Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 53

Rethinking Knowledge The Heuristic

View 1st Edition Carlo Cellucci (Auth.)


Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/rethinking-knowledge-the-heuristic-view-1st-edition-c
arlo-cellucci-auth/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Heuristic Search: The Emerging Science of Problem


Solving 1st Edition Saïd Salhi (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/heuristic-search-the-emerging-
science-of-problem-solving-1st-edition-said-salhi-auth/

Knowledge Graph and Semantic Computing Language


Knowledge and Intelligence Second China Conference CCKS
2017 Chengdu China August 26 29 2017 Revised Selected
Papers 1st Edition Juanzi Li
https://textbookfull.com/product/knowledge-graph-and-semantic-
computing-language-knowledge-and-intelligence-second-china-
conference-ccks-2017-chengdu-china-august-26-29-2017-revised-
selected-papers-1st-edition-juanzi-li/

The Event of Meaning in Gadamer's Hermeneutics 1st


Edition Carlo Davia

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-event-of-meaning-in-
gadamers-hermeneutics-1st-edition-carlo-davia/

Knowledge Engineering and the Semantic Web 5th


International Conference KESW 2014 Kazan Russia
September 29 October 1 2014 Proceedings 1st Edition
Pavel Klinov
https://textbookfull.com/product/knowledge-engineering-and-the-
semantic-web-5th-international-conference-kesw-2014-kazan-russia-
september-29-october-1-2014-proceedings-1st-edition-pavel-klinov/
Rethinking the American Labor Movement 1st Edition
Elizabeth Faue

https://textbookfull.com/product/rethinking-the-american-labor-
movement-1st-edition-elizabeth-faue/

Ductal Carcinoma in Situ of the Breast 1st Edition


Carlo Mariotti (Eds.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/ductal-carcinoma-in-situ-of-the-
breast-1st-edition-carlo-mariotti-eds/

Rethinking Mahler 1st Edition Jeremy Barham

https://textbookfull.com/product/rethinking-mahler-1st-edition-
jeremy-barham/

Applications of Modern Heuristic Optimization Methods


in Power and Energy Systems 1st Edition Kwang Y. Lee

https://textbookfull.com/product/applications-of-modern-
heuristic-optimization-methods-in-power-and-energy-systems-1st-
edition-kwang-y-lee/

Discrete Calculus Methods for Counting 1st Edition


Carlo Mariconda

https://textbookfull.com/product/discrete-calculus-methods-for-
counting-1st-edition-carlo-mariconda/
European Studies in Philosophy of Science

Carlo Cellucci

Rethinking
Knowledge
The Heuristic View
European Studies in Philosophy of Science

Volume 4

Series editors
Dennis Dieks, Institute for History & Foundations of Science, Utrecht University,
The Netherlands
Maria Carla Galavotti, Università di Bologna, Italy
Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, University of A Coruña, Spain

Editorial Board
Daniel Andler, University of Paris-Sorbonne, France
Theodore Arabatzis, University of Athens, Greece
Diderik Batens, Ghent University, Belgium
Michael Esfeld, University of Lausanne, Switzerland
Jan Faye, University of Copenhagen, Denmark
Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo, Norway
Stephan Hartmann, University of Munich, Germany
Gurol Irzik, Sabancı University, Turkey
Ladislav Kvasz, Charles University, Czech Republic
Adrian Miroiu, National School of Political Science and Public Administration,
Romania
Elizabeth Nemeth, University of Vienna, Austria
Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland
Samir Okasha, University of Bristol, UK
Katarzyna Paprzycka, University of Warsaw, Poland
Tomasz Placek, Jagiellonian University, Poland
Demetris Portides, University of Cyprus, Cyprus
Wlodek Rabinowicz, Lund University, Sweden
Miklos Redei, London School of Economics, UK
Friedrich Stadler, University of Vienna, Austria
Gereon Wolters, University of Konstanz, Germany
This new series results from the synergy of EPSA - European Philosophy of Science
Association - and PSE - Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective: ESF
Networking Programme (2008–2013). It continues the aims of the Springer series
“The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective” and is meant to give a new
impetus to European research in the philosophy of science. The main purpose of the
series is to provide a publication platform to young researchers working in Europe,
who will thus be encouraged to publish in English and make their work internationally
known and available. In addition, the series will host the EPSA conference
proceedings, selected papers coming from workshops, edited volumes on specific
issues in the philosophy of science, monographs and outstanding Ph.D. dissertations.
There will be a special emphasis on philosophy of science originating from Europe.
In all cases there will be a commitment to high standards of quality. The Editors will
be assisted by an Editorial Board of renowned scholars, who will advise on the
selection of manuscripts to be considered for publication.

More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/13909


Carlo Cellucci

Rethinking Knowledge
The Heuristic View
Carlo Cellucci
Department of Philosophy
Sapienza University of Rome
Rome, Italy

ISSN 2365-4228     ISSN 2365-4236 (electronic)


European Studies in Philosophy of Science
ISBN 978-3-319-53236-3    ISBN 978-3-319-53237-0 (eBook)
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-53237-0

Library of Congress Control Number: 2017934078

© Springer International Publishing AG 2017


This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of
the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation,
broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information
storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology
now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the
editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors
or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims
in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Printed on acid-free paper

This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature


The registered company is Springer International Publishing AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Preface

From its very beginning, philosophy has been viewed as aimed at knowledge and
methods to acquire knowledge. In the past century, however, this view of philoso-
phy has been generally abandoned, with the argument that, unlike the sciences,
philosophy does not rely on experiments or observation but only on thought.
The abandonment of the view that philosophy aims at knowledge and methods to
acquire knowledge has contributed to the increasing irrelevance of the subject, so
much so that several scientists, and even some philosophers, have concluded that
philosophy is dead and has dissolved into the sciences. The question then arises
whether philosophy can still be fruitful, and what kind of philosophy can be such.
In order to answer this question, this book attempts to revive the view that phi-
losophy aims at knowledge and methods to acquire knowledge. Reviving it requires
a rethinking of knowledge. The importance of such rethinking depends on the cen-
tral role knowledge plays in human life. In particular, a rethinking of knowledge
requires a rethinking of mathematical knowledge, which raises special problems.

Rome, Italy Carlo Cellucci

v
Acknowledgments

I first presented some of the ideas on knowledge developed in this book in


“Rethinking Knowledge,” Metaphilosophy 46 (2015), pp. 213–234, and some of the
ideas on mathematical knowledge developed in this book in Filosofia e Matematica,
Rome, Laterza, 2002, and in “Philosophy of Mathematics: Making a Fresh Start,”
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013): 32–42.
In writing this book, I have drawn from a number of earlier essays, although in
most cases I have substantially rewritten the material in question. I thank Springer
for the permission to draw from this material. In Chap. 2, I use material from
“Rethinking Philosophy,” Philosophia 42 (2014), pp. 271–288; in Chap. 5, material
from “Is Philosophy a Humanistic Discipline?,” Philosophia 43 (2015), pp. 259–
269; in Chaps. 8 and 9, material from “Knowledge, Truth and Plausibility,”
Axiomathes 24 (2014), pp. 517–532; in Chap. 13, material from “Models of Science
and Models in Science,” in Models and Inferences in Science, ed. Emiliano Ippoliti,
Fabio Sterpetti, and Thomas Nickles, Springer, Cham 2016, pp. 95–112; in Chap.
20, material from “Is Mathematics Problem Solving or Theorem Proving?,”
Foundations of Science 22 (2017), pp. 183–199; and in Chap. 23, material from
“Mathematical Beauty, Understanding, and Discovery,” Foundations of Science 20
(2015), pp. 339–355.
I am grateful to many people for the help they gave me, either reading a chapter
and making remarks, raising questions in correspondence, or making comments at
seminars or conferences. For their help in whatever form, I am especially indebted
to Atocha Aliseda, Arthur Bierman, Angela Breitenbach, Mirella Capozzi, Anjan
Chakravartty, Riccardo Chiaradonna, Tom Clark, Pascal Engel, Michèle Friend,
Roger Frye, Maria Carla Galavotti, Donald Gillies, Norma Goethe, Emily Grosholz,
Robert Hanna, Reuben Hersh, Hansmichael Hohenegger, Danielle Macbeth, David
B. Martens, Nicholas Maxwell, Thaddeus Metz, Dan Nesher, Thomas Nickles,
Aaron Preston, Nicholas Rescher, Howard Sankey, Stephen P. Schwartz, Hourya
Benis Sinaceur, Nathalie Sinclair, Fabio Sterpetti, Robert Thomas, Francesco Verde,
Alan White, Jan Woleński, and Semir Zeki. This does not mean that they share the
views expressed in this book or are in any way responsible for any remaining
inaccuracies.

vii
viii Acknowledgments

I am also grateful to an anonymous referee for useful comments and suggestions


and to Arlette Dupuis for reading the manuscript and suggesting several linguistic
improvements.
Contents

1 Introduction.............................................................................................. 1
1.1 Philosophy and the Birth of Modern Science............................... 1
1.2 Radical Answers............................................................................ 2
1.3 Moderate Answers........................................................................ 2
1.4 Death of Philosophy?.................................................................... 3
1.5 Criticisms by Scientists................................................................. 4
1.6 Why Still Philosophy?.................................................................. 5
1.7 Aim of the Book............................................................................ 5
1.8 Organization of the Book.............................................................. 6
1.9 Conventions................................................................................... 7
References.................................................................................................. 7

Part I The Nature of Philosophy


2 The Heuristic View................................................................................... 11
2.1 The Characteristics of Philosophy................................................ 11
2.2 Philosophy and the World............................................................. 12
2.3 Philosophy and Globality.............................................................. 13
2.4 Philosophy and Essential Problems.............................................. 14
2.5 Philosophy and Knowledge.......................................................... 14
2.6 Philosophy and the Armchair........................................................ 16
2.7 Philosophy and the Sciences......................................................... 16
2.8 Philosophy and the Results of the Sciences.................................. 17
2.9 Philosophy and Method................................................................ 18
2.10 Philosophy and the Aim to Acquire Knowledge.......................... 19
2.11 Philosophy and the Aim to Obtain Rules of Discovery................ 20
2.12 Philosophy and the Birth of New Sciences................................... 21
2.13 Philosophy and the History of Philosophy.................................... 22
2.14 Philosophy and Intuition............................................................... 23

ix
x Contents

2.15 Philosophy and Emotion............................................................... 24


2.16 Philosophy and the Solvability of Problems................................. 25
2.17 Philosophy and Progress............................................................... 25
2.18 Philosophy and Professionalization.............................................. 26
2.19 The Heuristic View vs. Philosophy as Criticism of Principles..... 27
References.................................................................................................. 28
3 The Foundationalist View........................................................................ 31
3.1 The Foundationalist View and the Architectural Metaphor.......... 31
3.2 The First Assumption of the Foundationalist View....................... 32
3.3 The Second Assumption of the Foundationalist View.................. 33
3.4 Frege’s and Russell’s Foundational Programs for Mathematics... 34
3.5 Russell’s Alternative Foundational Program for Mathematics..... 35
3.6 Hilbert’s Foundational Program for Mathematics........................ 36
3.7 Russell’s Foundational Program for Empirical Knowledge.......... 36
3.8 Inadequacy of the Architectural Metaphor................................... 37
3.9 The Weak Foundationalist View.................................................... 37
3.10 The Alleged Death of Epistemology............................................. 38
References.................................................................................................. 39
4 The Limits of Scepticism......................................................................... 41
4.1 The Question of Sceptical Doubt.................................................. 41
4.2 The Sceptical Doubts Raised by Two Ancient Schools................ 42
4.3 Aristotle’s Argument Against the Two Schools............................ 43
4.4 Limits of Aristotle’s Solution........................................................ 44
4.5 Self-Defeating Character of the Two Schools............................... 45
4.6 Sextus Empiricus’ Indeterminacy Doubt...................................... 46
4.7 Descartes’ Dream Doubt............................................................... 47
4.8 Descartes’ Demon Doubt.............................................................. 48
4.9 Hume’s Induction Doubt............................................................... 50
4.10 Scepticism, Mysticism, and the Foundationalist View.................. 51
References.................................................................................................. 52
5 Philosophy and the Humanistic Disciplines........................................... 53
5.1 The View That Philosophy Is a Humanistic Discipline................ 53
5.2 Relation with a Non-analytic Tradition......................................... 54
5.3 What Is Scientism, Really?........................................................... 55
5.4 Sciences and the World as It Is in Itself........................................ 55
5.5 Sciences and the Independence of Perspective............................. 55
5.6 Sciences and the Absolute Conception......................................... 56
5.7 Philosophy as Different from the Sciences................................... 56
5.8 Philosophy and History................................................................. 57
5.9 Continuity with the Philosophical Tradition................................. 58
5.10 Theoretical and Practical Knowledge........................................... 59
5.11 The Humanistic Disciplines Revisited.......................................... 61
References.................................................................................................. 61
Contents xi

Part II The Nature of Knowledge


6 Knowledge and Naturalism..................................................................... 65
6.1 What Is Knowledge?..................................................................... 65
6.2 A Naturalistic Approach to Knowledge........................................ 67
6.3 The Biological Role of Knowledge.............................................. 68
6.4 Knowledge as a Natural Process................................................... 70
6.5 Knowledge and Consciousness..................................................... 70
6.6 Knowledge and Evolution............................................................. 71
6.7 Cultural Role of Knowledge......................................................... 72
6.8 Biological Evolution and Cultural Evolution................................ 73
6.9 Objections to the Continuity View................................................ 74
6.10 Science and Evolution................................................................... 75
6.11 Mathematics and Evolution.......................................................... 76
6.12 Objections to the Dependence of Mathematics on Evolution....... 77
6.13 Evolution and Teleology............................................................... 78
6.14 Remarks on a Different Naturalistic Approach to Knowledge..... 79
6.15 A Theistic Objection to Naturalism.............................................. 79
References.................................................................................................. 80
7 Knowledge and Reality............................................................................ 83
7.1 The Relation of Knowledge to Reality......................................... 83
7.2 Direct Realism.............................................................................. 83
7.3 Representative Realism................................................................. 84
7.4 Scientific Realism......................................................................... 85
7.5 Liberalized Scientific Realism...................................................... 86
7.6 Mathematical Structural Realism.................................................. 87
7.7 Semantic Structural Realism......................................................... 88
7.8 Essentialist Realism...................................................................... 89
7.9 Subjective Idealism....................................................................... 90
7.10 Phenomenalism............................................................................. 90
References.................................................................................................. 91
8 Knowledge and Truth.............................................................................. 93
8.1 The Aim of Science and Truth...................................................... 93
8.2 Truth as Correspondence............................................................... 94
8.3 Concept of Truth and Criterion of Truth....................................... 95
8.4 Truth as Correspondence and Scientific Realism.......................... 96
8.5 Impossibility of a Criterion of Truth............................................. 97
8.6 An Alleged Rehabilitation of Truth as Correspondence............... 97
8.7 Truth as Intuition of the Essence................................................... 99
8.8 Truth and Modern Science............................................................ 100
8.9 Absoluteness Claims..................................................................... 101
8.10 Alternative Concepts of Truth....................................................... 102
xii Contents

8.11 Truth as Consistency..................................................................... 102


8.12 Truth as Systematic Coherence..................................................... 103
8.13 Truth as Satisfiability.................................................................... 104
8.14 Truth as Provability....................................................................... 104
8.15 Truth and Mythology.................................................................... 105
References.................................................................................................. 106
9 Knowledge, Plausibility, and Common Sense........................................ 107
9.1 Plausibility in Place of Truth........................................................ 107
9.2 Plausibility as Different from Truth.............................................. 108
9.3 Plausibility as Different from Probability..................................... 109
9.4 Plausibility as Different from Warranted Assertibility.................. 109
9.5 Plausibility and Endoxa................................................................ 110
9.6 Knowledge and Our Ways of Apprehending the World................ 111
9.7 Limitations of the Human Cognitive Apparatus........................... 111
9.8 The Relevance of Such Limitations.............................................. 112
9.9 Knowledge and Things in Themselves......................................... 113
9.10 Common Sense Knowledge and Scientific Knowledge................ 114
9.11 Common Sense Knowledge and Innate Knowledge..................... 115
9.12 Common Sense Knowledge and Scientific Realism..................... 116
References.................................................................................................. 117
10 Other Questions About Knowledge........................................................ 119
10.1 Objectivity as Independence of Any Subject................................ 119
10.2 Objectivity as the View from Nowhere......................................... 120
10.3 Objectivity as Plausibility............................................................. 121
10.4 Mathematical Knowledge and Plausibility................................... 122
10.5 Certainty........................................................................................ 123
10.6 Intuition......................................................................................... 124
10.7 Fallible Intuition............................................................................ 126
10.8 Deduction...................................................................................... 127
10.9 Rigour........................................................................................... 128
References.................................................................................................. 129

Part III The Methods to Acquire Knowledge


11 A Discourse on Method........................................................................... 133
11.1 The Need for Method.................................................................... 133
11.2 The Denial of a Logic of Discovery.............................................. 134
11.3 Discovery and the Romantic Myth of Genius............................... 135
11.4 Discovery and Serendipity............................................................ 136
11.5 Discovery and Deductive Logic.................................................... 137
11.6 The Denial of Method................................................................... 138
11.7 Method and Rationality................................................................. 139
Contents xiii

11.8 The Psychology of Discovery....................................................... 141


11.9 An Attempt to Trivialize Discovery.............................................. 142
11.10 Heuristic vs. Algorithmic Methods............................................... 142
11.11 Algorithmic Methods, Discovery, and Justification...................... 143
11.12 Consequences of the Denial of Method........................................ 144
11.13 The Alleged Obsoleteness of Method........................................... 145
11.14 The Vindication of Method........................................................... 146
References.................................................................................................. 147
12 The Methods of Knowledge..................................................................... 149
12.1 The Analytic Method.................................................................... 149
12.2 Original Formulation of the Analytic Method.............................. 150
12.3 Origin of the Analytic Method...................................................... 152
12.4 Analytic Method and Infinite Regress.......................................... 153
12.5 The Open-Ended Character of Rules of Discovery....................... 154
12.6 Non-ampliativity of Deductive Rules........................................... 154
12.7 Objections to the Non-Ampliativity of Deductive Rules.............. 155
12.8 The Plausibility Test Procedure.................................................... 156
12.9 Inference Rules, Plausibility, and Experience............................... 157
12.10 Inference Rules and Usefulness.................................................... 157
12.11 Basic Features of the Analytic Method......................................... 158
12.12 Analytic Method and Abduction................................................... 160
12.13 Fortune of the Analytic Method.................................................... 161
12.14 The Analytic-Synthetic Method.................................................... 162
12.15 Original Formulation of the Analytic-Synthetic Method.............. 163
12.16 Difference Between the Analytic
and the Analytic-­Synthetic Method.............................................. 164
12.17 Analytic-Synthetic Method and Intuition..................................... 165
12.18 The Material Axiomatic Method................................................... 165
12.19 Original Formulation of the Material Axiomatic Method............. 166
12.20 The Formal Axiomatic Method..................................................... 167
12.21 Original Formulation of the Formal Axiomatic Method............... 167
12.22 Motivations of the Formal Axiomatic Method.............................. 168
12.23 The Axiomatic Method................................................................. 170
References.................................................................................................. 170
13 Modelling Scientific Knowledge............................................................. 173
13.1 Models of Science and Models in Science................................... 173
13.2 The Analytic-Synthetic Model...................................................... 173
13.3 The Analytic-Synthetic Model and Modern Science.................... 174
13.4 The Fading Out of Analysis.......................................................... 175
13.5 The Hypothetico-Deductive Model............................................... 176
13.6 The Hypothetico-Deductive Model and Closed Systems............. 176
13.7 The Analytic-Synthetic Model, the Hypothetico-­
Deductive Model and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems............ 177
13.8 An Alleged Way Out of Incompleteness....................................... 177
xiv Contents

13.9 Other Limitations of the Hypothetico-Deductive Model.............. 178


13.10 The Semantic Model..................................................................... 178
13.11 The Analytic Model...................................................................... 179
13.12 The Analytic Model and Open Systems........................................ 179
13.13 The Analytic Model and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems....... 180
13.14 An Example of Use of the Analytic Model.................................. 180
13.15 The Neglect of the Analytic Model............................................... 181
13.16 Models in Science......................................................................... 182
13.17 The Analytic-Synthetic Model, the
Hypothetico-­Deductive Model and Models in Science................ 183
13.18 The Semantic Model and Models in Science................................ 183
13.19 Scientific Realism and Models in Science.................................... 184
13.20 The Analytic Model and Models in Science................................. 184
References.................................................................................................. 185
14 Knowledge as Problem Solving............................................................... 187
14.1 Knowledge and Problems............................................................. 187
14.2 The Nature of Problems................................................................ 188
14.3 Problem Posing............................................................................. 189
14.4 Problem Solving............................................................................ 190
14.5 The Steps of Problem Solving...................................................... 190
14.6 Meno’s Paradox............................................................................. 192
14.7 Knowledge as Problem Solving and Certainty............................. 193
14.8 Remarks on a Different View of Knowledge
as Problem Solving....................................................................... 193
14.9 A Priori Knowledge...................................................................... 194
14.10 A Priori Knowledge, Individual, and Species............................... 195
14.11 A Priori Knowledge, Trial and Error, and Innate Knowledge...... 196
References.................................................................................................. 198
15 Perceptual Knowledge............................................................................. 199
15.1 Philosophical and Psychological Theories of Perception............. 199
15.2 The View That Vision is a Passive Process................................... 200
15.3 Vision and Mental Images............................................................ 200
15.4 Vision as Problem Solving............................................................ 201
15.5 Vision and the Limitations of the Eye........................................... 203
15.6 Evidence for Vision as Problem Solving...................................... 204
15.7 Objections to Vision as Problem Solving..................................... 208
15.8 Vision and Movement................................................................... 209
15.9 Vision and Touch........................................................................... 210
References.................................................................................................. 211
16 Knowledge and Error.............................................................................. 213
16.1 The Heterogeneity View................................................................ 213
16.2 Limitations of the Heterogeneity View......................................... 214
16.3 Logic and Error............................................................................. 215
16.4 Mathematics and Error.................................................................. 216
Contents xv

16.5 Demonstration and Error............................................................... 217


16.6 Fruitfulness of Error...................................................................... 218
16.7 Error and the Rationality of Hypothesis Formation...................... 219
References.................................................................................................. 220
17 Knowledge and Mind............................................................................... 221
17.1 The View of Disembodied Knowledge......................................... 221
17.2 Shortcomings of the View of Disembodied Knowledge............... 222
17.3 The View of Embodied Knowledge.............................................. 223
17.4 Objections and Replies to the View
of Embodied Knowledge.............................................................. 224
17.5 Processes Internal and Processes External to the Mind................ 225
17.6 Examples of Processes External to the Mind................................ 225
17.7 Strengthening of the Mind with External Processes..................... 228
17.8 External Processes and Brain Plasticity........................................ 229
17.9 The Mind as an Incomplete Cognitive System............................. 230
17.10 Distributed Character of Knowledge............................................ 231
17.11 Knowledge and Other Minds........................................................ 231
References.................................................................................................. 232

Part IV The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge


18 Mathematics as Problem Solving........................................................... 235
18.1 A Global Approach to the Nature
of Mathematical Knowledge......................................................... 235
18.2 The Relevance of Philosophy to Mathematics.............................. 236
18.3 Philosophy of Mathematics and Philosophy of Mathematicians.. 237
18.4 Basic Limitations of Classical Philosophy of Mathematics......... 238
18.5 Natural Mathematics..................................................................... 240
18.6 Natural Mathematics and Evolution............................................. 241
18.7 Artificial Mathematics.................................................................. 242
18.8 Mathematics and Truth................................................................. 243
18.9 Mathematics and Plausibility........................................................ 244
18.10 Origin of the View That Mathematics Is Problem Solving........... 245
18.11 An Objection to the View that Mathematics
is Problem Solving........................................................................ 246
18.12 Mathematics and Intuition............................................................ 247
References.................................................................................................. 248
19 Mathematical Objects, Definitions, Diagrams...................................... 251
19.1 What Mathematics Is About.......................................................... 251
19.2 Mathematical Platonism................................................................ 252
19.3 Limitations of Mathematical Platonism........................................ 253
19.4 Early Modern Philosophers and Mathematical Objects................ 256
19.5 Mathematical Objects as Hypotheses........................................... 256
19.6 The Mental-Cultural Reality of Mathematical Objects................ 257
xvi Contents

19.7 Features of Mathematical Objects as Hypotheses........................ 258


19.8 Mathematical Fictionalism............................................................ 259
19.9 Hypotheses vs. Fictions................................................................ 260
19.10 Mathematical Definitions.............................................................. 261
19.11 Hybrids ........................................................................................ 264
19.12 Mathematical Diagrams................................................................ 264
19.13 Objections Against the Use of Mathematical Diagrams............... 265
References.................................................................................................. 270
20 Mathematics: Problem Solving or Theorem Proving?......................... 273
20.1 Problem Solving vs. Theorem Proving......................................... 273
20.2 Mathematicians’ Views on the Method of Mathematics............... 274
20.3 The Top-Down and the Bottom-Up Approach
to Mathematics.............................................................................. 275
20.4 Analytic vs. Axiomatic Method.................................................... 275
20.5 Problems vs. Theorems................................................................. 277
20.6 Opposition or Different Emphasis?............................................... 278
20.7 Hilbert on the Method of Mathematics......................................... 279
20.8 Breaking the Balance.................................................................... 281
20.9 The Axiomatic Ideology............................................................... 282
20.10 Hilbert on the Regressive Task...................................................... 283
20.11 Axiomatic Method and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems......... 284
20.12 Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems
and Recalcitrant Mathematicians.................................................. 284
20.13 The Impossibility of Achieving Hilbert’s Aim............................. 285
20.14 Analytic Method and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems............ 287
20.15 Other Shortcomings of the Axiomatic Method............................. 287
20.16 Other Advantages of the Analytic Method................................... 288
20.17 A Problematic View...................................................................... 289
20.18 Answering the Dilemma............................................................... 290
References.................................................................................................. 290
21 Concepts of Demonstration..................................................................... 293
21.1 Axiomatic and Analytic Demonstration....................................... 293
21.2 A Priori and A Posteriori Demonstration..................................... 294
21.3 Axiomatic and Analytic Theory.................................................... 295
21.4 A Limitation of Axiomatic Demonstration................................... 295
21.5 An Alleged Way Out for Axiomatic Demonstration..................... 296
21.6 A Further Limitation of Axiomatic Demonstration...................... 297
21.7 The Demand for Purity of Methods.............................................. 298
21.8 Impossibility of Satisfying the Demand
for Purity of Methods.................................................................... 299
21.9 The Point of Analytic Demonstration........................................... 300
21.10 Analytic Demonstration and Intuition.......................................... 301
21.11 Analytic Demonstration and Depth.............................................. 302
21.12 Analytic Demonstration and Published Demonstrations.............. 303
Contents xvii

21.13 The Purpose of Axiomatic Demonstration................................... 304


21.14 An Objection to the Heuristic Purpose
of Analytic Demonstration............................................................ 306
21.15 Axiomatic Demonstration and Formal Demonstration................. 307
21.16 Analytic Demonstration and Subformula Property....................... 308
21.17 Deductive Demonstration.............................................................. 309
21.18 Analytic Demonstration and Evolution......................................... 310
21.19 Mathematical Styles...................................................................... 311
21.20 The Heuristic View vs. the Foundationalist
View of Mathematics.................................................................... 312
References.................................................................................................. 313
22 Mathematical Explanations.................................................................... 315
22.1 Mathematical Explanations of Mathematical Facts...................... 315
22.2 The Deductive View of Explanation............................................. 316
22.3 Aristotle on Explanations.............................................................. 317
22.4 Descartes on Explanations............................................................ 319
22.5 Static and Dynamic Approach to Explanatory
Demonstrations............................................................................. 319
22.6 Explanatory Demonstrations and Published
Demonstrations............................................................................. 320
22.7 The Rhetorical Role of Axiomatic Demonstration....................... 321
22.8 Functions of Explanatory Demonstrations.................................... 322
22.9 Relevance to Mathematical Practice............................................. 322
22.10 Global and Local View of Mathematical Explanations................ 323
22.11 Mathematical Explanations and Mathematical
Understanding............................................................................... 324
22.12 The Nature of Mathematical Understanding................................. 324
22.13 Explanatory Demonstrations and Mathematical
Understanding............................................................................... 325
22.14 Explanatory Demonstrations and Memorability........................... 326
22.15 Mathematical Explanations of Empirical Facts............................ 327
22.16 The Honeycomb Problem............................................................. 327
22.17 The Magicicada Problem.............................................................. 329
22.18 The Königsberg Bridges Problem................................................. 330
22.19 Mathematical Explanations and Pythagoreanism......................... 331
22.20 Mathematical Explanations and Mathematical Platonism............ 332
References.................................................................................................. 333
23 Mathematical Beauty............................................................................... 335
23.1 Aesthetic Judgments and the Neuroscience of Aesthetics............ 335
23.2 Two Different Traditions About Mathematical Beauty................. 336
23.3 Mathematical Beauty as an Intrinsic Property.............................. 337
23.4 Mathematical Beauty as a Projection of the Subject.................... 338
23.5 Rota’s Phenomenology of Mathematical Beauty.......................... 340
23.6 Some Limitations of Rota’s Views................................................ 341
xviii Contents

23.7 Mathematical Beauty and Perception........................................... 342


23.8 From Enlightenment to Understanding......................................... 343
23.9 Beauty in Works of Art................................................................. 344
23.10 Beauty in Demonstrations............................................................. 345
23.11 An Example of a Beautiful Demonstration................................... 346
23.12 Differences in Beauty Between
Geometrical Demonstrations........................................................ 347
23.13 Differences in Beauty Between
Arithmetical Demonstrations........................................................ 349
23.14 An Example of a Beautiful Theorem............................................ 349
23.15 Mathematical Beauty and Discovery............................................ 351
23.16 An Example of the Role of Beauty in Discovery.......................... 353
23.17 Epistemic Role of the Aesthetic Factors....................................... 355
References.................................................................................................. 355
24 Mathematics and the World.................................................................... 357
24.1 Mathematical Objects and Abstraction......................................... 357
24.2 Mathematical Objects and Idealization......................................... 358
24.3 Mathematical Objects and Hypotheses......................................... 359
24.4 Mathematics and Applicability..................................................... 360
24.5 Natural Mathematics and the World............................................. 361
24.6 Artificial Mathematics and the World........................................... 361
24.7 The Theistic Account.................................................................... 362
24.8 The Parallelism Account............................................................... 362
24.9 The Friendly Universe Account.................................................... 363
24.10 The Mapping Account................................................................... 363
24.11 Galileo’s Philosophical Revolution and Mathematics.................. 364
24.12 The Fusion of Mathematics and Physics...................................... 365
24.13 Limits to the Applicability of Mathematics.................................. 366
24.14 Mathematics and Simplicity......................................................... 367
24.15 Mathematics and Simplification................................................... 368
24.16 Mathematics and Approximations................................................ 369
24.17 The Applicability of Mathematics and Evolution......................... 370
24.18 Explaining the Pre-established Harmony...................................... 371
References.................................................................................................. 372

Part V Coda
25 Knowledge and the Meaning of Human Life........................................ 377
25.1 Knowledge and Purpose and Meaning of Human Life................. 377
25.2 Purpose and Meaning of Human Life and Evolution................... 378
25.3 Purpose and Meaning of Human Life and God............................ 379
25.4 Why God?..................................................................................... 380
25.5 Belief in God and Rationality....................................................... 381
25.6 Morality and God.......................................................................... 382
Contents xix

25.7 Intelligibility of the World and Naturalism................................... 382


25.8 Purpose and Meaning of Human Life from
an External Point of View............................................................. 383
25.9 Purpose and Meaning of Human Life from
an Internal Point of View.............................................................. 384
25.10 Happiness and the Purpose and Meaning of Human Life............. 385
25.11 Happiness and Knowledge............................................................ 387
25.12 The Nature of Happiness.............................................................. 388
25.13 Seeking Happiness in One’s Individual Life................................. 389
25.14 Brevity and Value of Human Life................................................. 390
25.15 Knowledge as a Precondition of Happiness.................................. 390
References.................................................................................................. 391
26 Conclusion................................................................................................ 393
26.1 The Challenge to Philosophy........................................................ 393
26.2 The Nature of Philosophy............................................................. 394
26.3 The Nature of Knowledge............................................................. 394
26.4 The Relation of Knowledge to Reality......................................... 395
26.5 The Objectivity of Knowledge...................................................... 395
26.6 The Question of Discovery........................................................... 395
26.7 Modelling Scientific Knowledge.................................................. 396
26.8 Knowledge as Problem Solving.................................................... 396
26.9 The Nature of Perceptual Knowledge........................................... 397
26.10 The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge...................................... 397
26.11 The Nature of Mathematical Objects............................................ 398
26.12 Mathematics and Intuition............................................................ 398
26.13 The Nature of Mathematical Demonstration................................ 399
26.14 Mathematical Explanations........................................................... 399
26.15 The Applicability of Mathematics................................................ 400
26.16 The Role of Knowledge in Human Life........................................ 400

Bibliography..................................................................................................... 401

Index.................................................................................................................. 419
Chapter 1
Introduction

Abstract By invading many areas traditionally covered by philosophy, modern sci-


ence has made philosophy increasingly irrelevant, and has presented it with the
challenge to legitimate itself. This challenge has not been successfully met, so much
so that several scientists, and even some philosophers, have concluded that philoso-
phy is dead and has dissolved into the sciences. The question then arises whether
philosophy can still be fruitful, and what kind of philosophy can be such. This book
attempts to give an answer to this question, reviving the ancient view that philoso-
phy is the acquiring of knowledge. This involves rethinking knowledge and meth-
ods to acquire knowledge, including mathematical knowledge, which raises special
problems. In addition to describing the aim of the book, the introduction briefly
describes the parts and the individual chapters of the book, and outlines some con-
ventions adopted in the book.

1.1 Philosophy and the Birth of Modern Science

“One ought either to philosophize or say goodbye to life and depart hence, because,”
as compared with philosophy, “all other things seem to be a lot of nonsense and
foolishness” (Aristotle, Protrepticus Düring, 110).
Is this praise of philosophy even conceivable today? The question is justified,
because in the seventeenth century philosophy suffered a trauma from which it has
not recovered yet, the birth of modern science. The latter has invaded many areas
traditionally covered by philosophy. As a result, the role of philosophy has become
problematic, and philosophy has come to need legitimation in the face of science.
Thus Gadamer states that, “since the seventeenth century,” what “we today call
philosophy is found to be in a changed situation. It has come to need legitimation in
the face of science in a way that had never been true before” (Gadamer 1998, 6).
In fact, since the seventeenth century, a great deal of philosophy has been an
attempt to provide an answer to the trauma caused by the birth of modern science.
There have been both radical answers and moderate answers.

© Springer International Publishing AG 2017 1


C. Cellucci, Rethinking Knowledge, European Studies in Philosophy of Science 4,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-53237-0_1
2 1 Introduction

1.2 Radical Answers

A radical answer is that, with the birth of modern science, philosophy has nothing
left to speak of, because all questions about which one can say anything sensible
belong to the sciences.
Thus, Wittgenstein states that “the correct method in philosophy would really be
the following: to say nothing except what can be said, i.e. propositions of natural
science – i.e. something that has nothing to do with philosophy” (Wittgenstein
2002, 6.53). For, “philosophy is not one of the natural sciences” (ibid., 4.111).
This answer, however, is unsatisfactory, because it assumes that the whole field
of knowledge is exhausted by the present sciences. Such assumption is unjustified
because, as research proceeds, new questions arise which are essentially beyond the
present sciences, and may even give rise to new sciences.
Another radical answer, but opposite to the previous one, is that the sciences do
not give knowledge, only philosophy provides access to knowledge.
Thus, Heidegger states that “science does not think” (Heidegger 1968, 8). It “is
the disavowal of all knowledge of truth” (Heidegger 1994, 5). Therefore, “no one
who knows will envy scientists – the most miserable slaves of modern times” (ibid.,
6). Science aims at exactness and security but, with its “insistence on what is
demonstrable,” it blocks “the way to what-is” (Heidegger 1972, 72). Only philoso-
phy opens the way to what-is, because “philosophy is the knowledge of the essence
of things” (Heidegger 1994, 29).
This answer, however, is unsatisfactory, because the assumption that only phi-
losophy opens the way to what-is has no foundation. There is no special source of
knowledge which is available to philosophy but not to science.

1.3 Moderate Answers

A moderate answer is that we must admit that philosophy is not yet a science. While
no one would doubt the objective character of mathematics and natural sciences, the
same cannot be said of philosophy. A revolution in philosophy is necessary if phi-
losophy is to acquire the character of a rigorous science.
Thus, Husserl states that philosophy is still “incapable of giving itself the form
of actual science” (Husserl 2002, 250). It “does not merely have a doctrinal system
at its disposal that is incomplete and imperfect in one respect or another, but has
none whatsoever. Anything and everything is controversial here, every position-­
taking is a matter of individual conviction’” (ibid., 251). But, “the highest interests
of human culture demand the elaboration of a rigorously scientific philosophy”
(ibid., 253). So, “if a philosophical revolution is to prove itself in our time, it must
always be animated by the intention to found philosophy anew in the sense of rigor-
ous science” (ibid.).
1.4 Death of Philosophy? 3

This answer, however, is unsatisfactory, because philosophy has no specific field


of its own, therefore all attempts to give philosophy the character of a rigorous sci-
ence have been unsuccessful. Husserl wants to develop a philosophy that is a “uni-
versal science of the world, universal, definitive knowledge, the universe of truths in
themselves about the world, the world in itself” (Husserl 1970, 335). He aims at
“the discovery of the necessary concrete manner of being of absolute subjectivity”
in a “life of constant ‘world-constitution’” (ibid., 340). He also aims at “the new
discovery, correlative to this, of the ‘existing world’,” which “results in a new mean-
ing for what, in the earlier stages, was called world” (ibid.). His attempt, however,
fails because, starting from absolute subjectivity, Husserl arrives at the discovery,
not of the existing world, but only of a world as a correlative of subjectivity.
Another moderate answer, but opposite to the previous one, is that we must aban-
don the idea that science is the paradigmatic human activity, and hence philosophy
should try to become a science. Science has no privileged position with respect to
philosophy, both science and philosophy must be evaluated in terms of their capac-
ity to achieve the aims we would like to achieve through them.
Thus, Rorty criticizes the logical empiricists who maintained that “science was
the paradigmatic human activity,” and “what little there was to say about other areas
of culture amounted to a wistful hope that some of them (e.g., philosophy) might
themselves become more ‘scientific’” (Rorty 1991–2007, I, 46). Science has no
privileged position with respect to philosophy. Both science and philosophy must be
evaluated in terms of their capacity “to be reliable guides to getting what we want”
(Rorty 1999, 33).
This answer, however, is unsatisfactory, because Rorty states that we philoso-
phers “are not here to provide principles of foundations or deep theoretical diagno-
ses, or a synoptic vision” (ibid., 19). When we are asked what we “take contemporary
philosophy’s ‘mission’ or ‘task’ to be,” the best we “can do is to stammer that we
philosophy professors are people who have a certain familiarity with a certain intel-
lectual tradition,” and “can offer some advice about what will happen when you try
to combine or to separate certain ideas, on the basis of our knowledge of the results
of past experiments” (ibid., 19–20). But “we are not the people to come to if you
want confirmation that the things you love with all your heart are central to the
structure of the universe” (ibid., 20). That is, we philosophers are not the people to
come to if you want to have an answer to the questions you are most interested in.
This makes philosophy into a marginal activity with little utility.

1.4 Death of Philosophy?

The inadequacy of these answers to the trauma caused by the birth of modern sci-
ence, makes one doubt that trying to legitimate philosophy is a feasible enterprise.
This doubt is strengthened by the fact that, in the past century, some philosophers
have affirmed that philosophy is dead and has dissolved into the sciences.
4 1 Introduction

Thus, Quine states that philosophy, and specifically epistemology, or theory of


knowledge, has dissolved into psychology, because “the stimulation of his sensory
receptors is all the evidence anybody has had to go on, ultimately, in arriving at his
picture of the world. Why not just see how this construction really proceeds? Why
not settle for psychology?” (Quine 1969, 75). The “old epistemology aspired to
contain, in a sense, natural science; it would construct it from sense data.
Epistemology in its new setting, conversely, is contained in natural science, as a
chapter of psychology” (ibid., 83). Epistemology “simply falls into place as a chap-
ter of psychology and hence of natural science” (ibid., 82).
Heidegger states that “the sciences are now taking over as their own task what
philosophy in the course of its history tried to present in part, and even there only
inadequately, that is, the ontologies of the various regions of beings (nature, history,
law, art)” (Heidegger 1972, 58). The “development of philosophy into the indepen-
dent sciences” is “the legitimate completion of philosophy. Philosophy is ending in
the present age. It has found its place in the scientific attitude of socially active
humanity” (ibid.). The “end of philosophy means the completion” of philosophy,
where “however, completion does not mean perfection as a consequence of which
philosophy would have to have attained the highest perfection at its end” (ibid., 56).
On the contrary, completion means “the end of philosophy in the sense of its com-
plete dissolution into the sciences” (Heidegger 1998, 259, footnote).
But, if philosophy is dead and has dissolved into the sciences, then it is impos-
sible to try to legitimate it in the face of science.

1.5 Criticisms by Scientists

That philosophy is dead and has dissolved into the sciences is also the opinion of
many scientists.
Thus Hawking states that questions such as “What is the nature of reality? Where
did all this come from? Did the universe need a creator?” are traditionally “ques-
tions for philosophy, but philosophy is dead. Philosophy has not kept up with mod-
ern developments in science, particularly physics. Scientists have become the
bearers of the torch of discovery in our quest for knowledge” (Hawking and
Mlodinow 2010, 5).
Dyson states that, “compared with the giants of the past,” the present philoso-
phers “are a sorry bunch of dwarfs,” which compels us to ask: “When and why did
philosophy lose its bite? How did it become a toothless relic of past glories?”
(Dyson 2012).
Krauss states that “science progresses and philosophy doesn’t,” and “the worst
part of philosophy is the philosophy of science; the only people” who “read work by
philosophers of science are other philosophers of science. It has no impact on phys-
ics what so ever,” so “it’s really hard to understand what justifies it” (Andersen 2012).
Therefore, Pinker asserts that “philosophy today gets no respect. Many scientists
use the term as a synonym for effete speculation” (Pinker 2002, 11). What a difference
1.7 Aim of the Book 5

between this spiteful attitude toward philosophy, and the appreciative attitude of
Galileo, who stated that he had “studied for a greater number of years in philosophy
than months in pure mathematics” (Galilei 1968, X, 353).

1.6 Why Still Philosophy?

Since some philosophers and many scientists have affirmed that philosophy is dead
and has dissolved into the sciences, we must ask: Why still philosophy? Can phi-
losophy still be fruitful, and what kind of philosophy can be such? In particular,
what kind of philosophy can be legitimized in the face of science? Asking these
questions is nothing really new, because philosophy has always called into question
everything, including itself. But, with the birth of modern science, such questions
have become more pressing, as well as more difficult and embarrassing.
Some philosophers, however, scorn these questions. Thus, Popper states that a
philosopher “should try to solve philosophical problems, rather than talk about phi-
losophy” (Popper 1974, 68).
Rorty states that questions about “the nature of philosophical problems” are
“likely to prove unprofitable” (Rorty 1992, 374).
Williams states that “philosophy is not at its most interesting when it is talking
about itself” (Williams 2006, 169).
But this amounts to taking for granted that philosophy can still be fruitful. This
is unjustified because, as we have seen, it contrasts with the opinion of some phi-
losophers and many scientists. This makes it necessary to call philosophy into
question.

1.7 Aim of the Book

This book aims to give an answer to the question whether philosophy can still be fruit-
ful, and what kind of philosophy can be such. Briefly, its answer is that philosophy
can still be fruitful only if it aims at knowledge and methods to acquire knowledge,
because knowledge plays a central role in human life. To a large extent, we are what
we know, we reflect reality, and reality is for us what we have access to and we know.
Generally our aspirations, desires and hopes essentially depend on what we know.
The view that philosophy aims at knowledge and methods to acquire knowledge
may be called the heuristic view, because ‘heuristic’ is said of methods which guide
to acquire knowledge. Developing the heuristic view of philosophy requires a
rethinking of logic and a rethinking of knowledge. A rethinking of logic has been
carried out in Cellucci 2013a. A rethinking of knowledge is the aim of this book.
There are, however, some minor overlappings with Cellucci 2013a, which are moti-
vated by the desire to make the book self-contained.
6 1 Introduction

The questions about knowledge discussed in this book do not exhaust all ques-
tions about knowledge. Every investigation is a potentially infinite task, and this
book is no exception. However, the questions discussed in this book are essential for
the development of a fruitful philosophy.

1.8 Organization of the Book

In order to highlight the organization of the book, the text is divided into five parts,
after the present Introduction which occurs as Chapter 1.
Part I examines the nature of philosophy. Chapter 2 presents the heuristic view,
according to which philosophy aims at knowledge and methods to acquire knowl-
edge. Chapter 3 discusses the foundationalist view, according to which philosophy
aims to justify already acquired knowledge. Chapter 4 argues that the main motiva-
tion for the foundationalist view, namely, to save knowledge from sceptical doubt,
is unfounded, because absolute scepticism is not logically irrefutable. Chapter 5
argues against the view that philosophy is a humanistic discipline, opposed to the
sciences.
Part II examines the nature of knowledge. Chapter 6 explains the central role that
knowledge plays in human life. Chapter 7 examines several views about the relation
of knowledge to reality. Chapter 8 discusses the view that the aim of science is truth,
and considers several concepts of truth. Chapter 9 maintains that the aim of science
is plausibility, it distinguishes plausibility from truth, probability, and warranted
assertibility, and discusses the relation of science to common sense. Chapter 10
considers the relations of knowledge to certainty, objectivity, intuition, and
deduction.
Part III examines the methods to acquire knowledge. Chapter 11 maintains that
it is unjustified to say that there is no method to acquire knowledge. Chapter 12
considers various methods to acquire knowledge. Chapter 13 discusses various
models of science, and to what extent they are capable of accounting for models in
science. Chapter 14 maintains that knowledge is problem solving by the analytic
method. Chapter 15 maintains that perceptual knowledge is also problem solving by
the analytic method. Chapter 16 discusses the relation of knowledge to error.
Chapter 17 considers the relation of knowledge to mind.
Part IV examines the nature of mathematical knowledge. Chapter 18 maintains
that mathematics is problem solving by the analytic method. Chapter 19 discusses
the nature of mathematical objects, mathematical definitions, and mathematical dia-
grams. Chapter 20 argues that mathematics is not theorem proving. Chapter 21
examines various notions of demonstration. Chapter 22 considers the question of
mathematical explanation of mathematical facts, and the question of mathematical
explanation of empirical facts. Chapter 23 discusses the nature of mathematical
beauty, and its role in mathematical discovery. Chapter 24 considers the relation of
mathematics to the world.
References 7

Part V ends and completes the book. Chapter 25 examines the connection
between knowledge and the purpose and meaning of human life. Chapter 26 sum-
marizes some of the main theses of the book.

1.9 Conventions

Constant use of ‘he or she’ may be clumsy, while constant use of ‘she’ may give rise
to misunderstandings. Therefore, I use the generic ‘he’, while stipulating here that I
mean it to refer to persons of both genders.
When I quote Greek expressions, I use the so-called scientific transliteration
from the Greek to the Latin alphabet.
When I quote from ancient Greek philosophers, and even from some modern
philosophers, translations are mine unless stated otherwise. This is motivated by the
fact that every translation is an interpretation, and the interpretations given in this
book are often different from those on which current translations are based.
Moreover, current translations of different works of the same author by different
translators may be inconsistent with each other, so quoting from them would lead to
misunderstandings.

References

Andersen, Ross. 2012. Has physics made philosophy and religion obsolete? Interview to Lawrence
Krauss. The Atlantic, April 23.
Cellucci, Carlo. 2013a. Rethinking logic: Logic in relation to mathematics, evolution, and method.
Dordrecht: Springer.
Dyson, Freeman. 2012. What can you really know? The New York Review of Books 59(17,
November 8): 18–20.
Gadamer, Hans Georg. 1998. Reason in the age of science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Galilei, Galileo. 1968. Opere. Florence: Barbera.
Hawking, Stephen, and Leonard Mlodinow. 2010. The grand design. New York: Bantam Books.
Heidegger, Martin. 1968. What is called thinking? New York: Harper & Row.
———. 1972. On time and being. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
———. 1994. Basic questions of philosophy: Selected ‘problems’ of ‘logic’. Bloomington: Indiana
University Pres.
———. 1998. Pathmarks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology.
Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
———. 2002. Philosophy as rigorous science. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and
Phenomenological Philosophy 2: 249–295.
Pinker, Steven. 2002. The blank slate. The modern denial of human nature. London: Penguin
Books.
Popper, Karl Raimund. 1974. Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge.
London: Routledge.
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1969. Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia
University Press.
8 1 Introduction

Rorty, Richard. 1991–2007. Philosophical papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


———. 1992. Twenty-five years after. In The linguistic turn: Essays in philosophical method, ed.
Richard Rorty, 371–374. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
———. 1999. Philosophy and social hope. London: Penguin Books.
Williams, Bernard. 2006. Philosophy as a humanistic discipline. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2002. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge.
Part I
The Nature of Philosophy
Chapter 2
The Heuristic View

Abstract As a response to the increasing irrelevance of philosophy, this chapter


lists the characteristics philosophy should have in order to be fruitful. This results in
a view of philosophy that may be called the heuristic view, according to which phi-
losophy aims at knowledge and methods to acquire knowledge. In listing the char-
acteristics philosophy should have according to the heuristic view, the chapter
systematically compares them with those of classical analytic philosophy. This is
motivated by the fact that, in the past century, classical analytic philosophy has been
the prevailing philosophical tradition. The characteristics of philosophy listed in the
chapter are not intended to suggest that philosophies without such characteristics
are bad, but only that they cannot be expected to be legitimized in the face of
science.

2.1 The Characteristics of Philosophy

This part of the book examines the nature of philosophy. In the Introduction, the
question has been raised as to whether philosophy can still be fruitful and what kind
of philosophy can be such. This chapter answers the question, listing the character-
istics philosophy should have in order to be fruitful and legitimized in the face of
science. This results in the formulation of a view of philosophy that, as already
stated in the Introduction, may be called the heuristic view of philosophy.
In listing the characteristics philosophy should have according to the heuristic
view, this chapter systematically compares them with those of classical analytic
philosophy. This is motivated by the fact that, in the past century, classical analytic
philosophy has been the prevailing philosophical tradition.
Here, ‘classical analytic philosophy’ refers to the philosophical tradition started
by Russell and Moore, which developed through Wittgenstein and logical positivism,
knowing a moment of particular fortune with the Oxford ordinary language school of
philosophy, and had several followers in the second half of the twentieth century.
Dummett includes Frege in this tradition, saying that Frege “was the true father of
analytical philosophy” (Dummett 2007, 27). This, however, is controversial. For
example, Carl states that “Frege is not an analytic philosopher” (Carl 1994, 24).
In this chapter, special reference is made to Wittgenstein, since he is widely rec-
ognized as the single most significant figure in classical analytic philosophy.

© Springer International Publishing AG 2017 11


C. Cellucci, Rethinking Knowledge, European Studies in Philosophy of Science 4,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-53237-0_2
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
of Cortés, that he had come of his own free-will, and at the intimation
of the gods, to stay awhile with his guests. He told them to calm the
people with this assurance, and to disperse the gathering.

FOOTNOTES
[490] They had now been four days in Mexico, without going farther than the
palace, says Bernal Diaz. A page named Orteguilla, who had already acquired a
smattering of Aztec, was sent with the interpreters to ask this favor. Hist. Verdad.,
69.

[491] Soldiers who had been in Rome and Constantinople declared that never had
they seen so large and orderly a market, with so large an attendance. Bernal Diaz
indicates the site of the plaza to have been where the church of Santiago de
Tlatelulco was erected, and this still remains under the same name, over a mile
north-west-by-north of the central plaza of Mexico. Hist. Verdad., 70-1. The old
maps of Mexico already spoken of give the same site, and Alaman’s investigations
point out correctly the street which led and leads to it, although he has failed to
notice the above authorities, which give the very site. Disert., ii. 282-5.

[492] It has been generally accepted that the temple in the centre of the city was
visited, but Bernal Diaz, who is the only narrator of this excursion, states distinctly,
in several places, that the pyramid ascended was situated in the Tlatelulco
market-place, ‘adonde está aora señor Santiago, que se dize el Tlatelulco.’ Hist.
Verdad., 70-1. The description of the temple court and interior is somewhat
confused, and evidently combines points which belong to the central temple.

[493] Hence the contradictions between descriptions and views furnished by


different chroniclers, which have so greatly puzzled modern writers.

[494] Bernal Diaz, Hist. Verdad., 70-1. Sigüenza y Góngora, the well-known
Mexican scholar of the seventeenth century, follows Bernal Diaz. Anotaciones
Crit., MS., 1-2.

[495] ‘No dexarian de quedar aprobechados ... y satisfacer a su necesidad,’ says


Vetancurt, who knew the avarice of his countrymen too well to believe in denials.
Teatro, pt. iii. 131. Bernal Diaz says that Yañez, as the servant of Velazquez de
Leon and Lugo, revealed the discovery to them, and they told Cortés. The soldiers
all heard of it, and came quietly to gaze on the treasures, which rumor had already
located somewhere in the palace. ‘Being then a young man,’ says the old soldier,
‘and having never seen such wealth, I felt sure that there was not anything like it in
the world.’ Hist. Verdad., 72; Herrera, dec. ii. lib. viii. cap. ii. Tapia and Gomara
state that Cortés discovered the door-way as he was walking in his room one
evening, pondering on his plans for seizing Montezuma. ‘Cerro la puerta ... por no
escandalizar a Motecçuma, no se estoruasse por esso su prisiõ.’ Gomara, Hist.
Mex., 123; Tapia, Rel., in Icazbalceta, Col. Doc., ii. 579. Duran intimates that on
hearing of the existence of treasures in the palace, the Spaniards, including the
‘Santo Clérigo,’ occupied themselves more in searching for them than in
promoting the faith. They did not find them, however, till Montezuma revealed the
hiding-place, under the pressure of questions and, it seems, of hunger. Hist. Ind.,
MS., ii. 445-6.

[496] He refers to this promise in the second letter to the king, saying, ‘porque
certifiqué á V. A. que lo habria preso ó muerto ó súbdito.’ Cortés, Cartas, 52.

[497] ‘En la verdad era así é lo tinien acordado,’ affirms Tapia, Rel., in Icazbalceta,
Col. Doc., ii. 579. ‘Estas nueuas, falsas, o verdaderas,’ is the non-committing
phrase of Gomara. Hist. Mex., 123. Ixtlilxochitl takes firmer ground. ‘According to
an original letter in my possession, signed by the three heads of New Spain, and
written to his Majesty the emperor, our master, they exculpate Motecuhzoma and
the Mexicans of this and other charges, declaring them inventions of the
Tlascaltecs and of some Spaniards who feared that they would never see the hour
when they might leave the city and place in security the riches they had obtained.’
Hist. Chich., 296. Clavigero adopts the view that Cortés called for such testimony
from certain chiefs among his allies, whose dislike of the Mexicans would be sure
to prompt it. ‘Per giustificar vieppiù il suo attentato, e muovere i suoi Spagnuoli ad
eseguirlo, fece chiamar parecchie persone principali de’ suoi alleati (la cui
informazione dovrebbe sempre essergli sospettosa).’ Storia Mess., iii. 90-1.
Vetancurt has a story that, a drought prevailing at the time, the Spaniards induced
the heavens by means of masses and prayers to send rain. This made the priests
and idols jealous, and the emperor was prevailed on to rid himself of the
Spaniards. The Tlascaltecs learned of the plot and reported it. Teatro, pt. iii. 130.

[498] According to Bernal Diaz the members of this council suggested not only the
seizure but the reasons for it. Cortés responded that he had not been oblivious of
the danger, but saw not how the seizure could be effected. The captains proposed
to beguile the prince to their quarter and detain him. If Cortés hesitated they were
willing to undertake the task. The old soldier is evidently misled, as he was in the
scuttling affair, to assume too much credit for himself and his fellow-soldiers.
Cortés had no doubt adopted his common tactics, so frequently admitted by
Bernal Diaz himself, of inspiring his comrades to suggest what he had resolved
on. This is proved by the promise made to the emperor in his first letter, four
months before, to capture Montezuma.

[499] Bernal Diaz, Hist. Verdad., 73, followed by a number of other writers, states
that the letter was received at Mexico the morning after this meeting, but it has
been shown that he must be wrong. He mentions as one of the statements in the
letter that the Totonacs were in revolt, and it is probable that Cortés may have said
so to show the soldiers that retreat was cut off, and that seizure was the only
recourse.

[500] As both Peter Martyr and Gomara call it.

[501] The neglect of this less speedy plan does indicate that the rumors of danger
were credited to a great extent at least.

[502] Hist. Verdad., 74. Cortés in his quiet way writes to the king that, after
passing six days in the great city, and finding that for various reasons ‘it suited the
royal interest and our safety to have this lord in my power, and not wholly at liberty,
lest he change in the proposal and desire manifested to serve Y. H.... I resolved to
seize and place him in the quarter where I was.’ Cartas, 88-9.

[503] ‘Mandó que su gente dos á dos ó cuatro á cuatro se fuesen tras él ... é con
él entramos hasta treinta españoles é los demas quedaban á la puerta de la casa,
é en un patio della,’ says Tapia, who appears to have been one of those who
entered. Rel., in Icazbalceta, Col. Doc., ii. 579.

[504] ‘Cõ armas secretas,’ says Gomara, Hist. Mex., 123, and probably they did
bear extra weapons beneath their cloaks.

[505] ‘Y otras hijas de señores á algunos de mi compañía.’ Cortés, Cartas, 89. But
the customary mark of favor was to give them from his harem. See Native Races,
ii.

[506] ‘Per non dar disgusto al Re, e per avere occasione di farla Cristiana,’ is
Clavigero’s excuse for the acceptance. Storia Mess., iii. 93. Brasseur de
Bourbourg, and some other writers, assume that Cortés declined; but the original
authorities all say or intimate that he accepted. Even Cortés himself writes in his
letter to the emperor, ‘despues ... de haberme él dado algunas joyas de oro y una
hija suya,’ etc. Cartas, 89. ‘Le persuadió,’ says Ixtlilxochitl, Hist. Chich., 290.
Gomara is even more explicit, and Herrera says that Montezuma insisted, ‘porque
queria tener nietos de hombre tan valeroso.’ dec. ii. lib. viii. cap. ii. The affair is
perhaps less important in itself than as index to the character of Cortés, who could
accept so intimate an offer with one hand while he prepared a blow with the other.
It might also be made to indicate that Montezuma could have had no base designs
against him when he made the uncalled-for offer of intrusting a daughter (if such
she was) to his keeping. Still the imperial character would not have suffered had it
been shown that this was but an artifice to lull his intended victim into a false
security.

[507] Some authors, like Herrera and Torquemada, say that he denied all
knowledge of the occurrence, calling it an invention of enemies.

[508] Ixtlilxochitl, Hist. Chich., 297. ‘Q̄ tenia la figura de Vitzilopuchtli,’ Gomara,
123; and so says Bernal Diaz. Tapia states that Montezuma told Cortés to send
two Spaniards with the messengers; but he doubtless declined to risk two lives on
such a trip. Rel., in Icazbalceta, Col. Doc., ii. 583-4.

[509] ‘Ingrato rey!’ exclaims Gallo, in commenting upon this surrender of a devoted
officer. Hombres Ilust. Mex., i. 318.

[510] Bernal Diaz makes Cortés accuse the emperor of perfidy, and of having
instigated the Cholula massacre. Hist. Verdad., 74. But this he would hardly do,
since his purpose was clearly to persuade, not to arouse anger.

[511] ‘No querria començar guerra, ni destruir aquesta Ciudad ... que si alboroto, ò
vozes daua, que luego sereis muerto de aquestos mis Capitanes, que no los
traigo para otro efeto,’ is Bernal Diaz’ blunt version. Hist. Verdad., 74.

[512] ‘Auia tenido platica de su idolo Huichilobos ... que convenia para su salud, y
guardar su vida, estar con nosotros.’ Id., 75.

[513] ‘Estuuieron mas de media hora en estas platicas.’ Id., 74. Tapia and others
say four hours, which is unlikely.

[514] ‘Porque mas vale que desta vez asseguremos nuestras vidas, ò las
perdamos.’ Bernal Diaz, Hist. Verdad., 75.

[515] ‘Era, ó muy falto de ánimo, ó pusilánime, ó muy prudente.’ Oviedo, iii. 289.
‘En él se cumplió lo que de él se decia, que todo hombre cruel es cobarde,
aunque á la verdad, era ya llegada la voluntad de Dios.’ Ixtlilxochitl, Rel., 411.

[516] Bernal Diaz intimates clearly enough that no demonstration was made till
after his arrival. Hist. Verdad., 75. And so does Cortés. ‘Llorando lo tomaron en
ella [the litter] con mucho silencio, y así nos fuimos hasta el aposento donde
estaba, sin haber alboroto en la ciudad, aunque se comenzó á mover. Pero sabido
por el dicho Muteczuma, envió a mandar que no lo hubiese; y así, hubo toda
quietud.’ Cartas, 90. Ixtlilxochitl, however, allows Montezuma to stay long enough
in his palace, after ordering the litter, to enable the lords and nobles to come and
offer their services. A delay like this, which the Spaniards certainly never could
have permitted, might have given time for the tumultuous gathering which he
describes. Hist. Chich., 297. Prescott, in following this version, makes the emperor
so far overstep his usual dignity as to ‘call out’ to the people to disperse. ‘Tambien
detuvieron consigo á Itcuauhtzin, gobernador del Tlatilulco,’ says Sahagun, while
the leading nobles ‘cuando fue preso Mocthecuzoma le desampararon y se
escondieron.’ Hist. Conq., 25.
The seizure has, like the equally prominent episodes of the massacre at
Cholula, and the scuttling of the fleet, aroused no little comment in justification or
condemnation. ‘Now that I am old,’ says Bernal Diaz, ‘I stop to consider the heroic
deeds then performed, and I do say that our achievements were not effected by
ourselves, but were all brought about by God; for what men have existed in the
world who, less than 450 soldiers in number, dared to enter into so strong a city as
Mexico, larger than Venice, and so remote from Castile, to seize so great a lord?’
Hist. Verdad., 76. ‘Never Greek or Roman, nor of other nation, since kings exist,
performed a like deed, only Fernando Cortés, to seize Motecçuma, a king most
powerful, in his own house, in a place most strong, amid an infinity of people,
while possessing but 450 companions.’ Gomara, Hist. Mex., 124. Commenting on
this, Torquemada adds that ‘it was indeed a deed for daring never seen, and must
be attributed to God rather than to human heart.’ i. 458. Solis of course fails not to
extol the genius and daring of his hero, whose deed ‘appears rather in the light of
a fable’ than in consonance with simple history. Hist. Mex., i. 448. ‘A deed which
makes one tremble even to conceive, and much more to carry out. But God had
so determined it.’ Ixtlilxochitl, Hist. Chich., 296. ‘History contains nothing parallel to
this event, either with respect to the temerity of the attempt, or the success of the
execution,’ etc. Robertson’s Hist. Am., ii. 60. ‘An expedient, which none but the
most daring spirit, in the most desperate extremity, would have conceived.’
Prescott’s Mex., ii. 159. ‘An unparalleled transaction. There is nothing like it, I
believe, in the annals of the world.’ Helps’ Cortés, ii. 351. Clavigero is less carried
away by the incident, for he sees therein the hand of God. Nevertheless, he
sympathizes with Montezuma. Storia Mess., iii. 95, etc. Pizarro y Orellana finds
the deed eclipsed by the similar achievement, with a smaller force, under his
namesake Pizarro. Varones Ilvstres, 89-90. And later Mexican writers, like
Bustamante, see, naturally enough, nothing but what is detestable in the incident,
for according to the native records which form their gospel, Montezuma was
guiltless of any base intents. Unfortunately for them, these very records paint him
a blood-thirsty despot who punishes the slightest offence against himself, even
when merely suspected, with the most atrocious cruelty; one who is continually
seeking his aggrandizement at the expense of inoffensive, peace-loving tribes,
who oppresses not only conquered peoples, but his own subjects, with
extortionate taxes and levies to satisfy his inordinate appetite for pomp and for
new conquests. These records also admit that he had repeatedly sent sorcerers, if
not armies, to entrap and destroy the Spaniards. He who looked calmly on
hecatombs of his own subjects, slaughtered before his very eyes, would not
hesitate to condemn strangers for plotting against the throne which was dearer to
him than life itself. The Spaniards may have anticipated events considerably, but
there is no doubt that numerous personages, from Cuitlahuatzin downward, were
bitterly opposed to their enforced guests, and they would sooner or later have
realized the rumors which the allies began to circulate. Placed as he was, Cortés’
duty to himself, to the men intrusted to him, to his king, and to the cause of
religion, as then regarded, required him to give heed to such rumors, and, after
weighing their probability, to take the precautionary measure of seizing the
monarch, since retreat not only appeared fraught with disaster and dishonor, but
would be regarded as a neglect of opportunity and of duty. With Cortés, naught but
the first steps in assuming the conquest, and in usurping certain credit and means,
can be regarded as crimes, and the former of these was forced upon him by
circumstances of his age and surroundings. Every project, then, conceived by him
for the advancement of his great undertaking must redound to his genius as
soldier and leader. Of course, among these projects appear many which did not
advance the great object, and which must be condemned. But where do we find
greatness wholly free from stain?
CHAPTER XVIII.
DOUBLY REFINED DEALINGS.

1519-1520.

Hollow Homage to the Captive King—Montezuma has his Wives and


Nobles—He Rules his Kingdom through the Spaniards—The Playful
Page—Liberality of the Monarch—The Sacred Treasures—Cortés
Resents the Insults of the Guard—Diversions—Quauhpopoca, his Son
and Officers, Burned Alive—Plantations Formed—Villa Rica Affairs—
Vessels Built—Pleasure Excursions.

A pompous reception was accorded the imperial prisoner. With


no small ceremony was he conducted to apartments adjoining those
of Cortés, as selected by himself, and there surrounded by all
accustomed comforts and every show of greatness. At hand were
his favorite wives, his most devoted servants; he held court daily,
received ambassadors, issued orders, and with the aid of his learned
jurists administered justice. To outward appearance the monarch
was as absolute as ever; yet Montezuma knew that his glory had
departed, that the continued forms of greatness were hollow, and
that his power was but the power of a puppet. He was wise enough
to know that a strong man is not to be trusted who is officiously kind
to a weak one.
Henceforth the power of the nation, in the hands of these
insidious strangers, was to be directed against himself. It was a
cunning policy, craftily conceived and deftly executed.
Cortés took care that everything round the prisoner should move
smoothly, and that his presence in the Spanish quarters should
appear to the natives a voluntary rather than an enforced visit. To his
more intimate lords and subjects, however, who knew better his
condition, and who sometimes urged him to return to his palace, the
poor captive would say, “Ah, no! it is the will of the gods that I remain
with these men and be guided by their counsel.” But on no account
must the imperial influence be allowed for the present to decline
before the people. The deception must be continued, and the dignity
of the sovereign upheld by a deferential attention as profound as that
which was shown before his imprisonment. Daily, after prayers, the
Spanish general came to pay his respects, attended by several of his
captains, more frequently Alvarado, Velazquez, and Ordaz, and to
receive the imperial commands with respect to his comforts,
pleasures, and duties. On these occasions, and indeed whenever he
appeared before the emperor, says Bernal Diaz, Cortés set the
example to his followers by doffing his hat and bowing low, and
never did he presume to sit in the royal presence until requested to
do so.
Yet a most unpleasant reminder to the monarch of his
circumscribed authority was the ever present guard in and around
his apartments.[517] This was under the command of Juan Velazquez
de Leon, who enforced the strictest watch, particularly when it
became known that Montezuma’s courtiers lost no opportunity to
urge escape, and that he lent them a not unwilling ear, despite the
professed desire to remain with the Spaniards. Among the several
schemes with this object are mentioned bored walls, tunnels beneath
the palace, and an attempt by the emperor himself to leap from the
summit of the building into a safe receptacle prepared for him.[518]
Espionage was also established on the emperor in his
intercourse with courtiers, by placing in the apartment the page
Orteguilla, who had acquired a fair knowledge of Aztec. Of
prepossessing appearance, agreeable and sprightly in manner, the
youth became a favorite with the captive king. Among other things,
the little spy gave the monarch an insight into Spanish customs and
proceedings at home and abroad, into the power and grandeur of the
Castilian king, and into the mysteries of the faith. Being constantly
together they grew familiar, Montezuma delighting to play pranks on
the boy, throwing aloft his hat, and laughing at his efforts to regain it.
These tricks were always followed by a liberal reward.[519]
Montezuma was indeed most liberal with all who came in contact
with him, as became the character of a great and rich prince. Not
only jewels, robes, and curiosities, but male and female slaves, were
freely dispensed, partly no doubt with a view to secure good
treatment from the guard. A considerate thoughtfulness and gentle
manner added to his popularity, and “whenever he ordered,” says
the old soldier, “we flew to obey.” The inconsiderate pride and
selfishness of the independent monarch seems to have disappeared
in the prisoner, yet like the captive hawk he was submissive only to
his masters. Orteguilla kept him informed of the rank and character
of the men, and became the recognized medium for his favors. He
represented, for instance, that Bernal Diaz longed to be the master
of a pretty maiden, and Montezuma, having noticed the exceeding
deference of the soldier, called him, saying that he would bestow on
him a fine young woman, whom he must treat well, for she was the
daughter of a chief. He also gave him three quoits of gold and two
loads of robes.[520] The gift came from the emperor’s harem, from
which he frequently drew to please those whom he delighted to
honor. The vacancies thus created were filled from noble families,
who like those of more advanced countries regarded it an honor for a
daughter to occupy the position of royal concubine. After his
imprisonment Montezuma seems to have disposed of his wives quite
rapidly, a number of them falling to leading Spaniards.[521] To Cortés
he offered for the second time a daughter, prettier than the one given
him on the day of his capture, but in this instance the gift was
declined in favor of Olid, who accepted her, together with any
number of presents, and was henceforth treated as a relative by her
imperial father. Both she and the sister with Cortés were baptized.
[522]

The soldiers generally were by no means forgotten in the


distribution of women and other gifts, and in course of time the
quarter became so crowded with male and female attendants that
Cortés found it necessary to issue an order reducing the number to
one female servant for each man. Informed of this, Montezuma
instructed his mayordomo to provide good accommodation and
sustenance for them elsewhere.[523]
Encouraged by this generosity, Cortés approached him one day
regarding the secreted treasures, which had been so long respected,
but which he desired to have in his possession. He regretted to say
that his graceless soldiers had come upon the treasure-chamber,
and regardless of his instructions had abstracted a number of jewels.
The emperor hastened to reassure him; perhaps he understood the
hint. The contents of the chamber belonged to the gods, he said; but
the gold and silver might freely be taken so long as the rest was left.
[524] He would give more, if required. Cortés did not scruple to avail
himself of the permission, by appropriating for himself and his
intimate friends a large share. So charged the discontented soldiers,
but the main portion appears to have been reserved for the general
distribution not long after. Although the most valuable part of this
collection had been freely surrendered, the soldiers hesitated not to
seize also upon other effects, such as liquid amber and several
hundred loads of cotton fabrics. Cortés wished to restore them, but
Montezuma declined, saying that he never received anything back.
[525]
On another occasion the Spaniards discovered the imperial
warehouse for cacao beans, the most common currency of the
country, and for some time made nightly raids on it with their Indian
carriers. Cortés proposed to mete out punishment for this, but finding
that Alvarado was a leading culprit, he dropped the matter with a
private reprimand.[526]
Montezuma’s good nature was imposed upon in more ways than
one, and with all his kindness he could not command consideration
from the rougher soldiers and sailors. One of the guard, after being
requested, with a gift, to discontinue certain unseemly acts, repeated
the offence in the hope of receiving another bribe; but Montezuma
now reported him to his captain, and he was removed. Cortés, who
was determined to enforce respect for the captive, inflicted severe
punishment on offenders in this respect. Tired of patrol duty, Pedro
Lopez said one day in the hearing of Montezuma, “Confusion on this
dog! By guarding him constantly, I am sick at stomach unto death!”
Told of this, the general had the man lashed in the soldiers’ hall, and
this regardless of his standing as a good soldier and an archer of
great skill. Another who showed insolence to the emperor was
ordered hanged, but escaped with a lashing at the intercession of
the captains and of Montezuma.[527] This strictness insured respect
not only for the emperor, but for Cortés, so that the quarter became
most exemplary for its good order.[528]
The Spaniards united heartily with the native courtiers to
entertain the captive and to remove so far as possible whatever
might remind him of his lost liberty. He found great delight in their
military exercises, which recalled the faded prowess of his youth and
exhibited the tactics which contributed so powerfully to Spanish
supremacy over native arms. He also enjoyed sports, and among
games the totoloque was his favorite. This consisted in throwing
small golden balls at pieces of the same metal set up as targets at a
certain distance. Five points won the stakes. Cortés often played it
with him, and Alvarado, who kept count for the general, usually
marked more points than he was entitled to. Montezuma playfully
protested against such marking, although what Cortés won he gave
to the Mexican attendants, while Montezuma presented his gains to
the Spanish guard.[529]
Montezuma was at times allowed to visit his palaces, and to
enjoy the hunting-field, but these trips were of rare occurrence,
owing to the danger of popular demonstrations.[530] On such
occasions, says Cortés, the escort of prominent Mexicans numbered
at least three thousand. The first time Montezuma requested this
privilege it was for the purpose of offering prayer and sacrifice at the
great temple, as required by his gods, he said; and although Cortés
did not like the arrangement, his prisoner convinced him that this
public demonstration was necessary, in order to show the people
that he was not kept in compulsory confinement, but remained with
the strangers at the order of the deity he was about to consult. Four
captains were appointed to escort him with a guard of one hundred
and fifty soldiers, and he was warned that any attack upon them, or
any attempt at rescue, would result in his own death. He was carried
in a rich litter, attended by a brilliant procession of nobles, and
preceded, according to custom, by a dignitary bearing the triple
wand which indicated that the emperor was approaching and
demanded loyal veneration.
On reaching the temple the imperial worshipper stepped forth,
leaning on the arms of his relatives, and was assisted to the summit.
Human sacrifices had been forbidden, and Father Olmedo came to
watch over the observance of the order; but it appears that four
captives had been offered during the night, and despite the
remonstrances of the friar the attendant rites went on.[531] The
captains thought it prudent not to exceed a protest, and
congratulated themselves when the ceremony was ended and the
emperor safely back in their quarters.
A fortnight after the seizure of Montezuma, Quauhpopoca
arrived in the capital, accompanied by his son and fifteen of his staff.
He made his entry with the pomp befitting a powerful governor and a
relative of the sovereign, and hastened to the palace. As was
customary with subjects who were about to appear in the imperial
presence, the rich robes were covered with a coarse cloak, in token
of humiliation. His master received him with a stern countenance,
and signified his displeasure at the proceedings which under pretext
of his authority had caused loss of Spanish life. No attention was
paid to explanations, and he was surrendered with his followers to
the Spaniards, to be dealt with as they thought fit.[532] Cortés held a
trial: he was a shrewd inquisitor, and his sentence was sure to
accord with his own interests. “Are you a vassal of Montezuma?” he
asked of Quauhpopoca. “What else could I be?” was the reply. “Did
you attack Spaniards by his order?” The prisoner was in a most
serious dilemma. At first he refused to implicate the emperor, but
finding that his fate was sealed he confessed having acted under his
orders.[533] This could not avail him, however, for in obeying his
master he had injured the subjects and outraged the laws and
majesty of the Spanish king, who was sovereign of all, and this
demanded punishment.
The fact was that Spanish prestige, on which so much
depended, had suffered through the machinations of the governor,
and it was considered necessary to restore it. Therefore it was
decreed that Quauhpopoca, with his son and officers, should be
burned alive in the plaza, before the palace. Cortés availed himself
of the opportunity to seize all the arms in the arsenals,[534] and
therewith build a pyre worthy such noted offenders.
When all was ready Cortés presented himself before the
emperor, and announced with a severe tone that the evidence of the
condemned showed their acts to have been authorized by him, and
as a life called for a life, according to Spanish laws, he deserved
death. Cortés, however, loved him—for himself, his generosity, and
services he loved him too dearly to let justice have its course, and
would take on himself to appease its demands by a nominal
punishment.[535] He then turned on his heel, while one of the
soldiers clasped a pair of shackles round the prisoner’s ankles, and
the mighty emperor of the Aztecs was ironed. For a moment
Montezuma stood rooted to the floor. Then he groaned with anguish
at this the greatest indignity ever offered his sacred person. He
trembled with apprehension at what might yet follow. His courtiers
were no less afflicted, and with tears in their eyes they knelt to
lessen the weight at least of the shameful bonds, and with bandages
to relieve the imperial limbs.[536]
Meanwhile the troops formed an imposing cordon in front of the
palace to prevent a rescue of the condemned as they were led out
and tied to the stake. Writhing with pain, yet mute as became brave
warriors, with the ascending smoke from Aztec shields and darts
they rendered up their anguished souls. It was rare strategy thus
with the offenders to destroy the means of offence. Supposing that
the execution was by imperial sanction, the populace tacitly
assented, gazing on the horrid spectacle with pallid faces and bated
breath. Though accustomed to scenes like this in connection with
their religious festivals, it appeared terrible when perpetrated by
foreigners, to the dreary sound of muffled drums.[537]
All being over, Cortés reëntered the apartments of Montezuma
with his captains, and kneeling down he himself took off the fetters,
declaring that he felt deeply grieved at the infliction, for he loved him
as a brother. The monarch became almost hysteric with joy at this
deliverance, and with falling tears he expressed himself in abject
terms of gratitude, like the dog licking the hand which has chastised
it. Every fresh incident reveals some new trait in the character of this
unhappy man which calls for pity or contempt. “Yet further,”
continued Cortés, “to show my deep regard and confidence, you are
now at full liberty to return to your own house.” But Montezuma
understood well enough that these were but words, an empty offer;
indeed he had been informed by the well prompted page that,
although the general might wish to release him, the Spanish captains
would never permit it.[538] He accordingly expressed his thanks, and
said that he preferred to remain with him, giving as a reason that,
were he free, the importunities of his relatives and nobles to attack
the Spaniards might prevail over his friendship for them and their
king, and this would entail not only loss of life on both sides, but the
ruin of the city. Thereupon Cortés embraced him with every
appearance of deep devotion, and said, “Next to my king you shall
be king; vast as are your possessions, I will make you ruler of more
and greater provinces.”[539]
We can imagine the words by which the Spaniards might justify
to themselves the death of Quauhpopoca, but we cannot understand
the object in degrading the emperor in the eyes of his subjects—an
act which they had hitherto been so careful to avoid—unless it was
to lift themselves in their own esteem and that of the natives, far
above the highest American princes and powers, and to impress the
sacredness of their persons on the minds of the Indians. Further
than this, they seemed to think some punishment of the emperor
necessary, either because he had authorized the Nautla outrage, or
because he had countenanced it by neglecting to reprimand the
perpetrators. At all events, the effect was salutary, so much so that
Spaniards were to be seen wandering singly about the country
without fear of molestation.[540]
This effect, which extended also to adjoining independent
provinces, enabled Cortés to carry out the long-cherished project of
gathering information on the condition of the country, particularly its
political feeling and its mineral resources. Montezuma readily gave
the aid requested by providing maps and officials to guide the
exploring parties. The first investigations were directed to the upper
parts of Rio Zacatula and to Miztecapan, some eighty leagues south
of the capital, and to the northern branches of the Papaloapan,
whence most of the gold was said to come.[541] The Zacatula party
was headed by Pilot Gonzalo de Umbría, in compensation perhaps
for the loss of his feet at Villa Rica. He returned before the other
parties, within the forty days allowed for the trip, and brought about
three hundred pesos’ worth of gold dust, washed out in dishes from
three rivers, by order of the cacique. Two chiefs accompanied him,
bearing gold presents of nearly the same value as the dust, and
offering allegiance to the Spaniards in the name of their caciques.
[542] Small as was the treasure, it afforded a substantial proof of the
glowing report of Umbría. He had passed through three beautiful and
fertile provinces, filled with towns containing buildings equal to any in
Spain. He described a fortress finer in appearance and stronger than
the castle of Búrgos, and the people of Tamazulapan as most
superior in dress and intelligence.[543]

Another party, under one Pizarro,[544] proceeded south-


eastward, through Tochtepec and Malinaltepec, both of which
yielded them gold dust to the value of about three hundred pesos.
Descending along the northern fork of Papaloapan, they reached the
country of the Chinantecs, hostile to the Aztecs who had taken some
of the border towns. Their independence had not otherwise been
affected, owing to their mountain fastnesses, their warlike spirit, and
their formidable weapons, which were pikes about twenty feet in
length. They invited the Spaniards to enter, but would not allow the
Mexican escort to cross the boundary. The guides warned Pizarro
not to trust himself to what they termed a treacherous people, but
after a brief hesitation he advanced and received a hearty reception.
Aid was given to search for gold, of which seven hundred pesos’
worth was obtained from several rivers, most of it in rough grains.
[545]On his return he brought two chiefs, who bore presents of gold
from their chief cacique Cohuatlicamac, and tendered his allegiance
on condition that the Aztecs should not be allowed to enter the
country. Finding the inhabitants so friendly and the province rich in
resources, Pizarro left four of his small party behind to establish
cacao and maize plantations and to search for more gold.[546]

The project appears to have found favor with Cortés, who


besought Montezuma to form plantations for the king also in his
adjoining province of Malinaltepec. This was at once attended to,
and within two months four substantial houses and a vast reservoir
had been constructed, and a large tract of land brought under
cultivation, the improvements being valued at twenty thousand pesos
de oro.[547]
Another important object was to find a better harbor than Villa
Rica, and the emperor being consulted, he at once ordered a map to
be made, which showed very accurately not only the rivers and inlets
already known to the Spaniards, between Pánuco and Tabasco, but
the yet unknown Rio Goazacoalco, beyond the Mexican border. This
being said to have a large and deep entrance, Cortés availed himself
of Ordaz’ offer to examine it. Ten men, chiefly sailors and pilots, and
some guides, accompanied him, and authority was given to take
escorts from the frontier garrisons. He proceeded to
Chalchiuhcuecan or San Juan de Ulua, and thence followed the
coast examining the inlets.
On reaching the frontier complaints became numerous against
the native garrisons by reason of raids and outrages, and supported
by the chiefs who attended him he reprimanded the commanders,
threatening them with the fate of Quauhpopoca unless they
restrained the troops. They used to extend their raids into the
Goazacoalco province, but were at present somewhat guarded,
owing to a repulse wherein a number of comrades had perished.[548]
Ordaz’ proceedings served him well, for Tuchintlec, the cacique
of this province, sent a deputation of leading men to extend a
welcome, and furnished canoes and men to aid in sounding the river.
The bar was found to be at least two fathoms and a half deep at low
water, and above this, for twelve leagues, the soundings showed
fully five fathoms, with a prospect of an equal depth for some
distance, whereupon the pilots expressed the opinion that the
channel might be a strait leading to the southern sea.[549] Ordaz
received not only presents of gold and pretty women for himself, but
brought with him messengers bearing jewels, tiger-skins, feathers,
and precious stones for Cortés, together with an offer of allegiance
and tribute similar to those already tendered by the neighbors of
Tabasco. His report, which extolled the agricultural resources as well
as the port, induced the general to send with the returning
messengers another party to examine these features more
thoroughly and to test the disposition of the inhabitants. They again
sounded the river, selected a town site, and reported in favor of a
settlement. The cacique also expressed himself eager to receive
settlers, and offered to begin at once the construction of houses.
This decided Cortés to establish a colony on the river, and in April
Juan Velazquez and Rodrigo Rangel set out with one hundred and
fifty men to carry out the project. This, however, was not destined to
be so speedily accomplished.[550]
Meanwhile Villa Rica had been a source of no small anxiety to
Cortés. He had appointed Alonso de Grado to fill the vacant place of
Escalante, as commander of the fortress, and as his lieutenant in the
district. Grado was a man of agreeable presence and conversation,
and with some fame among his comrades as a writer and musician,
but more of a braggart than a soldier, with decided sympathies in
favor of Velazquez. Indeed, Bernal Diaz charges him with having
been the ringleader of the mutinous demonstration at Tlascala.
Cortés was well acquainted with the character of the man; but his
glib tongue had evidently overcome the prudence of the general, or
else he preferred a less bold spirit than Escalante’s at this post.
“Now, Señor Grado,” said he in handing him his commission, “here is
the fulfilment of your long felt desire of going to Villa Rica. Take care
of the fort, treat the Indians well, and do not undertake any
expeditions like that of Escalante, or you may meet his fate.” “In
saying this,” adds Bernal Diaz, “he gave us soldiers a wink, which we
readily enjoyed, knowing well enough that Grado would not venture
to do so, even under penalty of disgrace.” The office of alguacil
mayor, held by the former commander, was not included in the
present commission, but was given to Sandoval, and when Grado
remonstrated he was promised compensation in due time.
On reaching Villa Rica the evil nature of the man came to the
front. He assumed pompous demeanor, and expected the settlers to
serve him as a great lord, while the Totonacs were pressed for gold
and female slaves. The fort and the duties connected with it were
neglected, and the commander spent his time in gormandizing and
gambling, not to mention the secret efforts to undermine his
general’s influence and to gain adherents for Velazquez. This soon
reached the ears of Cortés, who felt not a little annoyed at having
trusted such a fellow. He recognized the necessity of intrusting this
district to one thoroughly devoted to himself, since a fleet from Cuba
might at any moment arrive and create mischief. Therefore he sent
Sandoval, who was brave and prudent, as well as loyal, and with him
Pedro de Ircio, a former equerry, of insinuating manners and
gossiping tongue, whom Sandoval elevated to a commanding
position.[551]
Grado was immediately sent up to Mexico under a native guard,
and when he arrived, with hands tied and a noose round his neck,
the soldiers derided him, while Cortés felt half inclined to hang the
fellow. After a few days’ exposure in the stocks he was released, and
soon his smooth persuasion paved once more a way to the favor of
his general, with whom he became so reconciled as to obtain the
office of contador not long afterward.
Among the instructions to Sandoval was one to send to Mexico
two shipwrights with ship-building implements, also chains, iron,
sails, rope, compass, and everything needful to fit out four vessels
which had been placed on the stocks shortly after the seizure of the
emperor.[552] The object was to afford a means for the ready
movement of troops and for escape in case of an uprising, when the
bridges would doubtless be raised. In asking Montezuma for aid to

You might also like