Karl Popper

You might also like

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 36

Karl Popper

First published Thu Nov 13, 1997; substantive revision Mon Sep 12, 2022
Karl Popper is generally regarded as one of the greatest philosophers of science of the
twentieth century. He was also a social and political philosopher of considerable stature, a
self-professed critical-rationalist, a dedicated opponent of all forms of scepticism and
relativism in science and in human affairs generally and a committed advocate and staunch
defender of the “Open Society”. One of the many remarkable features of Popper’s thought is
the scope of his intellectual influence: he was lauded by Bertrand Russell, taught Imre
Lakatos, Paul Feyerabend and philanthropist George Soros at the London School of
Economics, numbered David Miller, Joseph Agassi, Alan Musgrave and Jeremy Shearmur
amongst his research assistants, was counted by Thomas Szasz as “among my foremost
teachers” and had close ties with the economist Friedrich Hayek and the art historian Ernst
Gombrich. Additionally, Peter Medawar, John Eccles and Hermann Bondi are amongst the
distinguished scientists who have acknowledged their intellectual indebtedness to his work,
the latter declaring that “There is no more to science than its method, and there is no more to
its method than Popper has said”.

 1. Life
 2. Backdrop to Popper’s Thought
 3. The Problem of Demarcation
 4. Basic Statements, Falsifiability and Convention
 5. The Growth of Human Knowledge
 6. Probability, Knowledge and Verisimilitude
 7. Objective Knowledge and The Three Worlds
Ontology
 8. Social and Political Thought—The Critique of
Historicism and Holism
 9. Scientific Knowledge, History, and Prediction
 10. Immutable Laws and Contingent Trends
 11. Critical Evaluation
 Bibliography
o Primary Literature: Works by Popper
o Secondary Literature/Other Sources
 Academic Tools
 Other Internet Resources
 Related Entries

1. Life
Karl Raimund Popper was born on 28 July 1902 in Vienna. His parents, who were of Jewish
origin, brought him up in an atmosphere which he was later to describe as “decidedly
bookish”. His father was a lawyer by profession, but he also took a keen interest in the
classics and in philosophy, and communicated to his son an interest in social and political
issues. His mother inculcated in him such a passion for music that for a time he contemplated
taking it up as a career; he initially chose the history of music as a second subject for his
Ph.D. examination. Subsequently, his love for music became one of the inspirational forces
in the development of his thought, and manifested itself in his highly original interpretation
of the relationship between dogmatic and critical thinking, in his account of the distinction
between objectivity and subjectivity, and, most importantly, in the growth of his hostility
towards all forms of historicism, including historicist ideas about the nature of the
“progressive” in music. The young Karl attended the local Realgymnasium, where he was
unhappy with the standards of the teaching, and, after an illness he left to attend the
University of Vienna in 1918, matriculating four years later. In 1919 he became heavily
involved in left-wing politics and became for a time a Marxist. However, he was quickly
disillusioned with the doctrinaire character of the latter, and soon abandoned it entirely. He
also discovered the psychoanalytic theories of Freud and Adler (he served briefly as a
voluntary social worker with deprived children in one of the latter’s clinics in the 1920s), and
heard Einstein lecture on relativity theory. The dominance of the critical spirit in Einstein,
and its total absence in Marx, Freud and Adler, struck Popper as being of fundamental
importance: the pioneers of psychoanalysis, he came to think, couched their theories in terms
which made them amenable only to confirmation, while Einstein’s theory, crucially, had
testable implications which, if false, would have falsified the theory itself.
Popper took some time to settle on a career; he trained as a cabinetmaker, obtained a primary
school teaching diploma in 1925 and qualified to teach mathematics and physics in
secondary school in 1929. He undertook a doctoral programme with the department of
psychology at the University of Vienna, then under the supervision of Karl Bühler, one of the
founder members of the Würzburg school of experimental psychology. Popper’s project was
initially designed as a psychological investigation of human memory, on which he conducted
initial research. However, the subject matter of a planned introductory chapter on
methodology assumed a position of increasing pre-eminence and this resonated with Bühler,
who, as a Kant scholar (a professor of philosophy and psychology), had famously addressed
the issue of the contemporary “crisis in psychology”. This “crisis”, for Bühler, related to the
question of the unity of psychology and had been generated by the proliferation of then
competing paradigms within the discipline which had undermined the hitherto dominant
associationist one and problematized the question of method. Accordingly, under Bühler’s
direction, Popper switched his topic to the methodological problem of cognitive psychology
and received his doctorate in 1928 for his dissertation “Zur Methodenfrage der
Denkpsychologie”. In extending Bühler’s Kantian approach to the crisis in the dissertation,
Popper critiqued Moritz Schlick’s neutral monist programme to make psychology scientific
by transforming it into a science of brain processes. This latter ideal, Popper argued, was
misconceived, but the issues raised by it ultimately had the effect of refocusing Popper’s
attention away from Bühler’s question of the unity of psychology to that of its scientificity.
This philosophical focus on questions of method, objectivity and claims to scientific status
was to become a principal life-long concern, bringing the orientation of Popper’s thought
into line with that of such contemporary “analytic” philosophers as Frege and Russell as well
as that of many members of the Vienna Circle.
Popper married Josephine Anna Henninger (“Hennie”) in 1930, and she also served as his
amanuensis until her death in 1985. At an early stage of their marriage they decided that they
would never have children. In 1937 he took up a position teaching philosophy at the
University of Canterbury in New Zealand, where he was to remain for the duration of the
Second World War.
The annexation of Austria in 1938 became the catalyst which prompted Popper to refocus his
writings on social and political philosophy. He published The Open Society and Its Enemies,
his critique of totalitarianism, in 1945. In 1946 he moved to England to teach at the London
School of Economics, and became professor of logic and scientific method at the University
of London in 1949. From this point on his reputation and stature as a philosopher of science
and social thinker grew, and he continued to write prolifically—a number of his works,
particularly The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959), are now widely seen as pioneering
classics in the field. However, he combined a combative personality with a zeal for self-
aggrandisement that did little to endear him to professional colleagues. He was ill-at-ease in
the philosophical milieu of post-war Britain which was, as he saw it, fixated with trivial
linguistic concerns dictated by Wittgenstein, whom he considered his nemesis. Popper’s
commitment to the primacy of rational criticism was counterpointed by hostility towards
anything that amounted to less than total acceptance of his own thought, and in Britain—as
had been the case in Vienna—he increasingly became an isolated figure, though his ideas
continued to inspire admiration.
In later years Popper came under philosophical criticism for his prescriptive approach to
science and his emphasis on the logic of falsification. This was superseded in the eyes of
many by the socio-historical approach taken by Thomas Kuhn in The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions (1962). In that work, Kuhn, who argued for the incommensurability of rival
scientific paradigms, denied that science grows linearly through the accumulation of truths.
Popper was knighted in 1965, and retired from the University of London in 1969, remaining
active as a writer, broadcaster and lecturer until his death in 1994. (For more detail on
Popper’s life, see his Unended Quest [1976]).
2. Backdrop to Popper’s Thought
A number of biographical features may be identified as having a particular influence upon
Popper’s thought. His teenage flirtation with Marxism left him thoroughly familiar with the
Marxian dialectical view of economics, class-war, and history. But he was appalled by the
failure of the democratic parties to stem the rising tide of fascism in Austria in the 1920s and
1930s, and the effective welcome extended to it by the Marxists, who regarded fascism as a
necessary dialectical step towards the implosion of capitalism and the ultimate victory of
communism. The Poverty of Historicism (1944; 1957) and The Open Society and Its
Enemies (1945), Popper’s most impassioned and influential social works, are powerful
defences of democratic liberalism, and strident critiques of philosophical presuppositions
underpinning all forms of totalitarianism.
Popper was also profoundly impressed by the differences between the allegedly “scientific”
theories of Freud and Adler and the revolution effected by Einstein’s theory of Relativity in
physics in the first two decades of the twentieth century. The main difference between them,
as Popper saw it, was that while Einstein’s theory was highly “risky”, in the sense that it was
possible to deduce consequences from it which were, in the light of the then dominant
Newtonian physics, highly improbable (e.g., that light is deflected towards solid bodies—
confirmed by Eddington’s experiments in 1919), and which would, if they turned out to be
false, falsify the whole theory, nothing could, even in principle, falsify psychoanalytic
theories. They were, Popper argues, “simply non-testable, irrefutable. There was no
conceivable human behaviour which could contradict them” (1963: 37). As such, they have
more in common with myths than with genuine science; “They contain most interesting
psychological suggestions, but not in a testable form” (1963: 38). What is apparently the
chief source of strength of psychoanalysis, he concluded, viz. its capability to accommodate
and explain every possible form of human behaviour, is in fact a critical weakness, for it
entails that it is not, and could not be, genuinely predictive. To those who would respond that
psychoanalytic theory is supported by clinical observations, Popper points out that
… real support can be obtained only from observations undertaken as tests (by ‘attempted
refutations’); and for this purpose criteria of refutation have to be laid down beforehand: it
must be agree which observable situations, if actually observed, mean that the theory is
refuted. (1963: 38, footnote 3)
Popper also considers that contemporary Marxism also lacks scientific status. Unlike
psychoanalysis, he argues, Marxism had been initially scientific, in that it was genuinely
predictive. However, when these predictions were not in fact borne out, the theory was saved
from falsification by the addition of ad hoc hypotheses which made it compatible with the
facts. By this means, Popper asserts, a theory which was initially genuinely scientific
degenerated into pseudo-scientific dogma. As he sees it, the Hegelian dialectic was adopted
by Marxists not to oppose dogmatism but to accommodate it to their cause by eliminating the
possibility of contradictory evidence. It has thus become what Popper terms “reinforced
dogmatism” (1963: 334).
These factors combined to make Popper take falsifiability as his criterion for demarcating
science from non-science: if a theory is incompatible with possible empirical observations it
is scientific; conversely, a theory which is compatible with all such observations, either
because, as in the case of Marxism, it has been modified solely to accommodate such
observations, or because, as in the case of psychoanalytic theories, it is consistent with all
possible observations, is unscientific. However, Popper is not a positivist and acknowledges
that unscientific theories may be enlightening and that even purely mythogenic explanations
have performed a valuable function in the past in expediting our understanding of the nature
of reality.

3. The Problem of Demarcation


For Popper the central problem in the philosophy of science is that of demarcation, i.e., of
distinguishing between science and what he terms “non-science” (e.g., logic, metaphysics,
psychoanalysis, and Adler’s individual psychology). Popper is unusual amongst
contemporary philosophers in that he accepts the validity of the Humean critique of
induction, and indeed, goes beyond it in arguing that induction is never actually used in
science. However, he does not concede that this entails scepticism and argues that the
Baconian/Newtonian insistence on the primacy of “pure” observation, as the initial step in
the formation of theories, is completely misguided: all observation is selective and theory-
laden and there are no pure or theory-free observations. In this way he destabilises the
traditional view that science can be distinguished from non-science on the basis of its
inductive methodology. In contradistinction to this, Popper holds that there is no unique
methodology specific to science; rather, science, like virtually every other organic activity,
consists largely of problem-solving.
Popper accordingly rejects the view that induction is the characteristic method of scientific
investigation and inference, substituting falsifiability in its place. It is easy, he argues, to
obtain evidence in favour of virtually any theory, and he consequently holds that such
“corroboration”, as he terms it, should count scientifically only if it is the positive result of a
genuinely “risky” prediction, which might conceivably have been false. In a critical sense,
Popper’s theory of demarcation is based upon his perception of the asymmetry which, at the
level of logic, holds between verification and falsification: it is logically impossible to verify
a universal proposition by reference to experience (as Hume saw clearly), but a single
genuine counter-instance falsifies the corresponding universal law. In a word, an exception,
far from “proving” a rule, conclusively refutes it.
Every genuine scientific theory then, in Popper’s view, is prohibitive, because the theories of
natural science take the form of universal statements. “All As are X” is equivalent to “No A is
not-X” which is falsified if “Some A is not-X” turns out to be true. For example, the law of
the conservation of energy can be expressed as “There is no perpetual motion machine”.
However, the universality of such laws, he argues, does rule out the possibility of their
verification. Thus, a theory that has withstood rigorous testing should be deemed to have
received a high measure of corroboration. and may be retained provisionally as the best
available theory until it is finally falsified and/or is superseded by a better theory.
Popper stresses in particular that there is no unique way, no single method such as induction,
which functions as the route to scientific theory, and approvingly cites Einstein on that point:
There is no logical path leading to [the highly universal laws of science]. They can only be
reached by intuition, based upon something like an intellectual love of the objects of
experience. (2002: 8–9)
Science, in Popper’s view, starts with problems rather than with observations—it is, indeed,
precisely in the context of grappling with a problem that the scientist makes observations in
the first instance: his observations are selectively designed to test the extent to which a given
theory functions as a satisfactory solution to a given problem.
On this criterion of demarcation physics, chemistry, and (non-introspective) psychology,
amongst others, are classified as sciences, psychoanalysis is a pre-science and astrology and
phrenology are pseudo-sciences.

4. Basic Statements, Falsifiability and Convention


Popper draws a clear distinction between the logic of falsifiability and its applied
methodology. The logic of his theory is utterly simple: a universal statement is falsified by a
single genuine counter-instance. Methodologically, however, the situation is complex:
decisions about whether to accept an apparently falsifying observation as an actual
falsification can be problematic, as observational bias and measurement error, for example,
can yield results which are only apparently incompatible with the theory under scrutiny.
Thus, while advocating falsifiability as the criterion of demarcation for science, Popper
explicitly allows for the fact that in practice a single conflicting or counter-instance is never
sufficient methodologically for falsification, and that scientific theories are often retained
even though much of the available evidence conflicts with them, or is anomalous with
respect to them.
In this connection, in the Logic of Scientific Discovery Popper introduces the technical
concept of a “basic statement” or “basic proposition”, which he defines as a statement which
can serve as a premise in an empirical falsification and which takes the singular existential
form “There is an X at Y”. Basic statements are important because they can
formally contradict universal statements, and accordingly play the role of potential falsifiers.
To take an example, the (putative) basic statement “In space-time region k there is an
apparatus which is a perpetual motion machine” contradicts the law of the conservation of
energy, and would, if true, falsify it (2002: 48). Accordingly, Popper holds that basic
statements are objective and are governed by two requirements: (a) the formal, that they must
be both singular and existential and (b) the material, that they must be intersubjectively
testable.
In essence, basic statements are for Popper logical constructs which embrace and include
‘observation statements’, but for methodological reasons he seeks to avoid that terminology,
as it suggests that they are derived directly from, and known by, experience (2002: 12,
footnote 2), which would conflate them with the “protocol” statements of logical positivism
and reintroduce the empiricist idea that certain kinds of experiential reports are incorrigible.
The “objectivity” requirement in Popper’s account of basic statements, by contrast, amounts
to a rejection of the view that the truth of scientific statements can ever be reduced to
individual or collective human experience. (2002: 25).
Popper therefore argues that there are no statements in science which cannot be interrogated:
basic statements, which are used to test the universal theories of science, must themselves be
inter-subjectively testable and are therefore open to the possibility of refutation. He
acknowledges that this seems to present a practical difficulty, in that it appears to suggest
that testability must occur ad infinitum, which he acknowledges is an operational absurdity:
sooner or later all testing must come to an end. Where testing ends, he argues, is in a
convention-based decision to accept a basic statement or statements; it is at that point that
convention and intersubjective human agreement play an indispensable role in science:
Every test of a theory, whether resulting in its corroboration or falsification, must stop at
some basic statement or other which we decide to accept. If we do not come to any decision,
and do not accept some basic statement or other, then the test will have led nowhere. (2002:
86)
However, Popper contends that while such a decision is usually causally related to
perceptual experience, it is not and cannot be justified by such experience; basic statements
are experientially underdetermined.
Experiences can motivate a decision, and hence an acceptance or a rejection of a statement,
but a basic statement cannot be justified by them—no more than by thumping the table.
(2002: 87–88)
Statements can be justified only by other statements, and therefore testing comes to an end,
not in the establishment of a correlation between propositional content and observable
reality, as empiricism would hold, but by means of the conventional, inter-subjective
acceptance of the truth of certain basic statements by the research community.
The acceptance of basic statements is compared by Popper to trial by jury: the verdict of the
jury will be an agreement in accordance with the prevailing legal code and on the basis of the
evidence presented, and is analogous to the acceptance of a basic statement by the research
community:
By its decision, the jury accepts, by agreement, a statement about a factual occurrence—a
basic statement, as it were. (2002: 92)
The jury’s verdict is conventional in arising out of a procedure governed by clear rules, and
is an application of the legal system as a whole as it applies to the case in question. The
verdict is accordingly represented as a true statement of fact, but, as miscarriages of justice
demonstrate all too clearly,
the statement need not be true merely because the jury has accepted it. This … is
acknowledged in the rule allowing a verdict to be quashed or revised. (2002: 92)
This is comparable, he argues, to the case of basic statements: their acceptance-as-true is also
by agreement and, as such, it also constitutes an application of a theoretical system, and
it is only this application which makes any further applications of the theoretical system
possible. (2002: 93)
However, the agreed acceptance of basic statements, like that of judicial verdicts, remain
perennially susceptible to the requirement for further interrogation. Popper terms this “the
relativity of basic statements” (2002: 86), which is reflective of the provisional nature of the
entire corpus of scientific knowledge itself. Science does not, he maintains, rest upon any
foundational bedrock. Rather, the theoretical systems of science are akin to buildings in
swampy ground constructed with the support of piles:
The piles are driven down from above into the swamp, but not down to any natural or
“given” base; and if we stop driving the piles deeper, it is not because we have reached firm
ground. We simply stop when we are satisfied that the piles are firm enough to carry the
structure, at least for the time being. (2002: 94)

5. The Growth of Human Knowledge


For Popper, the growth of human knowledge proceeds from our problems and from our
attempts to solve them. These attempts involve the formulation of theories which must go
beyond existing knowledge and therefore require a leap of the imagination. For this reason,
he places special emphasis on the role played by the creative imagination in theory
formulation. The priority of problems in Popper’s account of science is paramount, and it is
this which leads him to characterise scientists as “problem-solvers”. Further, since the
scientist begins with problems rather than with observations or “bare facts”, he argues that
the only logical technique which is an integral part of scientific method is that of the
deductive testing of theories which are not themselves the product of any logical operation.
In this deductive procedure conclusions are inferred from a tentative hypothesis and are then
compared with one another and with other relevant statements to determine whether they
falsify or corroborate the hypothesis. Such conclusions are not directly compared with the
facts, Popper stresses, simply because there are no “pure” facts available; all observation-
statements are theory-laden, and are as much a function of purely subjective factors
(interests, expectations, wishes, etc.) as they are a function of what is objectively real.
How then does the deductive procedure work? Popper specifies four steps (2002: 9):

a. The first is formal, a testing of the internal


consistency of the theoretical system to see if it
involves any contradictions.
b. The second step is semi-formal, “the investigation
of the logical form of the theory, with the object of
determining whether it has the character of an
empirical or scientific theory, or whether it is, for
example, tautological” (2002: 9).
c. The third step is the comparing of the new theory
with existing ones to determine whether it
constitutes an advance upon them. If its
explanatory success matches that of the existing
theories, and it additionally explains some hitherto
anomalous phenomenon or solves some hitherto
unsolvable problems, it will be adopted as
constituting an advance upon the existing theories.
In that sense, science involves theoretical
progress: on this account, a theory X is better than
a “rival” theory Y if X has greater empirical
content, and hence greater predictive power,
than Y.
d. The fourth and final step is the testing of a theory
by the empirical application of the conclusions
derived from it. If such conclusions are shown to
be true, the theory is corroborated (but never
verified). If the conclusion is shown to be false,
then this is taken as a signal that the theory cannot
be completely correct (logically the theory is
falsified), and the scientist begins his quest for a
better theory. He does not, however, abandon the
present theory until such time as he has a better
one to substitute for it.
The general picture of Popper’s philosophy of science, then is this: Hume’s philosophy
demonstrates that there is a contradiction implicit in traditional empiricism, which holds that
universal scientific laws are in some way finally confirmable by experience, despite the
open-ended nature of the latter being acknowledged. Popper eliminates the contradiction by
removing the demand for empirical verification in favour of empirical falsification or
corroboration. Scientific theories, for him, are not inductively inferred from experience, nor
is scientific experimentation carried out with a view to verifying or finally establishing the
truth of theories; rather, all knowledge is provisional, conjectural, hypothetical—the
universal theories of science can never be conclusively established. Hence Popper’s
emphasis on the importance of the critical spirit to science—for him critical thinking is the
very essence of rationality. For it is only by critical thought that we can eliminate false
theories and determine which of the remaining theories is the best available one, in the sense
of possessing the highest level of explanatory force and predictive power.

6. Probability, Knowledge and Verisimilitude


In the view of many social scientists, the more probable a theory is, the better it is, and if we
have to choose between two theories which differ only in that one is probable and the other is
improbable, then we should choose the former. Popper rejects this. Science values theories
with a high informative content, because they possess a high predictive power and are
consequently highly testable. For that reason, the more improbable a theory is the better it is
scientifically, because the probability and informative content of a theory vary inversely—
the higher the informative content of a theory the lower will be its probability. Thus, the
statements which are of special interest to science are those with a high informative content
and (consequentially) a low probability, which nevertheless come close to the truth.
Informative content, which is in inverse proportion to probability, is in direct proportion to
testability. As a result, the severity of the test to which a theory can be subjected, and by
means of which it is falsified or corroborated, is of fundamental importance.
Popper also argues that all scientific criticism must be piecemeal, i.e., he holds that it is not
possible to question every aspect of a theory at once, as certain items of what he terms
“background knowledge” must be taken for granted. But that is not knowledge in the sense
of being conclusively established; it may be challenged at any time, especially if it is
suspected that its uncritical acceptance may be responsible for difficulties which are
subsequently encountered.
How then can one be certain that one is questioning the right thing? The Popperian answer is
that we cannot have absolute certainty here, but repeated tests usually show where the
trouble lies. As we saw, for Popper even observation statements are corrigible and open to
review, and science in his view is not a quest for certain knowledge, but an evolutionary
process in which hypotheses or conjectures are imaginatively proposed and tested in order to
explain facts or to solve problems. For that reason, he emphasises both the importance of
questioning the background knowledge when the need arises, and the significance of the fact
that observation-statements are theory-laden and corrigible.
Popper was initially uneasy with the concept of truth, and in his earliest writings he avoided
asserting that a theory which is corroborated is true—for clearly if every theory is an open-
ended hypothesis, then ipso facto it has to be at least potentially false. However, he came to
accept Tarski’s reformulation of the correspondence theory of truth, and in Conjectures and
Refutations (1963) he integrates the concepts of truth and content to frame the metalogical
concept of “truthlikeness” or “verisimilitude”. A “good” scientific theory, Popper argues in
that work, has a higher level of verisimilitude than its rivals, and he explicates this concept
by reference to the logical consequences of theories. A theory’s content is the totality of its
logical consequences, which can be divided into two classes:

a. the “truth-content”, which is the class of true


propositions which may be derived from it, and
b. the “falsity-content” of a theory, which is the class
of the theory’s false consequences (which may be
empty, and in the case of a theory which is true is
necessarily empty).
Popper offers two accounts of how rival theories can be compared in terms of their levels of
verisimilitude; these are the qualitative and quantitative definitions. On the qualitative
account, verisimilitude is defined in terms of subclass relationships: a theory t2𝑡2 has a
higher level of verisimilitude than t1𝑡1 if and only if their truth- and falsity-contents are
comparable through subclass relationships, and either

a. t2𝑡2’s truth-content includes t1𝑡1’s and t2𝑡2’s


falsity-content, if it exists, is included in, or is the
same as, t1𝑡1’s, or
b. t2𝑡2’s truth-content includes or is the same
as t1𝑡1’s and t2𝑡2’s falsity-content, if it exists, is
included in t1𝑡1’s.
On the quantitative account, verisimilitude is defined by assigning quantities to contents,
where the index of the content of a given theory is its logical improbability, given again that
content and probability vary inversely (1963: 233–4). The utilisation of either method of
computing verisimilitude shows, Popper argues, that even if a theory t2𝑡2 with a higher
content than a rival theory t1𝑡1 is subsequently falsified, it can still legitimately be regarded
as a better theory than t1𝑡1, and “better” is here now understood to mean t2𝑡2 is closer to the
truth than t1𝑡1 (1963: 235).
Thus, scientific progress involves, on this view, the abandonment of partially true, but
falsified, theories, for theories with a higher level of verisimilitude, i.e., which approach
more closely to the truth. In this way, verisimilitude allowed Popper to mitigate what some
saw as the pessimism of an anti-inductivist philosophy of science. With the introduction of
the concept, Popper was able to represent his account as an essentially realistic position in
terms of which scientific progress can be seen as progress towards the truth, and
experimental corroboration can be viewed as an indicator of verisimilitude.
However, subsequent research revealed defects in Popper’s formal definitions of
verisimilitude. The concept is most important in his system because of its application to
theories which are approximations (which are common in the social sciences) and thus
known to be false. In this connection, Popper had written:
Ultimately, the idea of verisimilitude is most important in cases where we know that we have
to work with theories which are at best approximations—that is to say, theories of which we
know that they cannot be true… In these cases we can still speak of better or worse
approximations to the truth (and we therefore do not need to interpret these cases in an
instrumentalist sense). (1963: 235)
In 1974, David Miller and Pavel Tichý, working independently, demonstrated that the
conditions specified by Popper in his accounts of both qualitative and quantitative
verisimilitude for comparing the truth- and falsity-contents of theories can be satisfied only
when the theories are true. In the crucially important case of false theories, Popper’s
definitions are formally defective: for with regard to a false theory t2𝑡2 which has excess
content over a rival theory t1𝑡1, both the truth-content and the falsity-content of t2𝑡2 will
exceed that of t1𝑡1. With respect to theories which are false then, Popper’s conditions for
comparing levels of verisimilitude, whether in quantitative and qualitative terms, can never
be met.
Popper’s response was two-fold. In the first place, he acknowledges the deficiencies in his
own formal account:
“…my main mistake was the failure to see at once that my ’A Theorem on Truth-Content’
[1966], could be extended to falsity content: if the content of a false statement a exceeds that
of a statement b, then the truth content of a exceeds the truth content of b, and the same holds
of their falsity contents.” (1979, 371)
But he argues that
“I do think that we should not conclude from the failure of my attempts to solve the problem
that the problem cannot be solved. Perhaps it cannot be solved by purely logical means but
only by a relativization to relevant problems or even by bringing in the historical problem
situation” (1979, 372).
This suggestion was to precipitate a great deal of important technical research in the field. He
additionally moves the task of formally defining the concept from centre-stage in his
philosophy of science by protesting that he had never intended to imply
that degrees of verisimilitude … can ever be numerically determined, except in certain
limiting cases. (1979: 59)
Instead, he argues, the chief value of the concept is heuristic, in which the absence of an
adequate formal definition is not an insuperable impediment to its utilisation in the actual
appraisal of theories relativised to problems in which we have an interest.
Many see the thrust of this latter strategy as genuinely reflecting the significance of the
concept of verisimilitude in Popper’s system, but it has not satisfied all of his critics.

7. Objective Knowledge and The Three Worlds


Ontology
Popper’s hostility to psychologistic approaches to epistemology is evident from his earliest
works. Questions relating to the origins of convictions, feelings of certainty and the like, he
argues, are properly considered the province of psychology; their attempted use in
epistemology, which has been characteristic in particular of some schools of empiricism, can
lead only to confusion and ultimately to scepticism. Against it, he repeatedly insists on the
objectivity of scientific knowledge and sees it as the principal task of epistemology to engage
with the questions of justification and validity in that connection (2002: 7).
In some of his later works in the field, particularly his “Epistemology Without a Knowing
Subject” (1967, republished in Objective Knowledge [1972]) and in his lecture “Three
Worlds” in the Tanner Lectures on Human Values delivered in 1978 (published 1980),
Popper develops the notion of objectivity further in a novel but controversial way by seeking
to free it completely from all psychological constraints. What is central to epistemology, he
reaffirms, is the concept of objectivity, which he seeks to show requires neither the notions
of subjective mental states nor even that of a subject “possessing” knowledge: knowledge in
its full objective sense, he argues, is knowledge “without a knowing subject”.
Popper’s angle of approach here is to situate the development of knowledge in the context of
animal and human evolution. It is characteristic of evolutionary processes, he points out, that
they come to take place in an environment which is itself in part fashioned by the species in
question. Examples of this abound, such as the reefs built by corals, the hives built by bees,
the dams built by beavers and the atmospheric effects yielded by plants. This, Popper
contends, is also true of human beings: we too have created new kinds of products,
“intellectual products”, which shape our environment. These are our myths, our ideas, our art
works and our scientific theories about the world in which we live. When placed in an
evolutionary context, he suggests, such products must be viewed instrumentally, as
exosomatic artefacts. Chief amongst them is knowledge
in the objective or impersonal sense, in which it may be said to be contained in a book; or
stored in a library; or taught in a university. (1979: 286)
On this view, termed “evolutionary epistemology”, the growth of human knowledge is an
objective evolutionary process which involves the creation and promulgation of new
problem-solving theories, which are then subjected to the challenge of criticism,
modification, elimination and replacement. These latter activities are seen by Popper as
growth-promoting in the evolution of knowledge, which he represents by means of a tetradic
schema (1979: 287):
P1→TT→EE→P2.𝑃1→TT→EE→𝑃2.
Here “P1𝑃1” stands for the “initial problem”; “TT” stands for “tentative theory” designed to
solve it, “EE” stands for “attempts at error-elimination”, and “P2𝑃2” represents further
problems that arise out of the critical process.
This kind of knowledge development, Popper argues, cannot be explained either by
physicalism, which seeks to reduce all mental processes and states to material ones, or by
dualism, which usually seeks to explicate knowledge by means of psychological categories
such as thought, perception and belief. Consequently, he proposes a novel form of pluralistic
realism, a “Three Worlds” ontology, which, while accommodating both the world of physical
states and processes (world 1) and the mental world of psychological processes (world 2),
represents knowledge in its objective sense as belonging to world 3, a third, objectively real
ontological category. That world is the world
of the products of the human mind, such as languages; tales and stories and religious myths;
scientific conjectures or theories, and mathematical constructions; songs and symphonies;
paintings and sculptures. (1980: 144)
In short, world 3 is the world of human cultural artifacts, which are products of world 2
mental processes, usually instantiated in the physical world 1 environment.
Popper proceeds to explicate his distinction between the subjective and objective senses of
knowledge by reference to this ontology. The subjective sense of knowledge relates to
psychological processes and states, mental dispositions, beliefs and expectations, which may
generically be termed “thought processes” and which belong to world 2. Knowledge in the
objective sense, by contrast, consists not of thought processes but of thought contents, that is
to say, the content of propositionalised theories: it is
the content which can be, at least approximately, translated from one language into another.
The objective thought content is that which remains invariant in a reasonably good
translation. (1980: 156)
And it is that thought content, when linguistically codified in texts, works of art, log tables,
mathematical formulae, which constitutes world 3, to which objective knowledge relates.
For those who would suggest that such objects are mere abstractions from world 2 thought
processes, Popper counters that world 3 objects are necessarily more than the thought
processes which have led to their creation. Theories, for example, usually have logical
implications beyond anything considered by their original author, as instanced in the case of
Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity. Moreover, what is most characteristic about such
objects is that, unlike world 2 mental processes, they can stand in logical relationships to
each other, such as equivalence, deducibility and compatibility, which makes them amenable
to the kind of critical rational analysis and development that is one of the hallmarks of
science. As he puts it,
Criticism of world 3 objects is of the greatest importance, both in art and especially in
science. Science can be said to be largely the result of the critical examination and selection
of conjectures, of thought contents. (1980: 160)
Popper takes Michelangelo’s sculpture The Dying Slave as an illustrative example of a world
3 object, embodied in a world 1 block of marble. Other examples given include memory
engrams in the brain, the American Constitution, Shakespeare’s tragedies, Beethoven’s Fifth
Symphony and Newton’s theory of gravitation. Each one of these, he contends, is a world 3
object that transcends both its physical, world 1 embodiments and its world 2 cognitive
origins (1980: 145).
Popper was aware that he would be accused of hypostatising abstractions in asserting the
reality and objectivity of world 3 objects. In response, he indicates strongly that he has no
interest in what he regards as pointless terminological disputes over the meaning of the term
“world” or “real”. He is therefore content, if required, to express his account of objective
knowledge in more familiar and perhaps more mundane terms: world 3 objects
are abstract objects while their physical embodiments are concrete objects. But that should
not be allowed to disguise the fact that he saw the relationships between the three categories
of his ontology as of enormous importance in understanding the role of science as an element
of culture:
my thesis is that our world 3 theories and our world 3 plans causally influence the physical
objects of world 1; that they have a causal action upon world 1. (1980: 164)
In the final analysis it is the causal interaction between the worlds that ultimately matters in
Popper’s objectivist epistemology: it allows him to represent the growth of human
knowledge as an evolutionary process of exosomatic adaptations, which is ultimately a
function of the interplay of relations between the physical and mental worlds and the world
of objective knowledge or thought content.
8. Social and Political Thought—The Critique of
Historicism and Holism
Given Popper’s personal history and background, it is hardly surprising that he developed a
deep and abiding interest in social and political philosophy. He understood holism as the
view that human social groupings are greater than the sum of their members, that they act on
their human members and shape their destinies and that they are subject to their own
independent laws of development. Historicism he identified as the belief that history
develops inexorably and necessarily according to certain principles or rules towards a
determinate end (as for example in the Marx’s dialectical materialism). The link between
them is that holism holds that individuals are essentially formed by the social groupings to
which they belong, while historicism suggests that we can understand such a social grouping
only in terms of the internal principles which determine its development.
These lead to what Popper calls “The Historicist Doctrine of the Social Sciences”, the views
(a) that the principal task of the social sciences is to make predictions about the social and
political development of man, and (b) that the task of politics, once the key predictions have
been made, is, in Marx’s words, to lessen the “birth pangs” of future social and political
developments. Popper thinks that this view of the social sciences is both theoretically
misconceived and socially dangerous, as it can give rise to totalitarianism and
authoritarianism—to centralised governmental control of the individual and the attempted
imposition of large-scale social planning. Against this, he advances the view that any human
social grouping is no more (or less) than the sum of its individual members, that what
happens in history is the (largely unforeseeable) result of the actions of such individuals, and
that large scale social planning to an antecedently conceived blueprint is inherently
misconceived—and inevitably disastrous—precisely because human actions have
consequences which cannot be foreseen. Popper, then, is an historical indeterminist, insofar
as he holds that history does not evolve in accordance with intrinsic laws or principles, that
in the absence of such laws and principles unconditional prediction in the social sciences is
an impossibility, and that there is no such thing as historical necessity.
The link between Popper’s theory of knowledge and his social philosophy is his fallibilism.
We make theoretical progress in science by subjecting our theories to critical scrutiny, and
abandoning those which have been falsified. So too in an open society the rights of the
individual to criticise administrative policies will be safeguarded and upheld, undesirable
policies will be eliminated in a manner analogous to the elimination of falsified scientific
theories, and political differences will be resolved by critical discussion and argument rather
than by coercion. The open society as thus conceived of by Popper may be defined as
an association of free individuals respecting each other’s rights within the framework of
mutual protection supplied by the state, and achieving, through the making of responsible,
rational decisions, a growing measure of humane and enlightened life. (R. B. Levinson 1953:
17)
Such as society is not a utopian ideal, Popper argues, but an empirically realised form of
social organisation which is in every respect superior to its (real or potential) totalitarian
rivals. His strategy, however, is not merely to engage in a moral defence of the ideology of
liberalism, but rather to show that totalitarianism is typically based upon historicist and holist
presuppositions, and of demonstrating that these presuppositions are fundamentally
incoherent.

9. Scientific Knowledge, History, and Prediction


Historicism and holism, Popper argues, have their origins in what he terms
one of the oldest dreams of mankind—the dream of prophecy, the idea that we can know
what the future has in store for us, and that we can profit from such knowledge by adjusting
our policy to it. (1963: 338)
This dream was given impetus, he suggests, by the emergence of a genuine predictive
capability regarding solar and lunar eclipses at an early stage in human civilisation, which
became refined with the development of the natural sciences. Historicism derives a
superficial plausibility from the suggestion that, just as the application of the laws of the
natural sciences can lead to the prediction of such events as eclipses, knowledge of “the laws
of history” as yielded by a social science or sciences can and should lead to the prediction of
future social phenomena. Why should we not conceive of a social science which would
function as the theoretical natural sciences function and yield precise unconditional
predictions in the appropriate sphere of application? Popper seeks to show that this idea is
based upon a series of misconceptions about the nature of science, and about the relationship
between scientific laws and scientific prediction.
In relation to the critically important concept of prediction, Popper makes a distinction
between what he terms “conditional scientific predictions”, which have the form “If X takes
place, then Y will take place”, and “unconditional scientific prophecies”, which have the
form “Y will take place”. Contrary to popular belief, it is the former rather than the latter
which are typical of the natural sciences, which means that typically prediction in natural
science is conditional and limited in scope—it takes the form of hypothetical assertions
stating that certain specified changes will come about if and only if particular specified
events antecedently take place. This is not to deny that “unconditional scientific prophecies”,
such as the prediction of eclipses, for example, do take place in science, and that the
theoretical natural sciences make them possible. However, Popper argues that (a) these
unconditional prophecies are not characteristic of the natural sciences, and (b) that the
mechanism whereby they occur, in the very limited way in which they do, is not understood
by the historicist.
What is the mechanism which makes “unconditional scientific prophecies” possible?
Popper’s answer is that they are possible because they are derived from a combination of
conditional predictions (themselves derived from scientific laws) and existential statements
specifying that the conditions in relation to the system being investigated are fulfilled.
Given that this is the mechanism which generates unconditional scientific prophecies, Popper
makes two related claims about historicism:
The first is that the historicist does not, as a matter of fact, derive his historical prophecies
from conditional scientific predictions. The second … is that he cannot possibly do so
because long term prophecies can be derived from scientific conditional predictions only if
they apply to systems which can be described as well isolated, stationary, and recurrent.
These systems are very rare in nature; and modern society is surely not one of them. (1963:
339)
Popper accordingly argues that it is a fundamental mistake for the historicist to take the
unconditional scientific prophecies of eclipses as being typical and characteristic of the
predictions of natural science; they are possible only because our solar system is a stationary
and repetitive system which is isolated from other such systems by immense expanses of
empty space. Human society and human history are not isolated systems and are continually
undergoing rapid, non-repetitive development. In the most fundamental sense possible, every
event in human history is discrete, novel, quite unique, and ontologically distinct from every
other historical event. For this reason, it is impossible in principle that unconditional
scientific prophecies could be made in relation to human history—the idea that the successful
unconditional prediction of eclipses provides us with reasonable grounds for the hope of
successful unconditional prediction regarding the evolution of human history turns out to be
based upon a gross misconception. As Popper succinctly concludes, “The fact that we predict
eclipses does not, therefore, provide a valid reason for expecting that we can predict
revolutions” (1963: 340).

10. Immutable Laws and Contingent Trends


An additional mistake which Popper discerns in historicism is the failure of the historicist to
distinguish between scientific laws and trends. This makes him think it possible to explain
change by discovering trends running through past history, and to anticipate and predict
future occurrences on the basis of such observations. Here Popper points out that there is a
critical difference between a trend and a scientific law: the latter is universal in form, while a
trend can be expressed only as a singular existential statement. This logical difference is
crucial: neither conditional nor unconditional predictions can be based upon trends, because
trends may change or be reversed with a change in the conditions which gave rise to them in
the first instance. As Popper puts it, there can be no doubt that
the habit of confusing trends with laws, together with the intuitive observation of trends such
as technical progress, inspired the central doctrines of … historicism. (1957: 106)
He does not, of course, dispute the existence of trends or deny that observing them can be of
practical utility value. But the essential point is that a trend is something
which itself ultimately stands in need of scientific explanation, and it cannot therefore
function as the frame of reference in terms of which an unconditional prediction can be
based.
A point which connects with this has to do with the role which the evolution of human
knowledge has played in the historical development of human society. Human history has,
Popper points out, been strongly influenced by the growth of human knowledge, and it is
extremely likely that this will continue to be the case—all the empirical evidence suggests
that the link between the two is progressively consolidating. However, this gives rise to a
further problem for the historicist: no scientific predictor, human or otherwise, can possibly
predict its own future results. From this it follows, he holds, that no society can predict,
scientifically, its own future states of knowledge. Thus, while the future evolution of human
history is extremely likely to be influenced by new developments in human knowledge, we
cannot now scientifically determine what such knowledge will be.
From this it follows that if the future holds any new discoveries or any new developments in
the growth of our knowledge, then it is impossible for us to predict them now, and it is
therefore impossible for us to predict the future development of human history now, given
that the latter will, at least in part, be determined by the future growth of our knowledge.
Thus, once again historicism collapses—the dream of a theoretical, predictive science of
history is unrealisable, because it is an impossible dream.
Popper’s argues against the propriety of large-scale planning of social structures on the basis
of this demonstration of the logical shortcomings of historicism. It is, he argues, theoretically
as well as practically misguided, because, again, part of what we are planning for is our
future knowledge, and our future knowledge is not something which we can in principle now
possess—we cannot adequately plan for unexpected advances in our future knowledge, or for
the effects which such advances will have upon society as a whole. For him, this necessitates
the acceptance of historical indeterminism as the only philosophy of history which is
commensurate with a proper understanding of the provisional and incomplete nature of
human knowledge.
This critique of historicism and holism is balanced, on the positive side, by Popper’s
affirmation of the ideals of individualism and market economics and his strong defence of
the open society—the view that a society is equivalent to the sum of its members, that the
actions of the members of society serve to fashion and to shape it, and that the social
consequences of intentional actions are very often, and very largely, unintentional. This part
of his social philosophy was influenced by the economist Friedrich Hayek, who worked with
him at the London School of Economics and who was a life-long friend. Popper advocates
what he (rather unfortunately) terms “piecemeal social engineering” as the central
mechanism for social planning: in utilising this mechanism, intentional actions are directed
to the achievement of one specific goal at a time, which makes it possible to determine
whether adverse unintended effects of intentional actions occur, in order to correct and
readjust when this proves necessary. This, of course, parallels precisely the critical testing of
theories in scientific investigation. This approach to social planning (which is explicitly
based upon the premise that we do not, because we cannot, know what the future will be
like) encourages attempts to put right what is problematic in society—generally-
acknowledged social ills—rather than attempts to impose some preconceived idea of the
“good” upon society as a whole. For Popper, in a genuinely open society piecemeal social
engineering goes hand-in-hand with negative utilitarianism, the attempt to minimise the
amount of suffering and misery, rather than, as with positive utilitarianism, the attempt to
maximise the amount of happiness. The state, he holds, should concern itself with the task of
progressively formulating and implementing policies designed to deal with the social
problems which actually confront it, with the goal of mitigating human misery and suffering
to the greatest possible degree. The positive task of increasing social and personal happiness,
by contrast, can and should be left to individual citizens, who may, of course, act collectively
to that end. “My thesis”, Popper states, is that
human misery is the most urgent problem of a rational public policy and that happiness is not
such a problem. The attainment of happiness should be left to our private endeavours. (1963:
361)
Thus, for Popper, in the final analysis the activity of problem-solving is as definitive of our
humanity at the level of social and political organisation as it is at the level of science, and it
is this key insight which unifies and integrates the broad spectrum of his thought.

11. Critical Evaluation


While it cannot be said that Popper was modest, he took criticism of his theories very
seriously, and spent much of his time in his later years in addressing them. The following is a
summary of some of the main ones which he had to address. (For Popper’s responses to
critical commentary, see his “Replies to My Critics” (1974) and his Realism and the Aim of
Science (1983).
First, Popper claims to be a realist and rejects conventionalist and instrumentalist accounts of
science. But his account in the Logic of Scientific Discovery of the role played by basic
statements in the methodology of falsification seems to sit uneasily with that. As we have
seen, he follows Kant in rejecting the positivist/empiricist view that observation statements
are incorrigible, and argues that they are descriptions of what is observed as interpreted by
the observer with reference to a determinate conceptual and theoretical framework. He
accordingly asserts that while basic statements may have a causal relationship to experience,
they are neither determined nor justified by it.
However, this would seem to pose a difficulty: if a theory is to be genuinely testable, it must
be possible to determine, at least in principle, whether the basic statements which are its
potential falsifiers are actually true or false. But how can this be known, if basic statements
cannot be justified by experience? As we have seen, Popper’s answer is that the acceptance
or rejection of basic statements depends upon a convention-based decision on the part of the
scientific community.
From a logical point of view, the testing of a theory depends upon basic statements whose
acceptance or rejection, in its turn, depends upon our decisions. Thus it is decisions which
settle the fate of theories. (2002: 91)
Traditional conventionalism, as exemplified in the work of Mach, Poincaré and Milhaud
amongst others, holds that a “successful” science is one in which universal theories have
assumed such explanatory critical mass that a convention emerges to pre-empt the possibility
of their empirical refutation. This is strongly rejected by Popper, who differentiates his
position from it by arguing that it is the acceptance of basic statements, rather than that
universal theory, which is determined by convention and intersubjective agreement. For him,
the acceptance or rejection of theory occurs only indirectly and at a higher investigative
level, through critical tests made possible by the conventional acceptance of basic
statements. As he puts it, “I differ from the conventionalist in holding that the statements
decided by agreement are not universal but singular” (2002: 92). Simultaneously, however,
he rejects any suggestion that basic statements are justifiable by direct experience:
I differ from the positivist in holding that basic statements are not justifiable by our
immediate experiences, but are, from the logical point of view, accepted by an act, by a free
decision. (2002: 92)
It is thus evident that Popper saw his account of basic statements as steering a course
between the Scylla of orthodox conventionalism and the Charybdis of positivism/empiricism.
However, while it is both coherent and consistent in that regard, there can be little doubt but
that it constitutes a form of conventionalism in its own right. And it is not clear that it is
compatible with scientific realism, understood as the view that scientific theories give true or
approximately true descriptions of elements of a mind-independent world. As Lakatos puts
it,
If a theory is falsified, it is proven false; if it is “falsified” [in Popper’s conventionalist
sense], it may still be true. If we follow up this sort of “falsification” by the actual
“elimination” of a theory, we may well end up by eliminating a true, and accepting a false,
theory. (Lakatos 1978: 24)
Second, Popper’s theory of demarcation hinges quite fundamentally on the assumption that
there are such things as critical tests, which either falsify a theory, or give it a strong measure
of corroboration. Popper himself is fond of citing, as an example of such a critical test, the
resolution, by Adams and Leverrier, of the problem which the anomalous orbit of Uranus
posed for nineteenth century astronomers. They independently came to the conclusion that,
assuming Newtonian mechanics to be precisely correct, the observed divergence in the
elliptical orbit of Uranus could be explained if the existence of a seventh, as yet unobserved
outer planet was posited. Further, they were able, again within the framework of Newtonian
mechanics, to calculate the precise position of the “new” planet. Thus when subsequent
research by Galle at the Berlin observatory revealed that such a planet (Neptune) did in fact
exist, and was situated precisely where Adams and Leverrier had calculated, this was hailed
as by all and sundry as a magnificent triumph for Newtonian physics: in Popperian terms,
Newton’s theory had been subjected to a critical test, and had passed with flying colours.
Yet Lakatos flatly denies that there are critical tests, in the Popperian sense, in science, and
argues the point convincingly by turning the above example of an alleged critical test on its
head. What, he asks, would have happened if Galle had not found the planet Neptune?
Would Newtonian physics have been abandoned, or would Newton’s theory have been
falsified? The answer is clearly not, for Galle’s failure could have been attributed to any
number of causes other than the falsity of Newtonian physics (e.g., the interference of the
earth’s atmosphere with the telescope, the existence of an asteroid belt which hides the new
planet from the earth, etc). The suggestion is that the “falsification/corroboration” disjunction
offered by Popper is unjustifiable binary: non-corroboration is not necessarily falsification,
and falsification of a high-level scientific theory is never brought about by an isolated
observation or set of observations. Such theories are, it is now widely accepted, highly
resistant to falsification; they are “tenaciously protected from refutation by a vast ‘protective
belt’ of auxiliary hypotheses” (Lakatos 1978: 4) and so are falsified, if at all, not by
Popperian critical tests, but rather within the elaborate context of the research programmes
associated with them gradually grinding to a halt. Popper’s distinction between the logic of
falsifiability and its applied methodology does not in the end do full justice to the fact that all
high-level theories grow and live despite the existence of anomalies (i.e., events/phenomena
which are incompatible with them). These, Lakatos suggests, are not usually taken by the
working scientist as an indication that the theory in question is false. On the contrary, in the
context of a progressive research programme he or she will necessarily assume that the
auxiliary hypotheses which are associated with the theory can in time be modified to
incorporate, and thereby explain, recalcitrant phenomena.
Third, Popper’s critique of Marxism has not, of course, gone unchallenged. The debate
arising from, however, has in many cases tended to revolve around ideological rather than
philosophical issues, which will be passed over here. However, there have also been some
trenchant philosophical responses. Cornforth sees Marxism as a rational scientific discipline
and Marxian thinking as “a rational and scientific approach to social problems” (Cornforth
1968: 6) of the kind which both Marx and Popper consider important. Consequently, he takes
Popper to task for representing Marxism as a system of dogmas designed to close minds or
pre-empt the operation of our rational faculties in addressing social issues. Against that view,
he argues that it constitutes a way of thinking designed to open minds to the real possibilities
of human life, and sees it as the philosophy best calculated to promote the ideals of the open
society to which he, like Popper, subscribes. Hudelson (1980) argues that Marxian
economics survives the Popperian critique of historicism and that, in any case, Marx did not
hold many of the tenets of historicism identified by Popper. He also contends that Popper
fails to show that there cannot be, and that we cannot know, laws of social development and
that Marx did not in fact confuse trends and laws in the way that Popper suggests.
Fourth, In the case of Freudian psychoanalysis, the adequacy of Popper’s critique has been
challenged on philosophical grounds by a number of commentators, particularly Adolf
Grünbaum (1984). Grünbaum is highly critical, indeed scornful, of Popper’s dismissal of the
claims of psychoanalysis to be scientific and argues that Freud showed “a keen appreciation
of methodological pitfalls that are commonly laid at his door by critics” (Grünbaum 1984:
168) such as Popper. He argues that Freud was sensitive to the question of the logic of the
confirmation and disconfirmation of psychoanalytic interpretations and cites Freud’s use of
the concept of consilience, the convergence of evidence from disparate sources, as a serious
and explicit attempt to meet the requirements of that logic. For Grünbaum, Popper’s critique
of Freud amounts a veritable parody of the pioneering thinker who established the discipline
of psychoanalysis, and he attributes that to Popper’s “obliviousness to Freud’s actual
writings” (1984: 124). He points out, for example, that the case of the drowning child which
Popper uses in Conjectures and Refutations (Popper 1963: 35), upon which he rests part of
his case against psychoanalysis, is contrived and not in any way derived from Freud’s actual
clinical texts.
Grünbaum contends that there are instances in Freud’s writings where he shows himself to
be “a sophisticated scientific methodologist” (Grünbaum 1984: 128), keenly aware of the
need for his theoretical system to meet the requirement of testability. One such occurs when
Freud, in his assessment that anxiety neuroses are due to disturbances in sexual life,
explicitly refers to the notion of falsifiability: “My theory can only be refuted when I have
been shown phobias where sexual life is normal” (Freud 1895 [1962: 134]). Another occurs
in Freud’s 1915 paper “A Case of Paranoia Running Counter to the Psycho-Analytic Theory
of the Disease”, in which, as the title suggests, he saw the patient’s collection of symptoms
as potentially falsifying the theory. Moreover, Freud’s entire account of paranoia as being
due to an underlying repressed homosexuality is open to empirical refutation, Grünbaum
argues, since it has the testable implication that a reduction in rates of paranoia should result
from a removal or loosening of social sanctions against same-sex relationships (1984: 111).
Grünbaum accordingly holds that Freudian theory should be considered falsifiable and
therefore genuinely scientific—albeit, in his view, ultimately unsuccessful, because the
clinical evidence offered in its favour is contaminated by suggestion on the part of the
analyst and cannot therefore support its conceptual weight. That is a verdict very different to
what Grünbaum sees as the reductive dismissal of Freud offered by Popper: “the inability of
certain philosophers of science to have discerned any testable consequences of Freud’s
theory”, he concludes, “betokens their insufficient command or scrutiny of its logical content
rather than a scientific liability of psychoanalysis” (1984: 113).
There can be little doubt of the seriousness of this challenge to Popper’s critique of the
claims of psychoanalytic theory to scientific status. Further, the unparalleled cultural impact
of Freudianism upon contemporary life can scarcely be denied, and even a cursory
examination of the vast corpus of Freud’s works reveals a thinker of quite extraordinary
theoretical power and imagination whose claims to scientific validity cannot be dismissed
lightly.
However, while the detail of this psychoanalytic response to Popper is contestable, what is
perhaps most striking and important about it is that, as articulated by Grünbaum, it is itself
couched in broad terms of an acceptance of a Popperian account of science. That is to say, in
rejecting the claim that psychoanalysis fails to meet the standard of falsifiability specified by
Popper, Grünbaum—who also rejects the hermeneutic interpretation of Freud offered by
thinkers such as Paul Ricoeur and Jurgen Habermas—nonetheless implicitly accepts that
very standard, and with it the broad sweep of Popper’s theory of demarcation. For that reason
alone, it seems clear that Popper’s work will continue to function as a critical reference point
in the ongoing debate regarding the scientific status of Freudian thought.
Fifth, scientific laws are usually expressed by universal statements (i.e., they take the logical
form “All As are X”, or some equivalent) which are therefore concealed conditionals—they
have to be understood as hypothetical statements asserting what would be the case under
certain ideal conditions. In themselves they are not existential in nature. Thus “All As are X”
means “If anything is an A, then it is X”. Since scientific laws are non-existential in nature,
they logically cannot in themselves imply any basic statements, since the latter are explicitly
existential. The question arises, then, as to how any basic statement can falsify a scientific
law, given that basic statements are not deducible from scientific laws in themselves? Popper
answers that scientific laws are always taken in conjunction with statements outlining the
“initial conditions” of the system under investigation; these latter, which are singular
existential statements, yield hard and fast implications when combined with the scientific
law.
This reply is adequate only if it is true, as Popper assumes, that singular existential
statements will always do the work of bridging the gap between a universal theory and a
prediction. Hilary Putnam in particular has argued that this assumption is false, in that in
some cases at least the statements required to bridge this gap (which he calls “auxiliary
hypotheses”) are general rather than particular, and consequently that when the prediction
turns out to be false we have no way of knowing whether this is due to the falsity of the
scientific law or the falsity of the auxiliary hypotheses. The working scientist, Putnam argues
(Putnam 1974; see also the 1991 reprinting with its retrospective note), always initially
assumes that it is the latter, which shows not only that, but also why, scientific laws
are, contra Popper, highly resistant to falsification, as Kuhn (1962) and Lakatos (1970, 1978)
have also argued.
Popper’s final position is that he acknowledges that it is impossible to discriminate science
from non-science on the basis of the falsifiability of the scientific statements alone; he
recognises that scientific theories are predictive, and consequently prohibitive, only when
taken in conjunction with auxiliary hypotheses, and he also recognises that readjustment or
modification of the latter is an integral part of scientific practice. Hence his final concern is
to outline conditions which indicate when such modification is genuinely scientific, and
when it is merely ad hoc. This is itself clearly a major alteration in his position, and arguably
represents a substantial retraction on his part: Marxism can no longer be dismissed as
“unscientific” simply because its advocates preserved the theory from falsification by
modifying it—for in general terms, such a procedure, it transpires, is perfectly respectable
scientific practice. It is now condemned as unscientific by Popper because the only rationale
for the modifications which were made to the original theory was to ensure that it evaded
falsification, and so such modifications were ad hoc, rather than scientific. This contention—
though not at all implausible—has, to hostile eyes, a somewhat contrived air about it, and is
unlikely to worry the convinced Marxist. On the other hand, the shift in Popper’s own basic
position is taken by some critics as an indicator that falsificationism, for all its apparent
merits, fares no better in the final analysis than verificationism.

Bibliography
Primary Literature: Works by Popper
 1928, Zur Methodenfrage der Denkpsychologie,
Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Vienna,
unpublished.
 1935, Logik der Forschung, Vienna: Julius
Springer Verlag.
 1944–45, “The Poverty of
Historicism”, Economica, Part 1, 11(42): 86–103;
Part II, 11(43): 119–137; Part III, 12(46): 69–89.
doi:10.2307/2549642 doi:10.2307/2550285
doi:10.2307/2549898
 1945, The Open Society and Its Enemies, 2
volumes, London: Routledge. Republished 1966.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
 1957, The Poverty of Historicism, London:
Routledge. Revised version of Popper 1944–5.
 1959 [2002], The Logic of Scientific Discovery,
translation by the author of Logik der
Forschung (1935), London: Hutchinson.
Republished 2002, London & New York:
Routledge Classics.
 1963, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of
Scientific Knowledge, London: Routledge.
 1966, Of Clouds and Clocks: An Approach to the
Problem of Rationality and the Freedom of Man.
Washington, DC: Washington University Press.
 1967 [1972], “Epistemology Without a Knowing
Subject”, in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy
of Science III, B. Van Rootselaar and J. F. Staal
(eds.), (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of
Mathematics 52), Amsterdam: Elsevier, 333–373.
Reprinted in Popper 1972a: 106–152.
doi:10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71204-7
 1968 [1972], “On the Theory of the Objective
Mind”, Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses
für Philosophie, vol. i, Vienna, 25–53. Translated
and expanded in 1972a: 153–190.
 1970 [1972], “A Realist View of Logic, Physics,
and History”, in Physics, Logic and History, W.
Yougrau and A. D. Breck (eds), Plenum Press, 1–
30. Reprinted in Popper 1972a: 285–318.
 1972 [1979], Objective Knowledge: An
Evolutionary Approach, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
 1972b, “Two Faces of Common Sense: An
Argument for Commonsense Realism and Against
the commonsense Theory of Knowledge”, in
1972a: 32–105.
 1974, “Replies to My Critics”, in Schilpp 1974:
vol. 2, 961–1197.
 1976, Unended Quest; An Intellectual
Autobiography, London: Fontana.
 1976, “A Note on Verisimilitude”, The British
Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 27: 147–
159.
 1977, The Self and Its Brain: An Argument for
Interactionism, with John C. Eccles, London:
Springer International.
doi:10.4324/9780203537480
 1979 [2007], Die Beiden Grundprobleme der
Erkenntnistheorie, Tübingen: Routledge. Based on
manuscripts written in the early 1930s. Translated
as The Two Fundamental Problems of the Theory
of Knowledge, Troels Eggers Hansen (ed.),
Andreas Pickel (trans.), London: Routledge, 2007.
 1980, “Three Worlds”, in The Tanner Lectures on
Human Values, volume 1, S.M. McMurrin (ed.),
Salt Lake City, UT: University of Utah Press,
141–167.
 1982, The Open Universe: An Argument for
Indeterminism, W.W. Bartley III (ed.), London:
Hutchinson.
 1983, Realism and the Aim of Science, W.W.
Bartley III (ed.), London: Hutchinson.
 1994, The Myth of the Framework: In Defence of
Science and Rationality, M.A. Notturno, (ed.),
London: Routledge.
 1994, Knowledge and the Mind-Body Problem: In
Defence of Interactionism, M.A. Notturno (ed.),
London: Routledge.
 2012, After the Open Society: Selected Social and
Political Writings, Jeremy Shearmur and Piers
Norris Turner (eds.), London and New York:
Routledge.
 2020, “The Feyerabend-Popper Correspondence
(1948–1967)”, in Feyerabend’s Formative Years.
Volume 1. Feyerabend and Popper, Matteo
Collodel and Eric Oberheim (eds.), (Vienna Circle
Institute Library 5), Cham: Springer International
Publishing, 59–420. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-
00961-8_4
 2022, Binder, D., Piecha, T., Schroeder-Heister, P.
(editors) (2022), The Logical Writings of Karl
Popper. Cham: Springer. [The Logical Writings of
Karl Popper available online]

Secondary Literature/Other Sources


 Ackermann, Robert, 1976, The Philosophy of Karl
Popper, Amherst, MA: University of
Massachusetts Press.
 Agassi, Joseph, 2014, Popper and His Popular
Critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre
Lakatos (SpringerBriefs in Philosophy), Cham:
Springer International Publishing.
doi:10.1007/978-3-319-06587-8.
 Akinci, Semiha, 2004, “Popper’ s
Conventionalism”, in Catton and Macdonald 2004:
28–49.
 Alamuiti, M. M., 2021, Critical Rationalism and
the Theory of Society: Critical Rationalism and
the Open Society (Volume 1), London: Routledge.
 Bambrough, Renford (ed.), 1967, Plato, Popper,
and Politics: Some Contributions to a Modern
Controversy, New York: Barnes and Noble.
 Baudoin, Jean, 1989, Karl Popper, Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
 Brink, Chris, 1989, “Verisimilitude: Views and
Reviews”, History and Philosophy of Logic, 10(2):
181–201. doi:10.1080/014453408908837149
 Brink, Chris and Johannes Heidema, 1987, “A
Verisimilar Ordering of Theories Phrased in a
Propositional Language”, The British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science, 38(4): 533–549.
doi:10.1093/bjps/38.4.533
 Briskman, Laurence Barry, 2020, A Sceptical
Theory of Scientific Inquiry: Problems and Their
Progress, Jeremy Shearmur (ed.), Leiden: Brill.
 Britz, Katarina and Chris Brink, 1995,
“Computing Verisimilitude”, Notre Dame Journal
of Formal Logic, 36(1): 30–43.
doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1040308827
 Bunge, Mario (ed.), 1964, The Critical Approach
to Science and Philosophy, London & New York:
The Free Press.
 Burke, T.E., 1983, The Philosophy of Popper,
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
 Carnap, Rudolf, 1966 [1995], Philosophical
Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the
Philosophy of Science, New York: Basic Books.
New edition entitled An Introduction to the
Philosophy of Science, New York: Dover, 1995.
 Catton, Philip and Graham MacDonald (eds.),
2004, Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals, New
York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203326886
 Cornforth, Maurice, 1968., The Open Philosophy
and the Open Society: A Reply to Dr. Popper’s
Refutations of Marxism, London: Lawrence &
Wishart.
 Corvi, Roberta, 1993 [1997], Invito al pensiero di
Karl Popper, Milan: Gruppo Ugo Mursia S.P.A.
Translated as An Introduction to the Thought of
Karl Popper, Patrick Camiller (trans), London &
New York: Routledge, 1997.
 Currie, Gregory and Alan Musgrave (eds.),
1985, Popper and the Human Sciences, Dordrecht:
Nijhoff.
 Del Santo, F. 2022. ‘Beyond Method: The Diatribe
Between Feyerabend and Popper Over the
Foundations of Quantum
Mechanics’, International Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, Vol. 35, 2022, 5–22.
Taylor&Francis Online.
doi:10.1080/02698595.2022.2031430
 Edmonds, David and John Eidinow,
2001, Wittgenstein’s Poker: The Story of a Ten-
Minute Argument Between Two Great
Philosophers, New York: Harper & Collins.
 Feyerabend, Paul, 1975, Against Method, London:
New Left Books.
 Freud, Sigmund, 1895 [1962], “Zur Kritik Der
‘Angstneurose’”, Wiener klinische Wochenschrift,
9(27): 417–19, 9(28): 435–7, and 9(29): 451–2;
translated as “A Reply to Criticisms of My Paper
on Anxiety Neurosis”, in the Standard Edition of
the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud, James Strackey (ed.), London: Hogarth,
1962, 3: 121–140.
 –––, 1915 [1957], “Mitteilung eines der
psychoanalytischen Theorie widersprechenden
Falles von Paranoia”, Internationale Zeitschrift für
Psychoanalyse, 3(6): 321–329; translated as “A
Case of Paranoia Running Counter to the Psycho-
Analytic Theory of the Disease”, in the Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of
Sigmund Freud, James Strackey (ed.), London:
Hogarth, 1957, 14: 263–272.
 Fuller, Steve, 2004, Kuhn vs. Popper: The
Struggle for the Soul of Science, New York:
Columbia University Press.
 Galbraith, D., 2022, “Pigden Revisited, or In
Defence of Popper’s Critique of the Conspiracy
Theory of Society”, in Philosophy of the Social
Sciences, 52(4): 235–257.
 Gattei, Stefano, 2010, Karl Popper’s Philosophy
of Science: Rationality without Foundations, New
York: Routledge.
 Grünbaum, Adolf, 1976, “Is the Method of Bold
Conjectures and Attempted
Refutations Justifiably the Method of
Science?”, The British Journal for the Philosophy
of Science, 27(2): 105–136.
doi:10.1093/bjps/27.2.105
 –––, 1984, The Foundations of Psycho-analysis: A
Philosophical Critique, Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press.
 Hacohen, Malachi Haim, 2000, Karl Popper—The
Formative Years, 1902–1945: Politics and
Philosophy in Interwar Vienna, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
 Harris, John H., 1974, “Popper’s Definitions of
‘Verisimilitude’”, The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 25(2): 160–166.
doi:10.1093/bjps/25.2.160
 Howson, Colin, 1984, “Popper’s Solution to the
Problem of Induction”, The Philosophical
Quarterly, 34(135): 143–147.
doi:10.2307/2219507
 Hudelson, Richard, 1980, “Popper’s Critique of
Marx”, Philosophical Studies: An International
Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition,
37(3): 259–70.
 Hume, David, 1739–40, A Treatise of Human
Nature, London. Reprinted in his The
Philosophical Works, T.H. Green & T.H. Grose
(eds), 4 vols., Darmstadt: Scientia Verlag Aalen,
1964 (reprint of 1886 edition).
 Jacobs, Struan, 1991, Science and British
Liberalism: Locke, Bentham, Mill and Popper,
Aldershot: Avebury.
 James, Roger, 1980, Return to Reason: Popper’s
Thought in Public Life, Shepton Mallet: Open
Books.
 Jarvie, Ian C. 2001, The Republic of Science: The
Emergence of Popper’s Social View of Science
1935–1945, Amsterdam: Brill | Rodopi
 Johansson, Ingvar, 1975, A Critique of Karl
Popper’s Methodology, Stockholm: Scandinavian
University Books.
 Kekes, John, 1977, “Popper in
Perspective”, Metaphilosophy, 8(1): 36–61.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1977.tb00261.x
 Keuth, Herbert, 1976, “Verisimilitude or the
Approach to the Whole Truth”, Philosophy of
Science, 43(3): 311–336. doi:10.1086/288691
 Keuth, Herbert, 2000 [2004], Die Philosophie
Karl Popper, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. Translated
by the author as The Philosophy of Karl Popper,
New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
 Kuhn, Thomas S., 1962, The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions, Chicago and London:
University of Chicago Press.
 Kuipers, Theo A.F., 1982, “Approaching
Descriptive and Theoretical Truth”, Erkenntnis,
18(3): 343–378. doi:10.1007/BF00205277
 ––– (ed.), 1987, What is Closer-to-the-Truth?,
Amsterdam: Rodopi.
 Lakatos, Imre, 1970, “Falsification and the
Methodology of Scientific Research
Programmes”, in Lakatos and Musgrave 1970: 91–
196. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139171434.009
 –––, 1978, The Methodology of Scientific
Research Programmes, J. Worrel and G. Currie
(eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 Lakatos, Imre and Alan Musgrave (eds.),
1970, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge:
Proceedings of the International Colloquium in
the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9781139171434
 Laudan, Larry, 1977, Progress and Its Problems:
Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth, Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press.
 Leplin, Jarrett, 2007, “Enlisting Popper in the Case
for Scientific Realism”, Philosophia Scientae,
11(1): 71–97.
doi:10.4000/philosophiascientiae.323 [Leplin 2007
available online]
 Levinson, Paul (ed.), 1982, In Pursuit of Truth:
Essays in Honour of Karl Popper on the Occasion
of his 80th Birthday, Atlantic Highlands, NJ:
Humanities Press.
 Levinson, Ronald B., 1953, In Defense of Plato,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
 Magee, Bryan, 1973, Karl Popper, London:
Penguin.
 Maxwell, N., 2002, “Karl Raimund Popper”,
in British Philosophers, 1800–2000 (Dictionary of
Literary Biography: 262), P. Dematteis, P. Fosl
and L. McHenry (eds.), Detroit: Gale Research
Inc., pp. 176–194
 –––, 2017, Karl Popper, Science and
Enlightenment, London: University College
London Press.
 –––, 2020, “Aim-Oriented Empiricism and the
Metaphysics of Science”, Philosophia, 48: 347–
364.
 Mellor, D. H., 1977, “The Popper
Phenomenon”, Philosophy, 52(200): 195–202.
doi:10.1017/S0031819100023135
 Milkov, Nikolay, 2012, “Karl Popper’s Debt to
Leonard Nelson”, Grazer Philosophische Studien,
86(1): 137–156. doi:10.1163/9789401209182_009
 Miller, David, 1974a, “On the Comparison of
False Theories by Their Bases”, The British
Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25(2): 178–
188. doi:10.1093/bjps/25.2.178
 –––, 1974b, “Popper’s Qualitative Theory of
Verisimilitude”, The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 25(2): 166–177.
doi:10.1093/bjps/25.2.166
 –––, 1994, Critical Rationalism: A Restatement
and Defence, Chicago: Open Court.
 Mulkay, Michael and G. Nigel Gilbert, 1981,
“Putting Philosophy to Work: Karl Popper’s
Influence on Scientific Practice”, Philosophy of
the Social Sciences, 11(3): 389–407.
doi:10.1177/004839318101100306
 Munz, Peter, 1985, Our Knowledge of the Growth
of Knowledge: Popper or Wittgenstein?, London:
Routledge.
 Naydler, Jeremy, 1982, “The Poverty of
Popperism”, The Thomist: A Speculative
Quarterly Review, 46(1): 92–107.
doi:10.1353/tho.1982.0048
 Niiniluoto, Ilkka, 1987, Truthlikeness, Dordrecht:
D. Reidel.
 Oddie, Graham, 1986, Likeness to Truth,
Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
 O’Hear, Anthony, 1980, Karl Popper, London:
Routledge.
 ––– (ed.), 1995, Karl Popper: Philosophy and
Problems, Cambridge & New York: Cambridge
University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511563751
 Parusniková, Z. & Merritt, D. (eds.), 2021, Karl
Popper’s Science and Philosophy, Cham:
Springer, ebook. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-67036-8
 Putnam, Hilary, 1974 [1991], “The
‘Corroboration’ of Theories”, in Schilpp 1974:
vol. 1: 221–240. Republished with Retrospective
Note in The Philosophy of Science, Richard Boyd,
Philip Gasper, and J. D. Trout (eds.), Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1991, 121–138.
 Quinton, Anthony, 1967, “Popper, Karl Raimund”,
in Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Volume 6), Paul
Edwards (ed.), New York: Collier Macmillan:
398–401.
 Radnitzky, Gerard and Gunnar Andersson (eds.),
1978, Progress and Rationality in Science,
Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
 Radnitzky, Gerard and W. W. Bartley (eds.),
1987, Evolutionary Epistemology, Rationality,
and the Sociology of Knowledge, La Salle, IL:
Open Court.
 Richmond, Sheldon, 1994, Aesthetic Criteria:
Gombrich and the Philosophies of Science of
Popper and Polanyi, Amsterdam/Atlanta, GA:
Rodopi.
 Rowbottom, Darrell P., 2010, Popper’s Critical
Rationalism: A Philosophical Investigation, New
York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203836187
 Salmon, Wesley C., 1967, The Foundations of
Scientific Inference, Pittsburgh: University of
Pittsburgh Press.
 Royer, C., Matei, L. (eds.), 2023, Open Society
Unresolved. The Contemporary Relevance of a
Contested Idea. Budapest, Vienna, New York:
Central European University Press.
 Sassower, Raphael and Nathaniel Laor (eds.),
2019, The Impact of Critical Rationalism:
Expanding the Popperian Legacy through the
Works of Ian C. Jarvie, Cham: Springer
International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-
90826-7
 Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.), 1974, The Philosophy
of Karl Popper, 2 volumes, La Salle, IL: Open
Court Press.
 Shearmur, Jeremy, 1996, Political Thought of
Karl Popper, London & New York: Routledge.
 Simkin, C. G. F., 1993, Popper’s Views on
Natural and Social Science, Leiden: Brill.
 Stokes, Geoffrey, 1998, Popper: Philosophy,
Politics and Scientific Method, New York: Wiley
& Sons.
 Stove, D. C., 1982, Popper and After: Four
Modern Irrationalists, Oxford: Pergamon Press.
 Sturm, Thomas, 2012, “Bühler and Popper:
Kantian Therapies for the Crisis in
Psychology”, Studies in History and Philosophy of
Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy
of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43(2):
462–472. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2011.11.006
 Tichý, Pavel, 1974, “On Popper’s Definitions of
Verisimilitude”, The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 25(2): 155–160.
doi:10.1093/bjps/25.2.155
 –––, 1978, “Verisimilitude Revisited”, Synthese,
38(2): 175–196. doi:10.1007/BF00486149
 Thomas, Allan James, 2019, “Thought Without a
Thinking Subject: or Karl Popper as Film-
Philosopher”, Screen Thought Journal, 3(1): 1–13.
 Vetter, Hermann, 1977, “A New Concept of
Verisimilitude”, Theory and Decision, 8(4): 369–
375. doi:10.1007/BF00141535
 Watkins, John W. N., 1984, Science and
Scepticism, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press and London: Hutchinson.
 –––, 1997. “Popperian Ideas on Progress and
Rationality in Science”, The Critical Rationalist,
2(2). [Watkins 1997 available online].
 Wilkins, Burleigh Taylor, 1978, Has History Any
Meaning? A Critique of Popper’s Philosophy of
History, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
 Williams, Douglas E., 1989, Truth, Hope and
Power: The Thought of Karl Popper, Toronto:
University of Toronto Press.
 Wuketits, Franz M., 1984, Concepts and
Approaches in Evolutionary Epistemology:
Towards an Evolutionary Theory of Knowledge,
Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
 Xiao, H., 2023, ‘On Popper’s Shifting Appraisal
of Scientific Status of Darwinian
Theory’, Academic Journal of Humanities &
Social Sciences, 6(3): 23–30.

Academic Tools
How to cite this entry .
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society .
Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology
Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources


 The Karl Popper Web.
 Open Universe of the Japan Popper Society.
 The Karl Popper Archives – University Library
Klagenfurt, AAU
 Karl Popper Foundation – Universität Klagenfurt
(aau.at)

Related Entries
confirmation | convention | Feyerabend, Paul | Hume, David | induction: problem of | Kuhn,
Thomas | Lakatos, Imre | science: and pseudo-science | scientific method | scientific
progress | scientific realism | truthlikeness | Vienna Circle
Copyright © 2022 by
Stephen Thornton <sfthornton4@gmail.com>
Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
Please Read How You Can Help Support the Growth and Development of the Encyclopedia
Browse
 Table of Contents
 What's New
 Random Entry
 Chronological
 Archives
About
 Editorial Information
 About the SEP
 Editorial Board
 How to Cite the SEP
 Special Characters
 Advanced Tools
 Accessibility
 Contact

Support SEP
 Support the SEP
 PDFs for SEP Friends
 Make a Donation
 SEPIA for Libraries

Mirror Sites
View this site from another server:
USA (Main Site)Philosophy, Stanford University
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab,
Department of Philosophy, Stanford University
Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

You might also like