Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 16

Journal of Business Ethics (2009) 85:201–216  Springer 2008

DOI 10.1007/s10551-008-9939-1

Mukesh Sud
Social Entrepreneurship: The Role Craig V. VanSandt
of Institutions Amanda M. Baugous

ABSTRACT. A relatively small segment of business, SE will soon be expected to provide answers to our most
known as social entrepreneurship (SE), is increasingly pressing social ills. In this paper we call into question the
being acknowledged as an effective source of solutions for ability of SE, by itself, to provide solutions on a scope
a variety of social problems. Because society tends to view necessary to address large-scale social issues. SE cannot
‘‘new’’ solutions as ‘‘the’’ solution, we are concerned that reasonably be expected to solve social problems on a large
scale for a variety of reasons. The first we label the orga-
nizational legitimacy argument. This argument leads to our
Dr. Mukesh Sud is currently an Assistant Professor of Man- second argument, the isomorphism argument. We also
agement at Augustana College in Rock Island, Illinois. An advance three other claims, the moral, political, and structural
engineer by profession, he has been an entrepreneur in the arguments. After making our arguments, we explore ways
Thermal Spraying field. After exiting from his business he in which SE, in concert with other social institutions, can
completed a Ph.D. in 2006, from the Indian Institute of effectively address social ills. We also present two exam-
Management, Bangalore. Dr. Sud’s doctoral work has been ples of successful ventures in which SEs partnered with
in the field of corporate entrepreneurship and emerging mar- governments and other institutions.
kets. Besides social entrepreneurship his research has focused
on the impact of failure both at the individual and firm level. KEY WORDS: social entrepreneurship, institutions,
Dr. Sud has published papers in the Academy of Entre- isomorphism, legitimacy
preneurship Journal and IIMB Management Review.
Dr. Craig V. VanSandt obtained his Ph.D. from Virginia
Tech, and is currently an Associate Professor of Management
at Augustana College in Rock Island, Illinois. He has au-
thored papers that have appeared in Law & Policy, Busi- We can’t solve problems by using the same kind of
ness and Society, Journal of Business Ethics, thinking we used when we created them. (attributed
International Journal of Organization Theory and to Albert Einstein)
Behavior, Journal of Management Education, and a
book chapter in Systematic Occupational Health and There is no question that the world today faces
Safety Management. Dr. VanSandt’s research interests numerous and severe problems. One need not expend
include organizational climate’s effect on employee behavior, much time or effort to encounter them in the popular
the role of business in society, and ethical issues of corporate press – global warming, poverty, increasing economic
governance. inequality, famine, potential pandemics, ethnic
Dr. Amanda M. Baugous obtained her Ph.D. in Industrial/ cleansing, terrorism, etc. In addition to the specific
Organizational Psychology from the University of Tennessee, problems we face, the virtual collapse of communism
Knoxville, and is currently an Assistant Professor of Man- and the effects of unbridled capitalism have exacer-
agement at Augustana College in Rock Island, Illinois. She bated social injustices (Wolman and Colamosca,
has authored papers that have been presented at Society
1997). Finding and implementing solutions to these
for Industrial and Organizational Psychology, Industrial/
Organizational Psychology & Organizational Behavior,
problems is becoming critical to our continued sur-
and North American Management Society conferences. vival as a species (Carson, 1962; Gore, 2006).
Dr. Baugous’s research and consulting interests include the Business, particularly a relatively small segment
design, evaluation, and implementation of employee selection known as social entrepreneurship (SE), is increas-
and performance management systems. ingly acknowledged as an effective source of
202 Mukesh Sud et al.

solutions for a variety of social problems (Mair et al., (and, in many ways, a basis for) our second argument,
2006; Nicholls, 2006). Because society tends to view the isomorphism argument. We will also advance three
‘‘new’’ solutions as ‘‘the’’ solution, we are concerned other claims, the moral, political, and structural arguments.
that SE will soon be expected to provide compre- These are depicted in the following model as forces
hensive answers to our most pressing social ills. In restraining the effectiveness of social entrepreneurship
this paper we call into question the ability of SE, by to solve wide-scale social problems.
itself, to provide solutions on a scope necessary to Our legitimacy argument is based on the fact that the
address large-scale social issues. Certainly, there is very existence of certain types of organizations de-
anecdotal evidence that social entrepreneurs have pends upon the consent of the society in which they
addressed and helped resolve many social problems are embedded. This acquiescence is based on the
(e.g., Bornstein, 2004; Leadbeater, 1997; Nicholls, perception that a type of organization serves some
2004, 2006; Nicholls and Cho, 2006). They have sort of useful purpose. For example, for-profit cor-
done so by being innovative, market-oriented, and porations are embraced by American society today,
socially focused (Nicholls and Cho, 2006). But, to but were highly discouraged and limited during the
date, these successes have been achieved locally and founding of the United States (Grossman and
on a relatively small scale. Adams, 1993; Kelly, 2003; Nace, 2003). Christian
We will argue that as attempts are being made to churches were all but obliterated in the USSR,
scale up the field, SE by itself, is inadequate to while they thrive in the United States. Private col-
address the extent and complexity of the social leges are common in the United States, but virtually
problems we currently face; nor should it be non-existent in western European countries.
expected to do so. We do not make these arguments Organizational legitimacy, in the context of this
because we do not believe that SE should address argument, is a generalized perception or assumption
social issues. We are certainly not Friedman disciples, that the actions of an entity are socially desirable,
of the mind that the sole social responsibility of proper, or appropriate within some socially con-
business is to increase its profits (Friedman, 1970) – structed system of norms, values, beliefs, and defini-
with one exception, as we will explain later. tions (Suchman, 1995). From an institutional
perspective, legitimacy is the means by which orga-
nizations obtain and maintain resources (Oliver,
Why social entrepreneurship is not enough 1991).
Social enterprises are the most recent organiza-
SE cannot reasonably be expected to solve social tional form, and, as such, are still seeking the legit-
problems on a large scale for a variety of reasons. The imacy already accorded to their predecessors.
first we will label the organizational legitimacy argument. Historically, markets (i.e., private, for-profit enter-
This argument is closely related to, but separate from prise) have sometimes failed to provide certain goods
or services. In contexts where governments have not
stepped in to resolve or ameliorate such failures,
Organizational
Legitimacy
non-profits have functioned as a vehicle to make
Pressures these services available to citizens, thus gaining
legitimacy for the non-profit sector. It is important
su hic

to be aware that the non-profit sector, by definition,


M ssu
Pr
re s

or re
Pr morp

Scaling Up
e

al s

has not been driven by monetary profit and is solely


es
Is o

concerned with filling the fissures that neither for-


Social
Entrepreneurship profits nor governments have satisfied.
Social enterprises, which represent a fundamental
Scaling Up
innovation in the non-profit sector, differ from non-
al
profit organizations in terms of their strategies,
ur
Po ct es structures, norms, and values (Dart, 2004) and are
Pre litica t ru sur
ss u l S es
r es Pr considered a rational and functional alternative to
public sector funding and philanthropic resource
Social Entrepreneurship 203

constraints (Dees et al., 2001). Just as non-profits markets to subsidize their social activities either by
originated to address market and government fail- exploiting profitable opportunities in the core
ures, social enterprises are now being formed activities of their for-profit subsidiaries or via
to address the issues that for-profits, government, for-profit subsidiary ventures and cross-sector part-
and non-profits miss. Scholars have viewed nerships with commercial corporations’’ (Nicholls,
social enterprises and social entrepreneurship as an 2004, p. 11). The number of stakeholders that social
‘‘encompassing set of strategic responses to many of enterprises engage with is hence likely to be larger
the varieties of environmental turbulence and situ- than those for non-profits. The diverse expectation
ational challenges that non profit organizations face’’ of these multiple stakeholders and the desire to be
(Dart, 2004, p. 413). self-sustaining is likely to further complicate these
Early definitions of the field suggest that social relationships. Significantly, philanthropy is becom-
entrepreneurs play the role of change agents in the ing more strategic in its largess, with donors calling
social sector by adopting a mission to create and for objective performance metrics and financial
sustain social value, not just private value (Dees, transparency.
1998). Although definitions in this emerging field The preceding paragraphs describe a typical pro-
remain fuzzy (Boschee, 1995; Dees, 1998), more cess – as social enterprises seek to scale their efforts to
recently there has been a broad acceptance of social address social problems, they need to acquire legit-
entrepreneurship as being an innovative use of imacy as a class of organization. However, in their
resources to explore and exploit opportunities that efforts to bridge the traditional field of for-profit
meet a social need in a sustainable manner. These operations and fill in the gaps left by governments
classifications are closely related to widely accepted and markets (the non-profit sector’s accustomed
definitions of entrepreneurship as the pursuit of role), financial results tend to subsume the social
opportunities without regard to resources under mission, if not in the social entrepreneur’s mind,
control (Stevenson, 1985) and the scholarly exami- certainly in the reporting requirements for investors
nation of how, by whom, and with what effect and donors (Bruck, 2006).
opportunities to create goods and services are dis- An early exemplar of this transition can be
covered, evaluated, and exploited (Venkataraman, observed in the microfinance field. With the arrival
1997). of private investment into the sector there have been
The authors of this paper suggest that the simi- calls to broaden its scope and multiply its impact.
larities in the accepted definitions of these fields are, Simultaneously, attempts are being made to reduce
in themselves, an indication that social enterprises its dependence on donors and government funding.
are closer ideologically to for-profit enterprises than Citigroup, the world’s biggest bank, started a
to non-profits. The early emphasis of social entre- microfinance division in 2005. The division’s global
preneurs seems to have been targeted toward inno- director commented, ‘‘[T]wo and a half billion
vation and using opportunities to create a social people ha[ve] never used a bank. Forty percent of
impact. However, as the field gains increasing rec- the world is beyond the world we know’’ (Bruck,
ognition (i.e., legitimacy), and social entrepreneurs 2006, p. 68). As a financial bank, the focus is likely
attempt to scale their efforts, the lack of adequate to be on ‘‘financial inclusion’’ [gaining new cus-
resources will be increasingly felt. The ability to tomers for the bank’s services] rather than reducing
attract and maintain resources is a key element in the poverty. Mouhammed Yunus, the founder of
search for legitimacy. Grameen Bank and recent Nobel Peace Prize win-
The evolving definitions of social entrepreneur- ner, observed that the traditional goal of business –
ship indirectly acknowledge this by emphasizing the maximizing profit – is inappropriate when dealing
sustainability of their efforts. Traditionally non- with the poor. In discussions with Pierre Omidyar of
profits have been funded by a mixture of member Ebay, who has supported microfinance but called for
fees, government funds, grants, and user fees a self-sustaining profitable model, Yunus said,
(DiMaggio and Anheier, 1990). Social enterprises, ‘‘[W]hy do you want to make money off the poor
on the other hand, are attempting to broaden this people? When they have enough flesh and blood
funding model by making ‘‘strategic moves into new in their bodies, go and suck them, no problem.
204 Mukesh Sud et al.

But, until then, don’t do that. Whatever money you structures. These mechanisms may result from either
are taking away, keep it with them instead, so that formal efforts or unofficial, even casual expectations.
they can come out more quickly from poverty’’ We see clear evidence of all three of these
(Bruck, 2006, p. 3). mechanisms operating in SE. The rapid proliferation
We are concerned that the desire to gain legiti- of the field in academia and the emergence of
macy and avoid dependency on donors may result in numerous citizen organizations all over the globe
unintended consequences in a field still in its infancy. will gradually lead to social and political imperatives
As a hybrid model emerges, we see a blurring of the for conformity. This process will be further accel-
factors that have traditionally distinguished non- erated, especially in the context of larger organiza-
profits from for-profits, such as goals, values, moti- tions, in their desire for legitimacy and funding to
vators, clientele, and types of clientele focus promote their objectives. This point is an integral
(DiMaggio and Anheier, 1990; Van Til, 1988). Such component of both the legitimacy and isomorphism
a hybrid model may have the drawbacks of both arguments.
organizational forms with none of their individual Ashoka, a non-profit entity organized in 1980, is
advantages. This lateral movement from a pro-social dedicated to helping social entrepreneurs build net-
mission to a double (or triple) bottom line, accom- works that will allow dissemination of approaches to
panied by a desire to gain legitimacy by emphasizing resolving social problems. Between 1990 and 2004 its
economic outcomes, may ultimately lead to the operations spread from 8 to 46 countries, while
premature discrediting of a promising field. Hence, increasing the number of ‘‘Ashoka Fellows’’ from 200
we suggest that the role of institutions becomes to 1,400 (Bornstein, 2004). This is a clear example of
critical to ensure that, as the field expands, the a formal effort to promote mimetic isomorphism
desirable outcomes of SE are met, without com- within the SE field. This desire is prompted by the
promising the essential building blocks on which it reality that the field is in an initial phase of existence,
has been founded and achieved early success. with few successful models to follow, and a plethora
Our second assertion is the isomorphism argument. of problems to solve. Finally, normative pressures are
Institutional isomorphism, as originally defined, is now beginning to exert themselves through profes-
‘‘…a constraining process that forces one unit in a sional structures within the SE field. Ironically, this
population to resemble other units that face the same pressure is emanating primarily from large corpora-
set of environmental conditions’’ in which ‘‘[o]rga- tions, which, as they dedicate themselves to the field
nizations compete not just for resources and cus- of SE, are demanding greater accountability in their
tomers, but for political power and institutional stated desire to achieve a higher impact (the Bill and
legitimacy, for social as well as economic fitness’’ Melinda Gates Foundation is probably the best
(DiMaggio and Powell, 1983, pp. 149–150). In known example). Financial markets are also begin-
other words, organizations in similar fields tend to ning to play a part in forcing conformity within the
become more homogeneous over time. Note that SE field, as efforts to establish structured investment
the isomorphism argument goes beyond that of the exchanges are being developed (Bruck, 2006; Mar-
legitimacy argument – not only do organizations ketplace, 2007). Thus, the theory of institutional
need society’s approval to exist, but once they isomorphism anticipates that social entrepreneurship
obtain that approbation, they are subject to pressures initiatives will, over time, increasingly resemble each
to conform to existing modes of structure and other.
operations. Nicholls and Cho, however, express concern that
DiMaggio and Powell (1983) go on to identify isomorphic pressures, inevitable in the scaling pro-
three mechanisms through which institutional iso- cess, may hinder the work of SE.
morphism operates: (1) coercive isomorphism –
political or social pressures, (2) mimetic isomorphism …[C]an social entrepreneurs adopt modes of ration-
– responses to uncertainty, one of which is imitation alization and professionalization consistent with the
need to escape these [the tendency toward institutional
of best practices, and (3) normative isomorphism –
isomorphism] pressures? …[T]here is an ongoing
processes of rationalization through professional
Social Entrepreneurship 205

process of antithesis that is a function of how social Social entrepreneurs, virtually by definition, are
entrepreneurs challenge existing, dysfunctional, social attacking social problems caused by shortcomings in
welfare delivery structures. Indeed, contra Marx and existing markets and social welfare systems (Mair
Hegel, there seems to be no evidence that the move to et al., 2006; Nicholls, 2006). The institutions that
a final synthesis is either desirable or likely. The more comprise these markets and social welfare systems are
social entrepreneurs continue to avoid institutional
part of the structure that created those very social
isomorphism and sectoral assimilation by defying the
logic of Hegelian-Marxian synthesis,…and the more
problems (refer back to Einstein’s quote at the
systemic and sustainable social impact they are likely to beginning of this paper). Those market and welfare
achieve (Nicholls and Cho, 2006, pp. 116–117). institutions are also clearly much further along in the
process of institutional isomorphism than are social
Although we anticipate that isomorphic forces entrepreneurs. Their existing power and legitimacy
will, as Nicholls and Cho (2006) predict, inhibit the will tend to resist the widespread isomorphism of SE,
effectiveness of SE, we also recognize that certain if for no other reason than to protect their own
factors will mitigate those forces. These mitigating status.
factors will help SE maintain effectiveness, but they Although social entrepreneurs may be able to
will also limit the scale upon which SE will operate. address specific social problems more effectively if
One such factor mitigating the general operation of they resist the forces of institutional isomorphism,
institutional isomorphism in the SE field is the very they will also be less likely to bring about the broad
nature of what social entrepreneurs do. SE has been and comprehensive reforms needed to bring about
characterized as a form of Schumpeterian entrepre- widespread solutions to those problems. ‘‘They
neurship, a disruptive force that acts as ‘‘…change [social entrepreneurs] defy the traditional isomorphic
agents for society, seizing opportunities others miss forces that often constrain and categorize organiza-
and improving systems, inventing new approaches tional innovation…preferring instead constantly to
and creating sustainable solutions to change society challenge the status quo by reconfiguring accepted
for the better’’ (Skoll Foundation, 2005). Certainly, value creation boundaries (public/private, for-profit/
Schumpeterian entrepreneurs are not inherently not-for-profit, and economic/social)’’ (Nicholls,
immune to the forces of institutional isomorphism 2006, p. 11).
(e.g., witness the railroad, pharmaceutical, and Our third argument why SE will be unable to
computer industries; or the multinational firm). All resolve social problems is the moral argument. To fully
were disruptive agents of ‘‘creative destruction’’ understand this argument, it is necessary to trace
(Schumpeter, 1942), but are now relatively homo- some facets of Western history. The amoral theory
geneous factors in the economy. However, SE of business (Shepard et al., 1995) is currently the
operates in a wide variety of cultures, geographic dominant paradigm in our society, one in which the
locales, and social problems, implying that it may economic institution is viewed as somewhat separate
not be as susceptible to the forces of institutional from the other institutions and immune to some
isomorphism as are many other industries and moral regulations. This paradigm is the result of the
organizational forms. ‘‘As a consequence, social shift, beginning in the seventeenth century, from the
entrepreneurs can avoid many of the coercive iso- ‘‘moral-unity’’ theory of business to the ‘‘amoral
morphic pressures typically experienced by other theory of business’’ (Shepard et al., 1995). The
organizations from outside forces.…[T]he moral-unity theory of business postulates that the
bespoke diversity of much successful social economic institution is viewed as an integral part of
action plays against mimetic forces and embodies a the overall society, and that it is subject to all of the
focus on social objectives rather than organizational same norms and moral regulations as all the other
form.…Using a legitimacy framework to explore the social institutions. In contrast, the amoral theory of
dynamic effectiveness of social entrepreneurship business sees the economic institution as separate
reveals not only their [sic] resistance to institutional from other social institutions, largely insulated from
isomorphic pressures…’’ (Nicholls and Cho, 2006, all of the moral norms followed in the rest of society.
pp. 114–115). It is imperative to note that the moral-unity theory
206 Mukesh Sud et al.

of business, as well as the amoral theory of business, Although neither Luther nor Calvin intended to
pertains to how people view the economic institution do so, both their doctrines promoted the accept-
and how they behave – not whether the economic ability of a more individualistic ideology. This in
institution is, in fact, normative or amoral. turn provided fertile ground in which the spirit of
In this shift, the economic institution has been capitalism could grow, as documented by Weber
separated morally in certain significant ways from (1904–1905/1958). Weber viewed the development
other social institutions such as the church, the state, of rationalism as an integral component of the
the community, and the family. As a result, the development of the spirit of capitalism. Along with
economic institution has come to be exempt from the Enlightenment’s conviction that humans could,
some generally accepted norms. Or, as some have through reason alone, solve the puzzles of the uni-
stated, the economic norms have become the only verse, it was a short road to the belief that man was
ones that matter. his own master (a notion completely foreign to
Luther and Calvin). This notion reduced the influ-
You may prefer to think it’s just a leftist structural ence of the church, and gradually, economic activity
theory that labor and export market stability are often was placed in a special domain somewhat removed
the underlying reasons for various U.S. sanctions,
from moral rules associated with other social insti-
military actions, and other foreign policies. Or you can
just read Investor’s Daily Business and the like, when tutions; this separation constitutes the amoral theory
such things are often spelled out explicitly by the of business.
players themselves, with remarkably little concept that Two major themes arise from this intellectual
any other paradigm for human behavior might exist history. The first is the rise of the individual as an
(Harris, 1999, pp. 122–123). entity separate from the society in which she is sit-
uated. Nisbet (1993) refers to this as the process of
Shepard et al. (1995) point to several factors in individualization, or the separation of individuals
this shift from the moral-unity to the amoral theory from communal social structures. The new societies
of business. From the earliest Western civilizations, heralded the rise of moral egoism and social atom-
the dominant ideology was uniformly communitar- ization. The second theme is the separation of the
ian. In ancient Greece, the prevailing view was that economy from other social institutions. Beginning with
individuals existed only within the context of the the ancient Greeks, Western civilization had viewed
overall society and that economic activity was a society as being composed of unified institutions,
necessary evil, useful only to provide the necessities including the family, the state, the church, and the
of life. Early Christians held views similar to the economy. However, because of the forces just out-
Greeks on the relation between the individual and lined, people came to see the economy as separate in
economic activities. With the birth of Jesus and the some ways from other institutions. Both the pro-
establishment of the Christian church (then the cesses described by these themes have been instru-
Catholic Church), most Western societies were mental in the rise of the amoral theory of business. In
unified under the domination of the church, clearly turn, this paradigm is quite possibly a major con-
representing the moral-unity theory. A significant tributor to the expectation that SE can, by itself,
turning point came with the Protestant Reforma- solve many of our current social problems.
tion, and its notion that individuals could have a Emile Durkheim, like other early sociologists, had
direct relation with their God, without the inter- seen the effects of the profound disruption of society
vention of the church. This novel idea laid the engendered by the shift just outlined, including the
groundwork for the first true recognition of the growing separation of the economy from the rest of
individual as an entity separate and apart from soci- society: ‘‘For two centuries economic life has taken
ety. Calvinism and its revolutionary idea of predes- on an expansion it never knew before. From being a
tination inadvertently provided further impetus for secondary function, despised and left to inferior
the acceptance of economic activity, and for the first classes, it passed on to one of first rank’’ (Durkheim,
time, approved the accumulation of individual 1937/1996, p. 11). In Professional Ethics and Civic
wealth – albeit toward the end of communitarian Morals, Durkheim explored the problems of an
purposes. advanced, complex society in which the economy
Social Entrepreneurship 207

had become so detached from other social institu- conditions in most of the industrialized world. Crime
tions that it became an end in itself. He wrote that in and social disorder began to rise, making inner-city
Western societies neither government nor society areas of the wealthiest societies on earth almost unin-
held moral sway over the economic institution; a habitable. The decline of kinship as a social institution,
state of anarchy within the economic sphere was which has been going on for more than 200 years,
accelerated sharply in the second half of the twentieth
therefore inevitable. He made several references to
century. Marriages and births declined and divorce
‘‘the anarchy of the economy’’ in this work (a con- soared; and one out of every three children in the
cept virtually identical to the amoral theory of United States and more than half of all children in
business). According to Durkheim, ‘‘We can give Scandinavia were born out of wedlock. Finally, trust
some idea of the present situation by saying that the and confidence in institutions went into a forty-year
greater part of the social functions (and this greater decline (Fukuyama, 1999, pp. 55–56).
part means to-day the economic – so wide is their
range) are almost devoid of any moral influence…’’ Durkheim’s concern over the social chaos in his
(Durkheim, 1937/1996, p. 29). Durkheim would time is clearly still relevant today. Within the eco-
argue that social institutions external to business nomic sphere, one of the common indicators of this
must provide effective moral guideposts for SE. condition is the continued prevalence of unethical
As Victor and Stephens (1994) note, for all intents business practices. To expect that any business
and purposes, everything and nothing has changed institution, even SE, can provide the moral leader-
since Durkheim, over one hundred years ago, gave ship needed to resolve multiple, large, complex
the lectures that now comprise Professional Ethics and social problems is simply unreasonable.
Civic Morals. In some ways the milieux are eerily In essence, Durkheim anticipated our argument
similar. Instead of the Industrial Revolution, we are over one hundred years ago. His concern about the
now undergoing the Information Revolution, and effects of the removal of moral constraints on eco-
instead of shifting from an agrarian society to an nomic behavior mirrors ours. To the extent that the
industrial one, we are in the midst of the transition good of all parties is not considered pertinent to
from industrial society to a post-industrial society. economic activities (as is the case under the amoral
Durkheim saw the effects of the transition from an theory of business), the growth of SE will be
agriculturally based economy to an industrial one, retarded.
and we are seeing the shift to a service and infor- The fourth reason that SE, as it scales up, is not
mation-based economy. Finally, we, like Durkheim, likely to be an effective solo agent to resolve social
are still looking for an institution that can instill problems we refer to as the political argument. Albert
morals into the economic institutions; Durkheim Cho (2006) makes the highly relevant point that the
was correct when he observed that the market in a ‘‘social’’ in SE is vacuous unless and until it is defined
capitalistic economy has difficulty imposing a set of – and the process of definition is, itself, fraught with
moral rules on the participants in that market. As tensions. Existing definitions of SE are clearly ap-
Turner notes, ‘‘The problem facing modern Europe probative – but they fail to delineate what social ends
[and the United States] is the separation of the are being pursued. Until the social end is specified,
economy from society and the absence of any Cho maintains that it is impossible to make value
effective regulation of the market place’’ (Turner, judgments about the benefits of SE. For example,
1996, p. xxxi). Society today is undergoing many of consider the social end of providing access to abor-
the same types of social upheavals, with the same tion procedures. If one happens to be ‘‘pro-choice,’’
types of effects that Durkheim witnessed a century the existence of a social venture to ensure access to
ago. Francis Fukuyama has termed this the ‘‘Great abortion procedures is probably a good thing; but if
Disruption’’ in the social values that had prevailed in one is ‘‘pro-life,’’ it is anathema.
the industrial-age society of the mid-twentieth He also points out that the process of establishing
century. social ends is political, and that the political process is
entangled in values; and those values may be dif-
This period, roughly the mid-1960s to the early 1990s, ferent depending on whether they are conceived of
was also marked by seriously deteriorating social in the private or public sphere. Thus, unless the
208 Mukesh Sud et al.

social end pursued by a social entrepreneur has been • Acting in an exclusively self-interested
determined through a public political process, that manner (often referred to as ethical egoism)
end is simply one person’s conception of ‘‘the good’’ renders integrity impossible (McFall, 1987).
(Cho, 2006). • Therefore self-interested behaviors by busi-
The relevance of Cho’s concerns in the current ness practitioners are more likely to occur
context is that, absent some method of reaching than are socially beneficial behaviors
agreement about the desirability of particular social (VanSandt, 2002, ‘A Structural Explanation
ends, SE is subject to varied degrees of approval and for Unethical Business Practices’, unpub-
support from entities external to the social entre- lished manuscript).
preneur. If general support from external bodies is
limited (due to disagreement with the social end or The emphasis on ‘‘winning’’ is a cultural phe-
alienation from the process of determining the end), nomenon that is prevalent in the West, especially in
SE will not be as effective as it otherwise could be. America. Alfie Kohn characterizes winning as ‘‘a
Thus, at the very least, social entrepreneurs are capsule description of our entire culture’’ (Kohn,
dependent on processes external to them to set 1992, p. 3). Winning and losing are the central
generally approved social goals. ‘‘Yet the act of components of structural competition. ‘‘To say that
defining the domain of the social inevitably requires an activity is structurally competitive is to say that it
exclusionary and ultimately political choices about is characterized by what I will call mutually exclusive
which concerns can claim to be in society’s ‘true’ goal attainment.…This means, very simply, that my
interest. These choices reveal that, despite its pro- success requires your failure’’ (Kohn, 1992, p. 4).
testations to the contrary, SE by its very nature is al- The nascent field of SE studies implicitly recog-
ways already a political phenomenon’’ (Cho, 2006, nizes this propensity toward self-interest and win-
p. 36, author’s emphasis). ning, and the dichotomy between self-interested
The final argument we advance here is the struc- behaviors and other-directed behaviors. ‘‘[U]nlike
tural argument. Simply put, this argument states that business entrepreneurs who are motivated by profits,
the very structure of a capitalistic economy works social entrepreneurs are motivated to improve soci-
against the idea of SE. The crux of this argument is ety’’ (Skoll Foundation, 2005). We must acknowl-
contained in the inherent tension that all business edge at this point that we realize that, in some ways,
enterprises face: competitive advantage (i.e., self- we are calling into question the most basic
interest) versus corporate social responsibility (i.e., assumptions about capitalism. Adam Smith is pop-
interest in others’ welfare). In more detail, this ularly thought to have argued in Wealth of Nations
argument is that the current way we view compe- that self-interest is the basis upon which an economy
tition in the marketplace makes it unlikely that creates wealth for all. ‘‘It is not from the benevo-
business people, even social entrepreneurs, will lence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that
pursue socially beneficial ends. we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their
The premises and conclusion of the argument are: own interest. We address ourselves, not to their
humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to
• The structure of the American economy has them of our own necessities but of their advantages’’
evolved into a bifurcated system of large, (Smith, 1776/1986, pp. 26–27).
powerful companies and relatively small, Smith’s supposed reliance on self-interest to guide
powerless organizations (Galbraith, 1967). economic activity is understandable when one
• Because of this division in the economic focuses on personal gain; but the title of his book,
system, the original meaning of competition, Wealth of Nations, reveals his true purpose. Smith
as envisioned by Adam Smith (1776/1986), hoped to show how an economy could be structured
has been bastardized into ‘‘winning’’ or so that it benefited everyone in the nation, not just a
‘‘maximizing profits.’’ few lucky (or hard-working) individuals (Muller,
• The emphasis on winning causes self- 1993). Unfortunately, he did not provide much in
interested behavior – adherence to ethical the way of an explanation about how that would
egoism. work. Instead, he relied on the now famous
Social Entrepreneurship 209

‘‘invisible hand’’ explanation to show how self- Smith failed to provide any support for his
interest would work to benefit all. contention, and was later contradicted by another
economist, who said, ‘‘Left to themselves, economic
But the annual revenue of every society is always forces do not work out for the best except perhaps
precisely equal to the exchangeable value of the whole
for the powerful’’ (Galbraith, 1973, p. xiii).
annual produce of its industry….As every individual,
Although there certainly are successful, selfless
therefore, endeavours as much as he can both to
employ his capital in the support of domestic industry,
social entrepreneurs, they are a minute minority of
and so to direct that industry that its produce may be of the population. Because these SEs so clearly stand
the greatest value; every individual necessarily labours out from the population of business entrepreneurs,
to render the annual revenue of the society as great as they are the exceptions that prove the rule inherent
he can. He generally, indeed, neither intends to pro- in the structural argument – that individual eco-
mote the public interest, nor knows how much he is nomic gain is the primary motivation for business
promoting it. By preferring the support of domestic to entrepreneurs. Early research efforts in the field of
that of foreign industry, he intends only his own SE implicitly recognize this by concentrating on
security; and by directing that industry in such a ‘‘profiles of ‘hero’ social entrepreneurs’’ (Nicholls
manner as its produce may be of the greatest value, he and Cho, 2006, p. 99), or by asking if they are
intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many
‘‘‘world-historical individuals,’ heroic men and
other cases led by an invisible hand to promote an end
women ‘with insight into what was needed and what
which was no part of his intention….By pursuing his
own interest he frequently promotes that of the society was timely,’ whose ‘deeds and…words are the best
more effectually than when he really intends to pro- of their time’?’’ (Nicholls and Cho, 2006, p. 106,
mote it (Smith, 1776, p. 265). quoting Hegel, 1988, p. 32). Expecting that such a
small percentage of the population, even if they are
Smith’s assertion is akin to the cartoon in which truly heroic, can make a sizeable dent in the plethora
one sophisticated mathematician is presenting his of social problems is simply unrealistic.
proof, with an intermediate step of ‘‘…then a mir- It is equally unrealistic to expect, given the way
acle occurs,’’ only to be critiqued by another, who markets operate, entrepreneurs to be motivated so-
says, ‘‘I think you should be more explicit here in lely to address socially beneficial issues. In one of the
step two.’’ examples, which addresses a pressing housing prob-
lem in Mumbai, India, an entrepreneur clearly states,
‘‘It makes a lot of investment sense for us. We are
not here just to serve a social cause’’ (Architecture
for Humanity, 2007). We must strike a note of
caution here. Foundations like the Grameen Bank
have demonstrated that providing financial services
to rural communities and micro-entrepreneurs can
be achieved on a sustainable and scalable basis. This
has resulted in developments which cause us con-
cern. As we described as part of the legitimacy
argument, existing financial institutions have begun
to enter the microfinance field. We call into ques-
tion whether the traditional goal of profit maximi-
zation, which these for-profit organizations espouse,
is appropriate in dealing with the poor.

How then shall we proceed?

If SE is not the answer to our social ills, then what is?


Certainly not business in general – many argue that
210 Mukesh Sud et al.

it has contributed far more to social problems than it especially government, religion, and education must
has to alleviating them (Derber, 1998; Ehrenreich, be intimately involved in finding solutions to our
2001; Kelly, 2003; Korten, 1995; Nace, 2003; social problems. The current imbalance is built into
Shulman, 2003). Governments, in all their various our social structures, as one legal scholar notes,
forms, seem almost entirely incapable of ‘‘fixing’’ the ‘‘I realized that the many social ills created by
social problems their citizens face. Religion appears corporations stem directly from corporate law. It dawned
to have virtually abdicated its influence in the West, on me that the law, in its current form, actually
along with its emphasis on helping the disadvan- inhibits executives and corporations from being
taged. ‘‘However, the decline of organized religion socially responsible’’ (Hinkley, 2002, p. 4, author’s
in some cultures has provided another set of social emphasis).
market failures’’ (Nicholls, 2006, p. 9). We mentioned previously that we are not
It is our contention that no single social institu- Friedman disciples, except in one instance. His
tion – an organizational system which functions to philosophy of corporate social responsibility is
satisfy basic social needs by providing an ordered summed up in his directive, ‘‘…there is one and
framework linking the individual to the larger cul- only one social responsibility of business – to use its
ture (Shepard, 2005) – is capable of resolving the resources and engage in activities designed to
large-scale problems now facing us, or those yet to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules
come. It will take the collaborative efforts of many of the game…’’ (Friedman, 1962, p. 133). Cur-
different sectors to effectively address our complex rently, for all practical purposes, business makes up
social problems. As Albert Einstein is purported to its own rules of the game (Kelly, 2003; Korten,
have said, ‘‘Everything should be made as simple as 1995; Nace, 2003; Stone, 1975). Until other social
possible, but not simpler.’’ If our social problems cut institutions provide an effective counterbalance to
across institutional boundaries (as they all do), Ein- business’s influence, and help develop more just
stein would tell us that all those institutions must be ‘‘rules,’’ the second and third bottom lines will
involved in the solutions. continue to be effectively ignored.
Although collaborative efforts among social
institutions sound good on paper, the current
imbalance of power may impede their ability to do How can social institutions work together?
so. Business, or the economy, is clearly the dominant
social institution in the West, and has been for more James Rest, building on the work of Lawrence
than two centuries (Durkheim, 1937/1996; Etzioni, Kohlberg and Jean Piaget, developed a model of
1991). This fact, by itself, is not necessarily indicative activities necessary for moral behavior to occur. His
of anything. However, problems arise when the Four Component Model specifies that a moral agent
‘‘currency’’ of one social sphere gains influence in must: (1) become sensitive to, or aware of, the moral
another sphere (Walzer, 1983). As an example, situation; (2) make moral judgments about the sit-
consider the influence that money (the currency of uation; (3) be sufficiently motivated to act, and (4)
the economy) has gained in the political sphere have courage to follow through with the action.
(whose currency ideally includes ideas, justice, and Other than needing to become aware of a moral
morality). Money’s influence in other spheres often situation before any of the other steps can occur,
manifests itself in the form of a single criterion for Rest is careful to say that his four components do not
decision making – that of profit, or other forms of necessarily occur in sequence, and they are likely to
monetary gain. interact (Rest, 1994). This model is a useful tool for
SE scholars are fond of talking about the ‘‘double’’ analyzing the likelihood that moral behavior (in this
or even ‘‘triple’’ bottom line. We agree with the particular instance, SE) will occur. If the amoral
desirability of such an approach. However, until we theory of business is accurate, we would expect
acknowledge that only one of those lines – monetary repeated failure in any and all of the four steps. With
profit – really matters to a large majority of decision business practitioners’ moral capabilities artificially
makers, our calls for more social justice will truncated, it becomes clear that other social institu-
remain largely unanswered. Other social institutions, tions’ input is necessary. As one author notes,
Social Entrepreneurship 211

‘‘Childline [an SE venture in India] and the Gram- the person wilts under pressure, is easily distracted or
een Bank could not have achieved national and discouraged, is a wimp and weak-willed, then moral
global impact without the financing and the legiti- failure occurs because of deficiency in Component
macy they received from governments’’ (Bornstein, IV (weak character)’’ (Rest, 1994, p. 24). Some of
2004, p. 269). Below, we postulate ways in which the defining characteristics of SEs are their extraor-
dissimilar social institutions might use Rest’s frame- dinary devotion to their causes and their persistence
work in order to work together to solve social in the face of often overwhelming obstacles (Born-
problems. stein, 2004; Nicholls, 2004, 2006). Although these
Awareness – The initial recognition that a social are obviously commendable qualities, they are not a
problem exists, and carries with it moral implica- sound basis upon which to build a system of social
tions, may arise from a plethora of sources. For justice. ‘‘We want [people] with moral courage. Yet
example, a religious order might recognize that a we must strive to create organizations where moral
number of its parishioners need basic medical care. courage is not needed’’ (Kidder, 2005, p. 179). As
Lacking the ability to provide those services by itself, we have discussed in the isomorphism argument,
it might enlist government agencies or SEs to address SEs’ ultimate goal is to change the system itself, so
the problem. Our moral argument clarifies the point that the obstacles they (and more importantly, their
that viewing business as an amoral enterprise severely clients) encounter cease to exist (Nicholls and Cho,
limits the operation of moral awareness. Seeing 2006; Skoll Foundation, 2005). Because these
business as an undertaking with moral implications is obstacles are the products of a wide range of social
necessary for moral awareness to operate. institutions, all of those institutions must be involved
Judgment – Moral judgment is the topic about in their destruction.
which philosophers have been debating for more
than two millennia. To assume that SEs, operating
in a vacuum, would know the ‘‘right’’ actions to Examples
take, gives them much more credit than they are
due. As we point out in the political argument, We have argued that as SE attempts to scale up, it will,
social ends may be highly contentious (take the by itself, be unable to solve the social problems we
pro-choice/right to life debate as one example). currently face. For a variety of reasons, it will take a
The process for establishing social ends is neces- joint effort by several social institutions to effectively
sarily political and, in many cases, would include address those issues. As we show in the following
input from other social institutions, such as the examples, varied social institutions are working with
family, religion, or education. SEs to address some of the most profound social
Motivation – As the Skoll Foundation points out problems currently faced. These institutions include
on its website, SEs are motivated by more than just governments, education systems, and for-profit
the bottom line; they seek to improve society. businesses. These examples provide clear evidence
However, we present the case in the structural that our arguments are sound, and that such inter-
argument that we cannot rely solely on SE’s benef- institutional collaboration is a necessary element in
icence. The profit motive is too strong in our society addressing our most serious social ills.
to realistically believe that a subset of the economic
institution will be able to bring about widespread
social improvements. Therefore, other social insti- One laptop per child
tutions like governments, religious orders, and
educational systems must become involved to either This is not just a matter of giving a laptop to each
change societal values or provide a system of rules child, as if bestowing on them some magical charm.
The magic lies within – within each child, within each
that guide economic behavior toward more social
scientist –, scholar –, or just-plain-citizen-in-the-
ends. making. This initiative is meant to bring it forth into
Courage – Rest points out, ‘‘A person may be the light of day.
morally sensitive, may make good moral judgments,
and may place high priority on moral values, but if Kofi Annan
212 Mukesh Sud et al.

Founded in 2005, it has been only a few short existence of a $100 laptop concerned many manu-
years since Nicholas Negroponte presented his facturers who were actively working to lower the
vision for a global educational program to the World price of laptops over a longer term. Moreover, many
Economic Forum in Davos, Switzerland. Joined by computer manufacturers were already planning and/
technological heavyweights AMD, Google, and or producing laptops designed for children (e.g.,
News Corp, Negroponte outlined his strategy for Intel and Asus) and had begun attempting to garner
providing ‘‘…children around the world with new market share in developing countries for their own
opportunities to explore, experiment, and express products. The development of the OLPC’s XO
themselves.’’ Negroponte’s organization, One represents not only a potentially acute downward
Laptop Per Child (OLPC), has chosen a bold and force on current laptop prices, but also represented
unique approach for achieving this goal. direct and vital competition for what has been
The strategy undertaken to reach these ends estimated to be billions of potential customers.
involves the coordination of experts in technological Additionally, the success of the OLPC initiative
design and manufacturing, as well as educational hinges on the buy-in by the leaders of developing
research and international relations (representing countries. While countries such as Brazil, Uruguay,
the social institutions of business, education, and Libya, Rwanda, and others have ceremoniously
government) to develop a means by which children committed to the OLPC cause, follow-through with
in underdeveloped nations and communities can orders on the magnitude expected by OLPC has
enhance their own learning process. Based on fallen short (Moon, 2007). Moreover, countries
research by Seymour Papert, an MIT professor and aggressively sought out by the OLPC, including
renowned expert on artificial intelligence and the India and China, have shown wavering interest in
use of technology in early education, and espoused the program. In both cases, politically oriented
by Negroponte in his book Being Digital (1995), the concerns have been raised as to whether or not these
organization has developed a rugged, energy-effi- countries could use their own advanced technolog-
cient, internet-capable laptop, called the XO, in- ical know-how to create machines within their own
stalled with software designed specifically to allow countries. To partially counter these obstacles, the
children not only access to the world via the inter- OLPC sold XO machines for $400 in a ‘‘give 1, get
net, but also the capability to manipulate and 1’’ campaign within the United States, a marked
experiment with programming in order to enhance change in strategy, for a 2-week period in
critical thinking and problem-solving skills. November of 2007 in order to generate interest and
Though the goals to which Negroponte and the funding to jumpstart the dissemination of the ma-
One Laptop Per Child organization aspire have met chines in target countries.
with little criticism, it is the strategy executed that Though these are just two of the influential
has instigated the most controversy and evoked challenges for the OLPC organization, they repre-
many pressures from outside constituencies that have sent well the conflict experienced by social entre-
attempted to inhibit the growth and achievements of preneurs as their organizations begin to gain
the OLPC organization. Negroponte’s organization momentum. The more support the OLPC gains in
has met with resistance from factions within for- terms of its mission, the more pressure the organi-
profit technology organizations, educational re- zation faces to conform to the expectations of
search, and governments of those countries targeted powerful, yet unintentional, constituencies. For
for distribution of OLPC’s machines. example, as OLPC began to make progress toward
Particular resistance stemmed from one of the key the design and production of a much more durable,
goals set forth by the OLPC, to build a computer for efficient, and economical computing machine iso-
less than $100. This price point, was set in the hopes morphic pressure was applied by both the techno-
that such a relatively low price for a fully functioning logical and educational systems to mold OLPC’s
laptop would allow countries to buy larger quantities approach into one more traditional, and thereby less
of laptops for their own educational systems. How- threatening. Moreover, though the leadership of
ever, at the same time, the market has been pres- many countries agree, in principle, with the goals of
suring laptop manufacturers to lower prices. The the OLPC organization and realize the potential for
Social Entrepreneurship 213

significant long-term benefits, they seem to resist the slums and that these numbers are expected to swell as
achievement of those goals in ways that do not di- the rural exodus continues.
rectly, and in the short term, benefit those nations. Dharavi houses close to a million people squeezed
These structural and political pressures created clear into 550 acres of swampy landfill in the center of
and challenging obstacles to the OLPC program’s India’s financial capital, Mumbai. Sewage filled
progress. gutters (there is a toilet for every 1,440 residents),
Recent events have indicated that the OLPC rickety ramshackle homes, labyrinthine lanes so
organization is taking action to address these iso- crowded with shanties that little sunlight penetrates,
morphic, political, and structural pressures. For and garbage piles everywhere are a common sight in
example, in 2007 the OLPC created a position on its what is probably Asia’s largest slum. This place is
Board for a representative from Intel, historically booming, however, with sometimes highly polluting
their most staunch and bitter competition. This industrial activity. A thriving pottery business exists
unlikely collaboration between not-for-profit and where potters have passed on their craft through
for-profit organizations, while surprising many generations. Other industries include soap making,
observers, was explained by Negroponte as a way for chemical manufacturing, and recycling, all of which
the OLPC organization to maximize the number of have existed side by side with sweat shops, in which
laptops distributed to children around the world workers on sewing machines toil for long hours in
(Krazit, 2007). tiny rooms. It has been estimated that the annual
Additionally, the OLPC organization has re- gross revenues of business emanating from Dharavi is
sponded to political and structural pressures by approximately $650 million (Slum Rehabilition
shifting its marketing strategy from a primary Authority, 2007).
emphasis on persuading national educational and The residents are also a source of cheap, skilled
political leaders of target countries to working di- and unskilled labor that is desperately required to
rectly with local and regional leadership of target help keep the wheels of India’s financial capital
nations in order to build demand from within. moving. However, successive governments’ apathy
While the outcome of this new strategic approach toward their citizens’ well-being, the prohibitive
remains to be seen, early evidence indicates that the cost of housing in the city, and the regular influx of
OLPC organization may make stronger headway people has further aggravated a serious housing
toward achieving its mission. In fact, in October of problem. Despite a number of attempts over the past
2007, after an initial rejection by the Indian gov- few decades to address this issue and get the squatters
ernment in order to evaluate India’s ability to build evicted from what is now valuable government land,
its own program from within, a pilot program was it has remained an intractable problem. This is due in
begun at Khairat School in Khairat-Dhangarwada, a no small measure to the so-called ‘‘vote bank poli-
small village in Maharashtra State, India (Vaz, tics’’ prevalent here. Local democratically elected
2008). governments have turned a blind eye simply because
the densely populated areas serve as a source of votes
during elections. A number of attempts, over the
Dharavi – the makeover of the largest slum in Asia years, by the city’s slum clearance board have also
been unsuccessful.
The root cause of urban slumming seems to lie not in Historically, slum rehabilitation has been ad-
urban poverty but in urban wealth. dressed on a piecemeal basis, more often being
Gita Verma tackled as a housing, rather than a socio-economic
problem. This has resulted in the lack of any sus-
The operational definition of a slum is poor or tainable model of rehabilitation. The Dharavi
informal housing which is characterized by over- Redeployment Project (DRP), a public/private
crowding, inadequate access to safe water and sani- partnership has adopted a significantly different
tation, and has insecurity of tenure. The United approach on three fronts. If successful, this model
Nations has estimated that more than a billion could be a blueprint for slum rehabilitation all over
people – a third of the urban population – live in the world.
214 Mukesh Sud et al.

First, it attempts to treat slum dwellers as a valu- the plan and legislation introduced that the slum
able human resource that can act as a cornerstone of resettlement proceeds after seventy percent of
a vibrant and robust economy. Unlike previous households sign up for it. The Free Space Index (the
urban planning initiatives, DRP seeks to integrate square footage of area a builder is typically allowed
slum areas with the rest of the city in order to to construct) has been increased to ensure viability of
provide sustainable development. The project rec- the project. The government is thus clearly luring
ognizes both the need of the slum dwellers to con- private builders both with the promise of huge re-
tinue their livelihood, as well as the necessity of turns on their investments and the ability to partic-
providing them infrastructure for HIKES (Heath, ipate in a noble cause.
Income, Knowledge, Environment, and Socio- Traditionally, the common approach for slum
cultural development). Significantly, the plan development has been for the government to sanc-
envisages full deployment of slum dwellers and tion slum clearance and then build low-cost housing
transit accommodation until the project is com- with public funds. Toshi Noda, Asia Director of the
pleted, within the same areas where they now reside. United Nations Human Settlement Program (UN-
Attempts are being made to upgrade their skills Habitat) said, ‘‘Free apartments is not common. It is
while maintaining their vocation. For example, a new scheme. I think it will work because the
people who for many generations have been en- private sector can get their profit by developing the
gaged in pottery will be provided training to im- other half of the real estate’’ (Giridharadas, 2006).
prove their skill sets using other mediums, such as Besides heralding it as a financial ‘‘opportunity of
ceramics, while opportunities will be provided to a life time’’ for prospective builders, the Global
them to market their crafts locally as well as a po- Expression of Interest highlighted the opportunity to
tential export market. participate in a noble cause with huge social benefits.
Secondly, in anticipation of likely moral and A director of a New York investment fund was
structural pressures that might arise, the plan has recently quoted in the local media as saying, ‘‘It
involved the private sector. International developers makes a lot of investment sense for us. We’re not
have been invited to transform Dharavi into an here just to serve a social cause’’ (Architecture for
integrated township with all modern civic amenities Humanity, 2007).
and complete infrastructure, including entrepre- The project, which is now at the bidding phase, is
neurial zones where small businesses could be run. likely to take 6–7 years to complete. The Global
Under the proposal each family would be entitled to Expression of Interest advertisement, inviting pro-
a 225 square foot dwelling unit equipped with spective bidders, was published in May 2007. Short-
proper sanitation in mid- and high-rise buildings. listing of bidders is in progress. Simultaneously, an
Approximately 36.6 million square feet of livable environmental impact assessment in each of the five
space will be constructed by the top five bidders, sectors of the redevelopment is in progress. The
each of whom would be allotted a 107-acre zone. In initial response from the international community
exchange for providing local inhabitants with free has been overwhelmingly positive with top-flight
homes and licensed industrial space, the successful builders submitting offers, which are in the process
builders will have the right to develop an additional of being evaluated. Mumbai’s Dharvai makeover is
43.5 million square feet in the open spaces freed up an exemplar of how social entrepreneurship can
by relocating the slum dwellers, which they would succeed by engaging other institutions.
be allowed to sell or lease commercially (Slum
Rehabilition Authority, 2007).
Finally, the government is confining its role to References
that of a facilitator. The original idea was conceived
by an architect who has since been invited to join Architecture for Humanity: 2007, ‘Dharavi’, http://
the DRP and has been made the project manage- www.architectureforhumanity.org/programs/Settle
ment consultant. To preempt likely political pres- ments/dharavi.html.
sures that this model might face NGO’s have been Bornstein, D.: 2004, How to Change the World (Oxford
entrusted with spreading awareness of the benefits of University Press, New York).
Social Entrepreneurship 215

Boschee, J.: 1995, ‘Social Entrepreneurship’, Across the Harris, B.: 1999, Steal This Book and Get Life Without
Board 32(3), 20–25. Parole (Common Courage Press, Monroe, ME).
Bruck, C.: 2006, ‘Millions for Millions’, New Yorker, Hegel, G.: 1988, Introduction to the Philosophy of History
October 30. (Hackett, Indianapolis, IN).
Carson, R.: 1962, Silent Spring (Houghton Mifflin, Hinkley, R.: 2002, ‘How Corporate Law Inhibits Ethics’,
Boston). Business Ethics, January/February.
Cho, A.: 2006, ‘Politics, Values and Social Entrepre- Kelly, M.: 2003, The Divine Right of Capital: Dethroning
neurship: A Critical Appraisal’, in J. Mair, J. Robinson the Corporate Aristocracy (Berrett-Koehler Publishers,
and K. Hockerts (eds.), Social Entrepreneurship (Palgrave Inc, San Francisco).
Macmillan, Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire). Kidder, R.: 2005, Moral Courage (W. Morrow,
Dart, R.: 2004, ‘The Legitimacy of Social Enterprise’, New York).
Nonprofit Management and Leadership 14(4), 411–424. Kohn, A.: 1992, No Contest: The Case Against Competition,
Dees, J.: 1998, ‘Enterprising Nonprofits’, Harvard Business Revised Edition (Houghton Mifflin, New York).
Review, January–February, 55–67. Korten, D.: 1995, When Corporations Rule the World
Dees, J., J. Emerson and P. Economy: 2001, Enterprising (Berrett-Koehler Publishers, Inc., San Francisco).
Nonprofits: A Toolkit for Social Entrepreneurs (Wiley, Krazit, T.: 2007, ‘OLPC and Intel Bury the Hatchet—for
New York). the Children’, Technology News, http://news.zdnet.
Derber, C.: 1998, Corporation Nation: How Corporations are com/2100-9595_22-152541.html.
Taking Over Our Lives and What We can Do About It Leadbeater, C.: 1997, The Rise of the Social Entrepreneur
(St. Martin’s Griffin, New York). (Demos, London).
DiMaggio, P. and H. Anheier: 1990, ‘The Sociology of Mair, J., J. Robinson and K. Hockerts: 2006, ‘Introduc-
Nonprofit Organizations and Sectors’, Annual Review tion’, in J. Mair, J. Robinson and K. Hockerts (eds.),
of Sociology 16, 137–159. Social Entrepreneurship (Palgrave Macmillan, Hound-
DiMaggio, P. and W. Powell: 1983, ‘The Iron Cage mills, Basingstoke, Hampshire).
Revisited: Institutional Isomorphism and Collective Marketplace: 2007, ‘Wall Street Donates Its Wisdom’, http://
Rationality in Organizational Fields’, American Socio- www.marketplace.publicradio.org. Accessed 2 Nov.
logical Review 48, 147–160. McFall, L.: 1987, ‘Integrity’, Ethics 98, 5–20.
Durkheim, E.: 1937/1996, Professional Ethics and Civic Moon, A.: 2007, ‘$100 Laptop Doubles in Price But
Morals (Routledge, London). Generates First Large Order’, IT News Digest, http://
Ehrenreich, B.: 2001, Nickel and Dimed: On (Not) Getting blogs.techrepublic.com.com/tech-news/?p=1457.
by in America (Metropolitan Books, New York). Muller, J.: 1993, Adam Smith in His Time and Ours:
Etzioni, A.: 1991, ‘Reflections on the Teaching of Business Designing the Decent Society (The Free Press, New York).
Ethics’, Business Ethics Quarterly 1(4), 355–365. Nace, T.: 2003, Gangs of America: The Rise of Corporate
Friedman, M.: 1962, Capitalism and Freedom (University Power and the Disabling of Democracy (Berrett-Koehler
of Chicago Press, Chicago). Publishers, Inc., San Francisco).
Friedman, M.: 1970, ‘Social Responsibility of Business’, Negroponte, N.: 1995, Being Digital (Alfred A. Knopf,
The New York Times Magazine Section, September 13. Inc., New York).
Fukuyama, F.: 1999, ‘The Great Disruption’, The Atlantic Nicholls, A.: 2004, ‘Social Entrepreneurship: The
Monthly 283, 55–80. Emerging Landscape’, in S. Crainer and D. Dearlove
Galbraith, J.: 1967, The New Industrial State (Houghton (eds.), Financial Times Handbook of Management, 3rd
Mifflin, Boston). Edition (FT Prentice-Hall, Harlow, UK).
Galbraith, J.: 1973, Economics & The Public Purpose Nicholls, A.: 2006, ‘Introduction’, in A. Nicholls (ed.),
(Houghton Mifflin, Boston). Social Entrepreneurship: New Models of Sustainable Social
Giridharadas, A.: 2006, ‘Not Everyone is Grateful as Change (Oxford University Press, Oxford).
Investors Build Free Apartments in Mumbai Slums’, Nicholls, A. and A. Cho: 2006, ‘Social Entrepreneurship:
New York Times December 14. http://www.nytimes. The Structuration of a Field’, in A. Nicholls (ed.),
com/2006/12/15/business/worldbusiness/15slums. Social Entrepreneurship: New Models of Sustainable Social
html?_r=1&oref=slogin. Change (Oxford University Press, Oxford).
Gore, A.: 2006, An Inconvenient Truth (Rodale Press, Nisbet, R.: 1993, The Sociological Tradition (Transaction
Emmaus, PA). Publishers, New Brunswick, CT).
Grossman, R. and F. Adams: 1993, Taking Care of Business: Oliver, C.: 1993, ‘Strategic Response to Institutional
Citizenship and the Charter of Incorporation (Charter, Ink., Processes’, Academy of Management Review 16(1),
Cambridge, MA). 145–179.
216 Mukesh Sud et al.

Rest, J.: 1994, ‘Background: Theory and Research’, in Van Til, J.: 1988, Mapping the Third World: Voluntarism in
J. R. Rest and D. Narváez (eds.), Moral Development in a Changing Social Economy (Foundation Centre, New
the Professions (Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publish- York).
ers, Hillsdale, NJ). Vaz, A.: 2008, ‘Khairat Village Comes Under One-
Schumpeter, J.: 1942, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy Child-One-Laptop Scheme’, Merinews, http://www.
(Harper & Brothers, New York). merinews.com/catFull.jsp?articleID=130117.
Shepard, J.: 2005, Sociology, 9th Edition (Thomson Venkataraman, S.: 1997, ‘The Distinctive Domain of
Wadsworth, Belmont, CA). Entrepreneurship Research: An Editor’s Perspective’,
Shepard, J., J. Shepard, J. Wimbush and C. Stephens: in J. Katz and R. Brockhaus (eds.), Advances in Entre-
1995, ‘The Place of Ethics in Business: Shifting Para- preneurship, Firm Emergence and Growth, Vol. 3 (Jai Press,
digms?’, Business Ethics Quarterly 5, 577–601. Greenwhich, CT), pp. 119–138.
Shulman, B.: 2003, The Betrayal of Work: How Low-Wage Victor, B. and Stephens, C.: 1994, ‘The Dark Side of the
Jobs Fail 30 Million Americans and Their Families New Organizational Forms: An Editorial Essay’,
(The New Press, New York). Organizational Science 5, 479–482.
Skoll Foundation: 2005, http://www.skollfoundation.org. Walzer, M.: 1983, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism
Slum Rehabilitation Authority: 2007, ‘Expression of and Equality (Basic Books, United States).
Interest’, http://www.sra.gov.in/. Weber, M.: 1904–1905/1958, The Protestant Ethic and the
Smith, A.: 1776/1986, The Wealth of Nations, in Spirit of Capitalism (Charles Scribner’s Sons, New
R. L. Heilbroner (ed.), The Essential Adam Smith York).
(W. W. Norton & Company, New York). Wolman, W. and A. Colamosca : 1997, The Judas Economy:
Stevenson, H.: 1985, ‘The Heart of Entrepreneurship’, The Triumph of Capital and the Betrayal of Work (Addison-
Harvard Business Review 85, 85–94. Wesley Publishing Company, Inc., Reading, MA).
Stone, C.: 1975, Where the Law Ends: The Social Control of
Corporate Behavior (Harper Torchbooks, New York). Augustana College,
Suchman, M.: 1995, ‘Managing Legitimacy: Strategic and 639 38th Street, Rock Island,
Institutional Approaches’, Academy of Management IL 61201-2296, U.S.A.
Review 20(3), 571–610. E-mail: mukeshsud@augustana.edu
Turner, B.: 1996, ‘Preface to the Second Edition’, in E-mail: craigvansandt@augustana.edu
E. Durkheim (Author), Professional Ethics and Civic
E-mail: amandabaugous@augustana.edu
Morals (Routledge, London).

You might also like