in (3b), the latter, containing a
short relative clause, is clearly less grammatical in the split ordering:
(3) a. I called almost all of the men from Boston up.
b. *I called the man you met up.
(Chomsky 1964 [1961]: 127, n. 18)
This contrastive pair of sentences seems very convincing. Surprisingly enough,
though, corpus studies so far have not been able to confirm that it is indeed com-
plexity and not sheer length that may prevent an object NP from occurring in the
split construction. Gries’s (2003) book-length study is aimed at dealing with just
this kind of issue: finding out which of the factors ever proposed in the literature
genuinely influence particle placement, and which of them are ‘parasitical’, in the
sense that their values usually co-occur with the values of these genuine factors
without themselves having an independent impact. If I interpret Gries’s (2003: 110)
results correctly, it looks as though complexity does not exert an influence on par-
ticle placement distinct from length. At least, his results appear to be rather
equivocal. On the one hand, non-complex NPs (defined by him as either pro-
nominal ones or as NPs consisting of only a head and possibly a determiner) and
NPs with intermediate complexity (defined by him as NPs with an adjective, NPs
with an of-PP or co-ordinated NPs) could both be shown to favor the split ordering
Contextual cues for particle placement 

independently of their length. On the other hand, complex NPs (defined as NPs
with a finite or nonfinite postmodifying clause) apparently did not, independently
of their length, prefer the joined ordering. I presume this non-finding is caused by
the non-occurrence of complex object NPs that weren’t also considerably long, as
in (3b), in his set of corpus examples, which contains fewer than 500 sentences.
Similarly indeterminate results are reported by Wasow (2002: 32–40), whose ex-
perimental and corpus findings could neither corroborate nor reject the above-
mentioned claim (e.g. Chomsky (1964 [1961]) that it is complexity rather than
length of the object NP that influences particle placement.

1.3 Two conditions for the price of one?

Given that pronouns are short and non-complex, we may capture a generalization
if we merge the two conditions on the form of the object NP, mentioned in Sec-
tion 1.1, into one single condition. Thus, (4) is the formulation of a more general
constraint on particle placement:
(4) For the choice as to the placement of the particle to be in principle avail-
able, the object NP should have moderate weight.
By stating that the NP should have moderate weight, we at once exclude heavy NPs
and unaccented pronouns from the set of object NPs that are allowed in the two
constructions.
However, object NPs consisting of a single, one-syllable, non-pronominal
word can still enter into the alternation (e.g. He sure knows how to pick {up girls /
girls up}). This means that our question whether weight might involve more than
just length and/or complexity (cf. the end of Section 1.1) may not have been un-
warranted. For an object NP to be light, it should not only have minimal length
and complexity, but it should also be phonologically reduced. What distinguishes
the set of unaccented pronominal objects from maximally light non-pronominal
NPs is their lack of phonological strength. That is, their initial consonant can be
dropped (in the case of him, her and them) and/or their vowel can be shortened (in
the case of me and you) or even neutralized to a schwa (in the case of you, her, us
and them), or they can be reduced to their final (syllabified) consonant (in the case
of her and them).4
That phonological strength may indeed also play a role in particle placement
seems to be confirmed by the fact that a pronominal object NP which receives an
accent (thereby rendering impossible its phonological reduction – *pick ’em up)
can occur to the right as well as to the left of the particle, as we have already point-
ed out above (compare He sure knows how to pick {*up ’em / ’em up} and He sure
knows how to pick {up them / them up}).
 Bert Cappelle

1.4 Lexical restrictions

It should be borne in mind that object NPs of moderate weight cannot always oc-
cur in the two constructional variants because there are some verb-particle com-
binations which happen to be lexically constrained to have only one truly conven-
tionalized manifestation, either the joined (V – Prt – NP) or the split (V – NP – Prt)
ordering. For example, blow off ‘release’, drum up ‘obtain’, give off ‘emit’, hold out
‘foster (a feeling) in the face of hardship’, kick up ‘cause (trouble)’ and the full ex-
pression take up arms ‘become involved in a conflict’, among others, only seem to
allow the joined ordering:
(5) a. We all need to blow {off steam / *steam off} from time to time.
b. It won’t be easy to drum {up support / *support up}.
c. Do you like candles that give {off a smell / *a smell off}?
d. Families of the missing continue to hold {out hope / *hope out}.
e. If it happens again, I’m gonna kick {up a fuss / *a fuss up}.
f. The peasants are threatening to take {up arms / *arms up}.
Conversely, the object NP always seems to occur between the verb and the par-
ticle in combinations like ask over ‘invite at one’s house’, push around ‘be bossy
towards’, see through ‘bring to a happy conclusion’, tell apart ‘distinguish’, and in full
expressions like push the boat out ‘celebrate regardless of expense’, laugh/work/…
one’s ass/butt/socks off ‘laugh/work excessively’ and the popular humorous taunt
{[Someone],} eat your heart out {[someone]}!:
(6) a. It’s been ages since we invited {*over the neighbors / the neighbors over}.
b. I don’t like the way he pushes {*around my mom / my mom around}.
c. You can depend on us to see {*through the job / the job through}.
d. She really pushed {*out the boat / the boat out} for her fortieth birthday.
e. I’ve been working {*off my ass / my ass off} all day.
f. Van Gogh, eat {*out your heart / your heart out}! (implies that the
speaker or someone known to the speaker can do something better than
the (absent) addressee, who is widely acclaimed for excelling in the rele-
vant field, in this case that of painting)
Combinations like those illustrated in (5) and (6) merely represent the extremes
on a continuum of word order preferences which lexicalized verb-particle combi-
nations can have (cf. Biber et al. 1999: 933; Gries and Stefanowitsch 2004: 110–113;
Szmrecsanyi 2005: 130 ff.). Less extreme cases are, for example, find out ‘discover’
and pluck up ‘muster’, which usually pattern like the combinations in (5) and, to-
wards the other extreme, combinations like answer back ‘reply or interrupt
Contextual cues for particle placement 

impudently when being scolded’ and get a word in edgewise ‘find an opportunity
to say something’, which usually pattern like those in (6):
(7) a. They will find {out the truth /??the truth out} someday.
b. I must pluck {up my courage /??my courage up} and tell her I love her.
c. In my days, we never answered {??back our parents / our parents back}.
d. When he talked, nobody else could get {??in a word / a word in} edge-
wise.
Around the middle of the continuum are combinations that have a less clear prefer-
ence for one ordering or the other, like beat up, hand over, shoot down, try out, etc.
Note, finally, that when the object NP is an unaccented pronoun, it still has to
precede the particle of a phrasal verb situated at the extreme represented by the
combinations in (5):
(8) a. The “angry youth” were allowed to blow off steam. Well they blew it off,
alright, and stabbed a visiting Australian yeshiva student named
Yankel Rosenbaum to death. (www) (cp. *… blew off it)
b. Still, many people find that if they want support for coping with a rare
disease, they have to drum it up themselves. (www) (cp. *… drum up it)
Apparently, the ‘grammatical rule’ requiring the particle to follow an unaccented
pronoun always takes precedence over any ordering convention on the level of
individual verb-particle combinations. Farrell (2005: 130) takes this as evidence
that unaccented pronominal objects ought to be distinguished from other kinds of
objects in that they attach to the right of verbs as clitics or as some kind of inflec-
tional affixes (more or less as in French, where unaccented object pronouns attach
to the left of the finite verb, e.g. M’as-tu vu?, Me-have you seen?, i.e. ‘Have you seen
me?’). We might therefore say that this cliticization/affixation mechanism, if that
is what it is, applies across the board, staying blind to whichever fixed order of the
particle vis-à-vis the object NP is otherwise observed with particular phrasal
verbs.5

1.5 Summary of Section 1

To sum up so far, there is a general ordering variation in English between the non-
verbal element (the ‘particle’) of transitive phrasal verbs and its direct object NP. In
the ‘joined’ ordering, the verb and the particle are in adjacent positions, with the
direct object NP occurring to the right of the particle (e.g. stick out your tongue);
in the ‘split’ ordering, the verb and the particle are separated from each other by
the intervening direct object NP (e.g. stick your tongue out).
 Bert Cappelle

If the direct object NP is extremely light, only the split ordering is possible; if
it is very heavy, only the joined ordering is possible. A direct object is extremely
light if it consists of a single syllable which is phonologically reducible, i.e. whose
initial consonant can be dropped and/or whose vowel can be shortened and/or
further neutralized. In practice, we can say that the direct object NP is extremely
light if and only if it is an unaccented pronoun. A direct object is very heavy if it
contains an embedded clause. In practice, such an object will also be quite long,
and a length of five words or over has proven to be by itself a sufficiently accurate
predictor for the choice of the joined ordering.
If the direct object NP has moderate weight (i.e. if it neither is an unaccented
pronoun nor has a length of more than four words), it can in principle occur be-
fore or after the particle. Individual verb-particle combinations, though, may still
favor one ordering or the other. Still, even combinations with a very strong prefer-
ence for the joined ordering cannot undo the ‘rule’ that unaccented pronouns
must precede the particle.

2. Discourse-familiarity of the object NP

2.1 ‘Old’ before ‘new’: Terminological specification

Discourse consists of both content which the speaker takes to be old or known to
the hearer and content which he or she assumes to be new or unknown to the
hearer. In constructing a sentence, the speaker ordinarily puts the informational
content which is supposed to be old before that which is supposed to be new. ‘Old’
and ‘new’ can be interpreted in a variety of ways (cf., e.g., Prince 1981), for example
as contextually given vs. contextually new, as ‘addressee-old’ vs. ‘addressee-new’, as
‘topic’ (what the sentence is about) versus ‘comment’ (what is said about the topic),
as ‘theme’ versus ‘rheme’ (a distinction featuring prominently in the ‘Prague
School’), or as ‘background’ / ‘presupposition’ versus ‘focus’ (cf. Section 3 for the
latter distinction). In this second section I am concerned with the first distinction
mentioned, also known as the distinction between ‘discourse-old’ and ‘discourse-
new’ information. Discourse-old information is information coded in parts of the
sentence that refer (either verbatim, or, more often, via the use of anaphoric pro-
nouns or other semantically related items – cf. Section 2.3 below) to entities,
properties, propositions, etc. that have already been mentioned earlier in the dis-
course. Discourse-new information is conveyed by parts of the sentence (possibly
all of it) that do not take up familiar elements from the preceding discourse.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

2.2 The relation between discourse-familiarity and weight

Discourse-familiarity usually correlates positively with weight, a fact that has not
gone unnoticed by linguists. For example, Quirk et al. (1985: 1361) point out that
“the new information often needs to be stated more fully than the given (that is,
with a longer, ‘heavier’ structure)”, and Arnold et al. (2000: 34) give some further
references to the generalization that “[i]tems which have been recently mentioned
tend to be accessible to both speaker and hearer, and require less complex descrip-
tions than items which are not”. Thus, because of their familiarity or lack thereof,
respectively, discourse-old NPs can be referred to by means of short forms – most
typically, of course, pronouns – while discourse-new NPs are often marked by the
presence of modifications, appositions, etc.
Now, given this correlation between weight and discourse-familiarity, Wasow
(2002: 81) asks the obvious question: “[D]o weight and information status exert
distinct influences on ordering, or is one just a side-effect of the other?” (cf. also
Arnold et al. 2000). That is: Do heavy constituents tend to be placed late in the
sentence because they are usually new or do new constituents tend to be placed
late in the sentence because they are usually heavy? Or, rather, is neither factor
‘parasitic’ on the other (cf. again Section 1.2 for this imagery) and do they have
independent influences on word order?
Without going into this question in any depth, I confine myself to putting to-
gether two relevant facts known from the literature. First of all, the correlation
between the length and/or complexity of clause constituents and the amount of
new information they convey is not perfect. It is quite possible for long and com-
plex constituents to convey discourse-old information and for short and simple
ones to convey discourse-new information (Ward, Birner and Huddleston
2002: 1371). Secondly, weight and familiarity are independent word order para­
meters. As a consequence, one parameter can be held constant to test the effect of
the other parameter. This is the underlying method in Arnold et al.’s (2000) care-
fully conducted study (whose actual statistical method is more complicated than
this text allows me to go into). Testing the individual effects of weight and famili-
arity on heavy NP shift and on the dative alternation (by means of corpus analyses
and an elicitation experiment), Arnold et al. could confidently conclude that both
factors significantly and independently contribute to end-placement. In other
words, they revealed that the tendency of heavy constituents to occur at or towards
the end of a clause is not epiphenomenal to (i.e. a side-effect of) their newness,
and, vice versa, that the frequent end-placement of discourse-new constituents is
not epiphenomenal to their weight.
 Bert Cappelle

2.3 Relevance of discourse-familiarity to particle placement

Gries’s (2003) study on particle placement supports Arnold et al.’s (2002) finding
that discourse-familiarity is independent of weight. Thus, not only can the length
(though less clearly the complexity) of the object NP be shown to be a certain,
significant influence on its position vis-à-vis the particle (cf. Section 1.2 above),
but so can a variety of discourse-functional factors bearing on the discourse-fa-
miliarity of the object NP. More in particular, Gries proves the significance of such
factors as the distance to the last mention of the object NP, the object NP’s ‘cohe-
siveness’ to the preceding discourse – that is, the degree to which it is evoked by
the previous occurrence of coreferential items or of items that stand in a hyp(er)
onymical (superordinate/subordinate) or in a meronymical (part/whole) relation
with it – and the number of times the object NP has been mentioned in the pre-
ceding discourse (Gries 2003: 72–74; 89–92).
By way of illustration, let us consider (9), the full context of which is cited and
discussed by Gries (2003: 72–74). For lack of space, I only provide the actual sen-
tence with the verb-particle combination.
(9) The lawyers took Valenzuela off to record his testimony.
(BNC corpus, cited and discussed in Gries 2003: 72–74)
While the object noun in this example consists of no fewer than five syllables (Va-
len-zu-e-la) and hence should be placed after the particle on account of its consider-
able length, its mid-position is by far the most natural placement, since this proper
noun refers to a discourse-familiar item, via its frequent anticipation in the form of
pronouns (like he, his etc.) and via an alternative description (as a kidnapper) which
cannot be mistaken to refer to the same person in the context concerned.
Gries’s results also confirm Bock’s (1977), Chen’s (1986) and Peters’ (2001) ear-
lier experiments on the role played by discourse-familiarity in the positioning of
the direct object in transitive verb-particle combinations. In turn, Gries’s results
have been corroborated by Szmrecsanyi’s (2005) findings. All these studies support,
in part, what Erades (1961: 57), among others, already had intuited, namely that
[t]he principle governing the place of the objects … is neither stress nor length
nor rhythm, but something quite different: the news value which the idea denoted
by the object has in the sentence. Objects denoting ideas that have news value, no
matter whether they are nouns or pronouns, long or short, have end-position;
those that have no such value come between verb and adverb.
(Erades 1961: 57; cited in Bolinger 1971: 51)

Erades is not correct, however, in considering the news value of the object as the
sole factor governing particle placement and, hence, in rejecting accent and length
Contextual cues for particle placement 

as possible co-determinants. Length does play a role, as we have seen, and so does
accent, which is a symptom of focality, the factor to be discussed in Section 3.

2.4 Interim conclusion and transition

We have seen in Section 1 that unaccented pronouns are placed as close as possible
to the verb, in other words, right after it and before the particle. This may not (just)
be because unaccented pronouns are extremely light and therefore act as clitics but
also because they convey information that is discourse-old or refer to elements
that are otherwise familiar to the addressee in the speech situation (e.g. me, you).
Elements with such information status tend to occur early in the sentence, and the
compulsory mid-positioning of unaccented pronouns in the verb-particle con-
struction may be seen as a grammaticalization of this tendency.
Conversely, long and heavily modified noun phrases are shifted as far as possi-
ble towards the end of the clause, in other words, after the particle, as we also stated
in Section 1. Again, this is not (just) because such NPs have much weight but also
because they typically refer to entities that are newly introduced into the discourse
and because discourse-new constituents generally tend to be put towards the end.
In the next section, we will discuss in considerable detail a factor that is often
wrongly collapsed with discourse-familiarity, namely focus structure. Although
discourse-new constituents usually do convey the most prominent and pertinent
information in the clause (and in this sense contain ‘new’ information), it is
nevertheless necessary to keep these two factors apart.

3. Focus structure

As Erades’s (1961) quote given at the end of Section 2.3 insinuates, it is sometimes
assumed that accent (i.e. stress, intonation) is a decisive factor in the placement of
the particle and the object NP. This assumption had already been made by Poutsma
(1928) and Kruisinga (1931/1932), but it is still voiced by present-day linguists.
For example, Svenonius (1996: 52), commenting on native speakers’ preference for
the joined construction with indefinite objects (e.g. for I’ll send out flyers as op-
posed to I’ll send flyers out), states: “I suggest that intonation is actually what
det[er]mines these preferences”. This view is repeated, more recently even, in
Büring (2005: 25), where some further references are given (repeated here in his
quote): “[…] object–particle order is preferred with unaccented objects, while
particle–object order is preferred with accented objects (Chen, 1986; Dehé, [2000],
[2001], 2002; Svenonius, 1996).”
 Bert Cappelle

Accented elements in a sentence signal ‘focal’ (or ‘focused’) information. This


is the most prominent and pertinent information in a given context, as opposed to
the ‘backgrounded’ or ‘presupposed’ information contained in what Ward, Birner
and Huddleston (2002: 1370) refer to as the ‘focus-frame’. If speakers prefer to put
an accented object after the particle, this is in accordance with a general principle
by which focal elements are put at the end of sentences (the principle of end-focus
– see, e.g., Quirk et al. 1985: 1356–1357).
Now, a number of oversimplifications are being circulated when it comes to
linking up particle placement with the role of sentence focus:
i. Focal elements correspond to discourse-new elements: “It is natural to place fo-
cus pitch on an element which is informationally novel”. (Svenonius 1996: 52)
ii. The nuclear accent of a sentence generally falls at the end: “It is also natural in
English for there to be a rising pitch at the right edge of a simple sentence”
(Svenonius 1996: 52). Hence, the natural place for a focal element, which is by
definition marked by accentuation, is at the end of the sentence, so that the
focal accent coincides with the natural sentence accent: “Accented items are
usually sentence-finally, which corresponds to the natural order of English
where end-focus is reserved for expressions denoting the focal referent of the
utterance”. (Gries 2003: 39)
iii. When uttering an active clause containing a transitive phrasal verb, the speaker
has the choice to assign the focus to either the object NP or the particle. De-
pending on this simple choice, either the object NP or the particle is put at the
end: “Whichever of the two constituents (the direct object or the particle) is to
be emphasized, it will be positioned sentence-finally”. (Gries 2003: 52)
In the following three sections, I will show that these at first sight straightforward
rules overlook a number of complications.

3.1 Focal elements need not be discourse-new

Quirk et al.’s (1985: 1356–1357) principle of end-focus is defined as “the linear


presentation from low to high information value”, where information value seems
to be further formulated and illustrated in terms of discourse-familiarity: elements
with low information value are those that are known from the preceding discourse
(‘given’) and that can accordingly be pronominalized, while elements with high
information value are unknown (‘new’) and require explicit expression with full
lexical material (p. 1430–1431). The link between the notion of focus and that of
discourse-familiarity is also established by Dehé (2002):
The focused part of an utterance cannot be taken for granted at a corresponding
time of utterance. It is not predictable and cannot be inferred/recovered from the
Contextual cues for particle placement 

preceding context or discourse situation. It is typically new information which has


not been mentioned before. (Dehé 2002: 105)

But note that the use of typically in the last sentence is not an unwarranted hedge,
since focal information is often but not necessarily discourse-new information.
Consider the following short question-answer pair:
(10) Did you prefer the movie or the book? — I preferred the book.
The focus in the response sentence is the book. It is intonationally as well as infor-
mationally the most prominent element in the response. In a sense, it provides
new information, since prior to the response, the first speaker did not yet know the
specific value of the variable x in the focus-frame ‘I (= second speaker) preferred
x’. Notwithstanding its status as focus and as ‘new information’, though, the NP the
book in this second sentence is not discourse-new, since it has been mentioned in
the preceding question. Thus, focus structure and discourse-familiarity are dis-
tinct concepts (Ward, Birner and Huddleston 2002: 1370).

3.2 Focal elements need not be sentence-final

The end of the sentence is generally acknowledged to be the prime focus position:
“The focus typically appears at or towards the end of the clause” (Ward, Birner and
Huddleston 2002: 1372). Granting this, we should not disregard the possibility of
assigning any word or constituent of a clause the status of focus depending on the
surrounding discourse, resulting in contrastive focus, a special case of marked focus
(Quirk et al. 1985: 1365). This kind of focus being available for any element in any
clause, it can also be applied, naturally, to the direct object NP in active clauses
with a transitive verb-particle combination. Thus, it is perfectly possible for an
object NP to occur in the split ordering and bear a marked focus accent. In other
words, it need not be the case, contrary to what Diessel and Tomasello (2005: 91)
write, that “[i]f the direct object carries stress accent the particle [precedes] it, even
if the object is pronominal”, as in
(11) Pick up HIM (not her).
(Diessel and Tomassello 2005: 91)
On the one hand, it is true that a pronominal object cannot occur sentence-finally
(cf. again example (2a) in Section 1.1) unless it is accented. Here is a similar, au-
thentic, example:
(12) Of all the dogs in the shelter, my Master picked out me! (www)
 Bert Cappelle

In this example, the narrating dog (referred to by the pronominal object me) puts
itself in contrast with all the other dogs in the shelter, and hence, me is contrastively
focused. On the other hand, it is by no means obligatory to put a pronominal object,
nor indeed any object NP (pronominal or not), at the end if it carries contrastive ac-
cent. This is illustrated by the following authentic examples (small capitals added):
(13) a. Well, it was me who finally asked him out instead of the other way
around. (www)
b. …quitting cold turkey is not an option. The withdraw[a]l not only
stresses the body out, but stresses the baby out as well. (www)
The occurrence of a contrastively accented object in the split ordering is possible,
as Dehé (2002) remarks, because “contrastive focus and the corresponding accent
placement is not bound to a certain position. It can be assigned to every constitu-
ent in the sentence, and can therefore be realized at every structural position”
(Dehé 2002: 172).
Bolinger (1971: 51), too, discusses the possibility of mid-position of accented
objects, giving examples like the following:
(14) a. Let’s take our friénds over.
b. They shot the whole pláce up.
(Bolinger 1971: 51)
It is important to note that Bolinger’s examples above could easily be uttered in
circumstances in which the object, though accented, is not contrasted with an-
other potential object in the context. This means that contrastive opposition is not
a prerequisite for the occurrence of accented objects in the split ordering, a point
to which we will return below, in Section 3.3 and, in more detail, in Section 6. The
occurrence of an accented object in the split ordering may be thought to be in vio-
lation of the unmarked placement of the nuclear accent, which is sentence-final.
Remember, though, our quote of Ward, Birner and Huddleston (2002: 1372) that
“[t]he focus typically appears at or towards the end of the clause” (emphasis add-
ed). More specifically, the nuclear sentence accent characteristically falls on “the
(stressed syllable of the) last open-class lexical item of the last clause element”
(Quirk et al. 1985: 1357). So, given that particles are closed-class elements, it seems
to me that examples like (14a-b) are in fact perfectly in keeping with this general
prosodic principle. Note, for example, that sentence-final prepositions are also
usually left unaccented (e.g. What are you talking about?).6
Contextual cues for particle placement 

3.3 Other options than focus on either object or particle

In view of the fact that the particle placement alternation concerns the position of
two elements relative to each other – the direct object and the particle – it is
tempting to reduce the issue of the prosodic pattern of the verb phrase to focal ac-
centuation on either of these two elements – see Van Dongen (1919: 331ff.) and
Gries (2003: 24–25) for an early and recent example, respectively. Gries uses the
following sets of question-answer pairs to illustrate the positional preferences (I
underline the focused part in the answers):
(15) a. What did he pick up? — He picked up the book.
b. Where did he bring the book? — He brought the book back.
(after Gries 2003: 25)
Dehé (2002: 132) correctly observes that the domain of the focus can vary in size.
That is, the focused part need not be restricted to the very word or smallest con-
stituent containing the accented syllable. So, we could also have the following
question-answer pairs.
(16) a. What did he do? — He picked up the book.
b. What happened? — He picked up the book.
(after Dehé 2002: 132)
Thus, in addition to the so-called ‘minimal focus’ on the object NP or on the par-
ticle, exemplified respectively in (15a) and (15b), we can have ‘non-minimal focus’
on the entire predicate and ‘maximal’ focus on the entire sentence, as in (16a) and
(16b), respectively. Furthermore, Dehé considers the case in which the predicate
minus the object NP is within the focus domain:
(17) What did he do with the book? — He picked the book up.
(after Dehé 2002: 132)
According to Dehé, the focal scenario with a backgrounded (presupposed) object
NP is the only one in which the split ordering is, and has to be, used.7,8 Dehé
(2002) does not go into a case like (15b), where the focus is on the particle, but
since such a sentence also has a backgrounded object NP, its obligatory use of the
split ordering conforms to her claim. Dehé (2002) acknowledges, though, that the
split ordering can also be used if the object NP is not backgrounded but (on the
contrary) bears contrastive focus accent, as we remarked in Section 3.2. The joined
ordering, still according to Dehé, is the default one, to be selected in all cases in
which the object NP constitutes or is a part of the focus domain without being
contrastively accented, as in (15a), (16a) and (16b).
 Bert Cappelle

This is not accurate, however. Consider again Bolinger’s (1971: 51) examples
given in Section 3.2 above (in 14), repeated here in (18):
(18) a. Let’s take our friénds over.
b. They shot the whole pláce up.
(Bolinger 1971: 51)
Here, the object NP carries (presumably non-contrastive) accent but nonetheless
occurs in the split ordering. I will come back to such examples in Section 6.
The examples given so far in this section still do not exhaust all the focal pos-
sibilities. There are, in fact, four more cases, logically speaking. First, there can be
minimal focus on the verb itself, namely when it is contrasted with another verb
combining with the same particle:
(19) a. Did he pick the book up? — No, it is more accurate to say that he
heaved the book up. It was a very heavy book, you know.
b. He did not wash any of the dust off. He brushed it off… (www)
In this case, the particle is preferably put in end-position (compare: Did he pick up
the book? —?No, he truly heaved up the book). I suppose the reason for this is that
a particle in the joined ordering is always accented to some degree. Accenting the
verb and its immediately following particle produces a violation of the prosodic
principle discussed by Gussenhoven (2004: 255–256) as the ‘NoClash’ constraint.
To avoid two accents in adjacent positions, then, the speaker can either de-accent
the particle in the joined ordering, which results in an unusual accent pattern for
verb-particle combinations, or she can select the split ordering, which is often
used for de-accented particles anyway (cf. again Bolinger’s examples above). In
short, the split ordering allows the accent on the verb to stand out.9
Second, we may actually be dealing with two independent foci, one on the
object NP and another on the particle. This possibility only arises with verbs that
combine with more than one particle in a semantically similar way. (We therefore
cannot use pick up: while we also have pick out, it is clear that the contribution of
pick is not constant in these combinations.) Here is an example:
(20) The next steps in the sequence must turn the red and amber lights off
before turning the green light on. (www)
Here again, the split ordering is preferred, but since the NoClash constraint is po-
tentially violated, this preference must be for a different reason. A particle can only
be contrasted with another particle if it makes an independent semantic contribu-
tion – independent of the verb, that is. This means, in effect, that it has some pred-
icative power (over the object NP) of its own: in the example above, for example,
the result of the actions involved is that the relevant lamps are off or on. Now,
Contextual cues for particle placement 

when both the object NP and the particle compete for end-position (which is the
neutral position for focal elements), the particle will be preferred in this position,
so that object and particle align themselves as in the grammatically very general
subject-predicate construction.10,11 The final placement of the particle in (15b)
may also be partly explained as inheriting the predicate-final ordering of clauses.
Third, it may be the case that the verb and the object NP are two independent
foci. Consider the following made-up example:
(21) Moody Max was in a particularly destructive temper and decided that
whatever made noise had to be turned off with violence. He smashed the
TV off and shot the radio off.
This situation is so rare that the preferred ordering cannot be deduced from cor-
pus data. On the one hand, the joined ordering may be preferred because it keeps
the focal elements, and hence their accented syllables, apart as far as possible. On
the other hand, the particle in the verb-particle combination is always slightly ac-
cented in pre-object position, and its accent then potentially clashes both with the
accent on the preceding verb and with the accent on the following noun. Keeping
the particle de-accented in end-position resolves this clash. Elicitation experi-
ments and judgment tasks would be needed to find out speakers’ preferences in
this special focal scenario.
Fourth, the final possibility is the trivial one in which neither the verb, nor the
object NP nor again the particle falls within the focus domain:
(22) How did he pick the book up? — He picked the book up with both hands.
In this case, both orderings are in principle possible, but the ordering preferred is
the one used in the question, as we will see in the next section (Section 4). Thus, if
the question were How did he pick up the book?, then the answer would be more
likely to repeat the joined ordering: He picked up the book with both hands. Al-
though pleading against this ordering would be the discourse-old status of the
object NP, this violation would be mitigated by the fact that the object-old NP
would not appear in the canonical position for focal elements, which would be
occupied by another element.

3.4 Summary of Section 3

In Table 1 below I summarize the different possibilities of assigning focal accen-


tuation and the impact this may or may not have on the choice of the joined or the
split construction.
 Bert Cappelle

Table 1. The two orderings by focal element(s)

Joined (V – Prt – NP) Split (V – Prt – NP)

V () 
 NoClash e.g. (19a–b)
V, Prt  
 OldObj-Left e.g. (17)
 Focus-Last
V, Prt, NP  
e.g. (16a–b) e.g. (18a–b)
V, NP () ()
 NoClash  NoClash
e.g. (21)
Prt  
 OldObj-Left e.g. (15b)
 Focus-Last
 Subj-Pred
Prt, NP  
 Subj-Pred  NoClash
e.g. (20a–b)
NP  
e.g. (15a)  Focus-Last
e.g. (13a–b)
other  
 OldObj-Left e.g. (22)
 = ‘the ordering on top is allowed under the focus structure on the left’
() = ‘the ordering on top is marginally allowed under the focus structure on the left’
 = ‘the ordering on top is not allowed under the focus structure on the left’
 = ‘the ordering on top violates the following principle under the focus structure on the
left: …’
Focus-Last: The focus of a clause appears at the end of that clause.
NoClash: Accented elements should not be in adjacent positions.
Subj-Pred: When aligning a subject and its predicate, put the subject first.
OldObj-Left: A discourse-old direct object NP is leftmost in the post-verbal field.

The table above also indicates how the different focus assignments may interact
with some general prosodic and ordering principles to rule out one or the other
particle placement construction. Note that selecting the split ordering generally
yields least violations.
It is important to remember from this section on focus structure that focal
NPs can occur in mid-position. In Section 6, we will look in more detail at sentences
Contextual cues for particle placement 

in which this is the case. First, however, we will briefly report on a couple of studies
into how the choice for the joined of the split construction is influenced by previ-
ous occurrences of one of these orderings (Section 4) and discuss the impact of
factors like register and region (Section 5).

4. Previous occurrence of one ordering or the other

It has been known for some time that speakers tend to reuse syntactic patterns that
they have come across (either produced themselves or heard) in the preceding
discourse. This tendency is known as ‘syntactic priming’ or ‘syntactic persistence’
– see Levelt and Kelter (1982), Weiner and Labov (1983), and Bock (1986) for
some early studies. In this short section I confine myself to summing up the find-
ings of two recent studies that discuss syntactic priming in relation with particle
placement: Gries (2005) and Szmrecsanyi (2005).
i. There is a general and strong tendency for speakers to stick to the same word
order choice of the transitive verb-particle construction. That is, if they have en-
countered an instance of the joined construction in the preceding linguistic con-
text, they will tend to repeat this construction when they subsequently utter an-
other instance of the transitive verb-particle construction; likewise if they have
first encountered an instance of the split construction, then this will tend to be
the word order that they will use again for a next use of a transitive phrasal verb.
ii. This persistence effect is somewhat stronger for a prior occurrence of an in-
stance of the split ordering than for a prior occurrence of an instance of the
joined ordering.
iii. In written discourse, there is a stronger persistence effect between instances
involving the same phrasal verb lemma (as in he’d fill all their bags up … he
wouldn’t fill our bags up) than between instances involving different phrasal
verb lemmas.
iv. In dialogues, the second speaker often copies the word order along with the
exact inflectional form and the lemma of the transitive phrasal verb used by
the first speaker.
v. For specific verb-particle combinations with a preference for one word order
manifestation or the other (cf. Section 1.4), there is only a marked persistence
effect for the order they prefer anyhow.
vi. The general priming effect decreases somewhat as the distance between the
two instances increases.
vii. Perhaps related to the previously-mentioned persistence factor, the longer the
sentence in which the new instance occurs, the weaker the persistence effect
from the previous instance on this new instance.
 Bert Cappelle

5. Lectal factors: Register and region

This section looks into the wider context of the sentence in which a transitive
verb-particle combination occurs: not just the preceding sentence(s) in the dis-
course but the entire setting in which the discourse is situated. Are we dealing with
spoken or written discourse? Which regional variety of English does the speaker
use? Which social background does the speaker have? Is the speaker a man or a
woman? Such potential influences on linguistic variation can be grouped under
what Geeraerts (2005) calls ‘lectal’ factors, a cover term for influences related to
the speaker’s dialect, regiolect, sociolect, etc. Below I single out two such factors
that are known to exert some influence on particle placement.

5.1 Written versus spoken discourse

As Gries (2003: 97; 2005: 381) and Cappelle (2006) have shown by means of re-
search into corpora containing both spoken and written material, there is a sig-
nificant preference for the split ordering in spoken discourse and a significant
preference for the joined ordering in written discourse. Table 2 below presents the
data for the British Component of the International Corpus of English (ICE-GB)
given in Cappelle (2006):

Table 2. The two orderings by medium in ICE-GB

Spoken Written

Joined (V – Prt – NP) 731 (± 42%) 543 (± 71%)


Split (V – NP – Prt) 917 (± 58%) 227 (± 29%)
Column totals 1648 (100%) 770 (100%)

According to Bolinger (1971: 57, fn. 8), the split ordering is rather informal (“at
the familiar end of the speech-level or register scale”). Hence, language users may
feel more restrained to select this word order option in written discourse than they
do in spoken discourse. Written language is, after all, much more of an ‘edited’
medium, allowing users to replace an option they might naturally have selected in
spoken discourse by an option that is a little more formal. This inhibition against
using an all too informal construction may also account, still according to Bolinger,
for the fact that the split ordering occurred even more rarely in pre-twentieth cen-
tury literature, which was relatively more censured than current literature.
Other reasons why the split ordering is used less often in written language will
be discussed in Section 9.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

5.2 Regional variation

Szmrecsanyi (2005: 133) observes that there is noticeable variation in ordering


preferences among British English dialects. If the dialect of England’s Southeast is
to be considered as the standard, then one finds the split ordering to be signifi-
cantly disfavored in the Hebrides and, to a lesser extent, in the Midlands, while it
is used more frequently in the North of England than it is elsewhere. This is an
interesting finding, especially since no other researcher (that I know of) has ever
considered the possibility that particle placement is subject to dialectal variation.
It would be worthwhile to investigate whether there are also differences in the
choice of ordering between speakers of more largely-defined varieties of English:
British English, American English, Australian/New-Zealand English, and so on.

Table 3. The two orderings by corpus of regional variety of English (adapted from Lohse
et al. 2004: 243)

British American

LOB corpus Brown corpus Wall Street Switchboard


(written) Journal corpus corpus

Joined 154 (± 65%) 324 (± 79%) 248 (± 86%) 521 (± 69%)


(V – Prt – NP)
Written American
572 (± 82%)

Written + spoken American


1093 (± 76%)
Split 83 (± 35%) 86 (± 21%) 39 (±14%) 229 (± 31%)
(V – NP – Prt)
Written American
125 (± 18%)

Written + spoken American


354 (± 24%)
Column totals 237 (100%) 410 (100%) 86 (100%) 750 (100%)

Written American
697 (100%)

Written + spoken American


1447 (100%)
 Bert Cappelle

There is some indication that there might be. Taking a look at Lohse et al.’s
(2004: 243) table of the distribution of split to joined orderings by corpus (adapted
as Table 3), I notice that their written British English material, taken from the
Lancaster-Oslo/Bergen corpus, contains a higher percentage of split orderings
than their combined material from corpora of American English, more than half
of which even consists of phone conversations (the Switchboard corpus). This dif-
ference between British English and American English in their dataset reaches
statistical significance (χ2(1) = 11.81; p ≤ 0.001).

6. Expectedness

6.1 ‘Context’: A fluid concept of linguistic and extra-linguistic senses

Up to now we have dealt with cues to particle placement provided by the linguistic
context. In this section, I deal with cues to the ordering variation at hand that come
from ‘context’ in a wider sense than we have used so far: not so much the sentence’s
linguistic or deictic embedding, but the entire body of expectations the discourse
participants bring to a discourse situation. These expectations have been shaped by
the domestic, societal and cultural environment in which they have been raised or
adopted. Thus, when I speak of contextual cues to particle placement in this section,
I should be understood as referring to the way the speaker/writer and hearer/reader
draw from their shared ‘knowledge of the world’, or, more precisely, the knowledge
of this kind that the speaker/writer assumes to share with the hearer/reader.
It should be clear, however, that no all too strict distinctions can be made be-
tween linguistic and extra-linguistic context. For example, to assess whether a di-
rect object is discourse-old, it does not suffice to look for a verbatim occurrence of
it in the preceding discourse. Rather, one must look for an item that is coreferential
with the object, or that stands in some sort of taxonomic relation with it. Thus, one
can only establish a coreferentiality relation in the discourse between, say, …En-
nelis… and …the girl… if one knows that Ennelis is a girl’s name, which is an extra-
linguistic piece of knowledge. Similarly, some world knowledge is required to per-
ceive the relation between discourse elements like …pheasant shoots… and …the
birds…, and between …black coffee… and …the taste…:
(23) a. “Mama, I am hungry,” 10-year-old Ennelis is saying as Rose gathers
the girl up in her arms. (www)
b. In the winter he used to have pheasant shoots there. HR’s been at many
of them, driving the birds out. (www)
Contextual cues for particle placement 

c. I only like black coffee when I’ve ground it myself and I’ve chosen the
beans, otherwise you really need milk to take the taste away. (www)

6.2 An example: Putting the kettle on

The following lengthy example will help to make clear what I mean by expectations
based on the discourse-participants’ “domestic, societal and cultural environment”:
(24) The kettle is the one thing we all have in common on these islands. Other
than us lot, hardly anybody else in the world has them. According to the
story I was told at school, it was watching a boiling kettle that gave
Stevenson [sic] the idea of the steam engine. Without the steam engine,
this country would not have been first off the starting block into the in-
dustrial revolution. … The kettle may have evolved over the years since
Stevenson [sic] but every home in the land has one, from Buckingham
Palace to the lowliest of doss houses. … Get invited into any home and the
first thing they will say is “I’ll just put the kettle on.” (www)
The boiling kettle is such a staple fixture in every British household that it needs
no prior introduction in the discourse to be comfortable in mid-position. In the
standard phrase I’ll (just) put the kettle on (or Shall I put the kettle on?), the kettle is
typically discourse-new (in that it is probably not mentioned in the preceding dis-
course), but this lack of discourse-familiarity is amply compensated for by its high
expectedness value, since its presence in a British home is fully taken for granted
nation-wide, as the author of the example above rightly claims.
In fact, it could be argued that discourse-familiarity (discussed in Section 2) is
a special case of expectedness. After all, the mention of an NP (or of a superordi-
nate, subordinate, or meronymical term) creates some expectation as to its reap-
pearance. Put differently and perhaps more accurately, prior mention of an NP
renders its referent mentally more accessible. Familiar items like a kettle in a British
home are mentally accessible without having to be linguistically mentioned or
evoked first, but there is a point in which mental accessibility is the factor that li-
censes the mid-positioning of discourse-familiar and ‘world’-familiar objects alike.
The main reason why I have nevertheless discussed discourse-familiarity in a
separate section is that it is a concept that is far easier to grasp and accordingly to
quantify (even taking into account the complications mentioned above in Sec-
tion 6.1) than the factor ‘expectedness on the basis of world knowledge’. Still, we can
gain a better understanding of world knowledge if we think of it in terms of frame-
semantic knowledge, in Fillmore’s sense. To use our kettle example again, paying a
visit to someone’s home in Britain can be conceived as a complex structure of re-
lated entities and events, among others the owner (or occupier) of the house offering
 Bert Cappelle

the visitor something to drink, usually a nice cuppa. Since the process of making tea
involves the use of a boiling kettle, and perhaps because Britons perceive some
impoliteness in forcing visitors straightaway to confirm that they would like to
drink some tea (as would be the case if the host asked, “Would you like some tea?”),
they offer to put the kettle on. In other words, the host’s suggestion to put the kettle
on is a part of the ‘visiting someone’s home in Britain’ frame.

6.3 Bolinger (1971): Frame semantics avant la lettre

Without being explicitly couched in frame-semantic terms, some observations


made by Bolinger (1971: 55–57) are clearly consonant with such a framework. He
associates the split ordering with “the ordinariness of certain actions and the fa-
miliarity of certain objects”. That is, “[i]f the noun retains the accent but the parti-
cle is put after it, the sensation most often seems to be just that of what is familiar
or usual under the circumstances”. Here is one of his examples:
(25) It’s almost ten o’clock. Put your níghtie on, now, and run up to bed.
(Bolinger 1971: 57)
Here, a nightie, the action of putting it on, and the temporal location at 10 p.m. are
apparently part of the bed-time routine of the hearer.12 A quite similar example is
the following:
(26) Do you want to squeeze some paste on? (father to young child, during a
conversation overheard in the bathroom of a camping in the UK)
Again, the speaker assumes the hearer’s familiarity with the tooth-brushing frame,
in which a toothpaste and a toothbrush are fixed entities, and of squeezing some
of the former on the latter is a fixed action.
Moving beyond this anecdotal evidence, let us consider a simple corpus investi-
gation. I entered the following two search patterns in the British National Corpus:
(27) a. put down [possessive determiner] [noun]
b. put [possessive determiner] [noun] down
The predictions were that instances of the joined ordering, returned by the query
in (27a), would contain fewer nouns whose referent is expected than instances of
the split ordering, returned by the query in (27b). The results of the 50 most fre-
quent results for these two queries are given in 0 and 0, respectively.13 By the way,
the query with the joined ordering yielded (only) 182 matches, compared to 344
matches for the query with the split ordering.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

(28) 1. his glass (15 instances); 2. her cup (12); 3. his knife (8); 4. his cup (5); 5.
her coffee (5); 6. her glass (4); 7. her knife (4); 8. his book (4); 9. his pen
(4); 10. his paper (3); 11. my pen (3); 12. her book (3); 13. her pen (3); 14.
her shopping (2); 15. her trowel (2); 16. her wine (2); 17. her coffee-cup
(2); 18. her basket (2); 19. her cloth (2); 20. his briefcase (2); 21. his coffee-
cup; 22. his spade (2); 23. her fork (2); 24. his newspaper (2); 25. his note-
book (1); 26. his notes (1); 27. his pint (1); 28. his pitchfork (1); 29. his
pocket (1); 30. his scalpel (1); 31. his scone (1); 32. my scythe (1); 33. my
shopping (1); 34. my suit-case (1); 35. their bibles (1); 36. their bowls (1);
37. their clues (1); 38. their deposits (1); 39. their guns (1); 40. their knives
(1); 41. their names (1); 42. their pens (1); 43. their porridge (1); 44. their
stakes (1); 45. your bag (1); 46. your case (1); 47. your drink (1); 48. your
guns (1); 49. your handbags (1); 50. your knives (1)
(29) 1. your foot (26 instances ); 2. your name (15); 3. his foot (15); 4. her head
(14); 5. her foot (14); 6. his head (14); 7. my foot (11); 8. my name (11); 9.
your head (10); 10. my head (9); 11. her cup (9); 12. their foot (8); 13. your
hands (7); 14. your phone (6); 15. his glass (6); 16. her glass (5); 17. his cup
(5); 18. your feet (5); 19. their names (5); 20. your hand (4); 21. your hand-
set (4); 22. their name (3); 23. his hand (3); 24. her bag (3); 25. her name
(3); 26. his name (3); 27. his money (2); 28. his mug (2); 29. his phone (2);
30. his paper (2); 31. his things (2); 32. its head (2); 33. her pen (2); 34. her
basket (2); 35. her feet (2); 36. his goblet (2); 37. her hand (2); 38. my hand
(2); 39. your age (2); 40. your bag (2); 41. your leg (2); 42. your pen (2); 43.
your mallet (1); 44. your papers (1); 45. your plate (1); 46. your things (1);
47. your welly (1). 48. your heel (1); 49. your keys (1); 50. your glass (1)
Even without considering the context of all the corpus hits, a pattern emerges.14
Each of the ten most frequently occurring nouns, apart from name, in the split
pattern refers to a body part of whomever the possessive determiner refers to.
Body parts, like a head, feet, hands, legs, etc. are (for all intents and purposes) in-
alienable possessions and therefore, they are expected entities. That somebody has
a head, for example, is taken for granted. It is an entity that is an inherent part of
the frame invoked by the entity to which the possessive determiner refers. Thus, as
soon as a ‘person’ frame is evoked – this happens, for instance, as soon as the
hearer makes a mental picture of the subject referent in She put her head down –
these body parts are automatically also activated to some degree. The same goes
for the noun name: people (ordinarily) have a name, so this entity is also co-acti-
vated along with the person referred to by the subject and/or possessive deter-
miner. Thus, body parts and more abstract entities like somebody’s name or age
are expected on the basis of the discourse participants’ familiarity with the ‘person’
 Bert Cappelle

frame (which in turn is inevitably evoked by the possessive pronoun and/or a


coreferential NP in the preceding discourse).
Interestingly, the first noun referring to an object not evoked by the ‘person’
frame (the noun cup) only comes in at the 11th position in the ranking for the split
ordering. Conversely, there are no nouns referring to body parts among the fifty
most frequent hits in the joined ordering and the first noun referring to an inalien-
able possession, names, only comes in at the 41st position in the ranking. These re-
sults go some way to supporting Bolinger’s (1971: 55) above-mentioned intuition.

6.4 Not just the expectedness of the object

We should emphasize here that Bolinger (1971) also considers the split ordering to
be eminently suited to suggesting that the verbal action, and not just the direct
object referent, is familiar or expected in a given situation. Sometimes, the latter
more or less naturally implies the former. Thus, to use one of his examples, cattle
entails the action of driving, which partly explains why the use of the split ordering
is acceptable in the response below.
(30) Where’s Joe? — He’s driving the cáttle in. He’ll be along in a minute.
(Bolinger 1971: 56)
Note also that the object NP here can, on the one hand, be discourse-new but may,
on the other hand, not be completely unpredictable to the addressee (assuming
that he or she knows Joe and knows he is a cattle-driver).
Similar cases in which the split ordering can be used despite the object NP
being discourse-new and falling within the focus domain are hanging the {wash-
ing / laundry} out, picking the kids up, dropping the kids off, etc. Not only are the
verbal actions expressed in these phrases notionally closely associated with their
respective objects, but the events in question may also take place regularly (e.g. as
part of a daily or weekly routine) or as a matter of course. The use of the split or-
dering, while by no means obligatory in such cases, may underscore this idea:
(31) Molly finds that she doesn’t need the car with her all the time, as she no
longer has to pick the kids up every day and now she is able to go to her
computer class in the bus. (www)
Ignoring the political correctness issues of the following example, we may invoke
the notion of ordinariness to account for its shift from one ordering to the other
for what is otherwise one and the same phrase (which I have underlined here for
ease of identification; the italics for emphasis are in the original):
Contextual cues for particle placement 

(32) Something happened the other day that made me feel uneasy. Yet I
shouldn’t have felt that way!
My wife had left for work and I was hanging the washing out to dry. A
neighbour from down the way was in his backyard doing the same. ‘Good
day for drying’, he called. ‘Let’s hope the rain stays away.’
I had to think about what made me uneasy. Then it hit me. Two men hang-
ing out the washing!
When I was a kid that would never have happened. That was women’s
work, after all! (www)
The first occurrence of hang out + the washing is meant to sound as unsuspicious
as possible, which may explain the use of the split ordering. On its second occur-
rence, hang out + the washing is used in the joined ordering, even though the di-
rect object is discourse-old (and might therefore have been put in mid-position).
In this second instance, the author wants to draw the attention to the extra-ordi-
nariness of the situation. One likely reason why he uses the joined ordering here is
that it permits him to put an accent on the particle, thus marking almost each
word with a separate accent (Twó mén hánging óut the wáshing!) rather than giving
hanging out + the washing one overarching accent (on washing). This way, form
and (pragmatic) content match up nicely.
Needless to say, the examples given in this section are merely suggestive. The
precise role played by the frame-semantic expectedness of the verbal action (given
the object) and/or the ordinariness of the entire event (as a Gestalt made up by the
verbal action and the object) in particle placement is something that needs to be
investigated in much more detail.

7 Stativity as a contextual factor?

A little-mentioned semantic constraint on the particle placement alternation (but


see Fraser 1976: 11; Huddleston 2002: 286, fn. 49; Cappelle 2005: 220) has to do
with the aspectual nature of the verb: dynamic verbs allow a spatial particle to
precede as well as follow the object NP, while stative verbs only allow a spatial
particle to follow the object NP. Compare, for example:
(33) a. He put {on his socks / his socks on}.
b. He kept {?on his socks / his socks on}.
(34) a. I pulled {up the blinds / the blinds up}.
b. I left {*up the blinds / the blinds up}.
 Bert Cappelle

In what way is this constraint relevant to our discussion on the role of context on
particle placement? To answer this question, let us consider some examples with
prima facie stative verbs that do allow the particle to precede the object:
(35) a. The nail holds up the picture.
b. The bricks keep down the sheet.
c. The load weighs down the car.
(McIntyre 2003)
Just because there is no overt motion involved in these examples, this does not
mean that they describe stative events. On the contrary, on the basis of encyclope-
dic knowledge, especially the laws of mechanics, we know that holding up a pic-
ture requires a sustained impediment to the force of gravity. Similarly, keeping
down a sheet which tends to be blown upwards requires the constant counteract-
ing input of a downward-pushing force, by releasing the brick’s potential energy.
And weighing down a car involves the sustained application of the load’s weight to
work against the spring force of the car’s suspension system. So, while the above
clauses depict steady situations, they also involve energy to maintain that steadi-
ness. What is important to our concerns is that it is the context in which the verb
is used which may reveal this ‘hidden’ dynamic aspect, and that the particle is part
of that context. Thus, while keeping one’s socks on does not require energy – rath-
er, energy is required to take them off – keeping them up may prove to be dy-
namic, in the way described above:
(36) …a pair of those old fashioned garters that men wore to keep up their
socks… (www)
In short, the requirement that the verb not be stative for the two orderings to be
allowed is context-dependent: the verb taken by itself does not tell us whether this
requirement is met; we need to consider the context in which the verb is used.

8 Literalness as a contextual factor?

As is well known, verb-particle combinations differ in the degree to which their com-
ponent parts independently contribute to the meaning of the composite whole, some
combinations being completely transparent (e.g. kick the ball out), others being quite
opaque (e.g. chew out someone ‘reprimand someone for doing something wrong’).
According to Cowie and Mackin (1993: ix), “[t]he fact that a particular combination
of verb + particle is idiomatic need not affect its grammar”, by which they mean that
both transparent and idiomatic combinations in principle allow the two orderings.
Yet, it has been shown on the basis of corpus research that the degree of idiomaticity
Contextual cues for particle placement 

does have an impact on word order preferences, in that combinations with a seman-
tically dependent particle significantly favor the joined ordering (e.g. Gries 2003: 87;
Lohse et al. 2004), a preference that is already manifest in early child language (Dies-
sel and Tomasello 2005) and that has also been supported by means of psycholin-
guistic experiments (Dehé 2002: 97; Gonnerman and Hayes 2005).
Gries (2003: 87) and Szmrecsanyi (2005: 132) also note a significant increase
in the choice of the split ordering with literal particles, although Lohse et al. (2004)
maintain that this increase does not, in their data set, amount to an actual prefer-
ence for the split ordering with literal particles – there is just a higher proportion of
split orderings. According to Gries (2003: 52), a characteristic of the split ordering
is that “the particle is positioned in the canonical position for focal elements, i.e.
clause-finally, so that the particle is processed more intensively than the direct
object.” Hence, the split ordering “naturally underscores the spatial contribution
the particle makes to the meaning of the utterance and would, therefore, be the
natural choice for a speaker who intends to communicate a state of affairs where
the spatial meaning is prominent” (Gries 2003: 52–53). In this account, the end-
placement of literal particles is linked up with focus structure, which would entail
that literalness is ultimately also a context-related factor.
In fact, however, of all literal particles that appear in end-position, the ones
that form the clause focus all by themselves probably make up a small minority.
Recall that a particle may be in end-position when it is not the only element under
focus, as in (37a-c), and even when it is not at all part of the focus, as in (38a-b).
(37) a. What happened? — I threw my radio away.
b. What did you do? — I threw my radio away.
c. What did you do with that old radio? — I threw the damn thing away.
(38) a. Did you give that old radio away? — No, I gave my computer away.
b. Did you give that old radio away? — No, I threw the damn thing away.
The reason why there is a higher proportion of split orderings with particles that
can be independently processed than with other particles has less to do with the
possibility of independent particles to have end-focus – which they can but do not
often have – than with a higher processing cost of the split ordering with depend-
ent particles, compared to the joined ordering with such particles. As Lohse et al.
(2004: 246­–247) explain, if a particle depends on the verb for its interpretation,
then processing benefits from putting that particle in close proximity to the verb.
This way, its “lexical dependency domain” is minimized. This is actually also
recognized by Gries (2003), who writes that
it would be uneconomical to process the opaque meaning of a [transitive phrasal
verb] but produce the parts that trigger this opaque meaning in possibly widely
 Bert Cappelle

disparate positions of the sentence. With literal phrasal verbs, by contrast, no


preference for a construction is to be expected on grounds of semantic dependency
because the low degree of interdependence does not require a particularly small
distance between the component parts and, thus, licenses both word orders.
(Gries 2003: 54)

As regards the question in the title of the present section, we have to conclude that
the influence of literalness on particle placement cannot plausibly be formulated
as a contextual, in the sense of focus-structural, factor. End-placed particles do not
ordinarily convey the most prominent information in a given context.

9 Motivating the contextual factors of particle placement

The above sections have made it clear that there is no one single context-related
factor that governs particle placement in English. At the same time, Gries (2003)
maintains that all factors that have ever been proposed (including those not in-
volving context) can be subsumed under a single motivating principle, related to
the processing cost of the object NP. His ‘processing hypothesis’ boils down to this:
the harder the object NP is to process, the more it tends to follow the particle; the
easier it is to process, the more likely it is to precede the particle. This hypothesis
can be expressed even more succinctly in the words of Bever (1970): “Save the
hardest for last”. In this section, I want to examine whether Gries’s processing hy-
pothesis is viable: can it account for all of the factors we have dealt with?

9.1 Re discourse-familiarity

The ratio of split to joined orderings is higher for discourse-old object NPs than
for discourse-new ones. This fact is straightforwardly related to processing issues.
For discourse-old NPs, both the speaker and the hearer already have a conceptual
representation with a high degree of mental activation (Gries 2003: 166). This
makes these NP’s easily accessible and useful anchor points for information units
that have not had any prior mention in the discourse. Proceeding from the famil-
iar to the unfamiliar does not only facilitate comprehension. By postponing a dis-
course-new constituent, speakers also buy themselves some time to think about
such matters as how they will refer to the newly introduced discourse entity; which
potentially complex structure they may have to retrieve from the grammar in or-
der to express all the information needed to help the hearer identify the referent;
how the lexical concepts have to be integrated into this grammatical structure, and
so on (Arnold et al. 2004: 33). Somewhat surprisingly, though, Gries (2003: 130,
note 33) and Lohse et al. (2004: 258) point out that factors relating to processing
Contextual cues for particle placement 

facilitation exert a stronger influence in writing than in speech (cf. also Section 9.4
below). Given that speed of planning and production plays a relatively small role
in written discourse, it seems, then, that the postponement of discourse-new NPs
predominantly targets comprehension rather than production facilitation.

9.2 Re focus structure

Gries (2003) seems to have conflicting ideas on whether focused items have a high
or a low amount of processing cost. On the one hand, Gries argues that “focused
elements require more processing effort” (p. 52) because the hearer’s brain has to
allocate more attention to elements that are marked as important, thus increasing
their processing cost. Insofar as focal elements appear clause-finally, there is sup-
port for his processing hypothesis. On the other hand, Gries agrees with claims in
the literature that focal elements have high activation in the mind of the speaker
(p. 172), which means that they are easily accessible and thus, from the perspective
of the speaker at least, require low processing effort. This, he admits, is then hard
to reconcile with the tendency to put focal material at the end.
His solution is to argue that speakers do not only select the joined or the split
construction on the basis of whether the particle or the object, respectively, hap-
pens to have the highest degree of mental activation – for example, if it is the ob-
ject, it is inserted in the syntax first, resulting in the generation of a split construc-
tion – but also on the basis of the intended communicative intention. If an element
is to be highlighted, the speaker will choose a constructional pattern that accords
a prominent position to this element, which in English is usually at the end.
Speakers thereby conform to the general Focus-Last principle, by which hearers
look for the most informative element at the end of clauses, after they have been
given all the background information required for its successful processing.
We have seen that focal elements do not always occur in sentence-final position:
any constituent in the clause, irrespective of its syntactic position, can contain the
nuclear accent. We have also just noted, in Section 9.1, that written texts seem to at-
tend to the needs of the reader more than spoken discourse does to the needs of the
hearer, when it comes to the choice of word orderings that facilitate processing. We
now have a possible explanation for why this may be so. In writing, the unavailabil-
ity of prosodic cues to the contrary may force writers to stick to the general Focus-
Last principle. Conversely, in speech, temporal constraints on planning may force
speakers to select the ordering that allows them to insert the most active item (the
one under semantic focus) as early as possible, even if this results in the selection of
a structure that deviates from the general Focus-Last principle. During the actual
phonological production stage, they may then overlay the syntactic structure with a
‘correcting’ pitch pattern. It goes without saying that these are mere hypotheses.
 Bert Cappelle

9.3 Re previous occurrence of one ordering or the other

The occurrence of a construction raises its mental activation level, making it more
likely to be selected again when the speaker is put before the choice of alternative
orderings. It is not clear, however, how the higher accessibility of either the split
ordering or the joined ordering as a whole ties in with Gries’s (2003) processing
hypothesis, which is stated in terms of the processing cost of the direct object
(relative to that of the particle) only.

9.4 Re register

The ratio of split to joined orderings is higher in speech than in writing. Gries
(2003: 100–101) notes that this should not surprise us, since speech is character-
ized by a higher occurrence of short object NPs and of literal verb-particle combi-
nations, which he shows to strongly favor the split ordering. However, the higher
occurrence of split orderings in spoken discourse cannot just be written off as a
simple side-effect of the well-established influence of lightness of the object and
literalness of the phrasal verb.
For one, although Lohse et al. (2004: 258) equally observe that the average
length of direct objects is shorter in speech than in writing, they find “no signifi-
cant difference in the distribution of dependent and independent particles”, so an
explanation for the higher ratio of split orderings in speech should not be sought
(in part) in the brute effect of a higher ratio of literal combinations in speech.
For another, Lohse et al. (2004: 258) note that as the length of NPs increases,
the ratio of split orderings decreases much more steeply in writing than in speech.
So, if there are more instances of the joined ordering in writing than in speech, this
is not only because there is a higher ratio of long objects in writing compared to
speech, but also because, for a same number of long objects, the effect of these long
objects on placement is more clearly noticeable in writing than in speech. Gries
(2003: 130, note 33) also observes that in writing, the decline of split orderings is
steeper for discourse-new NPs. These observations point to a finer attunement to
the needs of the parser in written discourse (cf. Section 9.1 above).
Lohse et al. (2004: 258) furthermore find that in written discourse, the ten-
dency to use the split ordering with literal particles is lower than in spoken dis-
course. (Again, it is not that writing is characterized by a lower occurrence of lit-
eral particles, as Gries (2003) reports. Instead, what they find is that, for any given
number of literal particles, the split ordering is selected for them with a lower fre-
quency in writing than in speech.) As we noted in Section 5.1, this may have to do
with the connotative value attached to the split ordering, whose perceived famili-
arity may lead to its avoidance in written texts.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

9.5 Re region

Clearly, regional variation in particle placement cannot be construed as a manifes-


tation of Gries’s (2003) processing hypothesis. It would be nonsensical to claim
that speakers of British English, when using transitive phrasal verbs, tend to use
object NPs with a lower degree of processing cost, which then accounts for their
higher use of the split ordering compared to speakers of American English. One
can only explain regional variation in terms of a higher entrenchment of the con-
struction most frequently used in a particular regional variety of English and/or in
terms of differences among regional varieties in the weights attached to certain
factors for particle placement whose values may sometimes be in conflict. Con-
sider, for example, the following question-answer pair:
(39) If you could jump in a time machine and relive a certain moment of your
life, which would it be? — I wouldn’t. I’d blow the damn thing up. (www)
The object NP the damn thing refers back to a time machine mentioned in the
question. Its status as a discourse-old entity plays a role in the use of the split or-
dering, which conforms to the principle by which discourse-familiar entities are
given as early as possible to facilitate processing. On the other hand, the object is a
three word long NP, and in general, objects of this length are more frequently put
in the joined ordering (since long NPs are hard to process and may therefore be
saved for last). So, there are at least two relevant processing-facilitating principles
that lead to opposing word order choices.
It may be plausible to assume that whenever two or more processing con-
straints are in conflict, speakers tend to select the constructional option which
incurs the least serious violation(s), where seriousness is determined with refer-
ence to a constraint hierarchy, as in Optimality Theory (Prince and Smolensky
2004 [1993]), or with respect to weights attached to the constraints, allowing for
higher predictability, as in probabilistic grammar.15 Suppose, now, for the sake
of the argument, that there are only two constraints to be considered: OldObj-
Left (i.e. discourse-old objects come first) and Heavy-Right (i.e. weighty ob-
jects come last).16 In the above example, putting a three-word-long object in mid-
position is felt to come at a much lower cost than putting a discourse-old object
after the particle. This is, in any case, how by far most speakers of British English
appear to rank the two constraints, based on a series of Google searches I did
on 5 September 2006. Using Google’s Language Tools function,17 I entered the
strings “up the stupid thing”, “up the damn thing” and “up the bloody thing”, as
well as “the stupid thing up”, “the damn thing up” and “the bloody thing up”, each
time selecting ‘Great Britain’ as the country in which the search pages were to be
located. I then performed the same searches, but with ‘United States’ selected as
 Bert Cappelle

Table 4. The two orderings by country for some selected Google search strings

Search pages in Search pages in the


Great Britain United States

Joined: 14 (± 9%) 298 (± 23%)


‘verb up the {stupid / damn / bloody} thing’
Split: 149 (± 91%) 974 (± 77%)
‘verb the {stupid / damn / bloody} thing up’
Column totals 163 (100%) 1272 (100%)

country. After that went manually through all the hit pages to cull out noise exam-
ples. The results are given in Table 4. The difference in ratios of split to joined or-
derings for the two selected countries is significant (χ2(1) = 18.70; p ≤ 0.001).
So, speakers of British English clearly let the OldObj-Left constraint prevail
on most usage occasions.18 For speakers of American English, the situation is less
clear. While most of them also appear to find that the selection of the split ordering
is preferred in cases with discourse-old objects of word-length three, a sizeable pro-
portion of them come up with the other ordering, which means that in American
English, some less weight is attached to the constraint that discourse-old objects
should be put early compared to British English and, by the same token, some more
weight is attached to putting long objects late in the clause, while the actual ranking
of these constraints with respect to each other is the same as in British English.
There is probably some interaction between the severity of a constraint violation
and the entrenchment of a construction. Thus, in Britain, where a violation of the
OldObj-Left is seen as comparably more serious than in the US, we may expect the
split ordering to be more entrenched than in the US. This deeper entrenchment may
in turn have an impact on the weights attached to the ordering constraints.

9.6 Re frame-semantic expectedness

The ratio of split to joined orderings is higher for frame-semantically expected


objects than for objects that do not form part of a particular frame evoked in the
discourse. This seems to be quite naturally related to the assumption that all the
elements belonging to an activated frame are themselves also activated to a higher
degree than other elements. Since this higher activation of a frame-expected ob-
ject (like a boiling kettle for making tea in the ‘visiting someone in Britain’ frame)
also renders it less hard to process, its typical mid-position is predicted under
Gries’s (2003) processing hypothesis.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

However, Gries’s (2003) processing hypothesis, which is stated in terms of the


processing cost of the direct object only, makes no prediction as to the choice of
word order for frame-semantically expected actions (as expressed by the verb-
particle combination). On the basis of the general processing constraint to put
familiar elements, including familiar actions, as early in the sentence as possible,
we would expect a preference of the joined ordering, with verb and particle pre-
ceding the rest of the VP. But this is not what the examples given in Section 6.4
tentatively suggest. The more felicitous option for the split ordering in these cases
may be made under the impulse of avoiding unneeded accents in the clause – re-
call our discussion of hanging the wáshing out vs. hánging óut the wáshing. If the
particle is put in end-position, it need not receive an accent in addition to the ac-
cent on the object. This leads to what Bolinger (1971: 56), perhaps somewhat im-
pressionistically, calls “the suffusion of the sentence as a whole with a kind of re-
laxed rhetorical effect”.

9.7 Re stativity

The split ordering is ordinarily selected for literal verb-particle combinations


whose verb receives, in the context concerned, a stative interpretation:
(40) a. It is hard to leave {out all this stuff / all this stuff out}. (suggests that an
urge to put the stuff in, or even the projected tendency of the stuff it-
self to be included, has to be overcome by force of will)
b. This morning, I just left {*down all the blinds / all the blinds down}.
(no force needed)
This constraint cannot be linked in any sensible way with Gries’s (2003) processing
hypothesis. What motivates this factor, rather, is probably the fact that the split
ordering underscores the family resemblance with a number of semantically re-
lated non-motional constructions, instantiated by, e.g., judge {*out the ball / the
ball out} and picture {*off all the lights / all the lights off}. The possibility of putting
the verb and the particle in adjacent positions is contingent on their semantic to-
getherness. Note in this respect that verbs and particles which resist being put in
adjacent positions cannot be replaced by a simplex verb. Compare:
(41) a. It is hard to {leave out / omit / exclude} all this stuff.
b. This morning, I just left all the blinds down. (no simplex verb available)
c. The umpire judged the ball out. (idem)
d. Can you picture all the lights off? (idem)
In the end, therefore, the stativity constraint may be (negatively) motivated by one
of the most basic word order principles, known as Behaghel’s (1932) “First Law”:
 Bert Cappelle

Das oberste Gesetz ist dieses, daß das geistig eng Zusammengehörige auch eng
zusammengestellt wird.
(Behaghel 1932: 4)
‘The supreme law is this: that which belongs closely together mentally is also
placed closely together’.

9.8 Summary of Section 9

While this paper has essentially been aimed at getting a sharper picture of what
kinds of contextual factors may influence the selection of one particle placement
option rather than the other, it has now become clear that these factors can ulti-
mately be motivated by the way in which they contribute to ease of processing
(i.e. production/comprehension), though not exactly in the way intended by Gries
(2003). More specifically, the processing ease of one or the other word order vari-
ant depends on such context-related parameters as:
i. the early positioning in the variant of an element which has heightened men-
tal accessibility as a result of its previous mention and, thus, which has the
potential of serving as a ‘stepping stone’, especially for the addressee, to reach
constructional elements with lower mental accessibility;
ii. the variant’s conformance, in the absence of ‘corrective’ intonation, to the
standard – and therefore processing-facilitating – Focus-Last principle, which
directs the addressee’s attention to the position in the sentence where he or she
expects to find the most important information, namely at or towards the end;
iii. the variant’s degree of mental accessibility as a result of activation through
previous use;
iv. in writing: the degree to which the variant reflects the extra requirement posed
by written discourse (as a medium that is more controlled and edited than
spoken discourse), namely that the writer should further enhance compre-
hension, e.g. by putting long objects towards the end and by not splitting up
idiomatic verb-particle combinations;
v. the variant’s degree of mental accessibility as a result of being the most en-
trenched ordering option in a regional variety, and/or whether or not it is the
ordering option in a given usage situation with the least severe constraint vio-
lations as evaluated by variety-specific rankings;
vi. the early positioning in the variant of a frame-semantically expected (hence
accessible) element and its absence of uncalled-for accents (which are costly to
produce, and, for the hearer, to give heed to).
vii. the separation of elements in the variant that could wrongfully be interpreted
as conceptual units if they were not separated.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

10 Towards modeling the contextual factors of particle placement

We have seen how the multiple context-related factors that play a role in the particle
placement alternation find their motivation in processing efficiency. The question,
first of all, is whether we ought to give a place at all to these processing-facilitating
factors in a grammar of English. Can’t they just be dismissed as a matter of per-
formance/parole? After all, isn’t what matters to a grammarian just to know which
word strings are grammatical rather than to know which ones are easy to process?
This narrow view of what counts as grammar proper seems to underlie a statement
like the following: “Given two equally grammatical outputs, a speaker is free to use
other, non-grammatical, criteria to decide which of them to use” (Svenonius
1996: 54). However, constructionist frameworks, like Construction Grammar, do
not a priori regard pragmatic, discourse-functional or even socio-linguistic consid-
erations in the choice of a constructional variant as falling outside the realm of
grammar. While the main achievement of Construction Grammar so far has been
to link up lexicon and semantics more closely with syntax (which is then no longer
considered to be an autonomous component of grammar), there is no denying that
this framework is now also taking an active part in a general trend within contem-
porary linguistic approaches towards what Geeraerts (2006) calls the “recontextu-
alization” of grammar, that is, towards reintegrating into grammar various forms of
context that had been severed from it during the Chomskyan revolution: “the social
context”, “the situational context of actual language use” and “the cognitive context
of meaning and experience”. In this paper, we have considered a variety of elements
which relate to these aspects of contexts and which provide information to the lan-
guage user (in other words, which serve as contextual ‘cues’) as to which ordering
option a speaker should select when using a transitive phrasal verb.19 These kinds
of information are drawn upon by language users – they know what to do with
these cues – and they should therefore be captured in a grammar that aspires at
reflecting all the knowledge speakers have about the language they use.
The next, and much less trivial, question is how we can incorporate these con-
text-based cues in a constructionist model. I can only offer some very sketchy
suggestions at this stage, pointing out some possible avenues for future endeavors.
A fruitful way to start looking at grammatical variation from a constructional
perspective is to look at the options as ‘allostructions’ (Cappelle 2006), that is, as
formally distinct realizations of a more abstract construction that remains under-
specified for one or more particular features – in our case, the exact placement of
the particle vis-à-vis the direct object and the internal constituency of the VP
(cf. Farrell 2005). This is visualized in Figure 1 for transitive blow up. It will be
observed (i) that the semantics of the two allostructions exactly matches that of
the more abstract construction, (ii) that the lexical leaves in the syntactic trees are
 Bert Cappelle

linked up with the lexically specified verb and particle in the otherwise more un-
specified syntactic representation in the upper construction, and (iii) that the NP
in each of the allostructions corresponds with the patient argument in the seman-
tic representation. Boldface in the semantic representation means that the seman-
tic roles involved must be realized syntactically. Of course, the agent role is syntac-
tically expressed as a subject argument, in keeping with standard linking rules.
We then have to ensure that the most appropriate ordering is chosen under cer-
tain contextual conditions. How are we to appeal to context-related processing con-
straints in a framework where one of the main tenets is that “[t]he totality of our
knowledge of language is captured by a network of constructions: a ‘construct-i-con’”
(Goldberg 2003: 219). That is, if a constructionist framework embraces “the idea that
the network of constructions captures our knowledge of language in toto – in other
words, it’s constructions all the way down” (Goldberg 2003: 223), does this mean that
general processing-facilitating constraints should also be described as constructions?

Constraints as constructions
transitive blow up

Sem CAUSE-BECOME < agt, pat, destroyed in an explosion >

Syn [VP [V blow] [Prt up]]transitive

Joined blow up Split blow up

Sem Idem Sem Idem

Syn VP Syn VP

V NP V NP PrtP

V Prt blow Prt

blow up up

Figure 1. The two allostructions (joined and split) of transitive blow up


Contextual cues for particle placement 

Some tentative proposals along these lines have been made by Stefanowitsch and
Gries (2002) with respect to the Given-before-New principle. Instead of treating
this as a universally valid principle – which it isn’t – with extra-grammatical status,
they suggest a number of constructional treatments, one of which is to give ‘Given-
X-New-Y’ (GXNY for short) the status of a general information-structure con-
struction within the grammar. A consequence of such an approach is that the ac-
ceptability of an allostruction in a given usage context is not evaluated in terms of
the number of constraints it does or does not violate but, rather, in terms of the
number of general constructions it does or does not inherit. In essence, constraint-
violation and construction-inheritance boil down to the same thing; they seem to
me to be alternative ways of looking at a single phenomenon. Choosing between
two constructional alternatives may then be described as an evaluation of the se-
verity of each alternative’s failing to inherit one or more general constructions.
This severity is partly determined by these constructions’ relative positions in a
ranking, more or less in the way of Optimality Theory, but also partly by their ab-
solute positions in that ranking (i.e. by their weights).
As a highly simplified example, consider again the variety-related difference in
distribution of ‘verb up the damn thing’ and ‘verb the damn thing up’. Recall that we
hypothesized that American English and British English do not differ with regard
to the relative ranking of the OldObj-Left constraint and the Heavy-Right con-
straint, but do so with regard to the degree to which the former constraint is felt to
be more important than the latter (cf. Section 9.5). This means that we should
represent the rank-ordered constraints (whether or not we construe them as con-
structions) as interval values and not just as ordinal values. Figure 2 shows, very
schematically, the relative positioning of these two constraints in British English
on a scale of importance. The further to the left a constraint is positioned, the less
easily it can be violated. Of course, other constraints on particle placement should
also be located somewhere on this scale, but I disregard them here for practical
purposes. (Some of these other constraints in fact have to be located even further
to the left than OldObj-Left.)20

Oldobj-left Heavy-Right

Very Not very


important important

Figure 2. Two rank-ordered constraints on particle placement in British English


 Bert Cappelle

This figure abstracts away from differences that may exist among regional dialects
within British English, as well as from possible differences among individual
speakers. Also not represented in this figure (but see Figure 4 below) is the fact
that OldObj-Left is a special instance of Given-X-new-Y and that Heavy-
Right may be further motivated by Hawkins’s (1994) ‘early immediate constitu-
ents principle’ (EIC), by which a heavy NP in end-position does not compromise
quick identification of all the immediate constituents of a VP as it would if it were
in mid-position (since then, the hearer would have to wait to add the particle to
the list of immediate constituents until he or she had heard the NP in its entirety).
Compare Figure 2 now with Figure 3, where the location of these two constraints
on an importance hierarchy is shown for American English. Observe that the
ranking order is maintained but that the difference in importance is smaller.

Oldobj-left Heavy-Right

Very Not very


important important

Figure 3. Two rank-ordered constraints on particle placement in American English

Such a partial constraint hierarchy can now be fused with the transitive blow up
construction so as to enable evaluation of constructs like blow up the damn thing
versus blow the damn thing up, where in each case the damn thing is a discourse-old
object NP consisting of three words. A proposal on how this might be done is shown
in Figure 4. On the right of this figure, we recognize a schematic rendering of the
constellation more fully represented in Figure 1 above. While I have left out the se-
mantic and syntactic particulars, I have added a piece of information, namely that,
out of context, the joined ordering should be selected more readily than the split
ordering, due to the semantic dependency of the particle and the verb. This relative
ranking of the joined and the split ordering is therefore represented as an instance
of Lohse et al.’s (2004) ‘lexical dependency domain (LDD)’ minimization principle.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

Given-X-new-Y EIC Minimize LDD

transitive
blow up

joined split
Oldobj-left Heavy-Right blow up blow up

» » »

Very Not very


important important

… [NP]i… { blow up [the damn thing]i / blow [the damn thing]iup }

Figure 4. Simplified evaluation of the joined vs. split ordering for the transitive phrasal
verb blow up, used with a 3-word discourse-old object in British English

On the same hierarchical scale we can also find again the OldObj-Left constraint
and the Heavy-Right constraint, among quite a few others that have been left out
for the sake of visual clarity. Their respective motivating principles are represented
as well (cf. the discussion below Figure 2). The distance between these two con-
straints iconically reflects the degree to which (I hypothesize) they are felt to differ
in absolute, rather than just relative, importance by speakers of British English
(cf. Figure 2). Remember that this difference can be smaller or greater for speakers
of other regional varieties. We now have four constraints/constructions placed on
a single interval scale. This will suffice to illustrate how speakers may go about
weighing up the two word order possibilities available with blow up when using
this phrasal verb with a relatively long object referring back to a discourse-old
entity. (The discourse-old status of the object NP is represented by means of a
subscripted index, indicating its coreferentiality with an NP in the preceding con-
text.) As far as the joined ordering is concerned, the speaker obeys the Heavy-
Right constraint and avoids the disjunction of the semantically dependent com-
ponents of the phrasal verb. However, its merits are outweighed by the advantage
of the split ordering. This ordering admittedly disintegrates the idiomatic unit of
verb and particle but complies with the important constraint of putting
 Bert Cappelle

discourse-old objects as far as possible to the left. Accordingly, the split ordering
will be opted for. In our representation, it deserves the pointing finger symbol,
which is also used by practitioners of Optimality Theory to indicate the best can-
didate of any number of competing options. The joined ordering does not receive
an asterisk for ungrammaticality, since it can be used, but its selection is predicted
to be far less likely.
In American English, the joined ordering is also the dispreferred option, but it
reaches higher frequency than in British English. I have assumed, mainly for argu-
mentative reasons, that this higher frequency is a result of the smaller difference in
importance between OldObj-Left and Heavy-Right in American English. I
should emphasize here that I do not feel strongly about this assumption and that it
needs to be tested empirically by taking other factors into account. For example, it
might just as well be the case that, compared to British English, more importance
is attached in American English to the Minimize LDD constraint, leading to high-
er observance of the adjacency of the components of an idiomatic phrasal verb.
Other issues that should be addressed in future research are the following:
i. Are general principles like GXNY and EIC also ranked relative to each other,
or is it just their construction-specific instantiations (in our case: OldObj-
Left and Heavy-Right) that are rank-ordered in each specific construc-
tion?
ii. Is what is shown in Figure 4 (minus the allostructs at the bottom) the result of
a fusion of the transitive blow up construction with a more general, higher-
ordered transitive V-Prt construction, or is it the actual representation of a
construction that speakers can directly retrieve from their mental grammar?
That is, does each lexically specified V-Prt construction contain only informa-
tion that is unique to that very combination (such as the weights of each of its
allostructions), or does it also contain information that is common to other
lexically specific constructions (cf. the “impoverished-entry” vs. “full-entry”
debate; see Goldberg [1995: 74])?
iii. Supposing that there is a more general constructional schema for transitive
V-Prt combinations, how does that schema represent the relative importance
of its two allostructions, given that this is different for individual V-Prt com-
binations? Does it set limits on how far apart these allostructions and on how
heavy the weight of each of the two allostructions can be? Or does it contain
default settings, which average out the strengths of all of the individual lexical-
ized V-Prt combinations?
iv. Given that a constraint like Heavy-Right becomes more important as the
object becomes longer and/or more complex, don’t we have to distinguish dif-
ferent heaviness subconstraints on the importance scale, each of them apply-
ing to an object of a certain length/complexity?
Contextual cues for particle placement 

However these issues may be resolved, though, the general evaluation mechanism
as modeled here would remain largely unaltered. While I have outlined it in neces-
sarily broad and suggestive strokes, the main virtues of the proposed model should
be clear. It provides a unified treatment of constructions and constraints, and of
various sorts of parameters involved in grammatical variation: lexical preferences,
structural factors, as well as contextual cues for making a grammatical choice.

Notes

1 This is not to say, of course, that there cannot be any acoustical variation in spoken dis-
course with respect to the height of pitch or amplitude a speaker wants to assign to an accented
pronoun, but this is irrelevant to what is said in the text, viz. that it is generally clear whether or
not a pronominal object receives an accent. So, accent (yes / no) is an abstraction of acoustic
reality (since an accented pronoun can be accented to various degrees of strength), but not a
distortion of it (since however strongly or lightly an accented pronoun is accented in a given
context, it is clearly different from a non-accented pronoun in that context). That there is a clear
difference between accented and unaccented object pronouns also appears from the fact that
some object pronouns have two spellings, one of which can only be used if it is unaccented: you
vs. ya/ye, her vs. ’er (e.g. Fill ’er up!), them vs. ’em. Compare:
(i) a. It was {you/her/them} who did it.
b. *It was {ya/ye/’er/’em} who did it.
2 In his monograph on particle placement, Gries (2003: 83–85) obtained quite analogous
results for different corpus data. Gries also considered length in terms of number of syllables,
not just in terms of words. Both operationalizations of the factor ‘length’ proved relevant, though
length measured in number of syllables appeared to be a slightly better predictor for particle
placement (Gries 2003: 110).
3 See also Gries (2003: 14–15) for some complementary references and for brief discussion of
the literature.
4 Except perhaps for some slight centralization, the pronoun it cannot be further reduced.
However, this pronoun is in its present appearance already a reduction from the original form
hit. An aspirated onset to the pronoun it can in fact still be heard in some isolated British and
American dialects (cf. AHD 2000: ‘Our living language’ note in the entry of it).
5 Besides, unaccented pronouns (me, you, him, her, …) are not shorter or simpler than many
particles (up, in, out, off, …), so the light-before-heavy tendency (cf. Behaghel’s law of increasing
elements) cannot by itself account for the obligatory position of an unaccented pronoun on the
left of the particle. Farrell’s (2005) cliticization/affixation analysis provides just such an addi-
tional explanation.
6 Admittedly, particles do get sentence-final accentuation in intransitive constructions (com-
pare, e.g., Please come in! vs. *Please come in!), despite their status as closed-class items.
7 It is not clear whether the split ordering is chosen in (17) because this ordering allows a part
of the focus domain (namely, the particle) to appear in the canonical position for focal elements
(cf. Gries 2003: 24–25, who refers to Halliday 1985: 185), or because this ordering simply allows
 Bert Cappelle

a discourse-old constituent (namely, the object NP) to stay in non-final position (cf. Section 2). I
see no way of finding out whether the first reason is an independent aspect of the explanation,
since I cannot think of an example in which the object NP is backgrounded (i.e. not a part of the
focus domain) without also being discourse-old. (But note that, conversely, discourse-old con-
stituents need not be backgrounded; cf. Section 3.1.) Of course, the focality of the particle and the
discourse-oldness of the object NP may be independent factors reinforcing each other in (17).
8 However, it is possible to use the joined ordering if the object NP is not actually back-
grounded but nonetheless considered to be less important information than the action expressed
by the verb-particle combination. In that case, the nuclear accent is placed on the particle
(cf. Bolinger 1971: 54). For example, consider the parenthetical clause in the sentence below:
(i) When you figure out which city you’re in, click on the Globulator icon (who thinks up
these names?) and then click on the world map to select the correct city. (BNC)
9 Note that there are no adjacently accented syllables if the inflected verb ends in an un-
stressed syllable, as in He lifted up the book.
10 I would not go so far as to claim, though, that the object NP and the particle form a true
‘small clause’ here, as they do in (i) below:
(i) [SC The red and amber lights off] is a necessary starting situation for turning the green
light on.
See Farrell (2005) for an extensive critique against the proposal, often made in the generative
literature, that the object and the particle in a case like turn the green light on also form such a
small clause.
11 We also find examples like the following, where the joined ordering is used:
(i) When he was ready to project a transparency, he turned off the lights before turning
on the projector and ended up tripping over some electrical cords in the dark.
(www)
It could be argued that in this example, the foci are not off vs. on (and the lights vs. the projector)
but rather, the full verb-particle combinations turn on vs. turn off (and their respective objects).
Some evidence that the verb is also focused on is provided by the impossibility to omit it in a
conjunction reduction construction. Naturally, a speaker would never omit an element that is
focused. Compare:
(ii) a. He turned off the lights and turned on the projector.
b. *He turned off the lights and Ø on the projector.
By contrast, if only the particle and the object NP are focused, the verb itself can be omitted:
(iii) a. He turned the lights off and turned the projector on.
b. He turned the lights off and Ø the projector on.
12 This example also shows that the knowledge of a frame need not be shared by all members
of a large linguistic community: the frame invoked in (25) – the ‘(older) child going to bed’
frame – is part of the shared world knowledge of a single family only.
13 Some of the determiner-noun sequences in (28) show only a part of the full object NP. For
example, among the instances of her cup, we may have (and actually do have) an example like
her cup of coffee. Similarly, a result like her shopping may mask the actual object NP, which is (in
one of the two cases) her shopping bag, and his pocket is part of the NP his pocket Bible. However,
this minor problem does not render our general findings suspicious in any way.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

14 I am ignoring here an observation that is perhaps more conspicuous, namely that out of the
50 most frequently used NPs in the joined ordering, 15 contain two-syllable nouns and another
4 even 3-syllable nouns, while there are only 6 two-syllable nouns among the 50 most frequent-
ly objects in the split ordering. The correlation between the length of the object NP and ordering
preferences was dealt with in Section 2 above.
15 I pass by the question as to what happens when option A violates lower-ranked but more
constraints than option B. In Optimality Theory, A will still win out in such a case. In probabil-
istic grammar, a more sophisticated metric would indicate which option is the most suitable
one, on the basis of all the factors and their associated weights.
16 So, we ignore here, among other things, the lexical dependency of the particle on the verb
in the example under discussion.
17 http:// www.google.com/language_tools?hl=en
18 I allow myself to make the perhaps unwarranted assumption that, for all practical pur-
poses, search pages from Great Britain reflect British English usage, and search pages from the
US reflect American English usage.
19 We excluded literalness as a context-related factor in Section 9, but Geeraerts (2006) would
probably consider this factor as belonging to “the cognitive context of meaning and experience”.
20 See Farrell (2005: 125–128) for the ranking of some broad syntactic word-order con-
straints. The most important constraint in his ranking is the one stipulating that heads have to
be leftmost in the phrases they expand (so that the verb is the first element in the VP).

References

Aarts, Bas (1989). Verb-preposition constructions and small clauses in English. Journal of Lin-
guistics, 25 (2), 277–290.
AHD (2000). The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, Fourth edition. Boston:
Houghton Mifflin.
Arnold, Jennifer E., Thomas Wasow, Anthony Losongco & Ryan Ginstrom (2000). Heaviness vs.
newness: The effects of structural complexity and discourse status on constituent ordering.
Language, 76 (1), 28­­–55.
Behaghel, Otto (1909/1910). Beziehungen zwischen Umfang und Reihenfolge von Satzgliedern.
Indogermanische Forschungen, 25, 110–142.
Behaghel, Otto (1930). Von deutscher Wortstellung. Zeitschrift für Deutschkunde, 44, 81–89.
Behaghel, Otto (1932). Die deutsche Syntax: Eine geschichtliche Darstellung, Volume 4: Wortstel-
lung, Heidelberg: Winter.
Bever, Thomas G. (1970). The cognitive basis for linguistic structures. In J. R. Hayes (ed.), Cogni-
tion and the Development of Language (279–362). New York: Wiley and Sons.
Biber, Douglas, Stig Johansson, Geoffrey Leech, Susan Conrad & Edward Finegan (1999). Long-
man Grammar of Spoken and Written English. Harlow: Longman.
Bock, J. Kathryn (1977). The effect of pragmatic presupposition on syntactic structure in ques-
tion answering. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 723–734.
Bock, J. Kathryn (1986). Syntactic persistence in language production. Cognitive Psychology, 18,
355–387.
 Bert Cappelle

Bolinger, Dwight (1971). The Phrasal Verb in English. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University
Press.
Büring, Daniel (2005). Semantics, intonation and information structure. Ms. University of Cal-
ifornia at Los Angeles. <semanticsarchive.net/Archive/GQ0YjgxM/buring.information.
structure.v2005.pdf>
Cappelle, Bert (2005). Particle patterns in English: A comprehensive coverage. Ph.D. disserta-
tion. K.U.Leuven.
Cappelle, Bert (2006). Particle placement and the case for ‘allostructions’. In: Doris Schönefeld
(ed.), Constructions all over: Case studies and theoretical implications [special volume of
Constructions], urn:nbn:de:0009–4-6839. < http://www.constructions-online.de/articles/
specvol1/683 >
Chen, Ping (1986). Discourse and particle movement in English. Studies in Language, 10 (1),
79–95.
Chomsky, Noam (1964 [1961]). On the notion “rule of grammar.” In J. A. Fodor & J. J. Katz
(eds.), The Structure of Language: Readings in the Philosophy of Language (119–136). Engle-
wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Chomsky, Noam (1975). The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory. New York & London: Ple-
num.
Dehé, Nicole (2000). On particle verbs in English: More evidence from information structure.
In N. M. Antrim, G. Goodall, M. Schulte-Nafeh, & V. Samiian (eds.), Proceedings of the 28th
Western Conference on Linguistics 11 (WECOL 1999) (92–105). California State University
at Fresno: Department of Linguistics.
Dehé, Nicole (2001). Intonation patterns of particle verb constructions in English. NELS, 31,
183–197.
Dehé, Nicole (2002). Particle Verbs in English: Syntax, Information Structure and Intonation.
Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Diessel, Holger & Michael Tomasello (2005). Particle placement in early child language: A mul-
tifactorial analysis. Corpus Linguistics and Linguistic Theory, 1 (1), 89–112.
Dik, Simon C. (1997 [1978]). The Theory of Functional Grammar, Part 1: The Structure of the
Clause, Second, revised edition, edited by Kees Hengeveld, Berlin & New York: Mouton de
Gruyter.
Erades, Peter A. (1961). Points of modern English syntax XL, English Studies, 42, 56–60.
Farrell, Patrick (2005). English verb-particle constructions: Constituency and order. Language,
81 (1), 96–137.
Fraser, Bruce (1966). Some remarks on the Verb-Particle Construction in English. In F. P. Din-
neen (ed.), Problems in Semantics, History of Linguistics, Linguistics and English (45–61).
Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Fraser, Bruce (1976). The Verb-Particle Combination in English. New York: Academic Press.
Geeraerts, Dirk (2005). Lectal data and empirical variation in Cognitive Linguistics. In F. Ruiz
de Mendoza Ibañez & S. Peña Cervel (ed.), Cognitive Linguistics. Internal Dynamics and
Interdisciplinary Interactions (163–189). Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Geeraerts, Dirk (2006). Towards a multifactorial grammar. Paper presented at the Second Bien-
nial Conference on Cognitive Science, 9–13 June 2006, State University of St. Petersburg,
Russia.
Goldberg, Adele E. (1995). Constructions: A Construction Grammar Approach to Argument
Structure. Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press.
Contextual cues for particle placement 

Goldberg, Adele E. (2003). Constructions: A new theoretical approach to language. Trends in


Cognitive Science, 7 (5), 219–224.
Gonnerman, Laura M. & Celina R. Hayes (2005). The professor chewed the students … out: Ef-
fects of dependency, length, and adjacency on word order preferences in sentences with
verb particle constructions. In B. G. Bara, L. Barsalou, & M. Bucciarelli (eds.), Proceedings
of the 27th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (785–790). Mahwah, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum [Cognitive Science Journal Archive maintained by Rensselaer Polytechnic
Institute: Cognitive Science Department]. < http://www.cogsci.rpi.edu/CSJarchive/Pro-
ceedings/2005/index.htm >
Gries, Stefan Thomas (2003). Multifactorial Analysis in Corpus Linguistics: A Study of Particle
Placement. New York & London: Continuum.
Gries, Stefan Thomas (2005). Syntactic priming: a corpus-based approach. Journal of Psycholin-
guistic Research, 34 (4), 365–399.
Gries, Stefan Thomas & Anatol Stefanowitsch (2004). Extending collostructional analysis: A
corpus-based perspective on ‘alternations’. International Journal of Corpus Linguistics, 9 (1):
97–129.
Gussenhoven, Carlos (2004). The Phonology of Tone and Intonation. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Hawkins, John A. (1994). A Performance Theory of Order and Constituency. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Huddleston, Rodney. (2002). The clause: complements. In R. Huddleston. and G. K. Pullum
(eds.), The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language (213–321). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kruisinga, Etsko (1931/1932). A Handbook of Present-day English, Part II: English Accidence
and Syntax. Fifth edition. Groningen: P. Noordhoff.
Levelt, Willem J. M., & Stephanie Kelter (1982). Surface form and memory in question answer-
ing. Cognitive Psychology, 14 (1), 78–106.
Lohse, Barbara, John A. Hawkins & Thomas Wasow (2004). Domain minimization in English
verb-particle constructions. Language, 30 (2), 238–261.
McIntyre, Andrew (2003). The semantic and syntactic decomposition of get and have: An inter-
action between verb meaning and particle placement. Ms. Universität Leipzig.
Peters, Julia (2001). Given vs. new information influencing the ordering of constituents in the
verb-particle construction. In R. Brend, A. K. Melby and A. Lommel (eds.), LACUS Forum
XXVII: Speaking and Comprehending (133–140). Fullerton, CA: LACUS.
Poutsma, H. (1928). A Grammar of Late Modern English, Part I: The Sentence, Second edition.
Groningen: P. Noordhoff.
Prince, Ellen F. (1981). Toward a taxonomy of given-new information. In P. Cole (ed.), Radical
Pragmatics (223–255). New York & London: Academic Press.
Prince, Alan & Paul Smolensky (2004 [1993]). Optimality Theory: Constraint Interaction in Gen-
erative Grammar. Malden, MA, Oxford & Carlton, Victoria: Blackwell.
Quirk, Randolph, Sidney Greenbaum, Geoffrey Leech & Jan Svartvik (1985). A Grammar of
Contemporary English. Harlow: Longman.
Quirk, Randolph, Sidney Greenbaum, Geoffrey Leech & Jan Svartvik (1985). A Comprehensive
Grammar of the English Language. Harlow: Longman.
Ross, John Robert (1986 [1967]). Infinite Syntax! (Language and Being 5). Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.
[publication of: Constraints on Variables in Syntax. Ph.D. dissertation. Massachusetts Insti-
tute of Technology]
 Bert Cappelle

Stefanowitsch, Anatol and Stefan Thomas Gries (2002). A construction-grammar approach to


linear-precedence principles. Paper presented at the Second International Conference on
Construction Grammar, 6–8 September 2002, University of Helsinki, Finland.
Svenonius, Peter (1996). The optionality of particle shift. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syn-
tax, 57, 47–75.
Szmrecsanyi, Benedikt (2005). Language users as creatures of habit: A corpus-based analysis of
persistence in spoken English. Corpus Linguistics and Linguistic Theory, 1 (1), 113–150.
Van Dongen, W. A. Sr. (1919). HE PUT ON HIS HAT and HE PUT HIS HAT ON. Neophilolo-
gus, 4, 322–353.
Ward, Gregory, Betty Birner & Rodney Huddleston (2002). Information packaging. In R. Hud-
dleston and G. K. Pullum (eds.), The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language (1363–
1447). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wasow, Thomas (1997). Remarks on grammatical weight. Language Variation and Change, 9
(1), 81–105.
Wasow, Thomas (2002). Postverbal Behavior. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Weiner, E. Judith & William Labov (1983). Constraints on the agentless passive. Journal of Lin-
guistics, 19, 29–58.
Conditionals and mental space set-up
Evidence from German word order

Ilona Vandergriff

Recent studies of conditionals in English have cited putative evidence from


German word order in support of the functional distinction between content
and speech-act conditionals (Dancygier & Sweetser 2005; Declerck & Reed
2001) while counterexamples have largely been ignored. The present study takes
a closer look at the syntactic marker in question, namely integrative and non-
integrative word order in wenn ‘if ’-initial conditionals. The findings raise doubts
about the hypothesized correlation of the construction’s syntactic form and the
cognitive domain in which it is interpreted. In this paper I explore how clausal
integration interacts with mental space construction in conditional speech acts
and show that integration does not mark content or predictive conditionality.
Rather, clausal integration signals that the if-clause (P) is the sole space where
the apodosis (Q) holds and that in all other spaces, ~ Q would take Q’s place.
From the perspective of Construction Grammar (CG), the form-function
mapping of syntactic integration and contrastivity observed in the German
data provides a window on functional distinctions which may exist but are not
formally marked in other languages.

1. Conditionals and mental spaces

Conditionals set up a “mental space” (Fauconnier 1985), defined as “construct[s]


distinct from linguistic structures but built up in any discourse according to guide-
lines provided by the linguistic expressions” (Fauconnier 1985: 16). These mental
spaces can be set up in various domains, in time or place, for example.1 Typically,
“if ” acts as a space builder in conditionals.
All conditionals share the simple format of if P, Q, yet different types are as-
sociated with different meanings. For present purposes it will be important to dis-
tinguish between predictives, or content conditionals and non-predictives, or
speech act conditionals.2 In (1), exemplifying a content conditional, the speaker is
predicting whether or not a hacker by the name of Hiro will transfer some data.
 Ilona Vandergriff

(1) If Hiro reaches out and takes the hypercard, then the data it represents will
be transferred from this guy’s system into Hiro’s computer.
(Dancygier & Sweetser 2005: 33)
Content conditionals show a causal or enablement dependency between two
events or states of affairs. Here, if sets up a primary conditional space and an alter-
native space. Diagram 1 “represents two alternative mental space set-ups […] both
interpreted as potential futures of the current base” (Dancygier & Sweetser
2005: 32). According to the authors, this alternative space gives rise to an if and
only if implicature. Here if P, Q carries the implication if ~P, ~Q.

Base/Present

Hiro is offered
the hypercard

If /Future Alt/Future
neutral stance

Hiro takes Hiro doesn’t


the card take the card

Ext/Future Alt/Ext

data are data not


transferred transferred

Diagram 1. Example (1) If Hiro reaches out and takes the hypercard, then the data it repre-
sents will be transferred from this guy’s system into Hiro’s computer
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

Predictives thus set up exactly two alternative scenarios. In Dancygier and Sweetser,
alternativity is defined as the existence of exactly two incompatible mental spaces,
generated in the same context from the same base space, which “cannot be com-
bined into a single coherent space” (Dancygier & Sweetser 2005: 35). What makes
prediction possible is that that these two alternative scenarios, P and ~P and their
correlates Q, and ~Q, respectively, exhaust all possibilities.
In these predictives neither the if-clause nor the main clause is asserted, rather
it is their relationship. Dancygier and Sweetser explain:
The if-clause cannot express an assertion because the conjunction sets up a hypo-
thetical mental space, different from the Base space where assertions could be made.
The main clause describes the predicted result in that same hypothetical space so it is
not asserted either. What a predictive conditional asserts is the causal dependency and
correlation between the events or states of affairs described by its clauses (2000: 122).

Conditional speech acts, by contrast, show a different relationship between P and


Q. In (2) the purpose of the if-clause is to establish as shared ground the reason for
producing Q. Dancygier and Sweetser do not show an alternative speech-act space.
Rather, for ~P the speaker would produce no apodosis at all.
(2) If you need any help my name is Ann. (Dancygier & Sweetser 2005: 111)
Unlike predictive conditionals exemplified in (1), speech-act conditionals like (2)
are described as one-scenario structures that do not allow a biconditional reading,
as shown in (3).
(3) * If you don’t need help (then) my name is not Ann.
In contrast with predictives which neither assert P nor Q, speech-act conditionals
do assert Q (Köpcke & Panther 1989; following König & van der Auwera 1988)
with P specifying the speech-act space in which Q is relevant. In the conditional
speech act the truth of Q is maintained regardless of the truth of P.
According to Dancygier and Sweetser, the functional distinction between pre-
dictive content and non-predictive speech-act conditionals is reflected in their
linguistic form in a number of ways. Predictive conditionals, for example, regu-
larly occur with correlative then (as illustrated in (1)) whereas speech-act condi-
tionals will typically not accept it (cf. (3)). Dancygier and Sweetser write that
then points deictically to a particular mental space, defined temporally or circum-
stantially, and locates the event or state described in the apodosis in that mental
space. By insisting on location within a particular mental space, the conditional
use of then brings on a natural inference that the content of the apodosis does not
hold in other alternative mental spaces (why else insist that it holds specifically in
this one?) (2005: 144).
 Ilona Vandergriff

Base/Present

Customers may need to ask


for help, using the staff
member’s name

If/Speech-Act Space

Hearer needs help

Ext/Speech-Act Space

Speaker introduces
herself

Diagram 2. Example (2) If you need help my name is Ann

They argue that correlative then is ungrammatical in (3) because it uniquely iden-
tifies “P as the (sole) space wherein Q holds” (2005: 149). Since the saleswoman’s
name is Ann regardless of whether P holds or not, correlative then is incompatible
with the intended meaning.
However, not all conditional speech acts are incompatible with correlative
then. Dancygier and Sweetser find that some speech-act contexts readily accept
then as illustrated in Example (4).
(4) If you’re so smart, (then) why aren’t you rich?
(Dancygier and Sweetser 2005: 149).
In their discussion, they argue that (4) differs from (2) in three ways. First, it allows
the speaker to emphasize the uniqueness of P as the only space in which Q is
relevant. Second, the relation between the clauses in (4) implies a predictive or in-
ferential interpretation to the effect that the speaker would normally expect a smart
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

person to get rich. And, third, (4) is “susceptible to contrasting interpretations”


(2005: 149) in that it gives expression to the speaker’s incredulity that an intelligent
person would be poor. Dancygier and Sweetser thus show that within the class of
speech-act conditionals - all of which specify the relevance condition for produc-
ing Q - differences exist with respect to the precise nature of the link between P and
Q. They argue that not all of the observed variables carry equal weight with respect
to the use of correlative then. While many speech-act contexts allow inferential,
predictive, or contrastive readings, the authors argue that it is the emphasis on P’s
uniqueness rather than other factors that motivates the use of then.

2. Clausal integration in German

Following initial wenn ‘if ’-clauses, conditional consequents or apodoses predomi-


nantly occur with integrative word order in German, i.e., the finite verb immedi-
ately follows the if-clause or protasis. This inversion is the unmarked ordering in all
complex clauses where the subordinate clause precedes the main clause. The sub-
ordinate clause can thus be taken as a constituent of the larger clause. Integrative
conditionals generally accept resumptive dann ‘then’ (Köpcke & Panther, 1989).
In spoken German, if-clauses are sometimes not syntactically integrated. In-
stead, the main clause will have the verb position of an independent main clause.
This ordering is considered standard in speech-act conditionals. Compare the fol-
lowing minimal pair in Table 1.

Table 1. Syntactic Integration, Resumption, and Non-integration


Pre-prefield Prefield Verbal Middle Field
Bracket
(5) Wenn du Lust hast, (dann) machen wir morgen einen
Kindergottesdienst.
if you interest have then make-FUT we tomorrow a
Content

Sunday-school
‘If you feel like it we’ll have Sunday school tomorrow.’
(Speaker is offering to organize Sunday school with the help of
the hearer if s/he feels like it.)
(6) Wenn du Lust hast, wir machen morgen einen
Speech-Act

Kindergottesdienst.3
if you interest have we make-FUT tomorrow a
Sunday-school
‘If you feel like it, tomorrow we’ll have Sunday school.’
(Speaker is inviting the hearer to join him/her for Sunday school if s/he feels like it.)
 Ilona Vandergriff

The conditionals in Table 1 show that different syntactic orderings sometimes


force different interpretations, a predictive interpretation in (5) and a relevance
interpretation in (6). In (5) the hearer’s attitude will cause or enable Sunday school
to take place. In (6), by contrast, Sunday school will take place regardless of how
the hearer feels about it. The if-construction allows the speaker to present the in-
formation tentatively, in case the hearer’s interested. Predictive conditionals such
as (5) with their real-world relationship between the clauses typically occur with
integrative word order, whereas speech-act conditionals like sentence (6) signal
their looser conceptual dependency via non-integrative word order (Gohl 2002;
Günthner 1999; Auer 1996, 2000; Pasch 2003; König & van der Auwera 19884).
If confirmed, these putative form-function correlations attested in German
are relevant to research on conditionality beyond German as they appear to pro-
vide formal evidence of the functional distinction between predictive (i.e., con-
tent) and non-predictive (i.e., speech-act) conditionals (Dancygier 1998; Dancy-
gier & Sweetser 2005; Declerck & Reed 2001). Drawing on results from Köpcke
and Panther’s 1989 paper, Dancygier and Sweetser (2005: 139) conclude that “stud-
ies of German have provided even more extensive evidence [than English or Greek]
in support of similar grammatically marked function distinctions.” For German,
clausal integration and resumption (using e.g. dann ‘then’) are claimed to lend sup-
port to the functional distinction between content and speech-act conditionals.
However, in the same study, Köpcke and Panther (1989) also discuss coun-
terexamples which show that some speech-act conditionals occur with integration
but neither Köpcke and Panther – nor Dancygier and Sweester - call into question
the hypothesized correlation between speech-act conditionality and clausal non-
integration. Rather, Köpcke and Panther posit an overriding pragmatic parameter
to explain why the putative form-function correlation does not hold in all cases.5

Table 2. Köpcke and Panther’s Correlations between Word Order and Pragmatic Func-
tion (1989)6
Clausal Integration Clausal Non-integration
(7) Wenn er das erfährt, gibt es Ärger. (8) Wenn er das erfährt, das gibt Ärger!
Content

If he that finds-out gives it trouble. If he that finds-out that gives trouble.


‘If he finds out about it there’ll be trouble.’ ‘If he finds out about it, there will be trouble!’
(unmarked) (marked – signaling affect)
(9) Wenn du meine Meinung hören willst, (10) Wenn du meine Meinung hören willst, die
(dann) fallen die Aktien bald. Aktien fallen bald.
Speech Act

If you my opinion hear want fall the If you my opinion hear want the stocks
stocks soon fall soon
‘If you want my prediction, stock prices ‘If you want to hear my point of view,
will drop soon.’ stock prices will drop soon.’
(marked – signaling speaker uncertainty) (unmarked)
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

While all speech-act conditionals allow non-integration, the authors present evi-
dence which shows that integration and resumption are more acceptable in some
speech-act conditionals than in others. Subjects were asked to rate German if-
clauses with integration and resumption on an acceptability scale ranging from 1
(the sentence is acceptable without hesitation) to 5 (the sentence is not acceptable
without hesitation.) The speech-act conditional Wenn Sie mich fragen, dann wird
es bald schneien ‘If you ask me, then we’ll soon have snow’ received a rating of 1.73,
whereas informants rated another resumptive speech-act conditional (Wenn du es
noch nicht wusstest, dann ist Hans wieder im Lande. ‘If you didn’t know yet, then
Hans is back in the country.’) relatively unacceptable at 4.68 (Köpcke & Panther
1989: 696). Based on their analysis, the authors claimed that clausal integration
and resumption signals a decrease in assertability of the apodosis and hypothe-
sized that speaker uncertainty about the truth of the apodosis can override the
expected forms and trigger the variant orderings:
… a relevance conditional may be grammaticalized as VS [verb-subject, i.e. inver-
sion] if the speaker wishes to communicate that the content of the apodosis does
not constitute an item of factual knowledge, but rather his/her opinion about the
truth of the apodosis (1989: 685).

They continue “that the factor degree of certainty influences the word order in the
apodosis. The higher the degree of the speaker’s uncertainty about the truth of the
apodosis, the more likely s/he will resort to integrative word order in the conse-
quent clause” (1989: 702). In effect, they assert that clausal integration correlates
with both (unmarked) content conditionality and (marked) speaker uncertainty
in speech-act conditionals. One formal marker is thus associated with two differ-
ent pragmatic meanings. In sum, no one meaning has been linked to clausal inte-
gration in all types of conditionals.
Köpcke and Panther’s (1989) findings that link clausal integration in speech-
act conditionals to lack of speaker certainty are based on a limited set of data. In all
the examples they analyze, Q does indeed present the speaker’s opinion suggesting
that the speaker may not be absolutely certain about the truth of the apodosis.
However, Vandergriff (1995) raises questions about the validity of their findings.
Her analysis based on a larger corpus shows that in some of the integrated speech-
act conditionals the speaker does not present an opinion but a fact.
(11) Wenn ich mal dabei bleibe, dann hat der Bundeskanzler gar in
If I once with-it remain then has the Chancellor even in
seiner Regierungserklärung am Freitag früh angeboten,
his state-of-the-union-address on Friday early offered
 Ilona Vandergriff

darüber zu reden.
about –it to talk.
‘If I pursue this for a moment, (then) the chancellor offered to talk about
this in his state-of-the-union address on Friday morning.’
Vandergriff argues that there is no evidence of speaker uncertainty about the truth
of the apodosis in (11). Her analysis is supported by Köpcke and Panther’s own test
criterion for speaker uncertainty. They had argued that integrated and/or resump-
tive speech-act conditionals “may be followed by an additional sentence such as
‘aber vielleicht irre ich mich/habe ich unrecht, etc. (‘ but maybe I am mistaken/I am
wrong’, etc.)” (1989: 703). Example (11) does not allow this reading. Instead, the
speaker leaves no doubt about his certainty as he states the topic of the chancellor’s
address. Vandergriff writes that the content of the apodosis or the speaker’s stance
toward it are not relevant to the use of clausal integration. Instead, her analysis
focuses on the interactional function of the syntactic marker. In (9) the speaker
opts for clausal integration in expressing a discourse-dominating function. Build-
ing on Held (1992), she argues that “integrative word order reduces the proposi-
tion’s illocutionary force” (Vandergriff 1995: 79). This weakening reduces “the
threat to the hearer’s negative face. The syntactic marker clausal integration, we can
thus conclude, has primarily interactional function in the speech-act domain.”
Both Köpcke and Panther’s (1989) and Vandergriff ’s (1995) studies build on
König and van der Auwera’s (1988) work on the subject which is much broader in
scope. Considering clause integration in German and Dutch conditionals, conces-
sive conditionals and concessives, König and van der Auwera try to pinpoint what
motivates clause integration and non-integration, respectively. Following Foley
and Van Valin (1984), they suggest that the reasons for syntactic variation may be
found on the semantic level: the more closely two clauses are semantically related,
the more closely they are syntactically integrated. Conversely, “non-integrative
word order occurs in complex sentences which assert or imply the independence
and mutual irrelevance of two propositions or their coocurrence against a back-
ground of general incompatibility” (König & van der Auwera 1988: 128).
In sum, previous research has shown that while clausal integration is prima-
rily associated with predictive conditionality, it is compatible with speech-act con-
ditionality under certain circumstances. Focusing on the speaker’s stance toward
the content of the apodosis, Köpcke and Panther (1989) try to link clausal integra-
tion to a reduction of the validity of Q. Vandergriff ’s (1995) analysis, by contrast,
claims that clausal integration reduces the illocutionary force of utterances with
discourse-dominating functions such as topic change.
In contrast to previous research that seeks to explain clausal integration for a
limited set of conditional data, the present study will try to tease out what the
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

specific formal features contribute to the meaning of a conditional speech act in


German. What precisely does clausal integration contribute in light of its conven-
tional meaning “close semantic relation of the clauses?” After all, it would be eco-
nomical to account for clausal integration, resumption and non-integration in
conditional speech acts in the same way linguists account for clausal integration in
general. To this end, I will firstly consider integration and secondly German re-
sumptive dann as formal aspects of speech-act conditional sentences in German
within the framework of Construction Grammar (Fillmore 1986, 1988, 1990a,
1990b; Fillmore, Kay & O’Connor 1988; Goldberg 1994; Shibatani & Thompson
1996). From this perspective, conditional sentences are examples of a construc-
tion, which Dancygier (1998: 5) defines as “a conventional pattern of linguistic
structure which is paired with features of interpretation.” Constructions thus have
predictable meanings, which are mapped onto the formal and semantic parame-
ters or their combinations.

3. Clausal integration in speech-act conditionals

It is a well established fact that all speech-act conditionals can occur and that the
majority of them do occur with clausal non-integration. As outlined in the re-
search overview, it is less well known that some speech-act conditionals do occur
with clausal integration (König & van der Auwera 1988; Köpcke & Panther 1989).
Therefore, the analyst needs to explain why syntactic integration – while not con-
ventionally associated with speech-act domain conditionality – is compatible with
it under certain circumstances. The following conditional, for example, can occur
with both integrative and non-integrative word order.
(12) Wenn du meine Meinung hören willst, die Aktien fallen bald.
If you my opinion hear want the stocks go-down soon
‘If you want to hear my point of view the stocks will go down soon.’
(Köpcke & Panther 1989: 702)
(13) Wenn du meine Meinung hören willst, fallen die Aktien bald.
If you my opinion hear want go-down the stocks soon
‘If you want to hear my point of view the stocks will go down soon.’
(Köpcke & Panther 1989: 702)
 Ilona Vandergriff

Base/Present
Hearer may be interested in
stock market predictions

If/Future Alt/Future

Hearer wants to Hearer does not want


hear speaker’s to hear speaker’s
stock market prediction stock market prediction

Ext/Future Alt/Ext

Stock prices Stock prices


will fall soon will not fall soon

Diagram 3. Example (12) Wenn Du meine Meinung hören willst, die Aktien fallen bald. ‘If
you want to hear my point of view the stocks will go down soon’

Example (12) is unambiguously interpreted in the speech act domain. The wenn
clause purports to request the hearer’s permission as a condition for producing Q.
The speaker’s prediction that stock prices will fall soon is relevant in the mental
space described in P. Consider initially Diagram 3, which illustrates the most like-
ly interpretation of sentence (12).
In the alternative scenario, neither Q nor ~Q would be performed. For this
reason, the alternative extension box is empty and the alternative scenario is shown
as incomplete.7 If P, Q; if ~P, Ø, where Ø stands for an empty syntactic position.
Without context, the integrated version (13) of the same conditional is prag-
matically ambiguous. In a narrowly defined context in which the speaker’s opinion
has regularly been followed by a fall in the stock market as though his prediction
were a bad omen, this sentence can be construed to be a predictive conditional.
Compare Diagram 4. In the absence of a suitable context, pragmatics would inter-
vene here to block the predictive reading shown in Diagram 4. Instead, hearers
will construct a more appropriate causal connection.
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

Base/Present
Hearer may be interested in
stock market predictions

If/Future Alt/Future

Hearer wants to Hearer does not want


hear speaker’s to hear speaker’s
stock market prediction stock market prediction

Ext/Future Alt/Ext

Stock prices Stock prices


will fall soon will not fall soon

Diagram 4. Example (13) Wenn Du meine Meinung hören willst, fallen die Aktien bald. ‘If
you want to hear my point of view the stocks will go down soon’

Base/Present
Hearer may be interested in
stock market predictions

If/Speech-Act Space

Hearer wants to Hearer wants to


hear speaker’s hear person3’s person4 person5 personn
stock market stock market
prediction prediction

Ext/Speech-Act Space

Speaker makes
prediction that Person3 makes
prediction y prediction z predictionn
stock prices prediction x
will fall soon

Diagram 5. Example (13) Wenn Du meine Meinung hören willst, fallen die Aktien bald. ‘If
you want to hear my point of view the stocks will go down soon’
 Ilona Vandergriff

Diagrams 3 and Diagrams 5 show conditional readings of (12) and (13) in the
speech-act domain which differ in important ways. In the default reading shown
in Diagram 3 Q holds in P, but the truth of Q (i.e., that the stocks will be falling) is
maintained irrespective of the truth of P. Here, the speaker’s opinion Q is pre-
sented as relatively independent of P. In Diagram 5, by contrast, P is identified as
the sole mental space where Q is relevant. In all other instances ( P2, P3, P4, Pn)
contrasting apodoses (Q2, Q3, Q4, Qn) are inferred. I propose that the range of con-
trasting scenarios if P2, Q2, if P3, Q3, etc. can be captured in the sentential hedge
aber man kann auch etwas anderes sagen ‘but one can also say something different’.
The conditional speech act readily accepts the hedge.
To test the hypothesized form-function mapping, I will check whether condi-
tional speech acts which are not compatible with integration or resumption do or
do not accept the hedge. Before I discuss these examples, it is important to clarify
the concept of contrastivity, how it relates to alternativity (Dancygier & Sweetser
2005), and how it will help to explain formal variations in speech-act conditionals.
Contrastivity is akin to Dancygier and Sweetser’s concept of alternativity de-
fined as “two spaces [that] are incompatible” (2005: 35). Both concepts, contrastiv-
ity and alternativity, share the basic mental structure that Q will hold only in P, not
in any other space. For ~P, something other than Q will be performed.
The difference between alternativity and contrastivity is that alternative-based
conditionals set up exactly two alternative, mutually exclusive scenarios. Because
only two scenarios are set up, and because one of these is specified in toto, the
speaker implicitly sets up a specific alternative mental scenario. Constrastivity, on
the other hand, means that ~P, namely P2, P3, P4, Pn would trigger one of n-tuple
~Q’s (Q2, Q3, Q4, Qn). Because more than one contrast provides the background to
the highlighted conditional speech act, no specific scenario is evoked in ~Q’s. As a
result, the other contrasting options are not mutually exclusive and cannot be
specified on the pragmatic scale.
Contrastive speech-act scenarios not only provide a justification for perform-
ing Q – as all other speech-act conditionals do - but also signal that P is the sole
space where Q holds. Compared to other conditional speech-acts such as Sentence
2 (Diagrams 2 and 3), which evoke two alternative scenarios - one in which Q is
performed and one in which it is not - contrastive conditional speech acts restrict
the relevance of Q by evoking contrasting options. This contrastivity and alterna-
tivity, respectively, signals that Q holds in P only and is thus functionally depend-
ent on P. I will argue that this functional dependence is mapped onto the syntactic
level, resulting in clausal integration or resumption.
In consideration of contrastivity, we can now explain why many of the inte-
grated speech act conditionals convey the speaker’s personal opinion. These con-
ditionals present the speaker’s contribution as one in an array of possible
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

contributions among many in the speech-act space. Hence, Q appears constrained


in its relevance, albeit not in its validity.
What needs to be shown is that the hypothesized contrastivity can account for
clausal integration even in conditional speech acts, where Köpcke and Panther’s
pragmatic parameter failed, namely, in cases where the speaker appears quite cer-
tain about the truth of the apodosis. The sentential hedge “aber vielleicht irre ich
mich/habe ich unrecht” [but maybe I am mistaken/I am wrong’] (1989: 703) is too
narrow here where the apodosis is presented as a fact. Going back to (11), cited
again here as (14), for example, the speaker wishes to project the image of a com-
petent professional who is certain about the truth of the apodosis.
(14) Wenn ich mal dabei bleibe, dann hat der Bundeskanzler gar in
if I once with-it remain then has the Chancellor even in
seiner Regierungserklärung am Freitag früh angeboten,
his state-of-the-union-address on Friday early offered
darüber zu reden.
about-it to talk.
‘If I pursue this for a moment, (then) in his state of the union address on
Friday morning the chancellor offered to talk about this.’
Wenn.. noch von meinem Fach her was
(15) gestattet
if still from my field from something permitted
ist, zur juristischen Form der--der Kaufverhandlungen, so
is to-the legal form of-the purchase-negotiations then
stellt also sich jedwede Handlung dieser
represents therefore itself each action of-this
Art als ein Vertrag dar
kind as a contract verb
‘If I may add something from my professional background to the legal process
of the purchase talks, (then) every process of this type is a legal contract…’
(Vandergriff, 1995: 269)
In Example (14), the speaker appears to contrast his topic maintenance (dabei bleibe
‘stick with it’) with topic change, which would trigger other discourse contribu-
tions. If he moved on to a different topic he might mention the Foreign Minister’s
comments on a similar topic, for example, or ask a political opponent a question.
In (15) the speaker explores the present discourse topic further by contributing
information from his area of expertise rather than moving on to a new topic. As
hypothesized, both (14) and (15) accept the sentential hedge.
In order to provide support for the hypothesized form-function correlation
between clausal integration and contrastivity, it must be shown that conditional
 Ilona Vandergriff

speech acts that do not accept the hedge also do not allow clausal integration or
resumption.
(16) Wenn du es noch nicht wusstest, die Aktien fallen bald.
if you it still not knew the stocks go-down soon
(17) ? /*Wenn du es noch nicht wusstest, (dann) fallen die Aktien bald.
if you it still not knew then go-down the stocks soon
‘If you didn’t know the stocks will go down soon.’
With the protasis wenn du es noch nicht wusstest ‘ if you didn’t know’ the speaker
sets up an alternative-based mental space, one in which addressee does not yet
know as opposed to one where he does already know. For ~P wenn du es schon
wusstest ‘if you already knew’ the speaker would produce no apodosis. Unlike the
apodosis P in (12) and (13) which evokes contrasting P1, P2, P3, Pn such as the
hearer wanting to hear John’s or Susan’s opinion on the stock market P in (16) and
(17) evokes exactly one ~P. Not surprisingly, the sentential hedge is not accepted.
(* If you didn’t know (I am telling you that) the stocks are falling but one can also say
something else.)
Example (17) demonstrates that speech-act conditionals that set up exactly
one alternative in ~P and are not open to a range of contrasting ~P’s do not accept
integration. This grammaticality judgment is supported by Köpcke and Panther’s
1989 experimental results, reported on in the research overview. In summarizing
the results, Table 3 shows that speech-act conditionals can be classified into those
that evoked contrasting scenarios and are therefore compatible with integration
and resumption and those which do not.
Predictive conditionality is conventionally associated with integrative word
order. Integrative conditionals, in turn, regularly allow the insertion of correlative
dann or so ‘then’ (Köpcke & Panther 1989). The conditions which constrain claus-
al integration in conditional speech acts should also hold for resumption (marked

Table 3. Clausal Integration and Relation of P and Q in Conditional Speech Acts

Domain Clausal Integration Relation of P and Q

Speech-Act Integration Contrastive Scenarios P is the sole space where


Resumption If P, (then) Q is said; If P2, Q holds
(then) Q2 is said;
If Pn, (then) Qn is said
Non-integration No Contrastive Scenario P is one space where Q
If P, Q is said; holds
If ~P, Ø is said
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

by dann or so ‘then’). Since German dann, in turn, is “semantically similar” to


English then and is “used with a function somewhat parallel to that of then in con-
ditional apodoses” (Dancygier & Sweetser 2005: 171), it will be interesting to see if
the findings for English then also apply to German dann/so.
Before I look at some examples, it will be useful to describe the function of
German dann and English then. English then, much like its equivalent German
counterparts, seems to function as a temporal and deictic pointer, indicating a
mental space in which the event or state described in Q will hold. In fact, it appears
that German dann is even more similar to English then than Dancygier and
Sweetser (2005) claimed. In stating only that German dann is used in predictive
but not in speech-act conditionals, they stop short of describing the full range of
functions dann interacts with. German dann is actually compatible with speech
act conditionality, just like its English counterpart, and subject to some of the same
restrictions.8 Both dann and then occur only in speech-act contexts that restrict
Q’s relevance to the particular mental space described in P.
Consider Austin’s famous example, which – according to Sweetser and
Dancygier (2005) - some speakers deem acceptable with correlative then.
(18) If you’re hungry (then) there are biscuits on the sideboard.
I agree with Dancygier and Sweetser who argue that correlative then is acceptable
in certain contexts, for example, if the addressee has just indicated that s/he is
hungry. We can generalize that all speech-act conditionals with correlative then
identify P as the sole space where Q is relevant and that any alternative to P such
as P2, P3, Pn would correlate with Q2, Q3, Qn,, respectively. P (i.e., if you are hungry)
appears as one of many possibilities, for instance, in opposition to if you’re thirsty
or if the baby is hungry, each matched to its relevant extension in the alternative
speech act space. For example, if you’re thirsty might cause the speaker to go on to
say (then) there is a beer in the fridge whereas if the baby is hungry (rather than you)
(then) there is some applesauce.
In German, speech-act conditionals involving contrastivity are also compati-
ble with resumptive dann.
(19) Wenn du Hunger hast, (dann) stehen da Kekse auf dem Buffet.
if you hunger have (then) stand there biscuits on the sideboard.
‘If you are hungry (then) there are biscuits on the sideboard.’
Based on Dancygier and Sweetser’s (2005) findings for English conditional speech
acts, I have argued that German dann much like English then emphasizes that Q’s
relevance is restricted to the state or event described in P. As a deictic marker the
correlate picks out one option P among possible options (P2, P3, P4, Pn) along with
its extension (Q2, Q3, Q4, Qn).
 Ilona Vandergriff

By setting up an alternative space or multiple contrasting spaces, the mental


space described in P becomes the sole space where Q will hold. Contrastivity and
alternativity in conditionals, then, necessarily involve the semantic-pragmatic de-
pendence of the apodosis on the protasis. In speech-act conditionals where no
contrastivity is implied as in (2) or (16), Q will hold in spaces other than P, reduc-
ing Q’s dependence on P. The relative assertability of Q and its functional depend-
ence on P are formally marked by clausal integration, resumption, and non-inte-
gration, respectively. With clausal integration marking a decrease in assertability
and greater semantic-pragmatic dependence, integration and resumption are thus
iconic markers in German conditionals, including speech-act conditionals. They
signal that the protasis P is not only one space but rather the only space in which
the utterance is relevant.
I have shown above how a speaker can link an utterance Q to a relevance con-
dition and how clausal integration or resumption mark the content of the apodosis
as one option among an array of scenarios. We are now in a position to see why
clausal integration has been linked to politeness functions (Vandergriff 1995). For
example, in the context of discourse-dominating functions such as topic change,
the speaker’s utterance may appear as a potentially face-threatening act. Restrict-
ing its relevance to a sole space minimizes the threat and provides the addressee
with options on the discourse record whereas non-integration would present
Q with full illocutionary force. By signaling to the hearer that Q is only one of
many alternative options, the speaker reduces Q’s independence and assertability.
However, it is not always more polite to reduce the independence of Q.
Dancygier and Sweetser point out that in some contexts, for example, when mak-
ing an offer as in If you’re hungry, then there are biscuits on the sideboard “it seems
rude to insist on the specific circumstances under which the biscuits are offered,
by adding then” (2005: 149). Clausal integration (and resumption) therefore is not
a politeness marker but may serve a politeness function in speech-act conditional-
ity in contexts where insisting on exclusiveness is more polite. While it seems at
first glance that discourse-dominating functions that threaten the hearer’s nega-
tive face (Brown & Levinson 1989) by requesting permission to speak or manipu-
late the topic progression will tend to show clausal integration while offers do not,
further research on conditionals in extended discourse will be necessary to ex-
plore the link between alternativity/contrastivity, clausal integration/resumption,
and politeness functions.
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

4. Conclusions

In conclusion, the findings provide strong evidence that the syntactic differentia-
tion of clausal integration and non-integration, respectively, marks neither the
distinction between predictive and non-predictive conditionals, nor between con-
tent and speech-act conditionals. Instead, clausal integration signals the semantic-
pragmatic dependence of the apodosis on the protasis, emphasizing that P is the
sole space where Q holds.
The concept of contrastivity in conditionals (paralleling Dancygier and Sweet-
ser’s concept of “alternativity”) as outlined here helps to bridge some of the previ-
ous research results. Whereas Köpcke and Panther’s (1989) analysis tried to link
clausal integration in speech-act conditionals with speaker stance, the present
study has shown that it signals contrastivity, with P as the only space where Q is
relevant. Speaker stance may also be involved but only as a pragmatic epiphenom-
enon. In other words, clausal integration signals that the opinion is only one
among many and not that the opinion is limited in its validity as Köpcke and Pan-
ther hypothesized.
Whereas Köpcke and Panther’s account posited an overriding parameter to
account for clausal integration in speech-act conditionals, Construction Grammar
requires a clear form-function mapping. Each form or combination of forms is
conventionally associated with a certain meaning or function. The proposed ac-
count which views clausal integration as an iconic marker aligns well with Con-
struction Grammar and is consistent with studies that link syntactic dependence
to semantic/pragmatic dependence. My findings thus complement and further il-
luminate König and van der Auwera’s result, who linked non-integration to “sepa-
rate assertability” (1988: 126).
Clausal integration and resumption with correlative dann constitute aspects of
constructional meaning and hence play an important role in communication as
they facilitate the hearer’s search for possible interpretations. In Sanders et al.
(1993: 94) understanding a discourse “means constructing a coherent representa-
tion of that discourse…” (cited in Rouchouta 1998: 21). From this perspective,
both markers along with other aspects of constructional meaning guide the hearer
in his/her interpretation.
The form-function correlation between contrastivity and alternativity on the
one hand and clausal integration (as well as correlative dann and so ‘then’) in
German on the other, emphasize the dependence of the apodosis on the protasis
in German conditional speech acts much like correlative then does in English con-
ditional speech acts. Further research will be necessary to determine the extent of
the functional overlap between the correlative markers in German and English.
 Ilona Vandergriff

Notes

1. Temporal when signals the speaker’s positive stance toward the contents of P, whereas if
signals non-positive stance. Dancygier and Sweetser point out that “if is not try neutral in stance,
but is indeterminate between a range of stances including almost everything except complete
positive stance P or ~P” (2005: 53). German wenn, by contrast, is ambiguous between temporal
and conditional meanings, i.e., the speaker stance is not formally marked. In most cases, speak-
er stance can be disambiguated from context, in some cases it remains unclear. Only in combi-
nation with subjunctive mood wenn-clauses are unambiguously conditional (Auer 2000: 7).
2. Examples and glosses for 1) – 2) from Sweetser (1990). In addition to the content condi-
tionals and speech-act conditionals discussed, Dancygier and Sweetser distinguish two other
types of conditionals, namely epistemic such as If John went to that party, (then) he was trying to
infuriate Miriam (If I know that John went to the party, then I conclude that he went to infuriate
Miriam.) and metalinguistic conditionals of the type Ok, I’ll have a tomahto, if that’s how you
pronounce it (If my pronunciation is acceptable I’ll take the tomato.)(All examples and glosses for
1) – 3) from Sweetser, 1990; examples 1) – 4) cited in Dancygier 1998.)
3. Example has been adapted/standardized from Günthner (1999: 210).
4. König and van der Auwera (1988) describe the correlation between form and function as
tendential rather than absolute. They make reference to the “general rule which requires or, at
least favors, non-integrative word order in Dutch and German, whenever an initial adverbial
clause relates to the speech act performed in uttering the following clause, rather than to the
proposition expressed by it.” (1988: 110)
5. Neither Declerck and Reed (2001) nor Dancygier and Sweetser (2005) discuss the German
counterexamples to the hypothesized link between content conditionality and integration, and
between speech-act conditionality and non-integration.
6. Examples and glosses from Köpcke and Panther (1989).
7. While my analysis parallels Dancygier and Sweetser, my diagram differs from theirs for
similar speech-act conditionals. Their diagram for speech-act conditionals (see Diagram 2) shows
the alternative set-up as non-existent rather than incomplete. The modified diagram allows the
analyst to highlight that even in an alternative space no alternative to Q would be performed.
8. While English then and German dann/so seem semantically and functionally similar, fur-
ther study involving authentic data will be necessary to determine the area of overlap. Generally
speaking, clausal integration and German dann seem possible in contexts whose English paral-
lels would be compatible with then. However, the reverse does not seem to be the case, as re-
sumption in German seems to enjoy broader distribution than in English.

References

Auer, Peter (1996). The pre-front field in spoken German and its relevance as a grammaticaliza-
tion position. Pragmatics, 6(3), 295–322.
Auer, Peter (2000). Pre- and post-positioning of wenn-clauses in spoken and written German.
In E. Couper- Kuhlen & B. Kortmann (Eds.), Cause, condition, concession, contrast
(173–204). Berlin & New York: de Gruyter.
Conditionals and mental space set-up 

Brown, Penelope & Stephen C. Levinson (1987). Politeness. Some universals in language usage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dancygier, Barbara (1998). Conditionals and prediction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dancygier, Barbara & Eve Sweetser (1996). Conditionals, distancing, and alternative spaces. In
A. Goldberg (Ed.), Conceptual structure, discourse and language (83–98). Stanford, CA:
CSLI Publications.
Dancygier, Barbara & Eve Sweetser (2000). Constructions with if, since and because. In E.
Couper-Kuhlen & B. Kortmann (Eds.), Cause, condition, concession, contrast (111–142).
Berlin & New York: de Gruyter.
Dancygier, Barbara & Eve Sweetser (2005). Mental spaces in grammar. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Declerck, Renaat & Susan Reed (2001). Conditionals. A Comprehensive Empirical Analysis.
Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Fauconnier, Gilles (1985). Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Reprinted 1994, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fillmore, Charles (1986). Varieties in conditional sentences. ESCOL 3 (Eastern States Confer-
ence on Linguistics), 163–82.
Fillmore, Charles (1988). The mechanisms of ‘Construction grammar.’ In S. Axmaker, A. Jaisser,
& H. Singmaster (Eds.), Proceedings of the 14th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics
Society, (35–55). Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Linguistics Society.
Fillmore, Charles (1990a). Epistemic stance and grammatical form in English conditional sen-
tences. In M. Ziolkowski, M. Noske, & K. Deaton (Eds.), Papers from the 26th Regional
Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, (137–62). Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
Fillmore, Charles (1990b). The contribution of linguistics to language understanding. In Pro-
ceedings of the 1st Symposium on Cognition, Language, and Culture, A. Bocaz (Ed.), 109–28.
Universidad the Chile.
Fillmore, Charles, Paul Kay, & Mary C. O’Connor (1988). Regularity and idiomaticity in gram-
matical constructions. Language 63(3): 501–38.
Gohl, Christine (2002). Zwischen Kausalität und Konditionalität: Begründende wenn-Kon-
struktionen. Deutsche Sprache 30, 193–219.
Goldberg, Adele (1994). Constructions: a Construction Grammar approach to argument struc-
ture. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Günthner, Susanne (1999). Wenn-Sätze im Vor-Vorfeld. Ihre Formen und Funktionen in der
gesprochenen Sprache. Deutsche Sprache 27(3), 209–235.
König, Ekkehard & Johan van der Auwera (1998). Clause integration in German and Dutch con-
ditionals, concessive conditionals and concessives. In J. Haiman & S. Thompson (Eds.), Clause
combining in grammar and discourse (101–129). Amsterdam, Philadelphia: Benjamins.
Köpcke, Klaus-Michael & Uwe-Klaus Panther (1989). On correlations between word order and
pragmatic function of conditional sentences in German. Journal of Pragmatics 13, 685–711.
Pasch, Renate et al. (2003). Handbuch der deutschen Konnektoren. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter.
Selting, Margaret (1993). Voranstellungen vor den Satz. Zeitschrift für germanistische Linguistik
21, 291–319.
Shibatani, Masayoshi & Sandra A. Thompson (1996). Grammatical constructions: Their form
and meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sweetser, Eve (1990). From etymology to pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Vandergriff, Ilona (1995). A study of German conditionals: Domain, verb position, and pragmatic
function. (Unpublished dissertation, University of California at Berkeley).
Semantics and pragmatics
in construction grammar
The case of modal verbs*

Ronny Boogaart
Leiden University

1. Introduction

At least since the work of Traugott (1989) and Sweetser (1990: 49–75), modal verbs
have been considered a schoolbook example of polysemy. However, for any given
modal verb, it is notoriously problematic to determine both the number and the
kind of modal ‘meanings’ to be distinguished as well as the exact relationships
among these (see e.g. Nuyts; 2005 and Narrog; 2005 for overviews and discussion).
In this paper, I will approach the problem from the perspective of construction
grammar (in the general sense outlined by Croft & Cruse; 2004: 225–257). I will
argue that constructions function as constraints on polysemy: in actual language
use, modal verbs occur exclusively as part of modal constructions and such con-
structions as a whole are, in principle, monosemous rather than polysemous.
In (1)–(3), the problem is illustrated for the Dutch verb kunnen (‘can’).
(Examples taken from the novel Hersenschimmen, by J. Bernlef, Querido, 1987).
Following the threefold distinction made by Nuyts (2005), this verb allows for
dynamic (1), deontic (2) and epistemic (3) readings.1
(1) Gedachten kun je niet lezen.
Thought can you not read
‘One can’t read thoughts’
(2) Van mij kunt u rustig naar huis gaan.
From me can you quietly to house go
‘As fas as I’m concerned, you can go home’
(3) Kan dat ze hem ergens gevonden hebben.
Could that they him somewhere found have
‘It could be that they found him somewhere’
 Ronny Boogaart

To account for such flexibility, most linguists have taken either a monosemous or
a polysemous view. On the monosemy view, more commonly referred to as the
vagueness approach2, verbs such as kunnen (‘can’) and moeten (‘must’) have one
general, encompassing meaning that is compatible with their various interpreta-
tions. For these particular verbs, as well as for their English counterparts can and
must, this characterization must be something like ‘possibility’ and ‘necessity’, re-
spectively (Kratzer 1977, 1981). On the polysemy account, the meaning of a modal
verb is represented as a network of different senses – some of them more periph-
eral than others – that are related to one another in systematic ways, for instance
by means of metaphorical extension (Sweetser 1990: 56ff). Obviously, the catego-
ries of dynamic, deontic and epistemic modality illustrated in (1)–(3) make good
candidates for the different senses associated with the modal verbs kunnen and
moeten – or their equivalents in other languages, for that matter.
The discussion on monosemy and polysemy is a classic one. In fact, some peo-
ple may feel that it is outdated, especially since the rise of cognitive and construc-
tionist approaches to language. Even though it is well known that both the mon-
osemy approach and the polysemy approach to meaning have their own specific
advantages and problems associated with them (see Section 2), it is clear that, in
cognitive linguistics at least, the dispute has been decided in favour of polysemy.
And it has been a landslide victory at that.3 In fact, polysemy is sometimes re-
garded as a defining feature of the cognitive approach to language. This is most
evident when Langacker labels the search for minimal lexical semantics, i.e. mon-
osemy, as one of the ‘ghosts from our theoretical past’ (2005: 151), suggesting it
may be compared, for instance, to the generative grammarians’ quest for the larg-
est generalizations possible.4
In this paper, however, I will argue that precisely within a constructionist ap-
proach to language, monosemy is neither a ‘ghost’, nor something ‘from the past’. In
fact, the taxonomic construction hierarchies that have been proposed in construc-
tion grammar may well be labeled monosemy networks. This paradoxical term is in-
troduced in this paper to capture the claim that a constructionist approach to lan-
guage combines the advantages of the polysemy and the monosemy approach while
at the same time overcoming the problems attached to either approach individually.
I will start out in Section 2 by presenting in more detail the monosemy and the
polysemy approach as applied to the semantics of modal verbs. In Section 3, I will
apply the principal claims of construction grammar to constructions that include
a modal verb as one of their constituting parts. In Section 4, it is concluded that,
from a constructionist perspective, examples such (1)–(3), do not illustrate one
form with three different meanings, but rather three different constructions, each
with their own meaning.
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

2. Monosemy versus polysemy in the domain of modality

Examples such as those given in (1)–(3) raise the question of what exactly is ‘the
meaning’ of a modal verb such as kunnen (‘can’) and how does this meaning relate
to the different usages exemplified in (1)–(3)? There are, at least, three possible
answers to this question and in Section 3, I will add a fourth one, from the per-
spective of construction grammar. In this section, I will present the advantages
and problems of the first three possible answers that may be characterized as ho-
monymy, monosemy and polysemy. While these matters will be familiar to most
readers and excellent discussions of the issue can be found elsewhere in the litera-
ture (e.g. Kirsner 1993; Geeraerts 1993; Tuggy 1993; Croft 1998; Sandra 1998; For-
tuin 2000; and, with special reference to modal verbs, Coates 1983; Kronning
1996; Janssen 2001 and Papafragou 2000), some remarks are necessary in order to
compare the constructionist solution of Section 3 to the answers that have been
around in the literature to date. Moreover, I will apply the issue specifically to mo-
dal verbs and, even more specifically, to the verb kunnen, the Dutch equivalent of
English can.

2.1 Homonymy

The first possible answer to the question ‘What is the meaning of the verb kunnen?’
is that there is no such thing as the meaning of this verb, but rather that the verb
simply has (at least) three different meanings, as represented in Figure 1.
For a linguist, this answer, which basically treats kunnen as a homonym, is
obviously not very satisfactory. The main reason is that Figure 1 does not show:
a. what exactly the three meanings have in common, nor
b. how exactly the three meanings are different from one another.

FORM 1
kunnen

MEANING 1 MEANING 2 MEANING 3


dynamic deontic epistemic

Figure 1. Homonymy
 Ronny Boogaart

The first aspect is especially problematic in view of the fact that other modal verbs,
including modal verbs in other languages, show the same kinds of usage types,
whereas the representation of Figure 1 makes it seem like more or less of a coinci-
dence that these three particular meanings are expressed by one and the same
form. (In this respect, the situation for kunnen is clearly different from the ambi-
guity of a word like bank, the standard example of genuine homonymy.) The sec-
ond aspect relates to the fact that, in addition to some common semantic core,
there are also clear differences between the three readings. Research on language
acquisition and grammaticalization, for instance, has made clear that, both on-
togenetically and diachronically, these three meanings occur in a definite order
and that one may be derived from the other – either via metaphorical extension
(Sweetser 1990) or by conventionalization of implicatures (Traugott 1989) – but
not vice versa.
A final problem for the homonymy ‘solution’, and the one that causes most
frustration for practicing linguists, is that it is often extremely difficult to classify a
specific use of a modal verb as belonging in one of the three categories. Take, for
instance, the use of zou kunnen (‘could’) in (4) (taken from the Corpus of Spoken
Dutch) (Brantjes 2005).
(4) Ik wou uh ik dacht dat jij aan de lange muur zou kunnen begin[nen].
lit. I wanted uh I thought you could start at the long wall.
Most researchers working on modality would classify the use of kunnen in (4) as
an instance of dynamic modality, expressing ‘participant-internal ability’ or ‘ca-
pacity’, much like in (1). However, it is clear from the context that the utterance in
(4) is used as a directive, i.e. it suggests – rather strongly, in fact – that the speaker
wants the addressee to perform the action (this is clear, for instance, from the fact
that the speaker first begins his sentence with ik wou (‘I wanted’) and then corrects
himself to the more polite form ik dacht (‘I thought’)). From this perspective, then,
the utterance belongs in the domain of deontic modality, like that in (2). Clearly,
we are dealing here with an indirect speech act in which a claim about the ability
of the addressee to perform a certain action (dynamic modality) has to be under-
stood as a rather strong incentive for the addressee to actually start performing
this action (deontic modality). The issue of indirect speech acts constitutes, of
course, one of the core issues of pragmatic theory and it is well beyond the limits
of this paper to treat it in any great depth. It suffices to note, for now, that Figure 1
does not offer any insight into the issue of indirect speech acts.
For many reasons, then, the ‘homonomy’ solution to the problem illustrated by
(1)–(3) is not really a solution and in recent years it has not really been advocated
as such for modal verbs at all. In the literature, it mainly functions as an ideal
strawman when arguing in favour of the other two answers to this question. In fact,
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

both approaches can use it as such since the monosemous approach basically tack-
les the first problem ((a) above), whereas the polysemous solution quite adequate-
ly handles the second one ((b) above). Neither one, however, is particularly suited,
or even interested, in accounting for uses such as the one demonstrated in (4),
which would require a separate pragmatic ‘module’ on either account.

2.2 Monosemy

Of the monosemy and the polysemy approach, the first one differs most radically
from the strawman in Figure 1. On this account, the answer to our question of
how to account for the different readings of kunnen in (1)–(3) is that, in actual fact,
these readings are not all that different. It is argued that the verb has only one
meaning, which is constituted by the conceptual content that is shared by all of its
uses. Drawing on existing accounts of English can (most notably those of Kratzer,
1991; Papafragou 2000 and, in particular, Perkins, 1983), we might hypothesize for
Dutch kunnen that its unitary, all-encompassing semantics is ‘x enables y’, as
represented in Figure 2.
In this representation, y is the propositional content of the entire clause, without
the modal information as expressed by the verb. x is a pragmatic variable, to be
resolved by the context, the nature of which will determine the kind of modality
involved. In the case of dynamic modality, x is supposed to be constituted either
by participant-internal properties (abilities, capacities), as in (1), or by participant-
external circumstances that enable an agent to perform a certain action. If x is an
authority or an ethical norm, we are automatically dealing with deontic modality;
in that case, x may, more specifically, also be the speaker himself, as is the

FORM 1
kunnen

MEANING 1
X enables (is
compatible with) Y

Figure 2. Monosemy (vagueness)


 Ronny Boogaart

case in (2), which gives rise to a directive-deontic reading. The category of epis-
temic modality, as in (3), is a bit more complex but it may nonetheless be captured
by ‘x enables y’ as well, in which x is the body of knowledge or evidence available
to the speaker at the time of speaking and y is not so much the state of affairs itself
as it is the conclusion that this state of affairs is holding.

Pro monosemy
The monosemous characterization of the meaning of kunnen in Figure 2, rather
convincingly, gives insight into the common semantic denominator of its different
uses, like those given in (1)–(3); in fact, it is the only thing that it does. Thus, un-
like in Figure 1, the fact that these three different ‘meanings’ are expressed by one
and the same form is not merely a coincidence. This, indeed, constitutes the prin-
cipal merit of the vagueness approach to meaning, that has been advocated most
consistently throughout the years by linguists of the so-called Columbia School
(Contini-Morava et al. 2004 and references cited there). With respect to modal
verbs, the monosemous approach is also the prevalent one in formal linguistics,
ranging from Kratzer’s (1977) work to the relevance-theoretic approach of
Papafragou (2000).
The monosemous perspective has one other important advantage, namely that
it allows for a clear distinction between the contribution of semantics and prag-
matics, as represented in Figure 2'.

FORM 1
kunnen

Semantics
MEANING 1
X enables Y

Pragmatics

INTERPRETATION 1 INTERPRETATION 2 INTERPRETATION 3


(dynamic) (deontic) (epistemic)

Figure 2'. Vagueness (semantics versus pragmatics, meaning versus interpretation)


Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

The only contribution of the semantics of the verb kunnen to the interpretation of
the utterance consists of imposing the rather global and schematic constraint of
Figure 2. All the rest, including the choice between the different kinds of modality,
is determined by features of the context of use, which – at the very least – will have
to provide a value for x (corresponding to Kratzer’s conversational background and
Papafragou’s modal restrictor).

Contra monosemy
While the monosemous approach thus solves the first problem of the homonomy
approach of Figure 1, it does not provide a solution for the second problem, that of
accounting for the differences and precise relationships between the different read-
ings of kunnen illustrated in (1)–(3), for instance, from a diachronic or a cross-
linguistic perspective. The latter two perspectives will be taken up in the next sub-
section, on polysemy, but also from a synchronic, language-specific perspective,
there are clear differences between the three readings, starting with their relative
frequency. This is evidenced in Table 1, which lists the frequency of the dynamic,
deontic and epistemic readings of kunnen in the novel Hersenschimmen.5

Table 1. Frequency of the different readings of kunnen in the novel Hersenschimmen

Modal type n %

Dynamic 227 85,3


Deontic 16 6
Epistemic    9 3,4
Other (blends, undecided) 14 5,3
Total 266 100

The differences in frequency between the readings allowed for by kunnen, in par-
ticular between the dynamic reading and the other two, are quite significant, but
since the monosemous analysis focuses exclusively on what the different uses have
in common, such differences are not noticed, let alone explained.
Furthermore, there are at least two other problems to the monosemy approach.
The first one is obvious: since the semantic characterization will have to cover all the
uses of a given form, it can only be highly abstract. So much so in fact that one may
well wonder whether language users have, or indeed need to have, access to this
abstract level of analysis at all. And, crucially, as abstract as the semantics of kunnen
proposed in Figure 2 might be, it still feels like stretching the notion of ‘enablement
(x,y)’ when applying it to actual cases, such as those given in (1)–(4).
The final objection to the monosemous approach to be mentioned here can be
characterized as the rule-list fallacy (Langacker 1987: 29) or the generality fallacy
 Ronny Boogaart

(Croft 1998: 156 ff.), which boil down to saying that if it is possible for a linguist to
come up with a general semantic characterization for a given form, this does not
mean that language users do this as well (the generality fallacy), nor that, in addition,
individual types of uses of the form are not stored independently (the rule-list fal-
lacy). This is precisely why, as mentioned in the introduction, Langacker (2005: 151)
has called the exclusive strive for abstract generalizations and rules ‘a ghost from the
past’ and this, of course, seems totally in accordance with the basic insights that
motivated the development of construction grammar – see Section 3.

2.3 Polysemy

In Section 2.1, I mentioned two problems with the idea of homonymy as applied
to the verb kunnen: (a) it does not show what the different uses have in common,
and (b) it does not show how exactly the various uses differ from one another.
While the monosemous analysis discussed in the previous subsection clearly
solves the first problem (but not the second one), the polysemous analysis is aimed
precisely at accounting for the second problem (but not for the first one).
The idea that modal verbs are polysemous is a well-established one in cogni-
tive linguistics (Mortelmans 2007: 869–970). In fact, the very existence of exam-
ples such as (1)–(3) may be taken as a sufficient condition for a polysemous analy-
sis: one and the same form allows for quite different readings that, nonetheless, are
felt to be connected in some way. The latter is what distinguishes the polysemous
analysis from simply assuming homonomy (or ambiguity). Thus, rather than say-
ing that the verb kunnen has three different meanings, it is now assumed that ‘the
meaning’ of this verb can be represented as an entire network of different ‘senses’.
If we restrict ourselves to the dynamic, deontic and epistemic sense of kunnen, the
resulting network might look like the one in Figure 3.
Figure 3 is meant to capture two ideas that are central to the polysemous ap-
proach to modal verbs. First, the common semantic denominator of the different
senses associated with kunnen – constituted by something like ‘x enables y’
(Figure 2) – is not represented here at all. This is not to say that such an overall
schematic characterization is principally incompatible with the polysemous ap-
proach, but rather that polysemists are either not too interested in it, or deny out-
right its relevance from a contemporary, usage-based approach to language.
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

FORM
kunnen

MEANING

dynamic

deontic

epistemic

Figure 3. A polysemy network for kunnen

Second, the three different senses of kunnen in Figure 3 are not on an equal foot-
ing: the bold line around the dynamic sense illustrates the idea that this sense is
somehow the prototypical one, i.e. the most ‘central’, ‘concrete’, ‘literal’ or ‘core’
sense (and, at least in the case of kunnen, also the most frequent one, as was obvi-
ous from Table 1), whereas the other senses are more peripheral and, in fact, can
be shown to be derived from the prototype. The latter is usually argued to be true
from the synchronic perspective of the adult language speaker, but it is all the
more clear from the perspective of grammaticalization and language acquisition,
where the dynamic sense can be shown to be prior to the deontic and the epis-
temic sense. How exactly the three senses are related is not given by the simplified
polysemy network of Figure 3, but it is one of the goals of the polysemous ap-
proach to describe precisely these types of relations. (Mortelmans 2007: 875–880
offers a recent overview of different solutions to the latter problem.)
 Ronny Boogaart

Pro polysemy
The last issue provides an important argument in favour of a polysemous analysis,
namely the argument from grammaticalization. Since the polysemy network of
Figure 3 is ‘directed’, as is witnessed by the arrows going from the core to the pe-
ripheral, to the even more peripheral sense, it allows for elegant diachronic gener-
alizations on the extent to which a given form has ‘grammaticalized’. For instance,
whereas both Dutch mogen and English may seem to have lost their original dy-
namic use, the Dutch form has hardly grammaticalized beyond the deontic sense,
whereas the English form is used both deontically and (even predominantly) epis-
temically these days. All this is not to say that a polysemy network is necessarily
identical to the ‘grammaticalization chains’ that are used in diachronic research,
but still, it is hard to see how this kind of language change could have taken place if
forms, at any synchronic point of their diachronic development, were not to some
extent polysemous. After all, grammaticalization is a gradual development in which
older uses are not lost immediately after a new kind of use starts to develop.
It is a further advantage of the polysemous approach, as compared to the mon-
osemous approach of Figure 2, that it is better suited for the comparison of differ-
ent modal constructions within one language as well as for cross-linguistic com-
parison. The semantic characterization of a modal verb in the monosemous
analysis can only be highly abstract, which makes comparative analysis, both with-
in one language and across languages, extremely difficult. At this level of abstrac-
tion or schematicity, different forms may be hard to distinguish from one another,
whereas their actual use may be quite different. For instance, the general semantic
characterization of both Dutch kunnen and English can has to be something like ‘x
enables y’, but this does not garantuee at all that they are always used in similar
contexts. On the polysemous account, it can more easily be shown to what extent
the use of ‘similar’ forms overlaps and to what extent they diverge from one an-
other. Thus, whereas Dutch kunnen clearly has all three senses represented in
Figure 3, English can does have a dynamic and a deontic sense, but the form is not
really used to express epistemic possibility (for which English exclusively uses
could, which is hardly felt to be the past tense form of can anymore, or may).

Contra polysemy
There are, however, also quite a few problems attached to the polysemy approach
to the semantics of modal auxiliaries. I will discuss three of those, the last one of
which, in particular, will show the need for a constructionist approach to the se-
mantics of modals, which will be presented in more detail in Section 3.
The first problem, obviously, is that we have now lost the idea that there is a
common semantic core to the various uses of the modal or, at least, the polyse-
mous approach is not principally – and, in some cases, even principally
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

not – occupied with trying to formulate it. In addition, two problems that we not-
ed above for the monosemous approach are (almost) equally applicable to the
polysemous approach, namely the rule-list fallacy and, interestingly enough, the
‘vagueness’ of the semantic characterizations used.
As for the first, the fallacy, of course, also works the other way round: if it is
possible for a linguist to come up with a network of different but related senses for
a given form, this does not exclude the possibility that, in addition, there is a sche-
matic semantic characterization available that is compatible with all the different
senses of that form. Moreover, one can now also commit the polysemy fallacy
(Sandra 1998), which consist of assuming, without further empirical support, that
the network of senses as envisaged by a clever linguist, will also be part of the lin-
guistic competence of language users. Besides, even clever linguists differ substan-
tially when it comes to the design of their modal network, both with respect to the
number of senses distinguished and with respect to the relationships assumed to
exist between them. As an example of the first, Goossens (1983) may be men-
tioned, since he distinguishes no less than twelve different senses for kunnen. As
an example of the latter, Van Ostaeyen & Nuyts (2004) have argued that the epis-
temic sense of kunnen does not derive from the deontic sense, as Sweetser would
have it and which was represented in Figure 3, but rather that both the deontic and
the epistemic sense are based on the dynamic sense, as they appear in Figure 3'.
Now, none of these analyses is necessarily wrong, but the point is that there are
still no clear criteria when it comes to determining either the number or the kind
of senses for any given form, or the exact nature of the relationships between them.
The principal problem of polysemy networks, then, is that they always seem to be
to some extent arbitrary; in other words, the senses are given by the analyst more
than by the language.
The final drawback of the polysemous analysis, namely the ‘vagueness’ of the
semantic characterizations, may need a bit more elaboration since, as I have al-
ready claimed, it is an advantage of the polysemous approach over the monose-
mous one that the senses in the polysemy network of Figure 3 are decidedly less
vague compared to the one unitary meaning of Figure 2. However, ‘vagueness’ is a
matter of degree, of course, and the senses proposed within a polysemy approach
to semantics are still rather ‘vaguely’ defined when compared to yet another ap-
proach, namely the constructionist approach to be presented in Section 3. Of
course, vagueness or schematicity in itself is not a problem – in fact, for monosem-
ists vagueness is a claim rather than a problem – and some degree of abstraction
from actual usage events will be an indispensable part of any grammatical theory,
 Ronny Boogaart

FORM
kunnen

MEANING

dynamic

deontic epistemic

Figure 3'. An alternative polysemy network for kunnen (Nuyts)

including construction grammar. However, since the traditional notion of mon-


osemy is rejected by polysemists precisely on account of its high level of abstrac-
tion, it might be worthwhile to point out in somewhat more detail the problems
that arise within polysemous analyses of modals precisely because of their own
level of abstraction. At the same time, the discussion will show the need for a ‘con-
structionist’ approach to language and thus pave the way for the following section.
To illustrate this crucial point, I will first have another look at the Dutch examples
(1) and (4) and then offer some additional data in support of a constructionist ap-
proach from the study of cross-linguistic variation.
If we have to choose between the senses of Figure 3 then the example in (1),
repeated here for convenience, comes out as a case of ‘dynamic modality’, and thus,
more specifically, as describing an ability or capacity of the subject referent.
(1) Gedachten kun je niet lezen.
Thought can you not read
‘You can’t read thoughts’
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

It is, however, quite different from the standard example of ‘dynamic modality’
given in the literature, which would be something like He can play the piano. On
closer scrutiny, it does not really make sense to say that (1) is about a property of
the subject referent or that it is ‘agent oriented’ at all. The sentence can, for in-
stance, not really be paraphrased with to be able to (or the Dutch equivalent there-
of). Rather, such sentences with a reduced form of the second person pronoun,
receiving a generic reading, are used in Dutch to present a property of the object-
NP rather than the subject-NP. (If the full form of the pronoun is used, the sen-
tence is about the ability of the addressee). Very often, as is the case in (1), the
object-NP will be preposed. This passive-like (agent backgrounding) function of
(1) is, thus, more adequately paraphrased as ‘thoughts are not readable’ or ‘thoughts
cannot be read’. This might seem like a minor problem and a minor divergence of
the ‘prototypical’ dynamic sense of kunnen, but it already shows that the meaning
of language-specific patterns can be more complex than, and actually even differ-
ent from, what is captured by the highly schematic sense of ‘dynamic modality’.
Turning to the category of deontic modality, example (4) likewise shows the
inadequacy of the polysemy approach when applied to actual instances. In fact, it
does so in two respects.
(4) Ik wou uh ik dacht dat jij aan de lange muur zou kunnen begin[nen].
lit. I wanted uh I thought you could start at the long wall.
First, as already noted in Section 2.1, these ‘deontic’ uses of kunnen are really
somewhere in between the dynamic and the deontic sense. From a polysemous
perspective, we might assign kunnen in (4) to the category of dynamic modality
and then leave the ‘directive-deontic’ impact of such utterances to pragmatics.
However, separating semantics and pragmatics in this way seems artificial and it
obscures the simple fact that knowing Dutch includes knowing that one can use
the specific construction instantiated in (4) to politely suggest to the addressee to
perform a certain action. Thus, indirect speech acts, at least to the extent that they
are conventionalized, may well be considered constructions (cf. Stefanowitsch
2003), i.e. conventionalized pairings of a certain form – which in the case of (4)
will include at least zou and a specific intonation pattern – and a specific meaning
(cf. Levinson’s 2000 utterance types).
Second, even if there were a way to assign the utterance in (4) to the deontic
sense of kunnen in the polysemy network, such a label would not tell us much. The
semantic pole of ‘indirect speech acts constructions’ will have to include quite
subtle pragmatic information on the type of situations in which it is appropriate to
use them, far beyond what is, schematically and vaguely, captured by the notion of
‘deontic modality’ in the polysemy network.
 Ronny Boogaart

A final illustration of the vagueness of polysemy networks is taken from cross-


linguistic comparison. It was argued above that the polysemy approach is quite
better suited for cross-linguistic comparison than is the monosemous approach.
Thus, ‘similar’ forms across languages, such as Dutch kunnen and mogen and their
English near-equivalents can and may, can be compared as to which senses of the
polysemy network they are used to express. Such an undertaking is practically im-
possible at the level of abstraction at which the monosemous approach formulates
its language-specific generalizations. However, at the same time, cross-linguistic
comparison brings out quite a serious problem for the polysemous approach. To
illustrate this, let us, once again, look at Dutch kunnen as it is used in the novel
Hersenschimmen, and compare it to the official English and German book transla-
tions, entitled Out of Mind and Hirngespinste, respectively. Table 2 shows the verbs
used most often in English and German as translations of Dutch kunnen (recall
that the Dutch original contained 266 occurrences of kunnen, see Table 1).
I will illustrate the relevance of Table 2 for the present discussion on the ba-
sis of the top left corner of the table which shows the frequency of English can
and could in Out of Mind. It can be noted that the English translation uses the
verb can (including could) (303 instances) quite a bit more than the Dutch origi-
nal uses kunnen (266 instances). The difference is, in fact, much bigger than it
might appear at first sight, since of the 303 instances of English can/could, only
about two thirds (201 instances) are based on an occurence of kunnen in the origi-
nal Dutch text, leaving 102 instances of can/could that are not based on kunnen.
Now, whereas the polysemy network for English can/could and Dutch kunnen will
undoubtedly look highly similar, these observations suggest that these networks
are not very good at describing, let alone explaining, the language-specific dis-
tribution of these forms, which is, apparently, quite different in either language.

Table 2. English and German renderings of Dutch kunnen in the official book transla-
tions of Hersenschimmen

English German

Total can/could in Out of mind: 303 Total können in Hirngespinste: 259


Based on Dutch kunnen: 201 Based on Dutch kunnen: 213
Not based on Dutch Kunnen: 102 Not based on Dutch kunnen 46
Total may/might in Out of mind: 42 Total dürfen in Hirngespinste: 49
Based on Dutch. Kunnen: 10 Based on Dutch kunnen:    2
Not based on Dutch Kunnen: 13 Not based on Dutch kunnen: 47
Total be able to in Out of mind: 17 Total sollen in Hirngespinste: 53
Based on Dutch kunnen: 17 Based on Dutch kunnen:    5
Not based on Dutch kunnen:    0 Not based on Dutch kunnen: 48
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

Thus, there are many contexts in which English uses a form of can whereas Dutch
does not (and vice versa, in fact).
Dutch may, for instance, use another modal verb in a particular context, as is
the case in ‘epistemic’ questions of the kind exemplified in (5).
(5) a. Zou Vera al naar bed zijn?
Would Vera already to bed be
b. Could Vera be in bed already?
Thus, if one is wondering whether or not a state of affairs is holding, one could
formulate a question – either to oneself or to some addressee – of the form given
in (5), of which there are 11 instances in the novel. In all cases, English uses the
verb could, whereas Dutch has opted for the past tense of zullen (though the
present tense would also be possible in such cases). For English, one might say that
the use of could in (5b) is in accordance with our earlier observation that can does
not really allow for epistemic uses; thus, (5b) may be regarded as the interrogative
version of (6b). In Dutch, however, there is no affirmative version for (5a) using a
form of the verb zullen at all. The sentence in (6a) is not ungrammatical, but it does
not allow for the epistemic reading that Vera is possibly in bed already, like English
(6 b)does.6
(6) a. Vera zou al naar bed zijn.
Vera would already to bed be
b. Vera could be in bed already.
In Dutch, then, both the polysemy network for kunnen and the one for zullen will
have to include a sense of ‘epistemic possibility’. However, such a move still would
not tell us that Dutch uses zullen rather than kunnen in the highly specific ‘epis-
temic interrogative construction’ exemplified in (5a) and there is of course no way
to predict this on the basis of the kind of information represented in polysemy
networks or existing classifications of modality.
As a final illustration of the same point, the high number of instances for can
in the English translation of this novel can be attributed to a large exent to one
particular group of verbs that are typically combined with can in English, but that
do not need any modal verb at all in Dutch. This group is constituted by, on the
one hand, the ‘sensory verbs’ to see, to hear, to feel and to smell and, on the other
hand, the ‘mental verbs’ to understand and to remember. Thus, whereas in English
these verbs are typically used as a complement to can, as in I can see it and I can’t
understand, in Dutch they are mostly used as main verbs without any modal qual-
ification in the form of an auxiliary, as in Ik zie het (‘I see it’) and Ik begrijp het niet
(‘I do not understand’). Taken together, this group of verbs accounts for 50 in-
stances of the English ‘surplus’ of can in the translation of Hersenschimmen. This
 Ronny Boogaart

particular use of can in English constitutes a clear example of ‘dynamic modality’,


more specifically of participant-internal ability, as does the use of kunnen to the
extent that it is used with these verbs in Dutch at all. Children who acquire English
and Dutch will at some point (quite early in fact for this particular sense) have ar-
rived at the generalization that can/kunnen is used to express ‘ability’, but clearly
this general meaning does not, as such, tell them when exactly to use it – or, for
that matter, not to use it. Thus, for English learners, more or less fixed combina-
tions such as can see and can feel will have to be learnt independently and presum-
ably stored as such. This conclusion could, of course, also have been arrived at on
the basis of language-specific research of English, but cross-linguistic analysis has
the potential of bringing to light the crucial role of language-specific conventions:
English typically uses can with verbs like see or feel, but, as is shown by the case
Dutch, this is merely a convention of English that does not automatically follow
from the fact that can expresses the general sense of ‘dynamic possibility’.7
In this section, I have pointed out the shortcomings of the polysemous ap-
proach to modal verbs, especially when it comes to describing the meaning and
use of language-specific constructions that contain a modal verb as one – but only
one – of their constituting parts. At the same time, I have, therefore, illustrated the
need for a constructionist approach to modal verbs. In Section 3, I will illustrate in
more detail what such an approach could look like. First, I will sum up the findings
of Section 2.

2.4 Summing up

In this section, I have compared the monosemous and the polysemous approach
to the semantics of modal verbs. While the monosemous approach is very good at
explaining why all the various uses of one and the same verb are expressed by one
particular form, the polysemous approach, instead, focuses on these various uses
themselves, as well as on the precise relationships amongst them.
In addition, each approach has some more specific advantage over the other.
The monosemy approach allows for a clear distinction between the contribution of
semantics and that of pragmatics, as was represented in Figure 2’; in polysemy ac-
counts, it is less clear to what extent the distinction between epistemic, deontic and
dynamic modality is semantic or pragmatic in nature. If specific senses are repre-
sented independently, then the role of pragmatics is presumably more limited than
it is on the ‘minimalist’ approach to semantics of monosemists, but it is hard to see
how much more limited it actually is, or where precisely pragmatics comes in.
The polysemous approach, on the other hand, has a crucial advantage over the
monosemous one in that the notions of dynamic, deontic and epistemic modality
(or perhaps some subtly different classification of senses) are necessary to allow for
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

a comparison of different modal verbs, or non-verbal modal expressions for that


matter, both within one language and accross languages. In addition, these senses
seem to play an explanatory role when considering consecutive stages in language
acquisition, or in the diachronic development of modal expressions.
Finally, the monosemous and the polysemous approach to meaning turned
out to share a crucial problem. The level of abstraction or schematicity they are
operating at does not really allow for a detailed description of the way in which
modal expressions are actually used in a specific language. This will be most obvi-
ous for the monosemy approach, in which the ‘vague’ or minimal semantics of
linguistic elements is actually being claimed, but it is hardly less of a problem for
the polysemous approach, as anyone can witness who has ever tried to classify
actual instances of modal expressions according to the modal classifications that
have been proposed in the literature.
In the following section, I will argue that a constructionist approach to the se-
mantics and pragmatics of modal verbs combines the advantages of the monosemous
and the polysemous approach without, however, inheriting their shortcomings.

3. From modal verbs to modal constructions

3.1 Introduction

Construction grammar presents an exception to the idea that functional and cog-
nitive linguists have always been more interested in the meaning and use of lan-
guage, and thus in semantics and pragmatics, than in aspects of its form, i.e. syn-
tax. In fact, construction grammar has been characterized as ‘the cognitive
linguistic approach to syntax’ (Croft & Cruse 2004: 225). (Which is not to say that
all branches of construction grammar are necessarily cognitive or functional in
nature.) The latter description suggests that construction grammar is not con-
cerned with the semantic and pragmatic issues that we have been discussing, as
applied to modal verbs, in the preceding sections. Now, while this is true to some
extent – and for some branches of construction grammar more so than for others
– the very starting point of construction grammar precisely consists of the claim
that the two, i.e. form and meaning, cannot be separated. In fact, I will show that,
precisely because of its focus on issues of form, the framework of construction
grammar provides a new perspective on the classic issue of monosemy versus
polysemy that is the central concern of the present paper.
The label of construction grammar is really an umbrella-term covering various
schools of linguistics, arguably including Langacker’s Cognitive Grammar, but in
line with the rather theoretical, and basically programmatic, outlook of the present
 Ronny Boogaart

contribution, I will not be formulating my findings in terms that are specific to any
of these schools. Rather, I will start off from the set of assumptions that Croft &
Cruse (2004: 265) have identified as ‘the three essential principles of construction
gammar’ and that are thus, by definition, shared by the different ‘constructionist’
schools. These have been summarized in (7).
(7) a. Constructions are symbolic units
b. All grammatical knowledge can be represented as a construction.
c. Constructions are linked to one another in a taxonomic hierarchy.
The principle in (7a), i.e. the symbolic nature of constructions, means that con-
structions are conventionalized pairings of form and meaning. Until now, in
Figures 1–3, I have been visualizing both forms and meanings as circles; construc-
tions I will represent as squares, as in Figure 4, containing both a form
(phonologial pole) and a meaning (semantic pole).
The symbolic nature of words has long been accepted in linguistics, but con-
struction grammar extends the symbolic claim to all kinds of grammatical knowl-
edge, as formulated above in principle (7b), thus ranging from morphemes to
words via idiomatic phrases to the most abstract grammatical patterns. This was
captured above when I pointed out that even when construction grammar is ‘doing
syntax’ it is still, as a matter of principle, occupied with semantic issues as well.
The third and final principle in (7c) captures the idea that a language does not
consist of simply a list of constructions. This follows naturally, in fact, from the
second principle: if morphemes, words, multi-word expressions and abstract
grammatical patterns are all constructions, then it will be clear that the more spe-
cific (lower level) constructions contain the more abstract (higher level) construc-
tions as constituting parts. Such relationships are represented in taxonomic hier-
archies, or construction networks, in which constructions inherit formal and
semantic aspects of more abstract constructions higher up in the taxonomy, while
at the same time exhibiting more specific features that make them into independ-
ent constructions of their own.

Form

Meaning

Figure 4. A construction
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

In the following subsection, I will apply these basic principles of constructionist


approaches to the problem, discussed at length in the previous section, of account-
ing for the many different readings allowed for by modal verbs.

3.2 Towards a network of modal constructions

A crucial difference between construction networks and the polysemy networks


that we have been discussing in Section 2.2 is that, following principle (7a) and
Figure 4, a network of constructions is a network of form-meaning pairings,
whereas a polysemy network is a network of senses associated with one particular
form. Construction taxonomies are concerned with forms (and their accompany-
ing meanings), whereas polysemy networks are concerned with meanings. The
two are not necessarily incompatible because they are operating at different levels
of linguistic analysis: since lexical items, just like grammatical rules, are construc-
tions (principle 7b), we could simply say that there is a kunnen-construction in
Dutch that, obviously, has kunnen as its phonological pole and some version of the
polysemy network for modal verbs, like the one in Figure 3, as its semantic pole.
Even though, in my view, a monosemous analysis of constructions, in which con-
structions are pairings of one form and one meaning, is more in accordance with
the sign-based spirit of construction grammar (principle 7a and Figure 4) and,
specifically, with the notion of inheritance (see below), it is true that the existence
of polysemy is not a priori excluded by the ‘essential principles’ cited in (7). In fact,
Goldberg (1995: 31–32) claims that ‘constructional polysemy’ is only to be ex-
pected given that polysemy is the norm for words, and constructions are not prin-
cipally different from words (cf. principle 7b).
At this point, then, it might feel like we could start the debate on monosemy
vs. polysemy as applied to kunnen all over again and that construction grammar as
such has no new insights to offer into this matter. This, however, is far from true.
While treating lexical items as constructions does not help us much in accounting
for the different readings of modals, lexical items are, of course, not the only kinds
of constructions that are relevant for the present discussion.8 In fact, it is one of the
merits of constructionist approaches that they have shifted the attention away
from abstract patterns and meanings to relatively specific and concrete ‘low-level’
constructions that can be observed in actual language use. From the latter per-
spective, there is, of course, no such thing as the lexical item kunnen being used in
isolation. Rather, the verb kunnen functions as just one element among others in
an almost indefinite number of lower level constructions. All these ‘modal con-
structions’ can be said to inherit the form and function of ‘the kunnen-construc-
tion’, but the meaning of the latter is, basically, an abstraction of all the different
constructions that kunnen is compatible with and it may well be questioned – as it
 Ronny Boogaart

is by construction grammarians – if constructions that are so high up in the tax-


onomy have any role to play other than in the most interesting linguistic papers.
(No irony intended.) Therefore, the issue of ‘the meaning’ of the verb kunnen by
itself loses much of its urgency since it will be the primary task of construction
grammarians to determine the form and meaning of the lower level modal con-
structions in which kunnen is only one of the constituting parts. The meaning of
these constructions, like those illustrated in (1), (4) and (5), will be so much more
specific, just like their forms are, that neither ‘vagueness’ nor ‘polysemy’ necessar-
ily enters the picture. In fact, this is why construction networks might be labeled,
paradoxically, monosemy networks rather than polysemy networks. Note that, in
my view, monosemy does, thus, not necessarily imply vagueness. I hope to make
this point more clear in the remainder of this section.
What might such a construction network for kunnen look like, and what posi-
tion in the network – if any – is occupied by the senses of dynamic, deontic and
epistemic possibility that were shown, in the previous section, to be indispensable
for the purpose of cross-linguistic comparison and the study of diachronic devel-
opments? A tentative answer to this question is visualised in Figure 5.
As an attractive – and yet untenable (see below) – hypothesis, we may assume
that rather than constituting senses in a polysemy network, the notions of dy-
namic, deontic and epistemic modality constitute the semantic pole of three inde-
pendent modal constructions, that are linked by the fact that all three of them in-
herit the form and meaning of the more abstract kunnen construction.9 In addition,
of course, the lower level constructions will have many more different ‘parent con-
structions’, including both lexical and grammatical constructions, but these are not
represented in Figure 5. If we take the notion of inheritance to mean complete in-
heritance, thus to capture the idea that constructions necessarily inherit all formal
and semantic specifications of their parent constructions, then we cannot but as-
sume a monosemous analysis for the top node in Figure 5. Otherwise, the three
lower-level constructions would inherit the entire polysemy network from the
kunnen construction, which is incompatible with the gist of our hypothesis.10 Thus,
Figure 5 seems to be an ideal way of combining the monosemous and the polyse-
mous approach to the semantics of kunnen, thereby escaping the rule-list fallacy.
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

Kunnen

X enables Y

Form ? Form ? Form ?

Dynamic Deontic Epistemic

Figure 5. Towards a construction network for kunnen

However, since constructions, other than senses in a polysemy network, are pair-
ings of form and meaning, our hypothesis requires us to formulate the distinctive
formal characteristics of each construction. Thus, we need to determine what ex-
actly, in addition to kunnen, is contained in the formal component of the three
constructions in Figure 5. This, in fact, is a definite advantage of construction net-
works over polysemy networks, since it non-arbitrarily restricts the number of con-
structions to be distinguished: at least in theory, constructions are ‘given’ by the
language rather than just by the analyst (cf. the criticism of polysemy networks in
Section 2.3). Thus, different conventionalized usages of a given form are stored in-
dependently in the taxonomy only to the extent that they can be shown to corre-
spond to formal features. Thereby, the sign-based nature of the network is preserved:
all constructions are pairings of a particular form and a particular meaning.
Even though Figure 5 does a good job illustrating the advantages of the con-
structionist approach to modals compared to monosemous and polysemous analy-
ses, it cannot be totally right. More specifically, it may very well be questioned if the
categories of dynamic, deontic and epistemic modality could actually figure at all in
a language-specific network of modal constructions. In one of the few explicitly con-
structionist papers on modal verbs, Wärnsby (2002) has actually tested the hypoth-
esis that I formulated above and that was visualised in Figure 5. More specifically, she
 Ronny Boogaart

used corpus-linguistic data to see if epistemic instances differ systematically from


non-epistemic ones in terms of the linguistic environment they appear in. Actually,
this was done before in non-constructionist terms, for instance by Coates (1983) and
Heine (1995). There clearly do seem to be such differences, most notably when it
comes to the nature of the complement (as stative versus eventive, cf. Diewald 2006
for German, and Barbiers 1995 for Dutch). In addition, it is clear that, in example
(2), the adjunct van mij (‘from me’) triggers a deontic reading of permission for kun-
nen. And, in a similar vein, the impersonal complementation construction in (3) can
only be epistemic. In fact, this type of complementation construction seems to con-
stitute the only pattern in which modal verbs in Dutch unambiguously receive an
epistemic reading (Nuyts 2001: 189–192); this reading follows quite naturally from
the general semantics of ‘the complementation construction’ as a kind of epistemic
stance marker proposed by Verhagen (2005: 94–113).11
(2) Van mij kunt u rustig naar huis gaan.
From me can you quietly to house go
‘As fas as I’m concerned, you can go home’
(3) Kan dat ze hem ergens gevonden hebben.
could that they him somewhere found have
‘It could be that they found him somewhere’
Nonetheless, Wärnsby concludes her paper by claiming that it is ‘doubtful’ wheth-
er the constructionist approach to modality is ‘fruitful’ (2002: 8), mainly since one
will be faced with a ‘bewildering web of constructions’ (2002: 7).
The basic flaw in Wärnsby’s paper, as well as in Figure 5, is the expectation that
the supposedly universal conceptual notions of dynamic, deontic and epistemic
modality as such constitute the semantic pole of any language-specific construc-
tion. This, in fact, should already be clear from the specific modal constructions
that we have been discussing so far and that were illustrated by means of (1), (4)
and (5) below (cf. also the findings on constructions containing sensory and men-
tal verbs discussed in Section 2.3).
(1) Gedachten kun je niet lezen.
Thought can you not read
‘You can’t read thoughts’
(4) Ik wou uh ik dacht dat jij aan de lange muur zou kunnen begin[nen].
‘I wanted uh I thought you could start at the long wall.’
(5) a. Zou Vera al naar bed zijn?
Would Vera already to bed be
b. Could Vera be in bed already?
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

These examples illustrate a couple of the shortcomings of the representation in


Figure 5. First, the examples (1), (4), and (5) exemplify cases of dynamic, deontic
and epistemic modality, respectively. However, each of them is, of course, an in-
stantiation of just one of the many dynamic, deontic and epistemic constructions
that Dutch has. Thus, if we would label all of the modal constructions of Dutch in
these general terms, then we are faced with an, indeed, bewildering number of
synonymous constructions, which should be at least as dissatisfying to any linguist
as the situation of homonymy discussed in 2.1.
Second, and related to the first point, the actual semantics and pragmatics of
the constructions in (1), (4) and (5) is, of course, much more specific than can be
captured by any of these highly schematic labels. In fact, it is even to be expected
that some language-specific constructions cannot really be classified as belonging
to one of the three categories at all: they could be ‘in between’, as I argued for (4),
or outside of these categories alltogether, which, for instance, seems to be the case
for the use of moeten (‘must’), mogen (‘may’) and willen (‘want’) in conditional and
concessive constructions (Boogaart 2007, cf. the ‘post modal’ uses in Van der
Auwera & Plungian 1998).
Thus, if we want to include the notions of dynamic, deontic and epistemic
modality in a language-specific construction network, then we are basically faced
with the same problems as noted in 2.2 for the polysemous approach. Therefore,
when investigating the particular synchronic network of modal constructions in a
specific language, it is not useful to employ the notions of dynamic, deontic and
epistemic modality as a necessary part of the semantic component of all construc-
tions that have a modal verb as one of their constituting parts. The fact that lin-
guists when trying to classify actual utterances as representing one of these types
of modality are often at a loss, or disagree with one another, should be telling us
something, other than that they are not clever enough.
Still, as was observed in Section 2.3, the senses of dynamic, deontic and epis-
temic modality (or another modal classification of ones choice) are necessary, or
– at the very least – quite handy, tools when analyzing cross-linguistic differences,
language acquisition and grammaticalization. Therefore, these labels should be re-
garded as pertaining to possibly universal conceptual content that probably all
languages will have means to express in some way. Thus, they are part of a ‘seman-
tic map’ (Haspelmath 2003), or a ‘conceptual space’ (Croft 2001), on which lan-
guage-specific construction networks may be projected – as has been, somewhat
simplistically, presented in Figure 6. (A more detailed semantic map for modality
is proposed by Van der Auwera & Plungian 1998.)
 Ronny Boogaart

Kunnen

X enables Y

1 4 2 3 5

Dynamic Deontic Epistemic

Figure 6. Construction network projected onto ‘semantic map’

The numbers (1)–(5) in Figure 6 refer to the specific constructions instantiated in


the ‘constructs’ (1)–(5), discussed at various points in the preceding sections. The
exact form and meaning of these particular constructions are more complex than
can be treated in the present paper, but that is precisely the point to be made here:
the notions of dynamic, deontic and epistemic modality do not suffice when it
comes to characterizing the semantic pole of modal constructions in a given lan-
guage, and sometimes they are not applicable at all.12

4. Conclusion

At the outset of this paper, examples (1), (2) and (3) were provided to show that
one ‘form’ can have multiple ‘meanings’. However, from the constructionist per-
spective on modal verbs developed in the course of this paper, we should now
conclude that examples (1), (2) and (3) differ not only in meaning but also in form.
It is true that all three utterances contain an instance of the verb kunnen, but that
is only one of their constituting parts. It is not the verb kunnen as such that is dy-
namic in (1), deontic in (2), and epistemic in (3). Rather, the three examples are
instantiations of particular modal constructions, that, as a whole, receive a par-
ticular kind of modal reading. The examples in (1)–(3), then, do not really illustrate
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

one form with different meanings, but different forms, each with their own meaning
and, thus, monosemy rather than polysemy.
Even though the notion of ‘form’ may be – literally – more complex than was
envisaged in the traditional monosemous account of modal verbs, modal construc-
tions may still be considered monosemous pairings of form and meaning. The se-
mantic component of such complex constructions does not have to contain the
kind of ‘abstract’ or ‘vague’ characterizations that have apparently given monose-
my its bad name (Section 2.2). In fact, the semantic component of lower level
constructions will even be more concrete and specific than the ‘senses’ distin-
guished in the polysemous approach (Section 2.3). It may include, for instance,
subtle pragmatic information about the use of a given construction, as is most
clear for the kind of indirect speech act construction exemplified in (4).
However, when going up in the taxonomy to higher level constructions, the
semantic pole, unavoidably, gets more abstract or schematic. On the continuum
from lexicon to grammar, modal verbs may, in many respects, be considered gram-
matical words. Being auxiliaries, they can be combined with any other verb to
form a complex VP-construction. In other words, modal verbs have a great many
‘daughter constructions’ and their semantics, by definition, will thus be fairly ab-
stract. In Figure 5 and Figure 6, it is assumed that there is such a thing as a ‘kunnen
construction’, with the kind of vague semantics proposed in Figure 2 (cf. Janssen
2001 for a similar proposal for Dutch moeten ‘must’). In doing so, I may have
opened the door for ‘a ghost from the past’ (Section 1) or I may have committed
the generality fallacy (Section 2.2). However, I am not claiming that such a con-
struction is a psychologically real entity. In fact, I agree with Kay (2004) that it
cannot be determined on the basis of linguistic data whether or not language users
actually make this kind of generalization (cf. Sandra 1998). Still, “the relevant ob-
ligation of the grammarian (…) is to abstract from the data of the language, all the
generalizations (…) that a speaker-hearer might extract” (Kay 2004: nt.5; cf. Fortuin
& Boogaart 2009).
One issue that will have to constitute a primary concern in the future develop-
ment of constructionist approaches such as the one proposed in this paper con-
cerns the contribution of pragmatics. Clearly, construction grammar allows for a
great deal of pragmatics to be incorporated in the semantic component of con-
structions, but I am talking here specifically of pragmatics in a different sense,
namely to refer to general inferencing on the basis of linguistic and, particularly,
non-linguistic information. In the traditional monosemous approach, all aspects
of the interpretation of a modal except its ‘minimalist’ semantics was ‘left to prag-
matics’, so to speak (see Figure 2'). Because of its focus on form-meaning pairings,
and a wider conception of ‘form’, constructionist approaches depend significantly
less on such a general appeal to pragmatics. However, not everything in construction
 Ronny Boogaart

grammar can obviously be ‘left to syntax’. In some instances, the intended reading
of the modal will not be explicitly indicated at all and it is only linguistic informa-
tion across clause boundaries or non-linguistic information which can provide
clues as to its interpretation. It might be questioned, as it has been by Janssen
(2001), if it is possible to make a principled distinction between, for instance, de-
ontic readings of the modal that are triggered by clause-mate particles and those
that are triggered by non-linguistic features of the context of use, such as the hier-
archical relationship between speaker and addressee.

Notes

* Email: r.j.u.boogaart@hum.leidenuniv.nl. Thanks are due to Theo Janssen, Esther Pascual


and Olga Fischer as well as to the series editors and an anonymous reviewer for comments on an
earlier draft.
1. Many other different classifications of modal notions have been proposed in the literature.
In Section 3, I will argue that from a constructionist perspective on modals, the classification of
modal concepts loses much of its relevance.
2. I prefer to use the term monosemy rather than vagueness since, as I will argue below, con-
structions may be monosemous without being vague at all. See Noordegraaf (2005) on the his-
tory of the term monosemy.
3. A noteworthy exception is constituted by researchers working within the Columbia School
of linguistics, see Contini-Morava et al. (2004) for a recent collection of papers within this
framework, including a comparison with Cognitive Grammar (Langacker 2004).
4. In the same paper, Langacker takes a rather extreme monosemous view himself when it
comes to defining the ‘meaning’ of grammatical categories. Since modal verbs are, in many re-
spects, grammatical words (see Section 4), this might open the door for a monosemous analysis
of modals even on Langacker’s account. Indeed, in his other work, he attributes a highly sche-
matic semantics to the meaning of the English modals (e.g. Langacker 1990: 27).
5. This type of corpus is obviously too limited in size and genre (written literary fiction) to be
able to draw conclusions about the frequency of the readings in general, but it may be noted that
the results are quite similar to those arrived at in the large-scale research reported on by Nuyts
(2001). The distribution of the various modal readings differs significantly depending on genre:
whereas the epistemic reading, for instance, is relatively rare in general language corpora, it is
quite frequent in highly specific genres such as weather reports (Brantjes 2005).
6. The affirmative Dutch sentence in (6)a could get either an evidential, hear-say reading
(‘Someone told me that Vera is in bed already’) or a hypothetical/counterfactual reading (‘If Vera
were still alive, she would be in bed already.’).
7. There are subtle differences of a similar kind even between different varieties of Dutch.
Thus, northern standard Dutch as spoken in the Netherlands typically uses kunnen with the
verb vinden (‘to find’), whereas the southern variety of Dutch spoken in Belgium significantly
more often uses the verb vinden without kunnen. However, with other verbs, such as geloven
(‘to believe’) the situation is the reverse (Diepeveen et al. 2006: 33–39).
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

8. One might argue that modal verbs are grammatical rather than lexical items, but given the
basic principles of construction grammar, in particular principle 7b, this should not make a real
difference for the way they are treated within construction grammar (but see Section 4.).
9. The top node of the construction network in Figure5 is constituted by the lexical item kun-
nen (‘can’) and its abstract unitary meaning. Representing lexical items as higher level construc-
tions is not standard practice and it may seem counterintuitive, but it is just taking seriously the
theoretical claim of construction grammar that words are themselves constructions as well. Since
lexical items, per definition, have a great many ‘daughter constructions’ their position in the
network must be such that their form and meaning can be inherited by all of these daughters.
10. Therefore, monosemy goes hand in hand with complete inheritance (Kay & Fillmore 1999)
rather than with default inheritance (Goldberg 1995). One might argue, in fact, that complete
inheritance is the constructionist way of representing monosemy.
11. A similar situation is described for Old English by Fischer, who argues that this restriction
on the epistemic reading of modals provides evidence against the received view that the devel-
opment of the epistemic reading constitutes an instance of scope increase. Rather, “the modal
becomes epistemic only via a more elaborate construction type” (2007: 268).
12. Needless to say, in drawing Figure6 I have not even begun to draw the network for the
kunnen-constructions of Dutch – for one thing, two levels hardly make up a hierarchy or a tax-
onomy. The methodological problems involved in determining what exactly constitutes a con-
struction are manifold; excellent discussions of some of them are offered, for instance, by Wray
(2002) and Hoffmann (2004). Let me just say at this point that contrastive analysis of two or
more languages, such as reported on in Section 2.3, is an interesting way to bring to light collo-
cations and idioms, i.e. constructions, that may go unnoticed in language-specific research.

References

Barbiers, Lambertus C. J. (1995). The syntax of interpretation. The Hague: Holland Academic
Graphics.
Boogaart, Ronny (2007). Conditionele constructies met moest(en) en mocht(en) in Belgisch-
Nederlands en Nederlands-Nederlands. www.neerlandistiek.nl, 07.05.
Brantjes, Jenneke (2005). Modaliteit en constructiegrammatica. Doctoraalscriptie, Vrije Univer-
siteit Amserdam.
Coates, Jennifer (1983). The semantics of modal auxiliaries. London: Croom Helm.
Contini-Morava, Ellen, Robert S. Kirsner, & Betsy Rodríguez-Bachiller (Eds.) (2004). Cognitive
and communicative approaches to linguistic analysis. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Croft, William (1998). Linguistic evidence and mental representations. Cognitive Linguistics, 9,
151–173.
Croft, William (2001). Radical construction grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Croft, William & D. A. Cruse (2004). Cognitive Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Diepeveen, Janneke, Ronny Boogaart, Jenneke Brantjes, Pieter Byloo, Theo Janssen, & Jan Nuyts
(2006). Modale uitdrukkingen in Belgisch-Nederlands en Nederlands-Nederlands: corpusonder-
zoek en enquête. Amsterdam/Münster: Stichting Neerlandistiek VU/Nodus Publikationen.
 Ronny Boogaart

Diewald, Gabriele (2006). Context types in grammaticalization as constructions. Constructions.


Special Volume 1: Constructions all over – case studies and theoretical implications, Ed.
Doris Schönefeld. http://www.constructions-online.de/articles/specvol1/
Fischer, Olga (2007). Morpho-syntactic Change. Functional and Formal Perpectives. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Fortuin, Egbert (2000). Polysemy or monosemy: Interpretation of the imperative and the dative-in-
finitive construction in Russian. Amsterdam: Institute for Logic, Language and Computation.
Fortuin, Egbert & Ronny Boogaart (2009). Imperative as conditional: from constructional to
compositional semantics. Cognitive Linguistics, 20, 641–673.
Geeraerts, Dirk (1993). Vagueness’s puzzles, polysemy’s vagaries. Cognitive Linguistics, 4, 223–273.
Goldberg, Adele (1995). Constructions: a construction grammar approach to argument structure.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Goossens, Louis (1983). Can and kunnen: Dutch and English potential compared. In F. Daems,
L. Goossens (Eds.), Een spyeghel voor G. Jo Steenbergen, huldealbum aangeboden bij zijn
emeritaat (147–158). Leuven: Acco.
Haspelmath, Martin (2003). The geometry of grammatical meaning: semantic maps and cross-
linguistic comparison. In Michael Tomasello (Ed.), The new psychology of language: cognitive
and functional approaches to language structure (211–242). Mahwah, New Jersey & London:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Heine, Bernd (1995). Agent-oriented vs Epistemic modality: some observations on German
modals. In J. Bybee & S. Fleischman (Eds.), Modality in grammar and discourse (17–53).
Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Hoffmann, Sebastian (2004). Are low-frequency complex prepositions grammaticalized? On
the limits of corpus data – and the importance of intuition. In Hans Lindquist & Christian
Mair (Eds.), Corpus approaches to grammaticalization in English (171–210). Amsterdam/
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Janssen, Theo A. J. M. (2001). The semantics of Dutch moeten ‘must, should, have to’ from a ty-
pological and a relevance-theoretical perspective. In P. Bogaards et al. (Eds.), Quitte ou
double sens (109–133). Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi.
Kay, Paul & Charles J. Fillmore (1999). Grammatical constructions and linguistic generaliza-
tions: the What’s X doing Y? construction. Language, 75, 1–33.
Kay, Paul (2004). Pragmatic aspects of grammatical constructions. In G. Ward & L. Horn (Eds.),
Handbook of pragmatics (675–700). Oxford: Blackwell.
Kirsner, Robert (1993). From meaning to message in two theories: Cognitive and Saussurean
views of the modern dutch demonstratives. In R. Geiger and B. Rudzka-Ostyn (Eds.), Con-
ceptualizations and mental processing in language (80–114). Berlin and New York: Mouton
de Gruyter.
Kratzer, Angelika (1977). What must and can must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1,
337–355.
Kratzer, Angelika (1981). The notional category of modality. In H.J. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (Eds.),
Worlds, words, and contexts. (38–74). Berlin: De Gruyter.
Kratzer, Angelika (1991). Modality. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: an
international handbook of contemporary research (639–650). Berlin: De Gruyter.
Kronning, Hans (1996). Modalité, cognition et polysémie: sémantique du verbe modal devoir. Acta
Universitatis Upsaliensis (Studia Romanica Upsaliensia 54), Almqvist & Wiksell International.
Langacker, Ronald (1987). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar. Stanford: Standford University Press.
Langacker, Ronald (1990). Subjectification. Cognitive Linguistics, 1, 5–38.
Semantics and pragmatics in construction grammar 

Langacker, Ronald (2004). Form, meaning, and behavior: the Cognitive Grammar analysis of
double subject constructions. In E. Contini-Morava et al (Eds.), 21–60.
Langacker, Ronald (2005). Construction grammars: Cognitive, Radical, and less so. In Ruiz de
Mendoza, Francisco J. and Sandra Peña Cervel (Eds.), Cognitive Linguistics: Internal Dy-
namics and Interdisciplinary Interaction (101–159). Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Levinson, Stephen (2000). Presumptive meanings: the theory of generalized conversational impli-
cature. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Mortelmans, Tanja (2007). Modality in Cognitive Linguistics. In Geeraerts, D. and H. Cuyckens
(Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics (869–890). Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Narrog, Heiko (2005). On defining modality again. Language Sciences, 27, 165–192.
Noordegraaf, Jan (2005). Over monosemie: Bally, Humboldt, Hemsterhuis. In J. Noordegraaf
(Ed.), Een kwestie van tijd: vakhistorische studies (134–148). Münster: Nodus Publikationen.
Nuyts, Jan (2001). Epistemic modality, language and conceptualization: a cognitive-pragmatic
perspective. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Nuyts, Jan (2005). The modal confusion: on terminology and the concepts behind it. In A. Klinge
& H. H. Müller (Eds.), Modality: studies in form and function (5–38). London: Equinox.
Papafragou, Anna (2000). Modality: Issues in the semantics-pragmatics interface. Amsterdam:
Elsevier.
Perkins, Michael R. (1983). Modal expressions in English. London: Frances Pinter.
Sandra, Dominiek (1998). What linguists can and can’t tell you about the human mind: a reply
to Croft. Cognitive Linguistics, 9, 4, 361–478.
Stefanowitsch, Anatol (2003). A construction-based approach to indirect speech acts. In
Klaus-Uwe Panther & Linda Thornburg (Eds), Metonymy and pragmatic inferencing
(105–126). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins.
Sweetser, Eve E. (1990). From etymology to pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Traugott, Elizabeth C. (1989). On the rise of epistemic meanings in English: an example of sub-
jectification in semantic change. Language, 57, 33–65.
Tuggy, David (1993). Ambiguity, polysemy and vagueness. Cognitive Linguistics, 4, 273–291.
Van der Auwera, Johan & Vladimir A. Plungian (1998). Modality’s semantic map. Linguistic
Typology, 2, 79–124.
Van Ostaeyen, Gert & Jan Nuyts (2004). De diachronie van kunnen. Antwerp papers in Linguis-
tics 109.
Verhagen, Arie (2005). Constructions of intersubjectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wärnsby, Anna (2002). Modal constructions? The Department of English in Lund: Working Papers
in Linguistics 2. (http://www.englund.lu.se/images/stories/pdf-files/workingspapers/vol02)
Wray, Alison (2002). Formulaic language and the lexicon. Cambrdige: Cambridge University Press.
Index of constructions

A F R
Apodosis 193-209 Focus structure 145, 155-163, Reactive construction 100,
173, 175 103, 107
B I Responsive construction 99-
Bare Parenthesis Construc- Insubordinate parce que 47 100, 106
tion 58
J T
C ‘Joined’ ordering 146-189 Topicalization 127
Clausal integration 193, 197-210
Concessive repair 102-103, 109 M X
Content conditional 11, 193-194, Modality 84-87, 90, 214-219, X-och-x construction,
210 224-225, 227-228, 232-236 Swedish 99-109
Context focussing parce que
Construction 8, 45 P
Correlative then 195-197, 207, Participle / participial 9, 58, 65,
209 70-71, 76-77, 82-84, 86-87, 91
Predictive conditional 193-209
Subject index

A Construction Grammar 1-6, Dialogical theory 97


Abstractions from concrete ut- 8-12, 38, 43-44, 67-68, 97, 106- Discourse dependency 50
terances 95 108, 111, 113, 136, 181, 193, 201, Discourse pattern 50, 55-57, 64,
Activation status 132 209, 213-215, 220, 224, 229-231, 84, 86
Activity 113, 131-139 237, 239 Discourse topic 133, 205
Affordances 7, 35-38, 40, 41, 99 Constructional scheme 138 Discourse-familiarity 145, 152-
Affordances of physical settings Content conditional 11, 193-194, 157, 167, 174
35-37, 40 210
Allostruction 181-183, 186, 190 Context focussing parce que E
Alternativity 195, 204, 208-209 Construction 8, 45 Emphasis 21, 140, 145, 158, 170,
Apodosis 193-209 Context(s) 1-14, 17-42, 43-45, 197
49, 51-53, 57, 59, 60, 63-70, 72, Enabling condition 104
B 75-76, 79-93, 97-99, 102-103, Encyclopaedic knowledge 6, 11
Background 1, 5, 7-8, 20, 33-34, 105-109, 111-139, 146-147, 152, Evidence 11, 13, 26, 29, 33, 38-42,
44-48, 58, 67-68, 80, 84, 105, 154, 156, 158, 163-164, 166, 169, 45, 87, 90-92, 121, 151, 168,
121, 132-134, 152, 156, 159, 164, 171-174, 179-189, 195-197, 202, 188, 190, 193, 198-200, 209,
175, 188, 200, 204-205, 219, 225 207-208, 210, 216-219, 222, 218-219, 239
Bare Parenthesis Construction 58 227, 238, 240 Expectedness 166-171, 178-179
Contrast 56, 71, 92, 109, 112-113, External syntax (of construc-
C 123, 127, 129, 131, 135, 148, 157- tions) 75, 84, 88, 106-107
Can 12, 213-215, 239 160, 193, 197, 204-211 Extra-linguistic context 6-7, 18,
Clausal integration 193, 197-210 Contrastive focus 157-159 19, 22, 33, 166
Cognitive process 40, 97 Contrastivity 193, 204-209
Coherence 6, 55-56, 131-138 Conventionalization 65-66, 82, F
Common ground 5, 8, 10, 33, 37, 88-90, 216 Focus structure 145, 155-163,
43-46, 53-54, 59, 122-123 Conversation 4-5, 27, 42, 43, 61, 173, 175
Complexity 39, 40, 147-149, 153- 97, 100-106, 109-110, 111-115, Formal idiom 101
154, 186, 189 120-129, 132, 134, 137, 139-140, Formalisation 107
Compositional / non-compo- 166, 168, 219, 241 Form-function mapping 193,
sitional 2, 43, 66-67, 74, 76, Conversation Analysis 204, 209
82, 146 (CA) 4-5, 100, 111, 113, 121 Frame semantics 6, 9, 12, 23, 39,
Compositionality 68, 83, 107 Co-occurring constructions 104 67, 90, 168
Concessive repair 102-103, 109 Corpus data 3, 27, 37-38, 161, Frequency 2, 29, 32, 40, 90, 176,
Consciousness 108, 132 187, 240 186, 219, 226, 238
Constitutive role of context 23 Correlative then 195-197, 207, Function 1-5, 8-9, 14, 25, 29-32,
Constraints as construction 182 209 40, 45-49, 52-59, 63-68, 71-72,
Construct 23, 43-47, 106, 114, 122, Co-selection 104 74, 76, 82-83, 86-90, 93, 99,
127-128, 134, 138, 182, 193, 202 Cross-linguistic 111, 222, 224, 101, 105, 110, 111-115, 117, 120,
Construction 1-14, 27-42, 43-47, 226, 228, 232, 235 127-140, 145, 154, 177, 181, 190,
55, 57-60, 63, 65, 67-68, 83-94, Cypriot Greek 7, 27, 29, 32-33, 193, 195, 198, 200, 204-211, 213,
97-110, 111-140, 145-148, 150, 36-38, 40, 42 216, 225, 229, 231, 240-241
155, 161-164, 174-192, 193, 198, Functional potential 99, 101,
201, 209-211, 213-215, 220, D 105, 110, 131, 135-136, 140
222-241 Diachrony 3, 65-66, 68, 72, 88,
216, 219, 222, 229, 232
246 Subject index

G M Polysemy network 89, 221-227,


Gesetz der wachsenden Meaning 1-2, 6-12, 17-18, 21-26, 34, 231-233
Glieder 147 37, 39, 41, 43, 52-53, 57-59, 63-93, versus construction net-
Gibsonian affordances 7 97-101, 105-110, 114, 129-131, 139, work 232-233, 235-236, 239
Grammaticalization 1, 10, 13, 61, 172-173, 181, 189, 191, 193, 196, Potential 10, 25, 35-36, 65-66,
63, 67, 90-94, 93, 108, 138, 155, 199, 201, 209-211, 213-241 68, 71-78, 84, 86-99, 101, 105,
210, 216, 221-222, 235, 240 Meaning potential 10, 99, 105, 108-110, 114, 125, 131, 135-136,
108, 109, 139 139-140, 158, 164, 172, 180,
H Mental space 11, 193-211 228, 240
Homonymy 215-216, 220, 235 Method 105-107, 110 Pragmatic consequences 6-7,
Minimal context 7, 27, 29-36, 21-22, 26, 37
I 40, 42 Pragmatic role 132
Iconic / iconicity 11, 47-48, 53, Minimalism 107, 108 Predictive conditional 193-209
55, 59, 185, 208-209 Mixed-category morphology 67 Prefaces 30, 32
Illocutionary force 7, 9, 18, 26- Modal verb 213-216, 222, 227- Processing hypothesis 174-179
27, 32-33, 35, 37, 40, 49-50, 53, 228, 235 Pronoun(s) 10, 36, 71, 73, 112,
200, 208 Deontic 213-214, 216-225, 228, 116-130, 135, 137, 145-155, 170,
Incrementality of interpreta- 232-238 187, 210, 225
tion 33, 35 Dynamic 5, 21, 39, 63, 97-98, Protasis 197, 206, 208-209
Indirect speech act 12, 18, 216, 107, 115, 171-172, 213-225, Prototype 68-69, 79, 81, 221
225, 237 228, 232-236
Generality fallacy 219-220, Epistemic 47, 59, 213-215, Q
235 218-224, 227-228, 232-236, Qualitative 19-20, 121
Polysemy fallacy 223 238-239 Quantitative 60-61, 105, 119, 121
Rule-list fallacy 219-220, Modality 84-87, 90, 214-219,
223, 232 224-225, 227-228, 232-236 R
Inflectional form 84, 163 Modeling 145, 181 Reactive construction 100,
Inflectional paradigm 9, 66, Moeten 214, 235, 237 103, 107
70, 87 Monosemy 12, 214-215, 217-219, Recontextualization of gram-
Inheritance network 45, 57-58, 224, 228-229, 231-232, 237-239 mar 181
Insubordinate parce que 47 Motivation 27, 82, 84, 145, 181 Reference 7, 18, 26, 37, 41, 49, 56,
Interactional linguistics (IL) 10, Must 214, 235, 237 58, 66, 71, 76, 123, 131-138
99, 109, 111, 113, 136, 138 Region 112, 146, 163-165, 177-178,
Inversion 197, 199 O 180, 184-185, 211
One clause at a time 98, 110 Register 2, 40, 91, 107, 146, 163-
J Other-responsive 101 166, 176
‘Joined’ ordering 146-189 Relevance 7-8, 39, 44, 91, 145,
P 154, 197-200, 204-210, 218,
K Participle / participial 9, 58, 65, 220, 226, 240
Knowledge of the world 19, 166 70-71, 76-77, 82-84, 86-87, 91 Requests 27, 29-32
Kunnen 12, 213-228, 231-234, Particle placement 3, 10-11, Responsive construction 99-
236-239 145-192 100, 106
Perspective 6, 11, 36, 39, 64, 80, Resumption 197-201, 204, 206,
L 82, 87-88, 114, 117, 120, 133, 135, 208-210
Language variation and 175, 181, 192, 201, 209, 213-216,
change 65 218-219, 221, 225, 229, 231, S
Lectal factors 164-166 236, 238 Semantic map 235 -236
Length 23, 145, 147-149, 152-155, Politeness 32, 39, 41-42, 168, Schematic idiom 101
167, 176-178, 186, 187, 189, 208, 211 Self-responsive 101-104
191, 231 Polysemy / polysemous struc- Semantic network / semantic
Lexical restrictions 150-151 ture / emerging polysemy 3, space 68-69, 82, 89
Lexico-grammatical change 63 66, 87, 89, 213-215, 217, 219- Sequential context 97, 99
Lexico-grammatical network 88 229, 231-233, 237 Sequential position 131-132, 136
Literalness 172-174, 176, 189
Subject index 247

Shared knowledge 5, 120, Syntactic persistence 163, 189 V


129-130 Syntactic priming 11, 163, 191 Vagueness 214, 217-218, 223,
Social action and interaction 97 226, 232, 238
Speech act 2, 7, 11-12, 18, 28-33, T Valence 68, 70-71, 73-75, 77, 79,
41-42, 52, 108, 114, 193-210, Token frequency 29, 32 84, 86, 130
216, 225, 237, 241 Topic 2, 127, 132-136, 139, 152
Speech-act conditionals 11, 193, Topicalization 127 W
195, 197-210 Truth conditions 8, 17-18 Weight 145, 147-155, 172, 177-178,
Split ordering 146-148, 151-152, Type frequency 29 183, 186, 189, 197
157-179, 184-189 Written language 8, 164
Spoken language 3, 42, 45, 61, U
90, 92, 97, 111-112, 115, 119-120, Unaccented pronoun 145-146, X
137, 138 149, 151-152, 155, 187 X-och-x construction,
Stativity 171-172, 179-180 Usage events 98-99, 105, 108, Swedish 99-109
Syntactic integration 58, 193, 223
197, 201
In the series Constructional Approaches to Language the following titles have been published
thus far or are scheduled for publication:

9 Bergs, Alexander and Gabriele Diewald (eds.): Contexts and Constructions. 2009. v, 247 pp.
8 Barðdal, Jóhanna: Productivity. Evidence from Case and Argument Structure in Icelandic. 2008.
xiii, 209 pp.
7 Hilpert, Martin: Germanic Future Constructions. A usage-based approach to language change. 2008.
ix, 205 pp.
6 Iwata, Seizi: Locative Alternation. A lexical-constructional approach. 2008. xiv, 239 pp.
5 Leino, Jaakko (ed.): Constructional Reorganization. 2008. vi, 155 pp.
4 Fried, Mirjam and Hans C. Boas (eds.): Grammatical Constructions. Back to the roots. 2005.
viii, 246 pp.
3 Östman, Jan-Ola and Mirjam Fried (eds.): Construction Grammars. Cognitive grounding and
theoretical extensions. 2005. viii, 325 pp.
2 Fried, Mirjam and Jan-Ola Östman (eds.): Construction Grammar in a Cross-Language Perspective.
2004. vi, 209 pp.
1 Kuno, Susumu and Ken-ichi Takami: Functional Constraints in Grammar. On the unergative–
unaccusative distinction. 2004. ix, 242 pp.

You might also like