PDF Surgical Ethics Principles and Practice 1St Edition Alberto R Ferreres Ebook Full Chapter

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 53

Surgical Ethics Principles and Practice

1st Edition Alberto R. Ferreres


Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/surgical-ethics-principles-and-practice-1st-edition-alb
erto-r-ferreres/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Surgical and Medical Treatment of Osteoporosis:


Principles and Practice Peter V. Giannoudis

https://textbookfull.com/product/surgical-and-medical-treatment-
of-osteoporosis-principles-and-practice-peter-v-giannoudis/

The Ethics of Vaccination Alberto Giubilini

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-ethics-of-vaccination-
alberto-giubilini/

Surgical oncology : theory and multidisciplinary


practice Second Edition Audisio

https://textbookfull.com/product/surgical-oncology-theory-and-
multidisciplinary-practice-second-edition-audisio/

Medical-surgical nursing: concepts and practice 3


edition Edition Dallred

https://textbookfull.com/product/medical-surgical-nursing-
concepts-and-practice-3-edition-edition-dallred/
Advancing Surgical Education Theory Evidence and
Practice Debra Nestel

https://textbookfull.com/product/advancing-surgical-education-
theory-evidence-and-practice-debra-nestel/

Medical Surgical Nursing Concepts Practice Susan C.


Dewit

https://textbookfull.com/product/medical-surgical-nursing-
concepts-practice-susan-c-dewit/

Tourism : principles and practice Fletcher

https://textbookfull.com/product/tourism-principles-and-practice-
fletcher/

Forecasting Principles and Practice Athanasopoulos

https://textbookfull.com/product/forecasting-principles-and-
practice-athanasopoulos/

Derivatives principles and practice Das

https://textbookfull.com/product/derivatives-principles-and-
practice-das/
Surgical Ethics
Principles and Practice
Alberto R. Ferreres
Editor

123
Surgical Ethics
Alberto R. Ferreres
Editor

Surgical Ethics
Principles and Practice
Editor
Alberto R. Ferreres
Department of Surgery
University of Buenos Aires
Buenos Aires
Argentina

Department of Surgery
University of Washington
Seattle, WA
USA

ISBN 978-3-030-05963-7    ISBN 978-3-030-05964-4 (eBook)


https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-05964-4

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019


This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or
part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way,
and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software,
or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this
publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are
exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in
this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor
the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material
contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains
neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Preface

This textbook Surgical Ethics: Principles and Practice is devoted to dissemi-


nate the foundations and implications of ethics in the surgical arena, the so-­
called surgical ethics. Theoretical ethics attempts to understand the underlying
grounds, assumptions, and concepts of ethical systems; meanwhile, practical
ethics is related to the application of ethical standards in everyday surgical
practice and care. This book attempts to provide acting surgeons in the differ-
ent fields with a thorough and deep practical insight of the field of ethics as
well as tools for solving ethical conflicts in everyday care.
Surgery is characterized by some unique features: it harms before healing,
penetrates the patient’s body, and thus is highly invasive; decision-making is
performed many times under conditions of uncertainty and is prone to risks,
errors, accidents, complications, and sequelae. Thus, surgery is a moral prac-
tice, and as such, the surgeon becomes a moral fiduciary agent for his or her
patient. Trust is paramount to build an effective and beneficial patient-­surgeon
relationship, placing the patient at the center of our fiduciary care.
Ethics lies at the core of surgical professionalism: surgeons should not
only achieve surgical competence and diligence but also need to be ethically
and morally reliable. In this way, an outstanding quality of care will be offered
to all members of our society.
I want to specially thank all the coauthors, leaders in their fields, who have
done an amazing job. Their collaboration has been outstanding, and without
their participation, this book would not be in your hands today.
My eternal gratitude to Dr. Carlos Pellegrini, a true beacon in my aca-
demic life and instrumental in allowing me to contribute to this field at the
University of Washington, Department of Surgery. He and his wife Kelly
have been long-standing friends, mentors, and supporters.
A special mention to our Editor Mr. Prakash Jagannathan, whose role was
fundamental and was highly effective in guiding our efforts.

Buenos Aires, Argentina Alberto R. Ferreres

v
Contents

Part I Principles and Foundations of Surgical Ethics

History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West��������������������   3


Georgina D. Campelia and Denise M. Dudzinski
The History of Surgical Ethics���������������������������������������������������������������� 17
Jukes P. Namm and Cassandra C. Krause
Surgical Ethics: Theory and Practice Background������������������������������ 27
Douglas Brown
Foundations and Principles of Surgical Ethics�������������������������������������� 45
Alberto R. Ferreres
The Ethical Challenges of Surgical Leadership������������������������������������ 53
E. Christopher Ellison
What Is Surgical Professionalism?�������������������������������������������������������� 75
Steven M. Steinberg and Andrew L. Warshaw
Ethics in Academic Surgery�������������������������������������������������������������������� 85
Charles W. Kimbrough and Timothy M. Pawlik
Ethical Issues of the Mentor-­Mentee Relationship ������������������������������ 97
Alberto R. Ferreres
Surgical Ethics and the Surgical Societies:
What Are We Doing? ������������������������������������������������������������������������������ 103
Richard I. Whyte
Ethical Issues in Surgical Research�������������������������������������������������������� 109
Richard Jacobson, Laurel Mulder, and John Alverdy
Surgical Ethics and Diversity������������������������������������������������������������������ 121
Judith C. French and R. Matthew Walsh
Why and How to Teach Surgical Ethics?���������������������������������������������� 133
Jonathan K. Chica and Jason D. Keune
The Surgeon, the Patient, and the Healthcare System:
Access, Equity, and Fairness ������������������������������������������������������������������ 139
Alexis G. Antunez and Andrew G. Shuman

vii
viii Contents

Ethics in Global Surgery ������������������������������������������������������������������������ 149


Anji E. Wall
The Anesthesiologist and the Surgeon: Two Professionals
Sharing the Command of the Patient in the Operating Room������������ 159
Anthony M. Roche and Gerald Dubowitz

Part II Surgical Ethics in Everyday Surgical Practice

The Surgeon-Patient Relationship: Built Upon Trust�������������������������� 171


H. Alejandro Rodriguez and Carlos A. Pellegrini
The Transformation and Challenges of the
Surgeon–Patient Relationship���������������������������������������������������������������� 179
Piroska K. Kopar
The Surgical Decision-Making Process:
Different Ethical Approaches������������������������������������������������������������������ 193
Christian J. Vercler and Sagar S. Deshpande
The Surgical Informed Consent Process: Myth or Reality?���������������� 203
Miguel A. Caínzos and Salustiano Gonzalez-Vinagre
Informed Consent and Disclosure of Surgeon Experience������������������ 217
Sabha Ganai
The Pediatric Patient as a Self-­Individual and Decision-Maker �������� 231
Rosa Angelina Pace, Susana Ciruzzi, and Alberto R. Ferreres
End of Life Issues ������������������������������������������������������������������������������������ 239
Karen Brasel and Mary Condron
Ethics and Surgical Innovation�������������������������������������������������������������� 249
Maria S. Altieri and Aurora D. Pryor
Ethics and Breast Cancer������������������������������������������������������������������������ 257
Amtul R. Carmichael and Kerstin Sandelin
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Liver Transplantation�������������������������������� 265
Imventarza Oscar Cesar and Rojas Luis Daniel
Ethical Issues in Cardiothoracic Surgery���������������������������������������������� 271
Richard I. Whyte and Douglas E. Wood
Ethics of Surgical Intervention in Jehovah’s Witness Patients������������ 283
Edward E. Cho and D. Rohan Jeyarajah
Ethical Issues in Bariatric Surgery�������������������������������������������������������� 295
Antonio J. Torres, Oscar Cano-Valderrama, and Inmaculada
Domínguez-Serrano
How to Solve Ethical Conflicts in Everyday
Surgical Practice: A Toolbox������������������������������������������������������������������ 305
Darren S. Bryan and Peter Angelos
Afterword�������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������� 313
Index���������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������� 315
Contributors

Maria S. Altieri, MD, MS Division of Bariatric, Foregut and Advanced GI


Surgery, Department of Surgery, Stony Brook Medicine, Stony Brook, NY,
USA
John Alverdy, MD University of Chicago, Department of Surgery, Chicago,
IL, USA
Peter Angelos, MD, PhD Department of Surgery, The University of
Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA
The MacLean Center for Medical Ethics, The University of Chicago, Chicago,
IL, USA
Alexis G. Antunez University of Michigan Medical School, Ann Arbor, MI,
USA
Karen Brasel, MD, MPH Department of Surgery, Oregon Health and
Science University, Portland, OR, USA
Douglas Brown, PhD Department of Surgery, Washington University in St.
Louis School of Medicine, St. Louis, MO, USA
Darren S. Bryan, MD Department of Surgery, The University of Chicago,
Chicago, IL, USA
The MacLean Center for Medical Ethics, The University of Chicago, Chicago,
IL, USA
Miguel A. Caínzos Department of Surgery, Hospital Clínico Universitario,
Santiago de Compostela, Spain
Georgina D. Campelia, PhD Department of Bioethics & Humanities,
University of Washington School of Medicine, & UW Medicine Ethics
Consultation Service, Seattle, WA, USA
Oscar Cano-Valderrama, MD, PhD Department of Surgery, Hospital
Clínico San Carlos, Madrid, Spain
Amtul R. Carmichael Queens Hospital, Burton-on-Trent, UK
University of Aston, Birmingham, UK
Imventarza Oscar Cesar Hospital Argerich- Hospital Garrahan, Buenos
Aires, Argentina

ix
x Contributors

Jonathan K. Chica, MD St. Louis University, St. Louis, MO, USA


Edward E. Cho, MD Department of Surgery, Methodist Richardson
Medical Center, Richardson, TX, USA
Susana Ciruzzi, JD, PhD Ethics Committee “Prof Juan P Garrahan”
Hospital and “Dr Alfredo Lanari” Institute, University of Buenos Aires,
Buenos Aires, Argentina
Mary Condron, MD Department of Surgery, Oregon Health and Science
University, Portland, OR, USA
Rojas Luis Daniel EAIT (Transplant Institute of Buenos Aires City), Buenos
Aires, Argentina
Sagar S. Deshpande University of Michigan Medical School, Ann Arbor,
MI, USA
Inmaculada Domínguez-Serrano, MD, PhD Department of Surgery,
Hospital Clínico San Carlos, Madrid, Spain
Gerald Dubowitz University of California, San Francisco, San Francisco,
CA, USA
Denise M. Dudzinski, PhD, MTS Department of Bioethics & Humanities,
University of Washington School of Medicine, & UW Medicine Ethics
Consultation Service, Seattle, WA, USA
E. Christopher Ellison, MD, FACS Department of Surgery, The Ohio State
University, Columbus, OH, USA
Alberto R. Ferreres, MD, PhD, JD, MPH Department of Surgery,
University of Buenos Aires, Buenos Aires, Argentina
Department of Surgery, University of Washington, Seattle, WA, USA
Judith C. French, PhD Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of the
Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH, USA
Department of General Surgery, Cleveland Clinic, Cleveland, OH, USA
Sabha Ganai, MD, PhD, MPH, FACS Southern Illinois University School
of Medicine, Department of Surgery, Springfield, IL, USA
Salustiano Gonzalez-Vinagre Department of Surgery, Hospital Clínico
Universitario, Santiago de Compostela, Spain
Richard Jacobson, MD University of Chicago, Department of Surgery,
Chicago, IL, USA
Rush University Medical Center, Department of Surgery, Chicago, IL, USA
D. Rohan Jeyarajah Department of Surgery, Methodist Richardson Medical
Center, Richardson, TX, USA
Jason D. Keune, MD, MBA, FACS St. Louis University, St. Louis, MO, USA
Charles W. Kimbrough, MD MPH Department of Surgery, The Ohio State
University, Wexner Medical Center, Columbus, OH, USA
Contributors xi

Piroska K. Kopar, MD Surgical Critical Care, Acute Care and Trauma


Surgery, Yale School of Medicine, New Haven, CT, USA
Cassandra C. Krause, MD, MA Department of Surgery, Loma Linda
University Health, Loma Linda, CA, USA
Laurel Mulder, MD Rush University Medical Center, Department of
Surgery, Chicago, IL, USA
Jukes P. Namm, MD, FACS Department of Surgery, Center for Christian
Bioethics, Loma Linda University Health, Loma Linda, CA, USA
Rosa Angelina Pace, MD Ethics Committee Italian Hospital, Buenos Aires,
Argentina
Timothy M. Pawlik, MD, MPH, PhD Department of Surgery, The Urban
Meyer III and Shelley Meyer Chair for Cancer Research, The Ohio State
University, Wexner Medical Center, Columbus, OH, USA
Carlos A. Pellegrini, MD UW Medicine, University of Washington, Seattle,
WA, USA
Aurora D. Pryor, MD, FACS Division of Bariatric, Foregut and Advanced
GI Surgery, Department of Surgery, Stony Brook Medicine, Stony Brook,
NY, USA
Anthony M. Roche University of Washington, Seattle, WA, USA
H. Alejandro Rodriguez, MD Department of Surgery, University of
Washington, Seattle, WA, USA
Kerstin Sandelin Department of Molecular Medicine and Surgery,
Karolinska Insitutet, Stockholm, Sweden
Andrew G. Shuman, MD, FACS, FRCSEd (Hon) Department of
Otolaryngology-Head and Neck Surgery, University of Michigan Medical
School, Ann Arbor, MI, USA
Center for Bioethics and Social Sciences in Medicine, University of Michigan
Medical School, Ann Arbor, MI, USA
Steven M. Steinberg, MD, FACS Division of Trauma, Critical Care and
Burn, The Ohio State University, Columbus, OH, USA
Antonio J. Torres, MD, PhD, FACS, FASMBS Department of Surgery,
Hospital Clínico San Carlos, Madrid, Spain
Christian J. Vercler, MD, MA, FACS, FAAP Department of Surgery,
University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI, USA
Center for Bioethics & Social Sciences in Medicine, University of Michigan,
Ann Arbor, MI, USA
Anji E. Wall, MD, PhD Stanford University, Division of Abdominal
Transplantation, Palo Alto, CA, USA
xii Contributors

R. Matthew Walsh, MD, FACS Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of


Medicine of the Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH, USA
Department of General Surgery, Cleveland Clinic, Cleveland, OH, USA
Andrew L. Warshaw Massachusetts General Hospital and Partners
HealthCare, Massachusetts General Hospital, Harvard Medical School,
Boston, MA, USA
Richard I. Whyte, MD, MBA Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA, USA
Douglas E. Wood University of Washington, Seattle, WA, USA
Robert M. Zollinger Department of Surgery, The Ohio State University,
Columbus, OH, USA
Part I
Principles and Foundations
of Surgical Ethics
History and Development
of Medical Ethics In the West

Georgina D. Campelia and Denise M. Dudzinski

Key Points
Introduction: From Professional
• In Western medicine, medical ethics
Ethics to Bioethics
evolved from an amorphous idea in “We have to be there at the birth of ideas, the burst-
ancient medicine to a distinct field of ing outward of their force: not in books expressing
study in the twentieth century. them, but in events manifesting this force, in strug-
• The different eras of medical ethics are gles carried on around ideas, for or against
them.” — Michel Foucault1
marked by struggles and responses, as
medical ethics moves from (1) oaths of
faith and fidelity grounded in the author-
ity of higher powers (state, church, Medical Ethics
crown) to (2) oaths of decorum grounded The application of moral reasoning in the
in professional consensus and contrac- setting of clinical practice and medical
tual agreements within the medical pro- research.
fession and finally to (3) ethical codes Today it is also distinguished by subfields:
formulated collaboratively and grounded
in moral reasoning. 1. Theoretical bioethics
• Many of the same virtues and obligations 2. Clinical ethics
have defined medical ethics throughout 3. Surgical ethics
the centuries (e.g., beneficence, compas-
sion, confidentiality, fidelity, trustworthi-
ness, respect, integrity, and justice), but
Philosopher, social theorist, and historian
their meaning and application have
Michel Foucault reminds us that terms like “med-
changed with evolving medical knowl-
ical ethics” do not simply name an idea. Rather
edge and technology, societal perceptions
the meaning and import of a term can be found in
and understanding, and historical events.
the interactions and even conflict that produces

1
Foucault, M. “Les Reportages d’Idees”, in Corriere
Della Sera (Milan, 12 Nov. 1978; repr. In Dilder Eribon,
Michel Foucault), 1989; Tr.1991.
G. D. Campelia (*) · D. M. Dudzinski
Department of Bioethics & Humanities, University
of Washington School of Medicine, & UW Medicine
Ethics Consultation Service, Seattle, WA, USA
e-mail: gdcamp@uw.edu
© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 3
A. R. Ferreres (ed.), Surgical Ethics, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-05964-4_1
4 G. D. Campelia and D. M. Dudzinski

and results from the terminology. Today, “medi- most importantly, in response to patients in need
cal ethics” refers to the application of moral rea- of the cures and remedies specific to the art (frac-
soning in the setting of clinical practice and tures, head wounds, wounds requiring sutures).3
medical research. This involves the use of moral Likewise, medical ethics took shape in the
theories (e.g., utilitarianism), moral principles day-to-day practice of medicine and the nature of
(e.g., respect for autonomy), and virtues (e.g., the physician’s relationship with a patient. It
trustworthiness) to help guide the medical field. highlighted the importance of physicians’ moral
With this in mind, our history begins before character. Physicians responded to injury and
Thomas Percival coined the term “medical eth- trauma because society called on them to heal. As
ics” in his 1803 book Medical Ethics. We con- philosopher and bioethicist Albert Jonsen articu-
sider how ethics’ influence on medicine has lates, the ethical norms go hand in hand with the
shifted over several centuries in the West. Medical healer’s role in restoring order:
ethics is an ancient professional ethos, but its Illness is seen as the consequence of a knowing or
path to a distinctive field of study is marked by an unknowing infraction of the order and law of
collaboration and heroism, as well as episodes of nature or society; the healer must apply the reme-
deep conflict and violence. dies that restore order and reintegrate the sick per-
son into conformity with that order… The work of
What conflicts or historical shifts informed the healer must not only be correct, that is, the
medical ethics as we understand it today and proper remedy for the illness is used, but it must
how has such naming distinguished the field also be right and good, done in conformity with
itself? We chart the transformation of the rules, customs, and beliefs that constituted the
meaning of life for the society. [29, p. 6]
­amorphous, unnamed idea of medical ethics,
beginning with some of the earliest evidence of The healer must never intend harm, so the art
the character and oaths of the profession to its and practice are grounded in beneficence. But,
establishment as a distinctive field of study for much of medicine’s history, scientific knowl-
informing patient care. edge and effective remedies were inadequate, so
the power to heal eluded many. Doctors who
failed to live up to the identity of healer were per-
 mergence of Medical Ethics,
E ceived as quacks because their treatments rarely
But Not Yet Bioethics restored health and were more likely to harm.
They also faced retributive justice as defined by
It is thus an open question whether a subject like legal codes. The Code of Hammurabi is one of
“medical ethics” existed before it had a designa-
tion. Could medical ethics really have existed
the oldest known set of laws guiding social jus-
before 1803, if no one had used an expression des- tice and punishment, including medical malprac-
ignating this concept? – Robert B. Baker & tice [7]. The law specifies, for instance, that “If a
Laurence B. McCullough.2 physician make a large incision with the operat-
ing knife, and kill him, or open a tumor with the
Baker and McCullough are right to question operating knife, and cut out the eye, his hands
whether medical ethics existed before it was shall be cut off” [10, p. Code 218].
named. Words matter, but as Foucault observes Prior to the nineteenth century, duties of phy-
above, ideas begin to form long before they are sicians were defined in oaths and codes, and they
named. Surgery, for instance, was not defined by were rarely grounded in moral reasoning (e.g.,
written accounts of the first surgical interventions one ought not do X because it takes advantage of
but materialized through the development of a patient’s vulnerability and so harms the patient).
tools and techniques, through conversations and Rather, these oaths were grounded in social
arguments about the trade, in the course of acci- expectation, moral beliefs, and valued character
dents and mistakes that cost lives, and, perhaps traits. This is not to say that they were not serious

2
Baker and McCullough [4]. 3
See, e.g., Ellis [13], Gawande [16].
History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West 5

commitments to beliefs about what was morally fifth century BCE). First printed as part of the
right. As Baker articulates, Corpus Hippocraticum in 1526 in Venice, it is
Oaths were taken so seriously that signing a loy- typically attributed to later generations of physi-
alty oath was taken as sufficient evidence of loy- cians rather than Hippocrates himself [25]. The
alty and could even secure pardons. Conversely, oath proclaims the same foundational principles
refusal to sign a loyalty oath was tantamount to that continue to characterize the “right” and the
treason… [3, p. 40]
“good” of the profession of medicine. Famously,
In fact, the oath obligates “First do no harm” (Latin,
Oaths, vows, and promises are quintessential deon- Primum non nocere) [22], known today as the
tological acts: they bind the person to his word, as principle of non-maleficence [5].
testified before a higher being… Oaths were taken The power and motivation of the Hippocratic
solemnly and observed stringently. [30, p. 4] Oath is the physician’s personal or societal duty
rather than more principled obligations to patients
(such as a duty to respect patient values because
Deontology human beings, especially vulnerable patients, are
An ethical framework based on duty and inherently morally worthy). Early physicians were
obligation (as opposed to consequences). primarily bound by fidelity to the gods and god-
Examples: desses: “I swear by Apollo the physician, and
Divine command theory – e.g., “One Asclepius, and Hygieia and Panacea and all the
ought not lie because the gods command gods and goddesses as my witnesses…” [22]; and
truthfulness.” to their teachers: “To hold him who taught me this
Kantian ethics – e.g., “One ought not lie art equally dear to me as my parents… to look
because rationality demands truthfulness.” upon his offspring as equals to my own siblings,
and to teach them this art… by the set rules, lec-
tures, and every other mode of instruction…” [22].
However, these codes of conduct are a better The health and well-being of one’s patients come
reflection of laws and customs that already only after these other obligations and are in honor
existed in society than of considered judgments of the gods: “In purity and according to divine law
using moral frameworks. As such, medical ethics will I carry out my life and my art” [22]. The prac-
did not yet have the weight of moral reasoning tice of medicine was essentially an act of faith. The
and justification. ethical obligations of the physician (e.g., do no
harm) fall out of and are beholden to the healer’s
broader societal duties and relationships (e.g., to
Moral Frameworks the gods/goddesses or to one’s teachers) as
Structured approaches to what one should opposed to being grounded in moral reasoning
do or who one should be that are grounded (e.g., utilitarianism – creating the greatest good for
in reasoned argumentation. the greatest number). This is not to say that moral
*Deontology *Utilitarianism *Virtue values and reasoning are no longer interwoven
Theory with social custom but rather that early medical
*Communitarianism *Feminist Ethics ethics was grounded in social custom.
*Care Ethics *Casuistry *Contract Theory Today, medical ethics is grounded in forms of
*Principlism moral reasoning that are particular to the medical
profession. While this does not characterize early
medical ethics, a similar structure of moral justifi-
Ethics as validated by custom rather than cation is found in ancient Greek ethics.
moral argument is exemplified in one of our ear- Philosophers like Plato (427–347 BCE) and
liest examples of ethics in Western medicine: the Aristotle (384–322 BCE) present an early demand
Hippocratic Oath (written in approximately the for a more objective approach to m ­ orality, one in
6 G. D. Campelia and D. M. Dudzinski

which the duties that spring from one’s relation- h­ealing of a wound (as we see in the above
ship to society are scrutinized and subordinated to codes), and we might say health and healing are
obligations to the “right” and the “good.” Both important because they lead to happiness
philosophers make significant connections (εὐδαιμονία/eudaimonia). But being or acting
between medicine and ethics, often invoking virtuously (i.e., manifesting eudaimonia) cannot
medicine as a parallel methodological model. be feigned (NE II.4) and cannot be justified
In Plato’s Republic, for instance, Socrates according to some further end. Virtue demands
questions his companions about whether it is just moral reasoning to articulate it as such and
to act according to what is advantageous for one- defend it against rational counter-arguments.
self and employs medicine as an example: Through the early eighteenth century, deco-
Now tell me, is the doctor in the precise sense, of rum, faith, and obedience dictated physician
whom you recently spoke, a money-maker or one behavior [3, 29, 30, 34]. The virtues and duties of
who cares for the sick? Speak about the man who the medical profession continued to be defined
is really a doctor. (Plato, Republic, 341c)4 largely by the trade’s customs and broader social
Similarly, Aristotle uses medicine (here as a kind norms. Beginning in the sixteenth century, medi-
of contrast) to gain a better understanding of the cal ethics was increasingly formalized by medi-
moral good: cal licensure and its legal-ethical codes. But the
ethical demands of these codes remained
Let us go back to the good we are looking for— grounded in social norms (e.g., decorum), the
what might it be? For it appears to be one thing in institutions themselves (e.g., the church), and
one activity or sphere of expertise, another in
another: it is different in medicine and in general- consensus more than analytic arguments. For
ship, and likewise in the rest. What then is the good instance, some of the earliest oaths of healers
that belongs to each? … In medicine this is health… regarded labor and delivery. In 1555 in England,
for it is for the sake of this that they all do the rest. Bishop Bonner constructed an oath required for
The consequence is that if there is some one end of
all practical undertakings, this will be the practica- midwifery licensure ([3, pp. 19–21]. This
ble good… (Aristotle, NE, 1097a15-24)5 medical-­ethical oath included duties to protect
mother and child, e.g., “ye shall not suffer any
While Plato and Aristotle differ in their philo- chylde to be murdered, maymed, or otherwise
sophical approaches, both sought an understand- hurtydem as nygh,” as well as duties in interest of
ing of moral goodness as separate from social the church, e.g., “when of necessity ye shall
custom. As is apparent in Aristotle’s passage chrystyn any chylde, ye shall use pure and cleane
above, there is a clear distinction between the water, nother mixt with rose water, damaske
practice of medicine as a form of τέχνη/technê water, or otherwise altered or confected” [3,
(i.e., art or craft) and the practice of virtue as the p. 21; 8, pp. 165–166].
manifestation of εὐδαιμονία/eudaimonia (i.e., These oaths were designed in the interest of
flourishing, happiness, or living well). the church and the crown, which often trumped
εὐδαιμονία/eudaimonia is the end or moral goal the interests of the women in labor [3, p. 23]. For
every human being properly strives for. Health instance:
may be required to achieve it, because illness
Item, ye shall never consent nor agree that any
often confounds human flourishing. But it is woman be delivered secretly, but in the presence
eudaimonia that is the final or complete end of of two or three lyghtes, if she travell nyght. [3,
human life. In other words, a proper identifica- p. 21; 15]
tion of a healer might require the successful
Throughout history, societal order (e.g., the
church, state, and/or crown) has demanded pun-
4
Here, and throughout, we use Allan Bloom’s translation
of Plato’s Republic [42]. ishment for pregnancies that fell outside of social
5
Here, and throughout, we use the Broadie and Rowe norms (e.g., because the woman was unmarried
translation of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics [2]. and bearing children out of wedlock). As such,
History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West 7

the well-being of the pregnant woman might have within the profession itself rather than com-
required delivering in secret. But in healers’ manded by the church and crown. This means
oaths at this time, this was prohibited because it that the force of the obligation no longer came
violated a social order that required reporting from duty to a higher power or simple fidelity to
unwed mothers, ‘bastard children’, and ‘true mentors but from agreement among members of
paternity’. As such, the woman’s interests in con- the medical profession, attesting to the greater
fidentiality were subordinate to the interests of social standing and influence of physicians.
the church and crown, which included the dual One of the first instances of this shift can be
efforts to protect children through proper chris- found in the Edinburgh University Medical Oath,
tening and protect social order through proper Circa 1732–1735:
identification of paternity.
Over the course of the sixteenth, seventeenth, [I A.B. do solemnly declare that I will] practice
physic cautiously, chastely, and honourably; and
and eighteenth centuries, as medicine became faithfully to procure all things conducive to the
more institutionalized and commercialized [30, health of the bodies of the sick; and lastly, never,
pp. 43–44], the power and meaning of the heal- without great cause, to divulge anything that ought
er’s duties began to shift and conflict ensued. As to be concealed, which may be heard or seen dur-
ing the professional attendance. To this oath let the
commerce developed in Western Europe, Deity be my witness. [47, pp. 50-51]
physician-­patient relationships were changed by
the formation of payment contracts and fixed The place of the deity, here, comes only after the
sums for services calculated by professionals duties of the art or trade, and the deity is a witness
rather than based on the patient’s ability to pay to rather than the source of the obligation. The
or satisfaction with the services provided [30, influence of this oath on Western medicine, par-
p. 44]. As such, physicians, communities, and ticularly in the Americas, was significant. Many
the state all struggled to reconcile conflict physicians in the colonies spent part of their
between the goals of healing and procurement of training at the University of Edinburgh [3, p. 38].
income [30, pp. 44–45]. Socrates’ question is And medical education in America was modeled
echoed, is the true physician a healer or a off of the Scottish example [3, p. 39].
money-maker? Moving through the eighteenth and nineteenth
At the same time, the oaths of physicians, centuries, a more contractarian model of medical
grounded as they were in the power of the church ethics develops. While many of the virtues are
and crown, transformed with the Catholic-­ similar (honor, beneficence, fidelity), medicine
Protestant struggle. In Scotland, for instance, the shifts to a “learned and gentlemanly profession”
Presbyterian (Scotland’s national religion) resis- [30, p. 57] as defined within the profession and
tance to Anglicization led to the revision of uni- agreed to by medical professionals. In 1766,
versity oaths and inquisitions to insure the oaths’ America’s first medical society was founded:
obligations were fulfilled [3, p. 41]. In 1688, a New Jersey Medical Society. Its foundational
Presbyterian inquisition sought to expunge fac- document, Instruments of Association, pledged
ulty and administration at Edinburgh University “never [to] enter any house in quality of our pro-
of non-Presbyterians [3, p. 42; 39]. It was a con- fession, nor undertake any case, either in physic
test of belonging, and it mattered less that you or in surgery, but with the purest intention of giv-
belonged to the medical profession than that you ing the utmost relief and assistance that our art
belonged to the right church or state. shall enable us, which we will diligently and
We see the influences of these struggles and faithfully exert for that purpose” [26, pp. 309–
the Enlightenment in the oaths of the eighteenth 311]. The moral demand is grounded in the art
century. Medical practitioners, scholars, and the itself (as defined by the medical institution) and
broader community questioned the authority of agreement among its practitioners, rather than in
religious institutions in the Age of Reason. And deference to a societal leader or broader societal
this conflict brought oaths built upon contracts customs.
8 G. D. Campelia and D. M. Dudzinski

This same shift is visible in the oaths of other Professional Conduct of Physicians and
foundational medical societies. For instance, the Surgeons, the term “medical ethics” is coined.
Oath of the Medical Society of the State of While not yet the field of medical ethics as we
New York, 1807, states: know it today, Percival’s work, like Gregory’s, is
grounded in philosophical thought, investigating
I, A. B., do solemnly declare, that I will honestly,
virtuously, and chastely, conduct myself in the and justifying a physician’s moral role rather than
practice of physic and surgery, with the privilege of merely articulating consensus. While his rules
exercising which profession I am now to be are sometimes consistent with historically inte-
invested; and that I will, with fidelity and honour,
grated principles of the profession, he draws on
do every thing in my power for the benefit of the
sick committed to my charge. [23] philosophical theory and renders those rules
accountable to reason or, at least, reflection.
In these oaths, it is not the character of the physi- Unlike other products of the Enlightenment,
cian that shifts significantly, as there is still a Percival sought a balance between philosophy,
focus on honesty, honor, fidelity, and benefi- religion, and medicine [41, p. 2266]. His thinking
cence. Likewise, the oath remains a “[distillation] was influenced by philosophers and theologians
of the ethical ideals of a community” [3, p. 37]. alike, and this is reflected in his focus on virtue.
The transformation is in the source and power of A virtue theoretical approach, which begins from
the demand. The demand continues to be a conceptualization of the sort of person one
grounded in social agreements and norms, but the should be rather than what actions one is obliged
source of the demand comes from the institution to take or avoid, had been common to both phi-
of medicine itself. The oaths were thus defined losophy (Plato, Aristotle, Hume) and theology
through social agreement among medical (St. Ambrose, Aquinas, Maimonides) over the
­professionals and made powerful by the nature of preceding centuries. Percival’s writings reveal a
this social contract. shift toward the same kind of justification sought
As the ethical obligations of the profession by Plato and Aristotle. He uses the virtue of
became increasingly specified and formalized in beneficence, for instance, to justify cost contain-
the oaths/contracts of medical institutions, sev- ment and fair distribution of resources (e.g., more
eral scholars began to theorize the character and rural dispensaries for the poor) [41, p. 2267]. As
ethos of medicine that took shape in those ethical Pellegrino explains, “his worry is less with main-
codes. As the oaths become subject to moral taining professional secrecy than with potential
reflection and reason, very quickly, the idea of harm to the patient” [41, p. 2267]. In this regard,
medical ethics emerges in the discourse. John Percival appealed to reason rather than custom
Gregory (1724–1773), a practicing physician and shifted the central concern of the profession
who also taught philosophy at King’s College, to the patient.
invoked moral reasoning to justify the virtues of But alongside rational justification for these
the profession. Influenced by philosophers such ethical duties, the public questioned the motives
as David Hume and Adam Smith, Gregory of the institution of medicine. For instance, New
accepted the historical virtues of the profession Jersey colonists denounced the formation and
(e.g., honor, patience, humanity) but sought to authority of the New Jersey Medical Society with
ground them in the moral sentiment of sympathy accusations of scheming and swindling the pub-
with the patient and a desire to relieve suffering lic [3, pp. 10–11]. And this was neither the begin-
[18, 30, p. 60]. Sympathy motivates the physician ning nor the end. Inside the profession arose
obligation to respond so as to relieve or heal. The critiques of self-interest and quackery, such as
other virtues, such as honor and patience, are Yale professor Worthington Hooker’s 1850 publi-
required in service of this goal. cation Lessons from the History of Medical
Then in 1803, with the publication of Thomas Delusions. More forceful were the violent public
Percival’s book Medical Ethics: Or a Code of protests in Edinburgh (1725) and New York
Institutes and Precepts Adapted to the (1788), which erupted against the practice of
History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West 9

“body snatching.” Body snatching involved rob- and (2) clashes between physicians and their
bing graves to supply cadavers for study [3, communities arose the implementation of medi-
pp. 57–58, 60]. In New York, bodies were typi- cal ethics in professional codes. In the American
cally taken from the graves of slaves and the poor Medical Association’s first Code of Ethics [11],
[36], in part because they were not able to afford the contractarian model of medical ethics contin-
the iron cages and security personnel that safe- ues but with a shift toward Percival’s focus on the
guarded the bodies of the wealthy [21, 35]. patient and stronger moral language. The code
Knowledge of the practice was met with building prominently displays the importance of duties
disgust and anger and eventually led to a group of and their corresponding rights, the reciprocity of
citizens storming New York Hospital. These con- vulnerability and protection, and the universality
flicts between physicians and the community of moral obligation. This shift is visible in the
were reflective of a kind of moral dissonance Table of Contents:
between medical practice and social expecta-
tions, and the struggle demanded a new under- • CHAPTER I. – Of the duties of physicians to
standing of the ethical obligations of physicians. their patients, and of the obligations of patients
As we turn toward the mid-nineteenth century, to their physicians.
we continue to see these clashes between the pro- • ART. I. – Of the duties of physicians to their
fession and the public play out in the practice and patients. ART. II. – Of the obligations of
research of individual physicians. Dr. Marion patients to their physicians.
Sims (1813–1883), for instance, remains immor- • CHAPTER II. – Of the duties of physicians to
talized in a statue in Central Park, NYC, as the each other, and to the profession at large.
founder of modern surgical gynecology. Yet, the • ART. I. – Of the duties of physicians for the
techniques that he invented and are still in use support of professional character.
today came from the objectification and torture of • ART. II. – Of the duties of physicians in
African American female slaves. One of his reward to professional services to each other.
“patients,” Anarcha Wescott, underwent 30 opera- • ART. III. – Of duties of physicians in regard to
tions to repair vesicovaginal fistulas [40]. Some vicarious offices.
defend Sims, arguing that he was well-intentioned • ART. IV. – Of the duties or physicians in
insofar as he sought cures when there were none consultations.
for the gruesome effects of the repeated rapes, • ART. V. – Of the duties of physicians in cases
pregnancies, and births that African American of interference with one another.
female slaves were forced to endure [54]. And yet, • ART. VI. – Of the duties of physicians when
however willingly these women cooperated with differences occur between them.
Dr. Sims, they were enslaved so their participation • ART. VII. – Of the duties of physicians in
could never have been truly voluntary, especially regard to pecuniary acknowledgements.
since the injuries they suffered were due to their • CHAPTER III. – Of the duties of the profes-
being raped by white male slave owners. Notably sion to the public, and of the obligations of the
Dr. Sims did not conduct these surgical experi- public to the profession.
ments on middle-class and wealthy white women, • ART. I. – Of the duties of the profession to the
perpetuating a pattern of exploitation of enslaved, public. ART. II. – Of the obligations of the
poor, and vulnerable people. Medicine, along public to physicians. [11, p. 91]
with every other human enterprise, has a tendency
to focus on the beneficial outcomes of Sims’ dis- And similarly in each declaration of ethical
coveries (techniques that have helped many obligation, for instance,
women) without acknowledging the means of dis-
§ 5. A physician ought not to abandon a patient
covery (human exploitation and violence). because the case is deemed incurable; for his atten-
So, it is not surprising that out of both (1) the- dance may continue to be highly useful to the
oretical work like that of Gregory’s and Percival’s patient, and comforting to the relatives around
10 G. D. Campelia and D. M. Dudzinski

him, even in the last period of a fatal malady, by The twentieth century is riddled with both sig-
alleviating pain and other symptoms, and by sooth-
ing mental anguish. To decline attendance, under
nificant medical advancements and moral-­
such circumstances, would be sacrificing to fanci- medical failures in which medicine was enlisted
ful delicacy and mistaken liberality, that moral in exploitative social programs and law enforce-
duty, which is independent of, and far superior to ment. Often the two went hand in hand.
all pecuniary consideration. [11, p. 94]
During this time, scientific advances dramati-
As Jonsen notes: cally changed the trustworthiness, allure, and
Here, then, medical ethics becomes in substance power of the medical profession. Vaccinations
that very American political fiction, a contract with became more commonplace, and many were
mutual rights and duties among the contracting par- developed for the first time (including influenza,
ties: doctors, patients, and society. An intriguing typhoid, polio, measles, chickenpox, and tubercu-
idea but, in this context, an odd one: it is only the
physicians who have written the contract. [30, p. 70] losis). The development of antibiotics and antivi-
rals made significant strides against communicable
So, even as these codes remained grounded in the disease. This included the discovery of penicillin
agreement among medical professionals, the lan- in 1928 by Alexander Fleming. Antibiotics also
guage slowly became infused with scholarly affected the safety of the already rising numbers
work on medical ethics and its demand for of surgical interventions. Breakthroughs were
accountability to reason. This, in addition to made in surgical interventions, including the first
medical and scientific progress, heightened the laparoscopic surgery (Hans Christian Jacobaeus
power and trustworthiness of the physician. 1910), the first splenectomy (Hermann Schloffer
Anesthesia, for instance, developed in early mid-­ 1916), the first open heart surgery (Henry Souttar
nineteenth century marked a dramatic shift in the 1925), and the first gender affirming surgery
ability of the surgeon to heal without causing fur- (1931). The practice of blood transfusion was
ther suffering. Likewise, the development of sta- developed in 1914. In 1929 at Boston Children’s
tistical methods in epidemiology led to far greater Hospital, Philip Drinker and Charles McKhann
accuracy in identifying pathogens responsible for published on their successful use of an artificial
epidemics (e.g., cholera) [34]. respirator (known as the “iron lung”) for patients
These evolutions in medicine and medical eth- with paralytic polio. And we see the first success-
ics, marked by both progress and pitfalls, lead us ful organ transplantations in the 1940s.
to modern-day medical ethics. But as we But these incredible advances in medicine often
approach the twentieth century, the conflict and came at costs that unjustly affected some social
violence that infused medical progress, along groups more than others. For example, in 1907
with its attendant resolutions, are what truly char- Indiana passed the first law authorizing forced ster-
acterize the emergence of medical ethics as a dis- ilization “of confirmed criminals, idiots, imbeciles
tinctive field. It was struggle (as Foucault and rapists” (1907 Indiana Eugenics Law, Chap.
recognizes), more than the softer persuasions of 215, H. 364). This practice became more prevalent,
scholars like Percival, that ultimately forced the and, ultimately, over 60,000 individuals underwent
materialization of the idea. compulsory sterilization in the USA [9, 12, 43].
This practice was common elsewhere in the
world as well. “Between 1934 and 1944 (when the
The Beginning of Bioethics population was 73 million) German doctors steril-
ized at least 400,000 persons, including the men-
“Respect every living being, in principle, as an end tally ill, the mentally disabled, the deaf, persons
in itself and treat it accordingly wherever it is
­possible” — Fritz Jahr.6
with tuberculosis, homosexuals, gypsies, and, of
course, Jews” [43, p. 358]. The infamous medical
experimentations of the Holocaust c­ ulminated in
the Nuremberg Trials (1945–46) and the
6
See Jahr [28]. Nuremberg Code. But, the USA too was guilty of
History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West 11

similar crimes. And African Americans were often disorders” [17]. In 1950 Dr. Joseph Strokes of the
the target. Some of the more well-­known incidents University of Pennsylvania infected 200 female
include the Tuskegee Study (1932–1974) in which prisoners with viral hepatitis to study the disease
black men in the USA were deceived into thinking [24, p. 91]. And in 1963–1973, the University of
they were being treated for syphilis and other Washington performed high-dose radiation tests
blood conditions, when in fact they were not [52]. on prisoners’ testicles to find a sterility dose [44].
Later, in 1951, Henrietta Lacks unknowingly Such brutally immoral experimentations were
became a vehicle for medical advancement not contained by US borders. In 1906, Dr.
through the creation of the first immortalized cell Richard Strong of Harvard conducted cholera
line, when cells from her tumor biopsy went on to experiments in the Philippines, killing 13 prison-
be used, and continue to be used, in medical ers [1]. In 1940, US doctors infected thousands of
research without her consent [49]. While few sub- Guatemalans with venereal disease [55]. And
jects at this time would have been informed, at across the world we see similar experimentation
least not in the sense of “informed consent” today, with the effects of nuclear and biological weap-
Ms. Lacks’ case, like the Tuskegee experiments, onry. For instance, Japanese armed forces (Unit
demonstrates how medical advancements were 731) field tested weapons with the plague,
built on the backs of black and/or poor people anthrax, and a number of other pathogens on
without fair ­opportunities for these communities Chinese prisoners [33].
to benefit from the treatments they were involved Mistreatment and violence against society’s
in developing. most vulnerable populations are not new and
Another fairly well-known example is the were sometimes normalized in medicine as it was
Manhattan Project (1942–57), in which partici- in the broader society. While scholars like
pants were injected with plutonium, uranium, and Percival initiated a distinct field of medical eth-
possibly other radioactive elements. The goal of ics, it was in the struggles of the twentieth cen-
the project was a better understanding of the tury that bioethics emerged as it is known today.
already known risks of ongoing exposure to work- It began with several declarations, reports, and
ers in the Manhattan Project (without their knowl- articles that attempted to respond to the atrocities
edge of said risks) (Georgetown Bioethics above. Theologians were enlisted first to help
Archive). As such, this project failed to aim at the doctors, quickly followed by philosophers. In
good of the relevant patient population (or at least papers in 1926 and 1927, Fritz Jahr, a German
minimize harm) in two senses: (1) failure of clini- protestant theologian, first coined the term “bio-
cal equipoise (i.e., “genuine uncertainty on the ethics” (German “Bio-Ethik,” directly translated
part of the… investigator regarding the compara- as “Bio-Ethics”) [27, 28]. Jahr’s use of the term
tive therapeutic merits of each arm of a trial.” [14, was broad with the goal of “safeguard[ing] all
p. 141]) insofar as there was no immediate benefit living nature from pointless destruction” [32].
to participants (e.g., a trial of a new curative treat- His moral imperative, though, resounded in mod-
ment that is expected to help at least some), but ern bioethics: “Respect every living being, in
rather known harm would be caused to the sub- principle, as an end in itself and treat it accord-
jects, and (2) any potential long-term benefit of ingly wherever it is possible” [28].
the knowledge was likely outweighed by the sig-
nificant risk of the exposure itself (already known
from observational data on workers). Ethical Imperative
Some lesser known examples targeted the dis- A demand, command, or rule that is
abled and prisoners. In 1943, researchers at grounded in moral reason and obligated of
University of Cincinnati Hospital kept 16 men- moral agents.
tally disabled patients in refrigerated cabinets for For example, physicians should respect
120 hours at 30 degrees Fahrenheit in order to their patients’ autonomous decisions.
“study the effect of frigid temperature on mental
12 G. D. Campelia and D. M. Dudzinski

So, it was not just the struggle and violence but Bioethics as part of the Kennedy Institute at
the reactions and pushback that came from other Georgetown University [19].
physicians, the public, theologians, and philoso- Then, in 1979, the National Commission for
phers. Bioethics took shape both in recognition of the Protection of Human Services of Biomedical
crimes society did not want to commit again and and Behavioral Research published the Belmont
also in a deepening commitment to physicians’ Report, named after the house in which the
moral roles and social responsibilities. authors convened to write it [31]. This report,
The 1948 Declaration of Geneva was formu- collaboratively written by MDs, PhDs, and JDs,
lated by the World Medical Association and was defines three ethical principles which have
built on the explicit ethical obligations to respect become central to the practice of medical
the lives and liberties of patients, e.g., “I WILL research: (1) respect for persons, (2) benefi-
MAINTAIN the utmost respect for human life cence, and (3) justice [46]. The principles were
from its beginning even under threat and I will justified through philosophical reasoning and
not use my medical knowledge contrary to the then applied to the field of medicine. As the
laws of humanity” [56]. report declares:
Henry K. Beecher, an American anesthesiolo-
gist, is famous for his 1966 article “Ethical and The expression "basic ethical principles" refers to
those general judgments that serve as a basic justi-
Clinical Research,” which criticized the human fication for the many particular ethical prescrip-
experimentations taking place since WWII [6]. In tions and evaluations of human actions. Three
the opening paragraph he states: basic principles, among those generally accepted
in our cultural tradition, are particularly relevant to
Evidence is at hand that many of the patients in the the ethics of research involving human subjects:
examples to follow never had the risk satisfactorily the principles of respect of persons, beneficence
explained to them, and it seems obvious that fur- and justice. [46]
ther hundreds have not known that they were the
subjects of an experiment although grave conse- Bioethics, accordingly, moved away from (1) the
quences have been suffered as a direct result of
experiments described here. [6, p. 1354]
standards of practice grounded in social order
and higher authorities and (2) the decorum and
Here, Beecher articulates two of the central prin- duties contractually agreed to within the profes-
ciples later developed in Beauchamp and sion, which we saw in earlier forms of medical
Childress’ Principles of Biomedical Ethics: (1) ethics. While consensus is still valued and soci-
beneficence and (2) respect for autonomy. The etal norms still influences, bioethics seeks clini-
idea that subjects of experimentation should be cal and ethical justification from multiple
informed about the risks (including known viewpoints (internal and external to the profes-
harms) of their participation in the research is sion of medicine). The applications of ethical
built on a principle of respect for autonomy as an principles and virtues must be grounded in rea-
essential component of humanity. soned arguments that can stand up to critique.
The resistance and response to the suffering of Now, moral theories and approaches long uti-
so many human subjects throughout the twenti- lized in philosophy and theology are brought to
eth century quickly became reflected in practice bear in medicine. These include principlism, vir-
and scholarship as clinicians, theologians, and tue ethics, deontology, consequentialism, com-
philosophers joined forces to analyze, critique, munitarianism, phenomenology, etc. In the past
and promote ethics in medicine. Suddenly, medi- 50 years, we’ve seen a shift in medicine from a
cal ethics went from a somewhat vague term focus on protecting one’s patient to respecting
studied by a small subset of physicians to an patient autonomy. The focus on respect for per-
interdisciplinary specialization that traversed the sons changes the way medicine interfaces with
bounds of the professions. It became formalized the population it serves, creating more of a part-
in articles, reports, and even institutions. In 1971, nership than had existed in the past centuries. The
André Hellegers established the first Center for conflict of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries
History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West 13

thus demanded multidisciplinary engagement, stereotypes, shortsightedness, and implicit bias.


and physicians often welcomed it. Bioethics Implicit bias is something that will not go away
became an academic discipline with its own edu- [48], and it can reside in ideas that we mistakenly
cational programs and scholarship, but it remains believe to be scientifically or theoretically dis-
fundamentally interdisciplinary. tinct from such social norms. Feminist ethicists,
for instance, have criticized rights-based
approaches and the principle of respect for auton-
Conclusion: The Role omy for their inherent understanding of persons
of the Bioethicist as individualistic, atomistic, and independently/
freely able to choose their paths in life [20, 37,
In the end, while advances in medicine in the 45, 50, 51, 53]. If we are not careful to acknowl-
nineteenth and twentieth centuries began to instill edge how practical-theoretical frameworks affect
greater trust of and dependence on medical pro- different individuals and communities in the
viders by large swaths of Western populations, practice of medicine, we will continue to exclude,
this trust was continuously abused in underrepre- disrespect, and cause harm to the same underrep-
sented populations and challenged by the public. resented populations who survived the twentieth
Medical ethics, including today’s bioethics, century’s abuses.
emerged in the course of this struggle through
collaboration between clinicians, theologians,
patients, attorneys, social workers, philosophers, Concluding Remarks
and other theorists. Now the field is distinct from
medicine itself and yet defined by ongoing con- • The transformation of medical ethics in the
flict and uncertainty over the meaning and appli- West is marked by collaboration and heroism,
cation of the very same terms that have defined as well as episodes of deep conflict and
the character of medicine since the ancient violence.
Greeks: beneficence, compassion, confidential- • Medical ethics takes shape in different eras,
ity, fidelity, trustworthiness, respect, integrity, beginning with (1) oaths of faith and fidelity
and justice. grounded in the authority of higher powers
The change has been both big and small, fast (state, church, crown), then (2) oaths of the
and slow. It is not so much the recognized virtues medical institution grounded in consensus of
and obligations of medical professionals that the profession, and finally (3) ethical codes
have shifted but how and to whom they are formulated collaboratively and grounded
applied. The principles of beneficence and non-­ moral reasoning.
maleficence, for example, are evidenced in the • Many of the same virtues and obligations have
Hippocratic Oath, but there they were unques- defined medical ethics throughout the centu-
tioned norms and subordinate to the dictates of ries (e.g., beneficence, compassion, confiden-
the gods. Today, these same principles and vir- tiality, fidelity, trustworthiness, respect,
tues are grounded in moral theory (utilitarianism, integrity, and justice), but their meaning and
communitarianism, etc.), and their application application in the medical setting are subject
must stand up to critique both internal and exter- to disagreement and will require moral cri-
nal to the profession. tique and reflection. Bioethicists are built to
This shift is not surprising given the increas- fulfill this role but only in ongoing interpro-
ing influence of empiricism and positivism in the fessional and interdisciplinary collaboration.
eighteenth to twentieth centuries. But, as contem-
porary bioethicists argue, we must cautiously The twentieth and twenty-first centuries have
recognize and remember the ongoing influence brought with them a host of life-sustaining (e.g.,
of detrimental social norms. Though bioethics implantable cardioverter defibrillators, ventricu-
exists as its own discipline, it is not immune to lar assist devices, extracorporeal life support),
14 G. D. Campelia and D. M. Dudzinski

curative (e.g., deep brain stimulation, targeted 11. Code of Medical Ethics of the American Medical
Association. Philadelphia: American Medical
gene therapy), and diagnostic (e.g., preimplanta- Association; 1847.
tion genetic diagnosis, direct to consumer genetic 12. Daniel K. In the name of eugenics: genetics and
testing) technologies that are likely to proliferate the uses of human heredity. New York, NY: Alfred
into the future. The interdisciplinary and delib- A. Knopf; 1985.
13. Ellis H. A history of surgery. London: Greenwich
erative nature of bioethics will help medicine and Medical Media; 2000.
society to critically reflect on ever-­evolving tech- 14. Freedman B. Equipoise and the ethics of clinical
nologies and reinforce robust critique and justifi- research. N Engl J Med. 1987;317(3):141–5.
cation without assuming that one can have a 15. Garnet R. The book of oaths. In: Aughterson K, edi-
tor. Renaissance woman: a sourcebook: constructions
completely objective or “god’s eye” view of the of femininity in England. New York, NY: Routledge;
moral obligations and virtues of medical practice. [1649]1995. p. 212–214.
In this way, bioethicists will continue to play a 16. Gawande A. Two hundred years of surgery. N Engl J
social role, offering ethical-­theoretical expertise, Med. 2012;366:1716–23.
17. Goldman D, Murray M. Studies on the use of refriger-
different perspectives, and much needed reflec- ation therapy in mental disease with report of sixteen
tive pauses in a fast-paced research and practice cases. J Nerv Ment Dis. 1943;97(2):152–65.
climate. 18. Gregory J. Observations on the duties and offices of a
physician and on the method of promoting enquiry in
philosophy. London: Strahan and Cadell; 1770.
19. Harvey JC. André Hellegers, the Kennedy institute,
Bibliography and the development of bioethics: the American–
European connection. In: Garrett JR, Jotterand F,
1. 1906: Richard Strong, MD, cholera. 2017. from Ralston DC, editors. The development of bioethics
Alliance for Human Research Protection. http://ahrp. in the United States. Dordrecht: Springer Science &
org/1906-richard-strong-md-cholera/. Business Media; 2013. p. 37–54.
2. Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics (trans: Broadie S and 20. Held V. Care and justice in the global context. Ratio
Rowe C, editors: Broadie S and Rowe C). Oxford: Juris. 2004;17:141–55.
Oxford University Press; 2002. 21. Highet MJ. Body Snatching & Grave Robbing: bodies
3. Baker R. Before bioethics: a history of American for science. Hist Anthropol. 2006;16(4):415–40.
medical ethics from the colonial period to the bio- 22. Hippocrates. The Hippocratic Oath (trans: North M):
ethics revolution. New York, NY: Oxford University National Library of Medicine; 2002. Retrieved from
Press; 2013. https://www.nlm.nih.gov/hmd/greek/greek_oath.
4. Baker RB, McCullough LB. What is the history of html.
medical ethics? In: Baker RB, McCullough LB, edi- 23. History of the Medical Society of the State of
tors. The Cambridge world history of medical ethics. New York. In: Walsh JJ, editor. New York, NY:
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 2009. Medical Society of the State of New York; 1907.
5. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedi- 24. Hornblum AM. Acres of skin: human experiments at
cal ethics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; Holmesburg prison. New York, NY: Routledge; 1998.
2012. 25. Iniesta I. Hippocratic Corpus. Br Med J.
6. Beecher H. Ethics and clinical research. N Engl J 2011;342(7803):929.
Med. 1966;274:1354–60. 26. Instruments of Association and Constitutions of the
7. Belli SR, Melvin M. The evolution of MEdical mal- New Jersey Medical Society. In: Rogers FB, Sayre
practice law. In: Vevaina JR, Bone RC, Kassoff E, AR, editors. The healing art: a history of the medi-
editors. Legal aspects of medicine. New York, NY: cal Society of new Jersey. Trenton, NJ: The Medical
Springer-Verlag; 1989. Society of New Jersey; 1966.
8. Bonner BE. Mid wife’s Oath. In: Helm W, editors. 27. Jahr F. Life sciences and the teaching of ethics. In:
Curious miscellaneous fragments of various sub- Miller IM, Sass H-M, editors. Essays in bioethics.
jects more particularly relative to english history Berlin: LIT Verlag Münster; 1926, 2013.
from the year 1050, to the year 1701, compiled from 28. Jahr F. Bio-Ethik. Eine Umschau über die eth-
British Writers during that period. London: Baldwin, ischen Beziehungen des Menschen zu Tier und
Cradock and Joy; [1555] 1815. Pflanze. Kosmos Handweiser für Naturfreunde.
9. Bruinius H. Better for all the world: the secret history 1927;24(1):2–4.
of forced sterilization and America's quest for racial 29. Jonsen AR. The birth of bioethics. New York, NY:
purity. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf; 2006. Oxford University Press; 1998.
10. The Code of Hammurabi. (c. 1754 BC). Retrieved from 30. Jonsen AR. A short history of medical ethics.
http://avalon.law.yale.edu/ancient/hamframe.asp. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2000.
History and Development of Medical Ethics In the West 15

31. Jonsen AR. Celebrating Professor Al Jonsen: Hastings Retrieved from https://biotech.law.lsu.edu/research/
Center Beecher Award Ceremony. Paper presented at reports/ACHRE/chap9_2.html.
the The 19th Annual Meeting of the American Society 45. Robinson F. Human rights and the global politics
for Bioethics and Humanities. Kansas City, MO; 2017. of resistance: feminist perspectives. Rev Int Stud.
32. Kalokairinou EM. Fritz Jahr’s bioethics impera- 2003;29(S1):161–80.
tive: its origin, point, and influence. JAHR. 46. National Commission for the Protection of Human
2016;7/2(14):149–56. Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The
33. Kristof N. Unmasking horror -- a special report.; Belmont report: ethical principles and guidelines for
Japan confronting gruesome war atrocity. The the protection of human subjects of research. United
New York Times; 1995. Retrieved from http://www. States of America: The Commission; 1979.
nytimes.com/1995/03/17/world/unmasking-horror- 47. Ryan M. A manual of medical jurisprudence, com-
a-special-report-japan-confronting-gruesome-war- piled from the best medical and legal works; being an
atrocity.html?pagewanted=all. analysis of a course of lectures on forensic medicine,
34. Kuhse H, Singer P. What is bioethics? A histori- Annually delivered in London. 2nd ed. Philadelphia:
cal introduction. In: Kuhse H, Singer P, editors. Carrey and Lea; 1832.
A Copanion to bioethics: second edition. Oxford: 48. Sabin JA, Rivara FP, Greenwald AG. Physician
Blackwell Publishing Ltd; 2009. implicit attitudes and stereotypes about race and qual-
35. Lovejoy B. Body Snatchers of Old New York. ity of medical care. Med Care. 2008;46(7):678–85.
Lapham's Quarterly; 2013. 49. Skloot R. The immortal life of Henrietta lacks.
36. Lovejoy B. The Gory New York City Riot that New York, NY: Crown Publishers; 2010.
Shaped American Medicine. Smithsonian; 2014. 50. Tietjens Meyers D, editor. Feminists rethink the self.
Retrieved from http://www.smithsonianmag.com/ Boulder: Westview Press; 1997.
history/gory-new-york-city-riot-shaped-american- 51. Tronto J. Moral boundaries: a political argument for
medicine-180951766/. an ethic of care. New York, NY: Routledge; 1993.
37. Mackenzie C, Stoljar N. Relational autonomy: femi- 52. The Tuskegee Timeline. Retrieved 18 Sept 2017, from
nist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social Centers for Disease Control and Prevention; 2015.
self. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2000. https://www.cdc.gov/tuskegee/timeline.htm
38. The Manhattan Project: A New and Secret World of 53. Urban Walker M. Moral understandings: feminist
Human Experimentation. Retrieved 18 Sept 2017, study in ethics. New York, NY: Routledge; 1998.
from Georgetown University. https://bioethicsarchive. 54. Wall LL. The medical ethics of Dr. J Marion Sims: a
georgetown.edu/achre/final/intro_3.html. fresh look at the historical record. Journal of Medical
39. Monro A. Presbyterian inquisition as it was lately Ethics. 2005;32(6):346–50.
Practised Against the Professors of the College of 55. Walter M. First, do harm. Nature. 2012;482:148–52.
Edinburgh, Agust and September, 1690, in which the 56. World Medical Association. Declaration of
Spirit of Presbytery and their Present Method of Procedure Geneva; 1948. Retrieved September 2017, from
is Plainly Discovered, Matter of Fact by Undeniable World Medical Association: https://www.wma.net/
Instances Cleared, and Libels Against Particular Persons policies-post/wma-declaration-of-geneva/.
Discussed. London: J. Hindmarsh; 1691.
40. Ojanuaga D. The medical ethics of the "father of
gynaecology", Dr J Marion Sims. J Med Ethics.
1993;19(1):28–31. Suggested Literature
41. Pellegrino ED. Percival's Medical Ethics: The moral
philosophy of an 18th-century English gentleman. Baker R. Before bioethics: a history of American medical
Arch Intern Med. 1986;146(11):2265–9. ethics from the colonial period to the bioethics revolu-
42. Plato. The Republic of Plato. (trans: Bloom A, editor: tion. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2013.
Bloom A). United States of America: Basic Books; Eckenwiler LA, Cohn FG, editors. The ethics of Bioethis:
1968. mapping the moral landscape. Baltimore: Johns
43. Reilly P. Eugenics and involuntary sterilization. Hopkins University Press; 2007.
Annual Review Genomics and Human Genetics. Jonsen AR. The birth of bioethics. New York, NY: Oxford
2015;16:351–68. University Press; 1998.
44. Richards EP. Advisory Committee on Human Jonsen AR. A short history of medical ethics. New York,
Radiation Experiments Report, Chapter 9; 1995. NY: Oxford University Press; 2000.
The History of Surgical Ethics

Jukes P. Namm and Cassandra C. Krause

is as old as the art of surgery itself, which can be


Key Points traced back to ancient Mesopotamia and Egypt.
• The unique issues that are encountered In addition to embalming, the ancient Egyptians
in surgery have made surgical ethics dis- performed eye surgery, reduced fractures, per-
tinct from medical ethics. formed wound care, and even placed prostheses.
• Surgical ethics has defined the surgical On the tomb of Nenkh-Sekhmet, chief of the
profession throughout the history and physicians during the 5th dynasty, is written:
evolution of modern surgery. “Never did I do evil towards any person” [2].
• As emphasized by Gregory and Percival, Much of Greek medicine was influenced by the
surgical ethics revolves around the sur- ancient Egyptians. However, surgical ethics as a
geon-patient relationship. field did not formally emerge until the advent of
modern surgery in the nineteenth century and the
establishment of surgery as a profession.
It is through the lens of surgical history, espe-
Introduction cially within the context of modern surgery, that
one can truly appreciate the role of ethics in the
Medical ethics dates back to ancient Greece, unique issues that surgeons have faced in the care
beginning with the writings of Hippocrates of their patients. From the eighteenth century
around the fourth century BCE who is given onward, ethical issues distinct to surgery such as
credit for writing one of the earliest works on the informed consent, fee splitting, itinerant surgery,
principles of nonmaleficence, physician deco- transplantation, and surgical innovation have
rum, and, of course, the Hippocratic Oath [1]. necessitated the emergence of a distinct offshoot
Although there is uncertainty regarding the ori- of medical ethics termed surgical ethics through
gin of surgical ethics, some would suggest that it the leadership of individuals and the surgical
profession.
J. P. Namm (*)
Department of Surgery, Center for Christian
Bioethics, Loma Linda University Health, Birth of Modern Ethics
Loma Linda, CA, USA
e-mail: jpnamm@llu.edu During the time of Hippocrates (460–370 BCE),
C. C. Krause medicine became a respected profession as a
Department of Surgery, Loma Linda University result of its influence in establishing a standard
Health, Loma Linda, CA, USA
e-mail: ckrause@llu.edu requiring physicians to be accountable for their

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 17


A. R. Ferreres (ed.), Surgical Ethics, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-05964-4_2
18 J. P. Namm and C. C. Krause

actions [1]. During the dark ages, the art of rather than dogma [5]. Furthermore, he believed
­medicine suffered as there was little accountabil- that if patients were sufficiently educated regard-
ity and physicians had little structure to guide ing the physician’s recommendations, they would
them. Medieval physicians were motivated more become more motivated to comply through a
by expedience than by beneficence. However, therapeutic relationship [6].
society in the eighteenth century witnessed resur- Although there is little mention of surgery in
gence in the profession of medicine through the his writings, Gregory does comment on the deco-
emergence of medical ethics by the work of two rum of a surgeon stating that a good operator
physicians, John Gregory and Thomas Percival. needs a resolute, collected mind, a good eye, and
These two individuals prepared the way for the a steady hand [3, 7]. His work helped redirect the
birth of modern medical ethics and laid the focus of medicine onto the relationship between
groundwork for many of the ethical principles the physician and patient which influenced many
that physicians uphold today. individuals, including Thomas Percival [1, 8].

John Gregory (1724–1773) Thomas Percival (1740–1804)

John Gregory was a physician and moralist from Through the influence of Gregory, Thomas
eighteenth century Scotland. During this time, Percival further pushed for the development of
modern surgery was in its infancy with the estab- medical ethics. He was a strong proponent in the
lishment of the Company of Surgeons in 1745 decorum of physicians and equality of treatment
and the Royal College of Surgeons of London in for all patients regardless of class. In his book
1800 that served to distinguish surgeons from Medical Ethics, he wrote about a physician’s
barbers [3]. The practice of medicine was duties, professional conduct, relationships with
extremely competitive and lacked a professional apothecaries, and duties relative to the law [9].
code of medical ethics. As a result, expedience He shifted the focus from a more physician-­
and self-interest prevailed with a concomitant centric profession to a patient-centric profession.
decline in medical competency. He stated: “The feelings and emotions of the
Gregory helped redefine medicine as a profes- patients, under critical circumstances, require to
sion by calling for physicians to set aside self-­ be known and to be attended to, no less than the
interest and to shift their focus back onto the symptoms of their disease” [9].
patient [4]. He emphasized the physician’s fidu- The American Medical Association (AMA)
ciary relationship to the patient and urged physi- was founded in 1847 through the influence of
cians to draw from a sense of sympathy: “The Percival [1]. It was his ideas on the professional
chief of these moral qualities required of a physi- responsibility toward patients laid the foundation
cian, is humanity; that sensibility that makes us for the 1847 AMA Code of Ethics, which became
feel for the distresses of our fellow-creatures, and the first national code of medical ethics [5, 10].
which, of consequence, incites in us the most Like Gregory, Percival also mentions little
powerful manner to relive them” [1]. He not only regarding surgery, but he was openly opposed to
emphasized the virtues of truth telling and patient itinerant surgery, emphasizing the importance of
confidentiality, which were progressive at the consultations before a surgeon operated on a
time, but he expected physicians to be knowl- patient [1, 3, 7]. He encouraged collaboration
edgeable in their treatment of patients and to con- between surgeons and physicians with a consen-
tinuously seek improvement in their area of sus agreement prior to any important surgical
practice. Medicine at that time was largely based operation [9]. And similarly to modern mortality
on authority and custom rather than scientific and morbidity conferences, he also encouraged
knowledge. Therefore, Gregory challenged phy- physicians to reflect on cases and to learn from
sicians to base medical decisions on evidence them: “An account of every case of ­operation,
The History of Surgical Ethics 19

which is rare, curious, or instructive should gery [12]. In 1846, John Warren and William
always be drawn up by the physician or surgeon, Morton successfully anesthetized a surgical
to whose charge it devolves, and entered in a reg- patient with ether in the Boston Ether Dome [13].
ister kept for the purpose, but open only to the Anesthesia dramatically changed the way that
physicians and hospital of the charity” [9]. surgeons approached disease as it allowed sur-
Though both Gregory and Percival did not geons to focus more on precision and technique
elaborate explicitly on surgical ethics, they were rather than speed. This changed not only how
the first to recognize surgery as a separate profes- surgery was performed but the men who were
sion and, more importantly, hold surgeons to the drawn to the field. Speed and nerves became less
same ethical standards as physicians. Going important compared to careful planning, thought-
forward, amidst the surgical advances of the
­ fulness, and refined skill. As surgery became
nineteenth and early twentieth century that dis- more accepted as an academic field, its recogni-
tinguished the field from the rest of medicine, it tion as a profession subsequently grew.
was surgeons who led the way to establish an The second major innovation was the advent
ethical code specific to surgery. of antisepsis. In 1850, over 90% of surgical
wounds became infected, and the mortality rate
for abdominal surgery was 75% [14]. In fact,
Story Apart from Text: Robert Liston many surgeons at that time considered abdominal
In the 1800s, amputations were a com- surgery unethical [15]. In 1867, Joseph Lister
monly performed procedure. Before the applied the concepts of microbiology from Louis
advent of anesthesia, surgeons needed to Pasteur and introduced the concept of hand wash-
perform surgeries as quickly as possible ing before a surgical procedure using carbolic
requiring multiple assistants to restrain the acid [13]. It did not catch on immediately, how-
awake patient. Robert Liston, a Scottish ever, as it took a few decades before surgeons
surgeon, boasted that he could perform a universally adopted the Lister sterile procedure.
leg amputation in under 2 minutes. It is In fact, by 1880, only a few surgeons had adopted
reported that during a demonstration of a sterile technique. But, it soon became apparent
leg amputation, he operated so quickly that that the patients of surgeons who practiced the
he accidently cut off his assistant’s finger. Lister technique fared better and were more
Furthermore, in his fervor, he also cut likely to recover [14]. Eventually, it became com-
through the coat of an elderly physician mon practice for all surgeons to wash their hands
bystander who subsequently had a heart before a procedure and later began wearing
attack and died thinking he had been gloves and using autoclaved instruments. Thus,
stabbed, as his coat was covered in blood. as the mortality rate for surgery decreased with
Both the patient and assistant eventually these advances, the field of surgery became more
died of gangrene. So in one operation, respected, and patients started viewing surgery as
Liston had a 300% mortality rate [11]. a viable option when they were ill resulting in an
increase in the rate of elective procedures.
As surgery became more common, this led to
new developments in surgical technique and
Birth of Modern Surgery advances in the field led by William Halsted.
Some of his advances included hernia repairs,
In the nineteenth century, two significant innova- mastectomies, vascular anastomosis, intestinal
tions—anesthesia and antisepsis—made it possi- anastomosis, thyroid procedures, and parathy-
ble for surgery to dramatically progress. Prior to roid transplants [12]. During this time of rapid
this, the mantra was to operate as quickly as pos- surgical innovation, there was little to no regula-
sible with patients physically restrained and often tion. New procedures were being attempted, and
passing out from the pain associated with the sur- individuals like Halsted had little idea of what
20 J. P. Namm and C. C. Krause

the long-term effects of procedures would be. incentive for the referring physician to recom-
Many innovations were actually performed by mend surgery to more patients. The concern was
itinerant surgeons who traveled from town to the significant financial conflict of interest with
town operating on patients referred to them by the potential of offering surgery for questionable
the local general practitioner [16]. At this time in if not inappropriate indications. Despite state-
history, surgeons were able to operate on a fully ments from the College against the unethical
anesthetized patient although a surgical informed practice of fee splitting, it persisted up into the
consent process had yet to be clearly defined. 1950s. In 1952, the ACS established a committee
The enthusiasm that surgeons had during this which conferred with the AMA trustees to
time of innovation likely led to more people develop a set of guidelines regarding fee split-
undergoing procedures than perhaps needed to ting declaring it unethical [14].
be done, which began to blur the lines of surgical Itinerant surgery was another issue that Martin
ethics [17]. felt needed to be addressed in the early stages of
the ACS. This was the practice of surgeons per-
forming surgeries, usually in rural areas, without
Surgical Ethics ever meeting the patient. Further, they would
depart after the surgery, leaving the management
Sir William Stokes of Scotland seems to be the of any postoperative complications to the medi-
first surgeon to mention the term surgical ethics. cal physician. Those in support of itinerant sur-
He stated in 1894: “A consideration of surgical gery stated that, though not ideal, it could fill the
ethics that frequently exercises the mind of the need for patients in rural areas that lacked access
operating surgeon is the question of the princi- to hospitals and surgical care [14]. However, the
ples that should guide him in dealing with can- ACS spoke against its practice because patient
cerous growths” [17]. However, surgical ethics well-being was at the core of its principles [3,
was merely in its infancy at the turn of the nine- 14]. The ethical issue that surfaced was the
teenth century. Surgeons in the 1900s began rec- importance of establishing a relationship between
ognizing the divergence in practice between the surgeon and patient prior to surgery.
medical physicians and surgeons due to advance- The College’s stance against fee splitting and
ments made in the 1800s. These created a unique itinerant surgery established ethical standards for
set of surgical issues, which required an expan- the emerging field of surgery reinforcing the
sion of medical ethics. In the early twentieth cen- importance of the patient, the surgeon-patient
tury, the AMA, the ethical voice at the time, relationship, and the duty of the surgeon to see
commented very little on surgical practice. their patient through to recovery. Influenced by
Franklin Martin, a well-respected surgeon in Gregory and Percival, the formation of surgery as
Chicago, recognized the need for a separate gov- a profession was founded on ethical principles
erning body to oversee surgeons. Martin, along centered on the surgeon-patient relationship.
with a few other surgeons, saw the need to create Martin and others realized the importance of
a professional society of surgeons that specifi- establishing societal trust and maintaining that
cally dealt with the emerging ethical issues trust by creating ethical and professional stan-
encountered in surgery as well as a governing dards in the field [14].
board that oversaw the establishment and mainte-
nance of standards in surgery [14]. In 1913, the
American College of Surgeons (ACS) was offi- Informed Consent
cially established.
Some of the major issues that Martin sought In the decision for surgery, the surgeon must
to address were fee splitting and itinerant sur- address the question of whether the risks of the
gery [14]. Fee splitting involved both the sur- operation outweigh the potential benefits to the
geon and referring physician and served as an patient [17]. Informed consent emerged as an
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
oligarchi. Fu assassinato nel 1832, da Sarah Jenkins, il cui marito era
stato ucciso trent’anni prima dai compagni di Farley, che impedivano gli
scioperi.

85. Le predizioni sociali di Everhard erano degne di nota. Con la stessa


chiarezza, come leggeva gli avvenimenti, prevedeva le defezioni dei
Sindacati privilegiati, la nascita e la lenta decadenza delle caste operaie,
come la lotta fra queste e l’oligarchia, per la direzione della macchina
del Governo.

86. Dobbiamo ammirare l’intuito di Everhard. Molto prima che la semplice


idea di città meravigliose, come Ardis e Asgard, nascesse nella mente
degli oligarchi, egli intravedeva queste città splendide e la necessità
della loro creazione.

87. Da quel giorno, sono passati tre secoli di dominio dell’Uomo, e oggi
calpestiamo le vie e abitiamo le città edificate dagli oligarchi. È vero che
abbiamo continuato a costruire, ma le città degli oligarchi sussistono; io
scrivo queste righe, in Ardis, una dalla più belle fra tutte.

88. Tutti i Sindacati delle ferrovie entrano in questa associazione. È


interessante osservare che la prima vera applicazione della politica delle
«parti dell’avanzo» era stata fatta nel Secolo XIX da un Sindacato di
ferrovieri, «l’Unione Fraterna del Meccanici delle locomotive», della
quale un certo P. M. Arthur era da vent’anni il capo. Dopo lo sciopero
della Pennsylvania Railroad nel 1877, egli sottopose ai meccanici delle
locomotive un disegno secondo il quale avrebbero dovuto intendersi
colla Direzione, staccandosi dagli altri Sindacati. Questo disegno
egoistico riuscì perfettamente; donde la parola «Arthurisation», per
significare la partecipazione dei Sindacati alla spoliazione. L’origine di
questa parola è stata per molto tempo dubbia per gli etimologi; ma mi
pare che tale origine sia ormai ben chiara.

89. Alberto Pocock, altro Farley, godeva, in quei lontani tempi, della stessa
notorietà; e fino alla morte riuscì a tenere soggetti tutti i minatori dal
Paese. Suo figlio, Levis Pocock, gli successe, e durante cinque
generazioni, il rinomato lignaggio del guardiaciurma ebbe la supremazia
sulle miniere di carbone. Pocock, il vecchio, conosciuto col nome di
Pocock Iº, è stato dipinto così: «Una testa lunga e sottile, mezzo
circondata da una frangia di capelli scuri e grigi, con zigomi salienti e un
grosso mento... Colorito pallido, occhi grigi senza splendore, voce
metallica, e un atteggiamento languido.» Era nato da genitori poveri e
aveva cominciato la sua carriera come garzone di bar. Divenne in
seguito poliziotto privato al servizio di una corporazione di tranvieri e al
trasformò a poco a poco in crumiro di professione.
Pocock Vº, l’ultimo della casata, morì in una camera, per lo scoppio di
una bomba durante una rivolta di minatori sul territorio indiano. Questo
avvenimento ebbe luogo nel 2073 dopo Gesù Cristo.

90. Quei gruppi di azione furono modellati in genere sul tipo delle
organizzazioni consimili della Rivoluzione Russa, e, nonostante gli sforzi
incessanti del Tallone di Ferro, durarono tre secoli, per tutto il periodo di
dominio del Tallone stesso. Composti di uomini e di donne ispirati da
propositi sublimi, e impavidi davanti alla morte, i Gruppi di
Combattimento esercitarono una prodigiosa influenza e moderarono la
brutalità dei governanti. La loro opera non si limitò a una guerra invisibile
contro gli agenti dell’oligarchìa. Gli oligarchi stessi e spesso, persino i
sottocapi degli oligarchi, ufficiali dell’esercito e capi delle caste operaie,
furono obbligati a prendere in considerazione i decreti dei Gruppi.
Le sentenze di questi rivendicatori organizzati erano conformi alla più
rigorosa giustizia; e soprattutto notevole era la loro procedura senza
passione e perfettamente giuridica. Non c’erano giudizi improvvisati.
Quando un uomo era preso, lo si giudicava lealmente e gli si lasciava la
possibilità di difendersi. Necessariamente, molti furono processati e
condannati per procura, come nel caso del generale Lampton, nel 2138
dopo G. C. Questi era forse il più sanguinario e il più crudele dei
mercenarii dell’oligarchia. Fu informato dai Gruppi di Combattimento che
era stato giudicato, riconosciuto colpevole e condannato a morte; e
questo avvertimento gli venne dato dopo di averlo tre volte esortato a
cessare dal trattare ferocemente il proletariato. Dopo questa condanna,
Lampton si circondò d’ogni mezzo di protezione, e, per anni ed anni i
Gruppi di Combattimento si sforzarono invano di eseguire la loro
sentenza. Molti compagni, uomini e donne, fallirono successivamente
nei loro tentativi e furono crudelmente condannati dall’oligarchia. Perciò
fu rimessa in vigore la crocifissione come mezzo di esecuzione legale.
Ma alla fine il condannato trovò il suo boia nella persona di una
giovinetta di diciassette anni, Maddalena Provence, che per ottenere il
suo scopo, serviva da due anni nel palazzo, come guardarobiera. Essa
morì dopo torture orribili e prolungate, in una cella. Ma oggi la sua statua
di bronzo sorge sul Pantheon della Fratellanza, nella meravigliosa Città
di Serles.
Noi che, per esperienza personale, non sappiamo che cosa sia un
omicidio, non dobbiamo giudicare troppo severamente gli eroi dei
Gruppi di Combattimento. Essi hanno dato la loro vita per l’umanità; per
la quale nessun sacrificio sembrava troppo grande. E, d’altra parte, una
necessità inesorabile li obbligava a dare al loro sentimento una forma
sanguinosa, in un’epoca sanguinaria. I Gruppi di Combattimento furono
l’unica freccia nel fianco che il Tallone di Ferro non potè mai estirparsi. A
Everhard spetta la paternità di questo strano esercito. I suoi successi e
la sua resistenza, durante trecento anni, mostrano la saggezza con la
quale egli organizzò, e la solidarietà della fondazione legata da lui ai
costruttori avvenire. Da certi punti di vista, questa organizzazione può
essere considerata come la sua opera principale, a parte il grande
valore dei suoi lavori economici e sociali e le sue gesta di capo supremo
della Rivoluzione.

91. Condizioni simili si osservano in India, nel secolo XIX, sotto il dominio
britannico. Gli indigeni morivano di fame a milioni, mentre i loro padroni
li privavano del frutto del lavoro e lo spendevano in cerimonie e cortei
feticisti. Non possiamo non vergognarci, in questo secolo di lumi, della
condotta dei nostri antenati, e dobbiamo limitarci a pensare
filosoficamente che nell’evoluzione sociale lo stadio capitalistico sia,
pressa poco, come l’età scimmiesca all’epoca dell’evoluzione animale.
L’Umanità doveva superare quei periodi per uscire dal fango degli
organismi inferiori; e le era naturalmente difficile liberarsi interamente di
quella viscida feccia.

92. Questa espressione è una trovata dovuta al genio di H. G. Wells, che


viveva alla fine del Secolo XIX. Era un veggente, in fatto di sociologia,
uno spirito sano e normale, e nello stesso tempo un cuore veramente
umano. Numerosi frammenti delle sue opere sono giunti fino a noi, e
due delle sue opere migliori: «Anticipations» e «Mankind in the Making»,
ci sono state conservate intatte. Prima degli oligarchi, e prima di
Everhard, Wells aveva preveduto la costruzione di città meravigliose di
cui parla nel suoi libri chiamandole «pleasure cities», città del piacere.

93. Persuasa che le sue memorie sarebbero state lette, nel suo tempo, Avis
Everhard ha tralasciato il risultato del processo per alto tradimento. Ci
sono nel manoscritto molte altre lacune del genere. Cinquantadue
membri socialisti del Congresso, furono giudicati e ritenuti colpevoli.
Cosa strana, però: nessuno fu condannato a morte. Everhard e undici
altri, fra cui Teodoro Donnelson e Matthew Kent, furono condannati al
carcere a vita.
Gli altri quaranta furono condannati, chi a trenta, chi a quarantacinque
anni; e Arturo Simpton, che il manoscritto dice ammalato di tifoidea al
momento dell’esplosione, non ebbe che quindici anni di carcere.
Secondo la tradizione, fu lasciato morire di fame nella sua cella per
punirlo della sua intransigenza ostinata, e del suo odio ardente ed
assoluto contro tutti i servi del dispotismo. Morì a Cabanas, nell’Isola di
Cuba, dove tre altri de’ suoi compagni erano detenuti. I cinquantadue
socialisti del Congresso furono rinchiusi nelle fortezze militari sparse sul
territorio degli Stati Uniti: così, Dubois e Woods furono rinchiusi a Porto
Rico; Everhard e Merryweather nell’isola di Alcatraz, nella baia di San
Francisco, che da molto tempo serviva da prigione militare.

94. Avis Everhard avrebbe dovuto aspettare molte generazioni prima di


ottenere la rivelazione del mistero. Quasi cento anni fa, e quindi più di
seicento anni dopo la sua morte, fu scoperta negli archivi segreti del
Vaticano, la confessione di Pervaise. Non è forse inopportuno fare un
cenno di quest’oscuro documento sebbene esso non abbia per gli storici
più alcun valore, ormai.
Pervaise, un americano di origine francese, nel 1913 era prigioniero a
Nuova York, in attesa di essere processato per omicidio. Sappiamo,
dalla sua confessione, che senza essere un criminale indurito, aveva un
carattere impulsivo, impressionabile ed appassionato. In un impeto di
gelosia folle aveva ucciso la moglie, cosa abbastanza comune, a quel
tempo. Il terrore della morte si impadronì di lui, come raccontò egli
stesso; e per sfuggirle si sentì disposto a fare qualunque cosa. Gli
agenti segreti, per ridurlo alle loro mire, gli confermarono che si era reso
colpevole di omicidio di primo grado, delitto che era punito colla pena
capitale, giacchè il condannato veniva legato a una poltrona apposita, e
per cura di medici specialisti era ucciso dalla corrente elettrica. Questo
modo di esecuzione chiamato elettrocuzione, era molto in voga, a quel
tempo: solo tempo dopo, fu sostituito dall’anestesia. Quest’uomo, che
non aveva cuore cattivo, ma una natura superficiale improntata a
un’animalità violenta, a che aspettava in una cella l’inevitabile morte, si
lasciò facilmente convincere a gettare una bomba alla Camera.
Dichiara, anzi, nella sua confessione, che gli agenti del Tallone dì Ferro
gli affermarono che l’ordigno sarebbe stato inoffensivo, e che non
avrebbe ucciso nessuno. Egli fu introdotto di nascosto in un palco
ostentatamente chiuso col pretesto ch’era in riparazione, e, incaricato di
scegliere il momento opportuno per gettare la bomba, conferma
ingenuamente che tanto era l’interessamento pel discorso di Ernesto e
pel tumulto suscitato da questo, che per poco non dimenticò il compito
affidatogli.
Non soltanto Pervaise fu liberato, ma gli fu concessa una pensione per
tutta la vita. Ma non potè fruirne a lungo: nel settembre del 1914 fu
colpito da reumatismo al cuore e morì dopo tre giorni. Allora mandò a
chiamare un prete cattolico, al quale fece la confessione. Il Padre
Durban, considerandola molto grave, la scrisse e la firmò, come
testimonio. Noi possiamo soltanto fare delle congetture su quanto
avvenne dopo. Il documento era certo abbastanza importante per
trovare la via di Roma. Potenti influenze furono messe in movimento per
evitare la divulgazione. Soltanto nel secolo scorso, Lorbia, il celebre
scienziato italiano, durante le sue ricerche, lo scoprì. Oggi, dunque, non
rimane alcun dubbio che il Tallone di Ferro sia il responsabile
dell’esplosione del 1913. Ed anche se la confessione di Pervaise non
avesse mai veduto la luce non vi sarebbe potuto essere dubbio
ragionevole: quell’atto che mandò in prigione cinquantadue deputati, è
della stessa natura degli altri innumerevoli delitti commessi dagli
oligarchi, e, prima di essi, dai capitalisti.
Come esempio classico di massacri di innocenti, commessi con ferocia
e indifferenza, bisogna citare quello dei cosiddetti anarchici di
Haymarket, a Chicago, nella penultima decade del secolo XIX. Bisogna
considerare a parte l’incendio doloso e la distrazione dei possedimenti
capitalistici compiuti dai capitalisti medesimi. Per delitti di questo genere
furono puniti numerosi innocenti, messi in ferrovia, (railroaded) secondo
un’espressione usata allora, nel senso che i giudici si erano intesi prima,
per liquidare i conti.
Durante le rivolte del lavoro che scoppiarono nella prima decade del
secolo XX fra i capitalisti e la Federazione Occidentale dei Minatori, fu
adoperata una tattica simile, ma più sanguinosa. Gli agenti dei capitalisti
fecero saltare in aria la stazione della ferrovia a Indipendenza: tredici
uomini furono uccisi, e molti altri feriti. I capitalisti che guidavano il
meccanismo legislativo e giudiziario dello Stato del Colorado,
accusarono di questo delitto i minatori e per poco non li fecero
condannare. Romaines, uno degli strumenti di questo «affare», era in
prigione in un altro Stato, nel Kansas, quando gli agenti del capitalisti gli
proposero il colpo. Ma le confessioni di Romaines furono pubblicate
durante la sua vita, al contrario di quelle di Pervaise. Nello stesso
tempo, vi fu ancora il caso di Moyer e Haywood, due capi di lavoratori,
forti e risoluti: l’uno presidente e l’altro segretario della Federazione
Occidentale dei Minatori. L’ex Governatore dell’Idaho era stato
assassinato misteriosamente; i socialisti e i minatori avevano
apertamente incolpato di questo delitto i proprietarî delle miniere. Pure,
violando le norme costituzionali statali, in seguito a una intesa fra i
governatori dell’Idaho e del Colorado, Moyer e Haywood furono presi,
gettati in carcere e accusati dell’omicidio.
Questo fatto provocò la seguente protesta di Eugenio V. Deba, capo del
Socialismo americano: «I capi del lavoratori, che non si possono
corrompere, si arrestano o si assassinano. Moyer e Haywood, sono
colpevoli soltanto del reato di fedeltà tenace e inconcussa alla classe
operaia. I capitalisti hanno spogliato il nostro paese, corrotto la nostra
politica, disonorato la nostra giustizia; ci hanno calpestato coi loro
scarponi ferrati, ed ora si propongono di ammazzare coloro che non
sono così abbietti da sottomettersi al loro brutale dominio. I governatori
del Colorado e dell’Idaho non fanno che eseguire gli ordini dei loro
padroni: i plutocrati. La lotta è incominciata fra i lavoratori e la
plutocrazia. Questa può, sì, assestare il primo colpo violento, ma noi
daremo l’ultimo».

95. Questa scena ridicola costituisce un documento tipico dell’epoca, e


dipinge bene la condotta di quel padroni senza cuore. Mentre il popolo
moriva di fame, i cagnolini di lusso avevano delle speciali cameriere. Il
travestimento dì Avis Everliard era una cosa ben pericolosa, ma era un
caso di vita o di morte ed era in gioco la causa, ed è perciò da
considerarsi veritiero.

96. Pullman, si chiamavano così le vetture più lussuose dei treni di quel
tempo, dal nome del loro inventore.

97. Nonostante i continui pericoli, quasi inimmaginabili, Anna Roylston


raggiunse la bella età di anni novantuno. Come i Pococks sfuggirono
agli esecutori del Gruppi di Combattimento, essa sfidò quelli del Tallone
di Ferro. Prospera in mezzo ai pericoli, la suo vita sembrava protetta da
un sortilegio. Essa stessa si era fatta giustiziera per conto di Gruppi di
Combattimento: la chiamavano la Vergine Rossa e diventò una delle
eroine della Rivoluzione. All’età di sessantanove anni, uccise Halcliffe «il
sanguinario», circondato da una scorta, e scappò, senza neppure una
scalfittura. Morì di vecchiaia nel suo letto, in un rifugio segreto e sicuro
di rivoluzionarî, sulle montagne di Ozark.

98. Socialista Labor Party.

99. Nonostante tutte le ricerche fra i documenti dell’epoca, non abbiamo


potuto trovare nessuna allusione al personaggio in questione. Non ne
parla che il manoscritto di Everhard.

100. Il viaggiatore curioso che si dirigesse verso il Sud, partendo da Glen-


Ellen, si troverebbe su un viale che segue precisamente l’antica strada
di sette secoli or sono. Un quarto di miglio da Glen-Ellen, dopo aver
passato il secondo ponte, vedrebbe a destra un botro che si estende
come una cicatrice, attraverso un gruppo di monticelli boscosi. Questo
botro rappresenta il posto dove si esercitava l’antico diritto di passaggio
che esisteva in quel tempo di proprietà individuale attraverso i terreni di
un certo signor Chauvet, pioniere francese venuto in California all’epoca
del cercatori d’oro. I monticelli boscosi, sono quelli di cui parla Avis
Everhard. Il grande terremoto del 2368, staccò il fianco di uno di quei
rialzi che riempì il baratro ove gli Everhard avevano il loro rifugio. Ma
dopo la scoperta del manoscritto sono stati fatti degli scavi, ed è stata
trovata la casa con le due camere interne contenenti gli utensili
accumulati durante una lunga residenza. Fra le altre reliquie degne di
nota, è stato trovato l’apparecchio distruttore del fumo, di cui si parla in
questo racconto. Gli studiosi che si interessassero dell’argomento in
questione, potrebbero leggere il volume di Arnold Bentham, che uscirà
in questi giorni.
A un miglio a nord ovest dei monticelli, si trova l’area della Wake Robin
Lodge, alla confluenza della Wild Water e della Sonoma. Osserviamo di
sfuggita che la Wild Water si chiamava un tempo Graham Greek, come
si legge in alcune vecchie carte. Ma il nuovo nome perdura. A Wake
Robin Lodge, Avis Everhard dimorò, poi, a parecchie riprese, quando,
mutatasi in agente provocatore del Tallone di Ferro, potè rappresentare
impunemente la sua parte, in mezzo agli uomini e agli avvenimenti. Il
permesso ufficiale le fu concesso da un signorotto non meno autorevole
del signor Wickson, l’oligarca secondario di cui tratta il manoscritto.

101. In quest’epoca il travestimento diventò una vera arte. I rivoluzionarî


avevano delle scuole di attori in tutti i loro rifugi. Sdegnavano gli
accessorî degli artisti ordinari come false barbe e parrucche, ch’erano
una trappola. Il travestimento doveva essere fondamentale, intrinseco,
doveva costituire nell’individuo come una seconda natura. Si racconta
che la Vergine Rossa fosse diventata seguace di quest’arte, alla quale si
deve il successo della lunga carriera di lei.

102. Queste sparizioni erano uno degli orrori dell’epoca. Di esse si parla
continuamente, nelle canzoni e nelle storie. Erano un risultato inevitabile
della guerra insidiosa che infuriò durante quei tre secoli. La cosa era
però frequente anche presso gli oligarchi e le classi operaie. Senza
preavviso, senza chiasso, uomini, donne e bambini sparivano; non si
rivedevano più, e la loro fine rimaneva avvolta nel mistero.

103. Du Bois, attuale bibliotecario di Ardis, discende in linea diretta da quei


rivoluzionarî.

104. Oltre le caste operaie, vi era la casta militare formata da un esercito


regolare di soldati di professione, i cui ufficiali erano membri
dall’Oligarchia, conosciuti tutti col nome di Mercenarî. Questa istituzione
sostituiva la milizia, divenuta impossibile sotto il nuovo regime. Era stato
istituito un servizio segreto di Mercenarî, oltre quello del Tallone di Ferro,
ch’era un che di mezzo fra l’esercito e la polizia.

105. Solo dopo la sconfitta della seconda rivolta, il gruppo dei Rossi di San
Francisco ricominciò a prosperare; e per due generazioni fu fiorente.
Allora un agente del Tallone di Ferro riuscì a farsi ammettere in esso e a
penetrarne tutti i segreti, conducendolo così alla fatale distruzione. Ciò
accadde nel 2002. I membri del Gruppo furono giustiziati, ad uno ad
uno, a tre settimane d’intervallo, e i loro cadaveri furono esposti nel
Ghetto del Lavoro di San Francisco.

106. Il rifugio di Benton Harbour era una catacomba la cui entrata era
abilmente dissimulata da un pozzo. È stata conservata in buono stato;
così che i visitatori possono attualmente percorrere il labirinto dei
corridoi fino alla sala delle riunioni, dove certamente avvenne la scena
descritta da Avis Everhard. Più oltre, sono le celle dove erano tenuti i
prigionieri, e la camera mortuaria dove avevano lungo le esecuzioni; più
lontano ancora, il cimitero: un insieme di lunghe e tortuose gallerie
scavate nella roccia, aventi, a ogni lato, nicchie dove riposano i
Rivoluzionari ivi deposti dai loro compagni, da tanti anni ormai.

107. A quest’epoca vi era ancora la poligamia in Turchia.

108. Il fior fiore del mondo artistico e intellettuale era composto di


rivoluzionarî. Ad eccezione di pochi musicisti e cantanti e di qualche
oligarca, tutti i grandi creatori dell’epoca, tutti coloro i cui nomi sono
giunti sino a noi, appartenevano alla rivoluzione.

109. Anche in quest’epoca la panna e il burro si estraevano ancora dal latte


di vacca, con procedimenti grossolani. Non era incominciata la
preparazione chimica del cibi.

110. Nei documenti letterarî dell’epoca si parla costantemente dei poemi di


Rudolph Mendenhall, che i suoi compagni chiamavano «La Fiamma».
Era di grande ingegno, però, tranne qualche frammento fantastico, citato
da altri autori, di lui non ci è giunto altro. Fu giustiziato dal Tallone di
Ferro, nel 1928.

111. Il caso di questo giovanotto non è straordinario. Molti figli d’oligarchi,


moralmente o romanticamente, votarono la loro vita all’ideale
rivoluzionario, spinti da un sentimento di onestà o dal fatto che la loro
fantasia era stata sedotta dall’aspetto glorioso della rivoluzione. Già
prima molti figli di nobili russi avevano fatto lo stesso, durante la lunga
rivoluzione del loro paese.
112. I Mercenarî ebbero una parte importante, negli ultimi tempi del Tallone di
Ferro. Essi mantenevano l’equilibrio del potere nei conflitti fra Oligarchi e
caste operaie, gettando il peso della loro forza sull’uno o sull’altro
piattello, secondo il gioco degli intrighi e delle cospirazioni.

113. Dall’inconsistenza e incoerenza del capitalismo, trassero tuttavia gli


Oligarchi una nuova etica coerente e definita, decisa e rigida come
l’acciaio, la più assurda e la meno scientifica e nello stesso tempo la più
possente che abbia mai servito una classe di tiranni. Gli oligarchi
credevano nella loro morale, sebbene essa fosse smentita dalla biologia
e dall’evoluzione, e per tre secoli poterono arrestare il movimento
potente del progresso umano: esempio profondo, terribile, sconcertante
per il moralista metafisico, e che deve ispirare al materialista molti dubbi
e ritorni su se stesso.

114. Ardis fu terminata nel 1924, e Asgard nel 1984. La costruzione di


quest’ultima durò cinquantadue anni, e occorse un lavoro continuo di
mezzo milione di servi. In certi periodi, il loro numero superò il milione,
senza tener conto delle centinaia di migliaia di lavoratori privilegiati e di
artisti.

115. Fra i Rivoluzionarî, c’erano numerosi chirurghi che avevano acquistato


una grande abilità nella vivisezione. Secondo le parole stesse di Avis
Everhard, potevano letteralmente trasformare un uomo in un altro. Per
essi l’eliminazione di cicatrici e deformità era un gioco. Mutavano le
linee del volto con tale cura minuziosa, che non rimaneva traccia
dell’operazione. Il naso era uno degli organi preferiti per tali operazioni.
Innestare la pelle e trasportare i capelli era una cosa ordinaria per essi,
che ottenevano cambiamenti d’espressione, con un’abilità strana, e
modificavano radicalmente gli occhi, le sopracciglia, le labbra, la bocca,
le orecchie. Mediante speciali procedimenti, alla lingua, alla gola, alla
laringe, alle fosse nasali, poteva essere modificato persino il modo di
parlare. A quell’epoca di disperazione occorrevano rimedî disperati, e i
medici rivoluzionarî assurgevano all’altezza del tempi. Tra gli altri
prodigi, era la possibilità d’ingrandire un adulto di tre o quattro pollici o
rimpicciolirlo di uno o due. La loro arte oggi è perduta. Non ne abbiamo
più bisogno.

116. Chicago era il pandemonio industriale del XIX secolo.


Viene riferito in proposito un curioso aneddoto di John Burns, grande
capo socialista inglese, che fu per qualche tempo membro del
Gabinetto. Egli visitava gli Stati Uniti quando, a Chicago, un giornalista
gli domandò cosa pensasse di questa città: «Chicago! — rispose, — è
un’edizione tascabile dell’inferno». Poco tempo dopo, mentre
s’imbarcava per ritornare in Inghilterra, un altro reporter lo avvicinò per
chiedergli se avevo modificato la sua opinione su Chicago: «Sì,
certamente! — rispose John Burns — La mia opinione attuale è che
l’inferno è un’edizione tascabile di Chicago».

117. Nome del treno reputato, a quell’epoca, il più rapido del mondo.

118. A quell’epoca la popolazione era così rada che pullulavano le bestie


selvatiche ed erano un vero flagello. In California si introdusse l’uso
delle cacce battute contro i conigli. A un dato giorno, tutti i fittavoli d’una
località si riunivano e percorrevano la contrada in linee convergenti,
spingendo i conigli a ventine di migliaia verso un recinto preparato
prima, dove uomini e ragazzi li uccidevano a colpi di randello.

119. Si è a lungo chiesto se il ghetto del sud fosse stato incendiato


incidentalmente o volontariamente dai Mercenarî. Ora è assodato che
furono questi ad appiccar l’incendio

120. Molte case resistettero più di una settimana: una di esse resistette
undici giorni. Ogni casa fu presa d’assalto come un forte, e i Mercenarî
furono obbligati ad attaccare piano per piano. Fu una lotta micidiale.
Non si chiedeva nè si concedeva tregua. In quel genere di
combattimento, i rivoluzionarii avevano il vantaggio di essere in alto.
Furono alla fine distrutti, ma a prezzo di forti perdite. Il fiero proletariato
di Chicago si mostrò degno della sua antica reputazione. Tanti morti
ebbe, altrettanti nemici uccise.

121. Gli annali di questo intermezzo di sconforto furono scritti col sangue. La
vendetta era il motivo dominante; i membri delle organizzazioni terroriste
non si preoccupavano punto della loro vita e non sapevano nulla
dell’avvenire. I Danites, ch’ebbero nome dagli angeli vendicatori della
Mitologia dei Mormoni, e origini nelle montagne del Great West, si
sparsero lungo tutta la costa del Pacifico, dal Panama all’Alaska. Le
Valchirie erano una organizzazione di donne, e la più terribile di tutte.
Non era ammessa nell’organizzazione se non colei che avesse avuto
parenti prossimi assassinati dall’Oligarchia. Avevano la crudeltà di
torturare i loro prigionieri fino alla morte. Un’altra famosa organizzazione
femminile era quella delle Vedove di Guerra. I Berserkers (guerrieri
invulnerabili della mitologia scandinava) formavano un gruppo affine a
quello delle Valchirie, composto di uomini che non davano importanza
alla vita. Furono essi a distruggere completamente la città dei Mercenarî
chiamata Bellona, con una popolazione di più di centomila anime. I
Bedlamiti e i Helldamiti erano associazioni gemelle di schiavi. Una
nuova setta religiosa, che non prosperò a lungo, si chiamava «Lo
sdegno di Dio». Questi gruppi di gente terribilmente seria, avevano i
nomi più fantastici; fra gli altri: «I cuori sanguinanti»; «I figli dell’alba»;
«Le stelle mattutine»; «I fenicotteri»; «I tre triangoli»; «Le tre Barre»; «I
Rubonici»; «I Vendicatori»; «Gli Apaches» e gli «Erebusiti».

122. Qui è interrotto il manoscritto di Everhard. Fu interrotto bruscamente, a


mezzo d’una frase. Avis dovette essere avvisata dell’arrivo dei
Mercenarî, perchè ebbe tempo di mettere in salvo il manoscritto prima di
scappare o di essere fatta prigioniera. È doloroso che non sia vissuta
per finirlo, poichè avrebbe certamente fatta la luce sul mistero che, da
settecento anni, avvolge la condanna e la morte di Ernesto Everhard.
Nota del Trascrittore

Ortografia e punteggiatura originali sono state


mantenute, correggendo senza annotazione minimi
errori tipografici.
Copertina creata dal trascrittore e posta nel pubblico
dominio.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK IL TALLONE DI
FERRO ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions


will be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright
in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and
distribute it in the United States without permission and without
paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General
Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and
distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the
PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept and trademark. Project
Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if
you charge for an eBook, except by following the terms of the
trademark license, including paying royalties for use of the
Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is
very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such
as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
research. Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and
printed and given away—you may do practically ANYTHING in
the United States with eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright
law. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially
commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the


free distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this
work (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase
“Project Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of
the Full Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or
online at www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand,
agree to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual
property (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to
abide by all the terms of this agreement, you must cease using
and return or destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee for
obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg™
electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the terms
of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only


be used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by
people who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement.
There are a few things that you can do with most Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works even without complying with the
full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There
are a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg™
electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement and
help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg™
electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright
law in the United States and you are located in the United
States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying,
distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works
based on the work as long as all references to Project
Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will
support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting free
access to electronic works by freely sharing Project
Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this
agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms
of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with
its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it
without charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside
the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to
the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying,
displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works
based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The
Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright
status of any work in any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project


Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project
Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed,
viewed, copied or distributed:

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United


States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it
away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg
License included with this eBook or online at
www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United
States, you will have to check the laws of the country where
you are located before using this eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is


derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to
anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges.
If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the
phrase “Project Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of
paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use
of the work and the Project Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth
in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is


posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and
distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder.
Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™
License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright
holder found at the beginning of this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files
containing a part of this work or any other work associated with
Project Gutenberg™.
1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute
this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1
with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the
Project Gutenberg™ License.

1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if
you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project
Gutenberg™ work in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or
other format used in the official version posted on the official
Project Gutenberg™ website (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at
no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a
means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other
form. Any alternate format must include the full Project
Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™
works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or


providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project


Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different
terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain
permission in writing from the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, the manager of the Project Gutenberg™
trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3
below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on,
transcribe and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright
law in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite
these efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the
medium on which they may be stored, may contain “Defects,”
such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt
data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other
medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES -


Except for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in
paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic
work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for
damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU
AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE,
STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH
OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH
1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER
THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR
ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE
OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF
THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If


you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of
receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you
paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you
received the work from. If you received the work on a physical
medium, you must return the medium with your written
explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the
defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu
of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or
entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund.
If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund
in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set


forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’,
WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS

You might also like