Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

S63

Parasites, desiderata lists and the paradox of the organism

R. DAWKINS
Department of Zoology, University of Oxford

Key words: parasites, evolution, organism.


argue - wrongly - that the species is an optimon,
INTRODUCTION
meaning that there are adaptations that are for the
Eavesdrop morning coffee at any major centre of good of the species. I have joined others in making
evolutionary theory today, and you will find 'para- the case that the optimon must be a self-replicating
site' to be one of the commonest words in the entity, and that therefore even the organism is not a
language. Parasites are touted as prime movers in the true optimon. Genes, and to a lesser extent larger
evolution of sex, promising the final solution to that fragments of genomes, are true self-replicating
problem of problems, the puzzle that led G. C. entities. Organisms, even asexually reproducing
Williams to proclaim in 1975 'a kind of crisis' at organisms, are not.
hand in evolutionary biology (Hamilton, 1980; Examine the logic of modern natural selection
Tooby, 1982; Seger & Hamilton, 1988). Parasites theory in sexual populations and observe that it is all
seem to offer a plausible justification for the about changes in frequencies of copies of things. In
otherwise futile effort females put into choosing practice these things are genes, in the sense of
among posturing males (Hamilton & Zuk, 1982; but Mendelian units independently assorting in gene
see Read, 1990). Frequency-dependent selection pools, but any self-replicating entity would do in
exerted by parasites is, according to one admittedly principle. In the perspective of evolutionary time,
minority view, largely responsible for the high levels the genes inhabit not a pool b u t a river, flowing
of diversity found in gene pools (Clarke, 1979). One through time, a broad-fronted turbulent river down
might even extrapolate to a time when the entire which the Mendelian particles zig-zag their way,
metazoan body could come to be seen as a gigantic changing partners at every generation, some in-
adaptation against microscopic pathogens. creasing in frequency, others decreasing. Successful
I want to use parasites in an entirely different kind genes are those that become more frequent, un-
of evolutionary argument, almost a philosophical successful ones those that become less frequent. But
argument. Parasites have a role in clarifying the very individual organisms do not have a frequency at all,
meaning of that most basic unit in the hierarchy of or rather each individual has a frequency of one.
life, the organism itself (Dawkins, 1982, 1989). This is one reason why genes, but not organisms, can
Parasites help us to think straight about the problem be optimons.
that I shall call the 'Paradox of the Organism'. The other reason is more important, and it applies
Much of the background to what I shall say is whether reproduction is sexual or asexual. It is that
discussed at greater length, as part of a com- genes, but not organisms, form replicating lineages
prehensive vision of life, in my book The Extended in which copying errors are passed in one direction
Phenotype. I shall not bother with further detailed along the lineage. Even in an asexual lineage of
citations of this book. organisms, for instance a mother to daughter to
To show the direction in which I am going, let me grand-daughter lineage of asexually reproducing
anticipate my answer to the question 'What is the Daphnia, the organisms are not true replicas of the
organism?' It will turn out that an individual previous generation. T o be sure, they resemble the
organism is an entity all of whose genes share the previous generation and may even be indistinguish-
same stochastic expectations of the distant future. I able from the previous generation. But identity is not
shall begin by showing one thing that the organism the same thing as heredity: heredity has causal
is not, though it is usually thought to be, namely a directionality. Clonal organisms resemble each other
unit of natural selection. in the same sense as 100 copies of a book run off the
same printing press resemble each other. Maybe you
can't distinguish one copy from another, but they
THE ORGANISM IS NOT AN 'OPTIMON1' have not derived their characteristics one from
I have used the word 'optimon ' for that kind of unit another. All have derived their characteristics from
in the hierarchy of life about which we may say: the same parent, the same printer's block. In order to
' Such and such an adaptation is for the benefit of simulate true heredity you would take one copy of
that unit.' For instance, a group selectionist might the book and Xerox it. Then Xerox a copy of the

Parasitology (1990), 100, S63-S73 Printed in Great Britain


R. Dawkins S64

copy, then a copy of that copy and so on. If you made world of the gene seems bounded by the skin of a
100 copies of a book by that method there would be particular individual organism. Its companions are
a true hereditary succession among the copies: the other genes that happen to make up the genome
number 49 would be the daughter of number 48 and of that organism. And it cooperates with those other
the mother of number 50, and so on. genes to produce a huge — by gene standards
The operational test of whether we have true — machine, bristling with apparently purposeful
heredity is to examine the fate of copying errors. In technical wizardry. To repeat, the paradox of the
a lineage of Daphnia, blemishes to genomes are organism is the paradox that organisms are such
inherited by subsequent members of the lineage; marvels of cooperative engineering; yet the
blemishes to bodies — lost limbs, for instance — are cooperating genetic replicators that build them, in
not. In terms of the book analogy, what is passed their other role as denizens of deep time, would seem
from mother to daughter is not a body but the to have every reason not to cooperate, every reason to
printer's block that made the body. Each body is cheat on their temporary partners and steal a march
independently run off a copy of the same printer's down the next reach of the evolutionary river. Why is
block, not run off any other body. Needless to say, the organism not torn apart by the conflicting
this isn't a new point. I am simply reiterating the interests of the multitude of self-interested units that
Weismannian dogma of the continuity of the germ it contains ?
line and the non-inheritance of acquired The potential for tearing apart is ever present. It is
characteristics. starkly demonstrated by the phenomenon of Meiotic
Organisms, then, are not replicators. So, what are Drive, and rather more subtly made manifest in the
they ? The answer is that they are vehicles for chain of reasoning that leads to the doctrine of the
replicators, built by a cooperative of independently 'extended phenotype'. I shall take these in order.
assorting replicators. As such, they are extremely
impressive units of function, but they are, never-
MEIOTIC DRIVE
theless, not replicators. The organism is not an
optimon. We should strictly never say of an Meiotic drive is well known and I can be brief. In
adaptation such as a wing or a behaviour pattern that normal meiosis, each member of an allelic pair
it is for the benefit of the organism. Nevertheless, enjoys an equal chance of getting into each gamete.
organisms are such coherent units of function that it Meiosis is a biological process like any other, and it
is extremely tempting to see organisms as units that can come under genetic influence like any other. If a
work to maximize something on behalf of all their gene happens to arise whose phenotypic effect is to
genes. Their existence as cohesive units of function, bias meiosis, so as to give itself more than the usual
in the teeth of potential conflict among the true 50 % probability of getting into each gamete, that
replicators that they contain, constitutes a paradox gene will tend to spread through the gene pool, even
which I shall call the Paradox of the Organism. if, as is usually the case, its other effects are
deleterious. The phenomenon really exists, and it is
called meiotic drive. The best known meiotic drive
THE PARADOX OF THE ORGANISM
gene is the Segregation Distorter gene in Drosophila
The paradox of the organism is that it is not torn (Ciow, 1979). Now, one way of expressing the
apart by its conflicting replicators but stays together paradox of the organism is this. Why aren't all genes
and works as a purposeful entity, apparently on segregation distorters or worse? Why, instead, do
behalf of all of them. Not only is it not torn apart; it most genes submit to the discipline of cooperating
functions as such a convincingly unified whole that with one another in building a shared phenotype ?
biologists in general have not seen that there is a
paradox at all! They have wrongly taken the
THE EXTENDED PHENOTYPE
organism for granted as the unit about which
questions of adaptation should be asked. I usually demonstrate the extended phenotype in
It is possible to do the mathematics of natural easy stages, beginning with the demonstration that
selection completely forgetting that, as a matter of an animal artifact, like a bird's nest, is a phenotype
fact, the genes are not swishing about in a liquid pool like any other, under the control of the animal's
or river but bound up in solid chunks - organisms genes in exactly the same sense as the shape of its
- and colossal chunks at that. The gene inhabits beak is under the control of its genes. So, there can
two time-scales, two worlds, corresponding to its be genes 'for' nest shape, nest colour and so on, in
two roles. In its evolutionary role the gene inhabits exactly the same sense as there are genes 'for' tail
eternity, or at least geological time. Its companions in length or eye colour. I then go on to parasites
the river of evolutionary time are other genes, and manipulating their hosts, and demonstrate that the
the fact that in any one generation they inhabit modification to the host, whether it is morphological,
individual bodies can almost be forgotten. physiological or behavioural, can be seen as pheno-
But in its other role, its embryological role, the typic expression of the parasite's genes. The final
The paradox of the organism S65

stage in the argument, the idea of genetic ' action at


ADAPTATION OR BORING BYPRODUCT?
a distance', again uses parasites, this time parasites
such as cuckoos whose manipulation is achieved by In many cases, undoubtedly, parasites benefit by
remote control. By the same logic as before, the their intermediate hosts's being devoured by their
modification to the host's behaviour can be seen as final host. Moreover, intermediate hosts are often, as
phenotypic expression of the parasite's genes. The a matter of fact, more likely to be eaten by final
'central theorem of the extended phenotype' hosts if they contain a parasite than if they don't. It
(Dawkins, 1982) is this: is tempting, therefore, to believe that this desirable
outcome has been engineered by the parasite. But
An animal's phenotype tends to maximize the survival of
there is always an alternative, killjoy explanation, the
the genes ' for' that phenotype, whether or not those genes
'boring byproduct' theory. Parasites are naturally
happen to be in the body of the particular animal
performing it. expected to have a debilitating effect on hosts, and
this obviously could make them less nimble in flight
Here I will leave out the artifacts and go straight to from predators. So the apparent adaptation could be
the parasites. The literature on parasites manipu- merely a side-effect.
lating their hosts has been reviewed several times Even the boring byproduct theory allows the
recently (Holmes & Bethel, 1972; Ewald, 1980; possibility that natural selection has, indeed, worked
Dobson, 1988; Keymer & Read, 1990; Moore & on parasites to increase the extent to which they make
Gotelli, 1990; the medical and epidemiological hosts feel ill, because of the benefit to the parasite.
implications have been reviewed by Ewald, But we are going to be impressed only in those cases
1980). where the intermediate host is made to do something
A typical and favourite example is the fluke that we should not obviously expect tin the boring
Dicrocoelium dendriticum, whose ungulate definitive byproduct theory. As in the case of any scientific
host needs to eat its ant intermediate host in order for theory, its predictions impress us only to the extent
the worm to complete its life-cycle. This aptly named that they are counterintuitive. It is not a theory's
' brainworm' burrows into the suboesophageal fault if its predictions happen to go along with
ganglion of the ant and, significantly, the ant's common sense, but nevertheless it can't expect us to
behaviour changes. Infected ants climb to the top of be impressed ! It is no use, moreover, multiplying up
grass stems at a time of day when normal ants would the number of different examples showing the same
retreat underground. There they clamp their jaws in kind of thing, if all the examples predict the same
the stem and remain as if alseep, immobile and commonsensical principle.
vulnerable to being grazed by ungulates. This story, What evidence would impress us ? There are
like many others, has long been treated as a plausible basically two kinds of effects on hosts that might
case of parasites manipulating their hosts for their persuade me that they are true parasitic adaptations.
own advantage (Wickler, 1976; Love, 1980). All that The first possibility is that, far from being made ill,
I am adding to this familiar point is that it must be the host might have some aspect of its life apparently
the parasite's genes that are doing the manipulating improved by the parasite. (Of course it is important to
and that, if you examine what it ever means to talk of stress 'some aspects' and 'apparently', otherwise we
genes as having phenotypic expression, it follows beg the whole question of whether the parasite is a
that the parasite's genes are having phenotypic parasite at all.) Thus, instead of being made smaller
expression in the host's body. by a parasite, hosts are sometimes made larger. This
I shall return to this logical argument about is often true in those cases known as 'parasitic
parasite genes having extended phenotypic effects castration' (Reinhard, 1956; Baudoin, 1975; Moore
upon host bodies. Meanwhile I must concede that it & Gotelli, 1990). And Noble & Noble's (1976)
depends upon the assumption that the host really is textbook describes the following case:
being manipulated for the benefit of the parasite:
that the host's altered phenotype really is an Some species of carpenter ants infected with metacercariae
adaptation for the benefit of the parasite. It isn't of the fluke Brachylecithutn mosquensis, are more obese than
always easy to be sure whether a phenotype is an noninfected ants and, unlike the latter, they do not conceal
themselves but crawl on exposed surfaces where they are
adaptation at all, or simply a byproduct, and the
easily found by birds that are the next hosts of the fluke.
question of parasites affecting hosts is indeed one of This behaviour seems to be a remarkable example of an
the areas in which this is disputed. This topic needs animal that sacrifices its life for its parasites. The
a digression. It is also possible in some cases that the 'sacrifice', of course, is induced by the parasite.
phenotype is an adaptation, not for the benefit of the
parasite but for the benefit of the host in combating Presumably the fluke benefits, not only by making
the parasite. I shall mention this at the end of the the ants crawl in exposed locations where birds can
digression. see them, but also by making the ants fatter and more
tempting targets for the birds. T h e economic
resources used by the ants to grow larger are not, of
R. Dawkins S66

course, provided by the parasite. The resources must book) able to see something so small as a gordian
be robbed from other uses in the ant colony to which worm bursting out of a bee ?
they might have been put: perhaps larvae went The second type of case in which the boring
hungry as the infected ants were induced to eat more byproduct theory seems less plausible is where the
and wax fat. parasite achieves a detailed fit to some complicated
Turning to behaviour, sometimes parasites, far aspect of its host's physiology, something too
from making their hosts seedy and listless, seem to statistically improbable to have come about by
pep up their activity levels. Moore & Gotelli (1990) chance. A beautiful example, quoted by Keymer &
note that acanthocephalans often increase the activity Read (1990) concerns a fungus called Monilinia
levels of their intermediate hosts. An example of this vaccinii-corymbosi, the 'Mummy-Berry fungus',
that I have used before is from the work of Bethel which infects blueberries and is economically quite
and Holmes on the behaviour of gammarids infected important (Batra & Batra, 1985). The fungus induces
with Polymorphus paradoxus and P. marilis (Holmes the blueberry plant to grow fake flowers. Insects visit
& Bethel, 1972; Bethel & Holmes, 1973, 1977). T h e these fake flowers, pick up the fungus's asexual
two species of acanthocephalans are 'aiming' at reproductive conidia and transport them to real
different definitive hosts, and they appear to change flowers. The conidia infect the host flowers and
the behaviour of their gammarid intermediate hosts, induce them to produce not normal blueberries but
in opposite directions that increase their vulner- seedless, inedible 'mummy-berries'. The fungus
ability to predation by their respective definitive overwinters in the mummy-berries. The fake flowers
hosts. In neither case does this change in behaviour induced by the fungus are impressive in their detail,
include an impairment in the activity level of the which is why I bring the example up here. They
gammarids. become reflective in ultraviolet light which is
T h e same is true of many examples of insect attractive to insects, make a smell, and secrete nectar.
vectors of blood parasites changing their behaviour It seems hard to write off such a cluster of apparently
when infected. Thus tsetse flies infected by specific adaptations as a boring side-effect of parasitic
Trypanosoma probe more frequently and feed more infection. The case for detailed parasite manipulation
voraciously than uninfected control flies (Jenni et al. seems strong.
1980). And bumblebee queens infected by the My favourite example along these lines is one
nematode Sphaerularia bombi 'flew almost incess- reported by Fisher in 1963. As it happens, this is
antly, stopping to dig, then moving on. In the another case where the host is induced to become
process, they deposited nematode larvae' (Moore & larger.
Gotelli, 1990). Giles (1983) and Milinski (1985)
reported that sticklebacks infected with the tape- Tribolium larvae infected with Nosema sp. attain larger size
than uninfected controls. Infected larvae undergo as many
worm Schistocephalus solidus were less fearful in the
as six supernumerary molts and most commonly die as
presence of predators than uninfected controls. giant larvae, weighing two times as much as nonpara-
From our point of view, parasites that make hosts sitized controls (Fisher, 1963).
larger rather than smaller, or more active and less
fearful, are interesting because it is harder to write Fisher went on to describe experiments on Blaberus
the effect off as a boring byproduct. T h e same is true cockroaches.
where the host is induced to do something un- From these experiments it was concluded that the parasite
expected by commonsense, something bizarre. One Nosema produced a substance with juvenile hormone ac-
of my favourite illustrations concerns nematomorph tivity and sufficed to replace or augment that produced by
larvae who need to break out of their insect hosts and the corpora allata of the host.
return to water: Cheng remarked in his textbook (1973):
...a major difficulty in the parasite's life is the return to If the situation in Tribolium is similar to that in Blaberus,
water. It is, therefore, of particular interest that the parasite and there is no reason to believe that it is not, then the
appears to affect the behaviour of its hosts, and enhanced growth in parasitized Tribolium can be
' encourages' it to return to water. The mechanism by attributed, directly or indirectly, to the contribution of a
which this is achieved is obscure, but there are sufficient juvenile hormonelike material by Nosema.
isolated reports to certify that the parasite does influence
its hosts, and often suicidally for the host...One of the Presumably a giant larva is a more bountiful source
more dramatic reports describes an infected bee flying over of food than an adult half its size. So, the parasite
a pool and, when about six feet over it, diving straight into would seem to have something to gain by the
the water. Immediately on impact the gordian worm burst
manipulation. Now to the point that this example is
out and swam into the water, the maimed bee being left to
die (Croll, 1966). making. The juvenile hormone molecule seems far
too improbable a specific juxtaposition of atoms for
Much as I enjoy this anecdote, I can't help worrying a protozoan to hit upon as a boring, accidental by-
about it. How was the observer (not identified in the product of something else. The case seems strong
The paradox of the organism S67

that it has evolved as a specific adaptation to responsible for drugging it. Moreover, an ant under
manipulate the physiology of the host. the sway of a manipulating caterpillar eventually
Another example, though here the functional enters a state called 'binding', in which it becomes
significance from the parasite's point of view is less inseparable from its caterpillar for a period of many
clear, is the effect of the tapeworm Spirometra days. Once again, the complex of elaborate organs in
mansonoides on rats. Under experimental conditions the caterpillar, and the complex of specific effects on
an infected rat may grow to nearly eight times its the ant's behaviour, seem to leave no doubt that
normal weight. It seems to be due to the secretion, natural selection, for the benefit of the parasite, has
by the parasite, of a growth-hormone-like substance. been at work, cumulatively over many generations.
Here it has been suggested that the tapeworm may Before leaving the digression on boring
have ' borrowed' a mammalian, even specifically byproducts as an alternative to parasitic adaptation,
human, gene and is using it to manufacture a I must also deal with the third possibility, host
mammalian hormone (Phares, 1987). Whether this is adaptation. Raised temperature in response to in-
so, or whether it has independently evolved the fection is just the kind of effect that might tempt one
ability to synthesize the hormone, we can hardly to ingenious stories about parasites manipulating
write off the parasite's effect on the host as a boring, hosts. No doubt a feverish brain does all sorts of
accidental side-effect. things that make its unfortunate possessor more
But in any case, as Darwinians, the word accident likely to be eaten by predators, and in some cases this
should give us pause. Do not all adaptations start off might benefit the parasite. There seems good reason
as accidents, random mutations ? What is the to believe, however, that fever is an adaptation by
difference between an accidental side-effect that hosts to create unfavourable conditions for parasites;
happens to benefit the parasite (which I am calling a see, for example, Boorstein & Ewald (1987) whose
non-adaptation) and a favoured mutation (which I paper has the added attraction of including an
am calling an adaptation) ? The solution to this experimental investigation of protozoan-induced
conundrum lies in the distinction between single fever in grasshoppers.
step and cumulative selection (Dawkins, 1986). A I must also mention that, since The Extended
single step of natural selection cannot produce an Phenotype was published, one of its main examples
adaptation sufficiently complex to impress us as of parasite manipulation has been claimed to be a
being obviously an adaptation. All the undisputed host adaptation. Snails are frequently induced by
adaptations, from the aerodynamics of a swift's wing trematode parasites to grow larger, and specifically
to the acoustics of an owl's ear, impress us because in some cases to develop thicker shells. Following
they fit their purpose in many different respects the logic above, this seems temptingly to argue a
which could not have come about in a single strong case for parasite manipulation. A smaller
mutational step. They have evolved their efficiency snail, or a thinner shell, could have been put down to
cumulatively, in series, over many steps of accidental general debilitation, a boring side-effect. But a
mutation followed by non-accidental selection. At thicker shell must surely mean that something more
least some alleged cases of parasites manipulating interesting is going on. The parasite, I suggested, is
their hosts seem to meet the criterion: it really is selfishly prolonging the life of the individual snail in
hard to imagine that the synthesis of insect juvenile which it lives, at the expense of the snail's re-
hormone by the protozoan Nosema is anything other production.
than a highly specific Darwinian adaptation that The theory makes use of the idea of an economic
must have taken many cumulative steps of natural trade-off. From the snail's point of view, I suggested,
selection to perfect. there is an optimal shell thickness, a compromise
The same seems to me true of some of the between the protective benefits conferred by a thick
behavioural effects of symphylic caterpillars in ants' shell and the economic savings in calcium and other
nests. Often they bristle, literally, with equipment resources conferred by a thin one. If snails would
for manipulating their protectors. The caterpillar of really benefit from thicker shells they would grow
Thisbe irenea has a sound-producing organ in its them without being prompted by flukes. I regarded
head which apparently has no purpose other than the compromise as one between reproduction and
summoning ants (De Vries, 1988). Near the insect's individual survival. A thicker shell would favour
rear end is a pair of telescopic spouts which exude survival of the individual snail but would exact
seductive nectar. On its shoulders stand another pair economic costs that would reduce its reproductive
of nozzles secreting not food but a volatile substance, success. The parasite has the same interest as the
which has a dramatic impact upon the ants' be- snail in the snail's survival, but it has no interest in
haviour. An ant coming under the influence of this the snail's reproducing itself. F r om the parasite's
chemical leaps clear into the air. Its mandibles gape point of view the optimum shell thickness is shifted
and it turns aggressive, far readier than usual to bite towards favouring individual snail survival at the
or sting any moving object except the caterpillar expense of snail reproduction.
R. Dawkins S68

Minchella (1985), however, put forward an shells of each of these species to withstand attacks by
alternative theory. His paper discussed the phenom- duck and crayfish predators, and correlated it with
enon of parasite-induced gigantism and parasitic reproductive rate measured as the intrinsic rate of
castration in general, and listed three hypotheses increase. She found a negative association across
about it. Firstly, the boring byproduct theory: species between effectiveness of armour and re-
productive rate. Although it is always risky to draw
The traditional view of gigantism has been that it is a side-
effect or non-adaptive consequence of parasite-induced conclusions about trade-offs from across-species
cessation of reproduction ... The energy which was to be comparative studies (the 'other things being equal'
used for reproduction becomes available to the host for assumptions are so fragile), her data are undeniably
increased growth. exactly what I should wish them to be. Her
conclusion is aptly summed up in her title:
Secondly, he took the parasite adaptation theory, ' Reproduction or shell armour - a trade-off in fresh-
which he attributed to Baudoin (1975) and to me. He water gastropods'.
remarked that both these first two hypotheses regard For the purpose of developing my argument
the host as 'an unresponsive partner whose actions further, any example of parasite manipulation would
are dictated by the actions of the parasite'. He was serve. I'll use the snail shell thickness example on the
sceptical and, as a third option, put forward his own assumption that it really is an authentic case of
theory. Gigantism, parasitic castration, and pro- parasite manipulation. If you do not find this
longed life at the expense of reproduction generally, example plausible, simply substitute any case where
are, Minchella suggested, adaptations on the part of you are prepared to accept that a parasite has evolved
the host. The host temporarily switches resources to manipulate a host's phenotype for the parasite's
into fostering its own longevity, at the temporary benefit.
expense of its reproduction, in an attempt to outlive
the parasite and return to reproduce at a later date.
EXTENDED GENETICS
Minchella and three colleagues attempted to test
between the three hypotheses, using the specific case Let's assume, then, that flukes really are manipu-
of trematode effects upon snail shells (Minchella lating snails into growing larger shells, and translate
et al. 1985). Rather surprisingly, since these results the story into the language of the extended pheno-
appeared in the same year as Minchella's hypothesis type. Essentially, this means taking a gene's-eye-
was published, they found against that very hy- view.
pothesis : it turned out that the snails cannot outlive Any Darwinian adaptation comes about through
the parasites anyway. They concluded in favour of the non-random survival of genes in a gene pool.
the parasite manipulation hypothesis of Baudoin and There must have been genetic variation in tendency
myself. to produce the adaptation of interest: some animals
This is gratifying, though I take passing exception had it, others didn't, because of differences in their
to the label 'prudent parasite' that they attach to the genes. The ones that had it were more successful,
parasite manipulation hypothesis. They say that it is and so more copies of the relevant genes were passed
equivalent to Slobodkin's (1961) 'prudent predator' into future gene pools. This process continued until
theory. Slobodkin's theory notoriously was based on the phenotypes associated with these genes became
an uncritical group-selectionism that was egregious the norm. In this case, since it is a fluke adaptation
even by the standard of ecologists. Predators were we are talking about the genes are in the fluke gene
supposed to restrain their hunting in the interests of pool. But the phenotypic effects that we are talking
conserving stocks for the future. This does not quite about are manifested in the snail's body. It is the
have to be group selectionist: we could assume that snail's shell, not any part of the fluke's body, that is
each individual predator has exclusive hunting rights the phenotype of interest.
over a geographical area, or in some other way Of course the fluke genes work proximally via
secures privileged access to the benefits of its own phenotypic effects on the fluke's body. But this does
prudence. But there was no indication that not nullify the conclusion that these fluke genes are
Slobodkin was aware of this need, and 'prudent also exerting phenotypic effects on the snail's body.
predators' have rightly had a bad name among the Any conventionally recognized phenotypic effect of a
Darwinian cognoscenti ever since. gene is the end of a cascade of earlier embryological
The parasite manipulation hypothesis is also effects, in this case all within the same body. A gene
shored up by indirect evidence of its underlying ' for' waltzing behaviour in mice presumably begins,
economic assumption of trade-offs between snail like most other functional genes, by influencing the
shell thickness and reproductive rates. Hamilton synthesis of a protein. This affects something else
(1980) looked at 5 snail species coexisting in the which affects something else which, further down
Potomac river, Physa heterostropha, Bithynia the causal cascade, distorts the embryonic devel-
tentaculata, Helisoma trivolvis, Mudalia carinata and opment of the balance organs in the inner ear. This
Goniobasis virginica. She measured the ability of the is the penultimate step in the cascade, and it leads to
The paradox of the organism S69

the 'ultimate', behavioural effect that we actually flukes (in different snails). The phenotype that she is
observe, namely waltzing behaviour. studying seems unambiguously a snail phenotype.
But I p u t ' ultimate' in inverted commas advisedly. But it turns out to vary under the influence of both
There is nothing to stop us recognizing any stage in fluke genes and snail genes. The two sources of
the cascade as ' t h e ' phenotypic effect of interest. genetic influence interact with one another in just the
Instead of assaying phenotype behaviourally, a same kind of way as we conventionally see different
geneticist could dissect the ears of specimens and genes from the same genome interacting with one
study the genetics of abnormal inner ear anatomy. another. Most phenotypes are influenced by a large
Or a biochemical geneticist could detect the ab- number of interacting genes, often pushing in
normal protein product of the 'waltzing' gene, and different directions. The final phenotype is a
use that as its phenotypic marker. Similarly, there is compromise between these shared genetic influences,
no necessary reason why waltzing behaviour should and these interact too, with non-genetic
be regarded as the last step in the cascade. Waltzing 'environmental' influences.
mice might be especially vulnerable to predation by In the present case the fluke geneticist admits
cats. The gene might therefore be labelled, not the complicated interactions and compromises among
'waltzing gene' nor the 'abnormal inner ear gene' fluke genes, but consigns the snail genes to
but the 'vulnerable to cats' gene. Which label we 'environmental noise'. The snail geneticist
choose will depend upon which step in the cascade of acknowledges complicated interactions and
causal effects seems to be the most salient in the life compromises among snail genes, but relegates the
of the animal, or the most relevant to the interests of fluke genes to environmental noise. The extended
the geneticist. geneticist achieves a more penetrating analysis. She
Similarly, fluke genes must exert their effect on sees interactions among fluke genes, interactions
snail shells via a cascade of prior effects within the among snail genes, and interactions between fluke
fluke body, but this does not prevent us from seeing and snail genes, all bearing upon the same, shared
the cascade as extending on outside the fluke's body. phenotype. All these factors, of course, also interact
To say that fluke genes have phenotypic effects on with environmental variables. For the extended
snail bodies is to make exactly the same kind of geneticist the category 'environmental noise' is
logical extension as we are accustomed to making smaller. It includes the calcium content of the pond
anyway. It is just a little startling because it is an but does not include the genes of the fluke or the
unfamiliar idea. Nevertheless, the logical correctness genes of the snail. These have been taken out of the
of the principle is inescapable. environmental residue, into the fold of genetically
I imagine three geneticists examining the same explained variation.
data and analysing it in three ways. The first is a Later in her extended genetic analysis, the ex-
fluke geneticist. He observes that some flukes secrete tended geneticist might investigate the possibility of
a chemical and others do not. This chemical affects hijacking even more sources of variation out of the
the physiology of the host snail, and induces it to category of 'environmental noise' and into the
build a thicker shell, diverting into this project category of 'extended genetic influence'. Perhaps
resources that it would have preferred to use for even the calcium content of the pond is unde r the
other purposes such as reproduction. The fluke genetic influence of some animal or plant, and
geneticist studies this phenotype in successive natural selection is working on these genes because
generations of flukes, and observes that it breeds their phenotypic effects feed back and influence their
true, or at least has a hereditary component. For the own welfare.
fluke geneticist, the snail is just part of the en- There is, indeed, no obvious limit to the distance
vironment, like the pond in which it lives. over which extended genetic influences may travel. A
The second geneticist is a snail geneticist. He beaver dam is an undoubted adaptation. Exactly how
observes that some snails have thicker shells than it benefits beavers is not clearly understood, but it
others and he looks to see if the characteristic breeds presumably has something to do with the lake that it
true over generations of snails. He finds that it does creates. Part of the story is probably that the lake
not; or at least that there is also a substantial provides a secure and convenient route for
environmental component to the variation which he transporting logs. Whatever the exact advantages,
identifies as associated with the presence of flukes. beaver lakes are certainly adaptive phenotypes that
As far as the snail geneticist is concerned, the flukes have evolved through the natural selection of beaver
constitute environmental noise, comparable to the genes. There must have been genes 'for' lakes of
noise that might be introduced by differing calcium various kinds, or natural selection would have had
levels in the water of different ponds. nothing to work on. Presumably there were genes
The third geneticist — and the one whose approach for lake size, genes for lake shape, genes for lake
I commend - is an extended geneticist. She looks at depth, and so on. The fact that all these genes must
variation in snail shell thickness down pedigrees of have worked via influences on the building behaviour
snails (with different flukes) and down pedigrees of of beavers is irrelevant to the logical point being
R. Dawkins S70

made. In just the same way as it is legitimate to speak vehicles. The phenotypic effects by which a gene
of genes for beaver behaviour, even though this levers itself into future gene pools comprise all of
phenotype is a product of some prior effect, say on that gene's effects on the world. It is only a
neuroanatomical wiring, so it is in principle legit- contingent fact, not a necessary one, that so many
imate to speak of genes for round lakes versus phenotypic effects of genes are, as matter of fact, tied
elongated lakes. The point of introducing beaver together in the gigantic and ingenious clusters that
dams as extended phenotypes is that they can be very we call individual organisms. The paradox of the
extended indeed - several square miles! organism remains, and the time has finally come to
Returning to parasites, some of the most striking show how parasites help us to solve it.
examples of extended phenotypes are provided by
the galls that plants are induced by insects to make. BLURRING THE BOUNDARIES
I have previously quoted Mayr on the subject
because, as long ago as 1963 galls moved him to use Thinking about parasites can help us to solve the
language highly congenial to the extended phenotype paradox of the organism because parasites blur the
thesis. A recent paper on the subject makes explicit practical dividing line between one organism and
use of extended phenotype terminology (Weis, another, between themselves and their hosts. By
Walton & Crego, 1988): examining this practical blurring between organisms
we can sharpen up our theoretical perception of what
The evolution of the plant-gall interaction is complicated it means to be an organism at all.
by the fact that galls are phenotypic entities that develop Smith (1979) used the vivid simile of the Cheshire
under the influence of both plant and insect genotypes. Cat's grin to dramatize the blurring of boundaries
From the plant's perspective, the gall is a developmental
between parasite and host.
abnormality, induced by an environmental stimulus, i.e.
the insect. When viewed from the insect's perspective, the In non-living habitats, an organism either exists or it does
gall is a phenotypic extension. Selection may act upon the not. In the cell habitat, an invading organism can progress-
insect to alter this extended phenotype, and thus gall ively lose pieces of itself, slowly blending into the general
formation is an adaptation of the insect. background, its former existence betrayed only by some
relic. Indeed, one is reminded of Alice in Wonderland's
Galls also provide an excellent example of an encounter with the Cheshire Cat. As she watched it, 'it
adaptation too complicated to be written off as a vanished quite slowly, beginning with the tail, and ending
boring pathological byproduct: with the grin, which remained some time after the rest of
it had gone'.
Unlike microbe-induced plant tumours with their
unstructured cell proliferation, insect galls are Smith was talking about intracellular symbionts,
' harmoniously organized entities with an orderly arrange- including putatively ancient ones such as mito-
ment of cell layers and determinate growth which results chondria. Here the blurring is so complete that the
in structures with particular size and shapes'. New, historical separation of the parties may become all
localized developmental gradients emanating from the gall but undetectable. But there is a kind of blurring
maker take over plant cell differentiation. Concentric tissue between parasite and host that can arise even though
layers, with nutritive and protective function, differentiate
their tissues may not physically blend. There is a
around the insect. The information for this developmental
process undoubtedly lies in both the insect and plant teleonomic blending — a blending of functional
genomes (Weis, Walton & Crego, 1988). interests — which may or may not be accompanied by
a blurring of physical boundaries.
Meiotic drive and the extended phenotype, then,
from their different directions, serve to emphasize
OVERLAPPING AND NON-OVERLAPPING
the dilemma that I am calling the paradox of the
DESIDERATA LISTS
organism. T h e phenomenon of meiotic drive
reminds us that the organism is a cooperative of Think about the conflict of interest between a
entities that — one might have thought — would be parasite's genes and the genes of its host, and note
constantly at civil war. It is a highly successful unit that the conflict is only partial. If you make a list
of pacification of fundamentally warring particles. of those outcomes in the future that would benefit
How does it do it? Or, to phrase the question at the the host's genes, and those that would benefit the
gene level where it should be phrased, why d o the parasite's genes, they diverge in many ways, but there
genes cooperate so spectacularly ? Why don't they all is a partial overlap between them. Both sets of genes
behave like segregation distorters ? 'want' the host to go on living, at least for a while,
Meanwhile the doctrine of the extended phenotype because the host's body is the present vehicle for
reminds us that there is no necessary reason why both sets of genes. But they may differ in how long
organisms should exist in the first place. Genes they want it to go on living. The parasite's genes may
survive in the gene pool by virtue of their phenotypic require the host to be eaten by a definitive host, while
effects. But those phenotypic effects do not necess- the host's genes would prefer this not to happen. In
arily have to be bundled up into discrete organismal such a case, selection on host genes is pushing the
The paradox of the organism S71

shared phenotype towards increasing longevity, Presumably both lists will mention keeping the host
while selection on parasite genes is pushing it alive for a while, but the parasite list wants it alive
towards decreasing longevity. In other cases, such as only enough to build up a good bulk of spores.
the snails discussed above, the host's genes may be Thereafter the lists diverge markedly. The parasite
selected to divert resources towards reproduction at genes care nothing for the reproduction of the host;
the expense of survival, so tending to reduce they have no interest in making it sexually attractive,
longevity, while the parasite's genes are pushing it to no interest in its proficiency as a nest-builder or as a
survive longer at the expense of reproduction. parent.
But those are details, specifics. My general point at Between these two extremes will be a spectrum of
the moment is that there is a partial overlap in parasite/host relationships with varying overlaps of
interests between the two sets of genes. We could, in future interests. My point is that the key variable
principle, make a list of events in the future that both affecting the degree of overlap in interests is the
sets of genes would 'want'. There will also, of extent to which the parasite and host share the same
course, be a list of events in the future that only the gametes (or spores, etc). Where parasite and host
host genes want, and another list that only the share gametes, the shared desiderata list will be
parasite genes will want. Let us call these two the relatively large, and the parasite will evolve to
'host desiderata list' and the 'parasite desiderata become benign. Where parasite reproduction is via
list', and we'll call the overlap between the two lists an entirely separate channel from host reproduction,
the 'shared desiderata list'. For completeness we the shared desiderata list will be relatively short, and
should note that in theory the shared list includes the parasite will be malignant.
future outcomes that we take for granted like the My hypothetical parasite with spores travelling
sun's continuing to shine, but we are specifically inside host eggs is not quite the most extreme along
concerned with outcomes over which the genes can the spectrum towards benignness. The shared de-
have some phenotypic influence. The doctrine of the siderata list here is undoubtedly large, but there
extended phenotype has taught us not to ignore the could be a slight divergence of interests. Over the
parasite desiderata list where the host phenotype is host's sex ratio, for instance. Host genes desire,
concerned, for the parasite genes can have an according to Fisherian logic, equal investment in
influence over the shared phenotype just as the host sons and daughters. Parasite genes, in this hy-
genes can. Now, what kinds of factors will affect the pothetical example, have an interest in the host's
size of the shared list in comparison to the other two successfully rearing daughters; but these genes have
lists ? no interest in the host's rearing sons since they do
I believe that it is possible to give a powerful not stand to be passed on in host sperms. These
general answer to this question. The answer is that hypothetical parasite genes are in the same position
parasite genes and host genes will agree on the same as mammalian mitochondrial or cytoplasmic DNA
desiderata list to the extent that they use the same (Eberhard, 1980; Cosmides & Tooby, 1981;
route into future generations. What are the routes of Charnov, 1982).
a gene into future generations ? Sperms, eggs, spores, The largest possible shared desiderata list will be
runners, suckers, airborne capsules of DNA, what- found in those cases where the parasite DNA not
ever vehicles are used to transport DNA into the only shares gametes with host DNA but is actually
future, it is here that we must concentrate our spliced into the host chromosome.
measurement of overlap or divergence. Suppose a And so we are led full circle, back to the paradox
parasite reproduces by spores which it inserts into of the organism. The paradox can now be restated in
the eggs of its host, and the spores then grow up to terms of desiderata lists. We take it for granted that
form a new generation in the body of the host's child. all the genes in the genome of an organism share the
In this case there will be a substantial overlap same desiderata list, but this is a contingent, not a
between the parasite and host desiderata lists. Both necessary fact. Why does it so often turn out to be
sets of genes want the host to reproduce successfully; true? Why don't the separate genes, or subsets of
both will probably agree on what is the desirable them, go their separate ways with separate desiderata
balance in the trade-off between longevity and lists ? The solution to the paradox now almost states
reproduction; both will agree that the host should itself, so clear has the parasite spectrum made
not be eaten by predators, should be sexually matters. An organism's own nuclear genes share the
attractive, should build a good nest and be a good same desiderata list for exactly the same reason as
parent. Both sets of genes will probably agree on parasite genes and host genes do when they share
what is the best song for the host to sing, what is the gametes. The important fact about an organism's
best colour for its tail, and so on. own nuclear genes is that they all share the same
At the other extreme, consider a parasite that gametes. It is for this reason, and this reason alone,
causes its host's body to burst, shedding parasite that they stand to gain from the same set of outcomes
spores into the wind in a puff of dust. In this case the in the future. It is for this reason alone that they all
two desiderata lists will scarcely overlap at all. 'agree' over what is the optimum state of every
R. Dawkins S72

aspect of the phenotype, all agree on the correct wing this is because they do not share reproductive
length, leg colour, clutch size, growth rate, and so propagules. What keeps host genes together with
on. host genes — and parasite genes together with parasite
Those cases where nuclear genes don't share the genes - is that they do share future interests.
same gametic expectations are precisely the cases Parasites, then, have led us to the solution to the
where they 'rebel' and don't pull together with the paradox of the organism. The genes in an organism
rest - segregation distorters and their ilk. Even more share desiderata lists. And this is simply because
rebellious would be nuclear genes that found a they submit to the same meiotic lottery and possess
wholly non-gametic avenue into the future. Suppose the same stochastic gametic destiny.
that a human nuclear gene discovered the trick of
splicing itself directly into chromosomes of another I am grateful to Anne Keymer and Andrew Read for
individual — a trick that is now known to be quite inviting me to the conference at which this paper was
delivered, and to Helena Cronin for the advice and
common in prokaryotic DNA. Now natural selection
assistance at every stage.
might favour such a gene if it mutated in such a way
as to circumvent the orderly, communal, gametic
route into the next generation and move sideways REFERENCES
instead. It might, for instance, cause strategically BATRA, L. H. & BATRA, s. w . T. (1985). Floral mimicry
placed cells to tickle the lining of the nose, inducing induced by mummy-berry fungus exploits host
a sneeze. The speculation has to be completed, of pollinators as vectors. Science 228, 1011-12.
course, by the assumption that the rebel DNA, BAUDOIN, M. (1975). Host castration as a parasitic
strategy. Evolution 29, 335-52.
blown out in a sneeze, is then breathed in by another
BETHEL, w. M. & HOLMES, J. c . (1973). Altered evasive
human where it splices itself into the new victim's behaviour and responses to light in amphipods
genome. Whether this example is wholly speculative, harbouring acanthocephalan cystacanths. Journal of
or whether viruses and their kind are in fact derived Parasitology 59, 945-56.
from rebellious host DNA does not matter too BETHEL, w. M. & HOLMES, j . c. (1977). Increased
much. The example serves, in any case, to underline vulnerability of amphipods to predation owing to
the central point: that the only thing that really binds altered behaviour induced by larval acanthocephalans.
all of an organism's 'own' genes in a common Canadian Journal of Zoology 55, 110-15.
enterprise is the fact that they all share the same BOORSTEIN, S. M. & EWALD, P. W. (1987). Costs a n d
gametic route into the future. benefits of behavioural fever in Melanopus sanguinipes
infected by Nosema acridophagus. Physiological Zoology
Of course, sexual reproduction ensures that the
60, 586-95.
genes of an organism share the same genetic route
CHARNOV, E. L. (1982). The Theory of Sex Allocation.
into the future only in a probabilistic sense. Every Princeton, N . J . : Princeton University Press.
sperm or egg produced by an individual in normal CHENG, T. c. (1973). General Parasitology. New York:
sexual reproduction is unique, so the genes in the Academic Press.
diploid genotype do not share future expectations in CLARKE, B. c. (1979). T h e evolution of genetic diversity.
an absolute sense. But so long as meiosis is a fair Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B 205,
lottery - and it looks significantly as though elaborate 453-74.
steps have been taken to ensure that it is - every CROLL, N. A. (1966). Ecology of Parasites. Cambridge,
gene in an individual's genome has the same Mass: Harvard University Press.
stochastic expectations of the future. This is why CROW, j . F. (1979). G e n e s that violate Mendel's rules.
Scientific American 240, 104-13.
they cooperate with one another, and this is the
COSMIDES, L. M . & TOOBY, j . (1981). Cytoplasmic
explanation of the definition of the organism with
inheritance and intragenomic conflict. Journal of
which I began: 'An individual organism is an entity Theoretical Biology 8 9 , 83-129.
all of whose genes share the same stochastic DAWKINS, R. (1982). The Extended Phenotype. Oxford:
expectations of the distant future'. W. H. Freeman.
By this definition, parasites and hosts whose DAWKINS, R. (1989). The Selfish Gene, 2nd Edn. Oxford:
stochastic future expectations were identical would Oxford University Press.
evolve closer and closer together, with more and DAWKINS, R. (1986). The Blind Watchmaker. Harlow:
more blurred edges, until they would fuse and Longman.
become the same individual. The reason why fluke DE VRIES, P. J. (1988). T h e larval ant-organs of Thisbe
tissue and snail tissue are still not fused is that their irenea (Lepidoptera: Riodinidae) and their effects
upon attending ants. Zoological Journal of the Linnean
desiderata lists are not totally overlapping. It is not
Society 94, 379-93.
that there is something qualitatively fluky about one
DOBSON, A. P. (1988). T h e population biology of parasite-
set of genes and something qualitatively snaily about induced changes in host behavior. Quarterly Reviezv
the other set. Either of both sets of genes could have of Biology 63, 139-65.
been put together, originally, by fusion of earlier EBERHARD, w. G. (1980). Evolutionary consequences of
symbiotic unions. What keeps snails and flukes apart intracellular organelle competition. Quarterly Review
in evolution is their divergent future interests, and of Biology 55, 231-49.
The paradox of the organism S73

EVVALD, P. w. (1980). Evolutionary biology and the MCNAIR, j . N. (1985). Host and parasite
treatment of signs and symptoms of infectious disease. counteradaptations: an example from a freshwater
Journal of Theoretical Biology 86, 169-76. snail. American Naturalist 126, 843-54.
FISHER, F. M. (1963). Production of host endocrine MOORE, j . & GOTELLI, N. j . (1990). A phylogenetic
substances by parasites. Annals of the New York perspective on the evolution of host behaviours. In
Academy of Science 113, 63-73. Parasitism and Host Behaviour (ed. Barnard, C. J. &
GILES, N. (1983). Behavioural effects of the parasite Behnke, J. M.). London: Taylor & Francis (in the
Schistocephalus solidus (Cestoda) on an intermediate Press).
host, the three-spined stickleback, Gasterosteus NOBLE, E. R. & NOBLE, G. A. (1976). Parasitology : the
aculeatus. Animal Behaviour 31, 1192-4. Biology of Animal Parasites, 4th Edn. Philadelphia:
HAMILTON, s. (1980). Reproduction or shell armor - a Lee & Febiger.
trade-off in freshwater gastropods. Bulletin of PHARES, c. K. (1987). Plerocercoid growth factor: a
American Malacological Union, 46th Annual Meeting, homologue of human growth hormone. Parasitology
American Malacological Union, Louisville, p. 71 Today 3, 346-9.
(Abstract). READ, A. F. (1990). Parasites and the evolution of host
HAMILTON, w. D. (1980). Sex versus non-sex versus sexual behaviour. In Parasitism and Host Behaviour
parasite. Oikos 35, 282-90. (ed. Barnard, C. J. & Behnke, J. M.). L o n d o n : Taylor
HAMILTON, w. D. & ZUK, M. (1982). Heritable true fitness & Francis (in the Press).
and bright birds: a role for parasites? Science 218, REINHARD, E. G. (1956). Parasitic castration of Crustacea.
384-7. Experimental Parasitology 5, 79-107.
HOLMES, j . c. & BETHEL, w. M. (1972). Modification of SEGER, j . & HAMILTON, w. D. (1988). Parasites and sex. In
intermediate host behaviour by parasites. In The Evolution of Sex (ed. Michod, R. E. & Levin,
Behavioural Aspects of Parasite Transmission (ed. B. R.), pp. 176-93. Sunderland, Massachusetts:
Canning, E. U. & Wright, C. A.), pp. 123-149. Sinauer.
London: Academic Press. SLOBODKIN, L. B. (1961). Growth and Regulation of
JENNI, L., MOLYNEUX, D. H . , LIVESEY, J. L. & GALUN, R. Animal Populations. New York: Holt, Rinehart &
(1980). Feeding behaviour of tsetse flies infected with Winston.
salivarian trypanosomes. Nature, London 283, 383-5. SMITH, D. c. (1979). From extracellular to intracellular:
KEYMER, A. & READ, A. (1990). Behavioural ecology: the the establishment of a symbiosis. Proceedings of the
impact of parasitism. In Parasitism - Co-existence or Royal Society of London, B 204, 115-30.
Conflict (ed. Toft, C. A. & Aeschlimann, A.). Oxford: TOOBY, j . (1982). Pathogens, polymorphism, and the
Oxford University Press (in the Press). evolution of sex. Journal of Theoretical Biology 97,
LOVE, M. (1980). The alien strategy. Natural History 89, 557-76.
30-2. WEIS, A. E., WALTON, R. & CREGO, c. L. (1988). Reactive
MAYR, E. (1963). Animal Species and Evolution. plant tissue sites and the population biology of gall
Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. makers. Annual Review of Entomology 33, 467-86.
MILINSKI, M. (1985). Risk of predation of parasitized WICKLER, w. (1976). Evolution-oriented ethology, kin
sticklebacks (Gasterosteus aculeatus L.) under selection and altruistic parasites. Zeitschrift fur
competition for food. Behaviour 93, 203-26. Tierpsychologie 42, 206-14.
MINCHELLA, D. j . (1985). Host life-history variation in WILLIAMS, G. c. (1975). Sex and Evolution. Prince-
response to parasitism. Parasitology 90, 205-16. ton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
MINCHELLA, D. J., LEATHERS, B. K., BROWN, K. M. &

You might also like