Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 16

This art icle was downloaded by: [ Lisa Guent her]

On: 09 August 2011, At : 07: 54


Publisher: Rout ledge
I nform a Lt d Regist ered in England and Wales Regist ered Num ber: 1072954 Regist ered
office: Mort im er House, 37- 41 Mort im er St reet , London W1T 3JH, UK

Angelaki
Publicat ion det ails, including inst ruct ions for aut hors and
subscript ion informat ion:
ht t p:/ / www.t andfonline.com/ loi/ cang20

Merleau-Ponty and the Sense of Sexual


Difference
a
Lisa Guent her
a
Depart ment of Philosophy, Vanderbilt Universit y, 229 Furman
Hall, Nashville, TN 37240, USA

Available online: 09 Aug 2011

To cite this article: Lisa Guent her (2011): Merleau-Pont y and t he Sense of Sexual Difference,
Angelaki, 16:2, 19-33

To link to this article: ht t p:/ / dx.doi.org/ 10.1080/ 0969725X.2011.591583

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTI CLE

Full t erm s and condit ions of use: ht t p: / / www.t andfonline.com / page/ t erm s- and-
condit ions

This art icle m ay be used for research, t eaching and privat e st udy purposes. Any
subst ant ial or syst em at ic reproduct ion, re- dist ribut ion, re- selling, loan, sub- licensing,
syst em at ic supply or dist ribut ion in any form t o anyone is expressly forbidden.

The publisher does not give any warrant y express or im plied or m ake any represent at ion
t hat t he cont ent s will be com plet e or accurat e or up t o dat e. The accuracy of any
inst ruct ions, form ulae and drug doses should be independent ly verified wit h prim ary
sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, act ions, claim s, proceedings,
dem and or cost s or dam ages what soever or howsoever caused arising direct ly or
indirect ly in connect ion wit h or arising out of t he use of t his m at erial.
ANGEL AK I
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 16 number 2 june 2011

hat is the sense of sexual difference?


W What is its meaning, and what is its
direction or orientation? Popular understandings
of sexual difference tend to locate its sense in
either ‘‘nature’’ or ‘‘nurture’’; either the meaning
and orientation of sex is determined by chromo-
somes, hormones and patterns of brain activity,
or it is constructed through social norms, parental
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

guidance, and media. In either case, the sense


of sexual difference is invariably defined in
relation to ‘‘normal’’ men and women; exceptions
are admitted, and may even be celebrated, but the
duality of male and female nevertheless outlines
the terrain of sexual difference. However radically lisa guenther
certain bodies depart from the norm, whether as
androgynous, intersexed or transsexual subjects,
they are still thought to gain their sense from MERLEAU-PONTY AND
that norm; they are conceived as mixtures or
combinations of male and female, tending THE SENSE OF SEXUAL
towards one or the other side of the duality.
Whether one takes the side of nature or of DIFFERENCE
nurture, it is difficult to avoid borrowing the
sense of sexual difference from current gender
norms. A masculine woman appears as an or female norms. No matter how inclusive these
exception to the rule precisely because women popular conceptions of sex try to be, they tend to
are presumed to be normally feminine. Similarly, reinscribe current gender norms at the level of
intersexed bodies seem abnormal to the extent sex, reading gender back into sex in order to then
that we normally expect either males or females; discover that sex was already moving in the
these bodies seem to require surgical disambigua- direction of gender. To the extent that theories of
tion at birth because we can’t imagine what it nurture or social construction avoid this circular-
would be like to live as (or with) someone who is ity, they posit the sexed infant as a blank slate
both male and female, or neither male nor female. upon which social meanings are inscribed
Transsexual bodies make the most sense to the through the giving or withholding of Barbie
popular imagination in drag performances where dolls and toy guns. But whenever these social
gender is exaggerated, allowing us to see the man inscriptions fail to take hold, the nurture theorist
as a woman, or the woman as a man; they make falls back into nature’s vicious circle, often
less sense when the gender performance is more producing the confession: ‘‘I thought that
ambiguous, or not clearly oriented towards male gender was socially constructed – until I had

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN1469-2899 online/11/020019^15 ß 2011 Taylor & Francis


DOI: 10.1080/0969725X.2011.591583

19
sexual difference

kids of my own!’’ Likewise, when the nature produced not in spite of deviations, nor through
theorist is faced with exceptions to the rule of their exclusion, but rather through a process of
biological determination, she is forced to admit mutual divergence which both produces and
weakly that ‘‘society also plays a role.’’ destabilizes the norm.
The philosophical mistake common to both In what follows, I approach the sense of sexual
nature and nurture arguments is that they both difference from two directions, firstly in relation
locate the sense of sexual difference in a to Merleau-Ponty’s ontological concept of the
substance which is presumed to hold the secret flesh as developed in his last work, The Visible
of its meaning and to determine the direction of and the Invisible, and secondly in relation to the
its unfolding. Both approach the body and the concept of institution as developed in his lecture
mind as different substances, only one of which course at the Collège de France (1954–55).
‘‘makes sense’’ and therefore determines the In both approaches, the question of sexual
sense of the other. They may disagree about difference emerges in relation to pregnancy,
where to locate the origin of sense, but they birth and gestation, firstly in an ontological
nevertheless agree that it must be localized on one sense, and secondly in the biological sense of
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

or the other side of a duality. In doing so, they embryological development. Birth is a privileged
fall into the trap of what David Morris has called site for the interrogation of sexual difference
‘‘ontological localism’’ (69); they locate sense in because it both engenders and is engendered by
a determinate thing or part of a thing, for sexed bodies; but what often remains uninterro-
example in male or female bodies, in the gated in both ontological and biological discus-
hormones running through these bodies, or in sions of birth are the intersubjective relations
the social messages to which young minds are between these sexed bodies, the alterity which
exposed. What this approach misses is the whole both separates them and orients them towards
field of being out of which meaningful determi- one another. By analyzing ontological and
nations arise, the ontological background in biological accounts of birth alongside one
relation to which things and parts may be another, and in relation to questions of inter-
distinguished in the first place, and the process subjectivity, I hope to demonstrate the non-
of mutual differentiation which gives rise to opposition or mutual entwinement of domains
recognizably different beings. For Morris, follow- that are often regarded as mutually exclusive,
ing Merleau-Ponty, the origin of sense is not in even by theorists who otherwise seek to challenge
things or parts, but in ‘‘the global dynamics and the dualisms of body and mind, biology and
directions of a field of being’’ (70). To shift our culture, nature and nurture.
attention from local substances to the field of
being is, in effect, to move from the natural
I sexual difference in the flesh
attitude into phenomenological reflection. In this
paper, I propose to reflect on the ontological field In many of his engagements with the question
which gives sense to sexual difference, without of intersubjectivity, Merleau-Ponty compares the
locating this sense on the side of either nature or relation between self and other to a pregnancy.
nurture, bodies or minds. In so doing, I hope to But it is not clear who – or what – occupies the
clarify some of the confusions about sexual place of the mother in this comparison, nor is it
difference that arise in the natural attitude, and clear that the comparison works the same way
to suggest a more critical approach to everyday in different texts. In ‘‘The Philosopher and his
assumptions about sexed bodies. My central aim Shadow,’’ it seems that we are all mothers,
in this analysis is to raise possibilities for thinking regardless of sexual difference: ‘‘each one of us is
the logic of sexual difference beyond the duality pregnant with the others and confirmed by them
of male and female in relation to which certain in his body’’ (181). Likewise, in ‘‘Dialogue
bodies can only appear as deviations from the and the Perception of the Other,’’ the other is
norm. As I will argue, the sense of sexual ‘‘reproduced from me’’ through ‘‘that strange
difference – its meaning and its direction – is filiation which makes the other forever my

20
guenther

second, even when I prefer him to myself’’ (135). or nothingness nor to a determinate negation of
This image echoes Husserl’s account of inter- something that is, but rather to a temporalization,
subjectivity in the Cartesian Meditations, a delay whereby reversibility is ‘‘always imminent
in which the ego’s experience of the other is and never realized in fact’’ (VI 147). My right
constituted on the basis of a coordination or hand touches my left hand, and in so touching
‘‘pairing’’ which always begins on the side becomes touched, just as the touched hand begins
of consciousness (108–20). It is open to the to touch; but touching and touched never
criticism, made by Levinas and others, that the absolutely coincide. They are rather always on
other is thereby reduced to an alter ego or the verge of one another, diverging and encroach-
‘‘another me’’ whose alterity is limited or even ing upon one another, with an endless reversi-
foreclosed by the consciousness that (re)produces bility which hollows out a space into which the
it.1 As if to confirm this suspicion, Merleau-Ponty other is received. The temporalization of the flesh
sometimes presents the other as a kind of clone thus implies a spatialization: the hollowing-out
or ‘‘replica of myself,’’ ‘‘a wandering double,’’ of a place for possible emergence, or for the
even a sprout: emergence of the possible. In resistance to
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

Sartre’s ontology, Merleau-Ponty writes, ‘‘The


To the infinity that was me something else still soul, the for itself is a hollow [un creux] and not
adds itself; a sprout shoots forth, I grow; I give
a void, not absolute non-being with respect to
birth, this other is made from my flesh and
a Being that would be plenitude and hard core’’
blood and yet is no longer me. How is that
possible? How can the cogito emigrate beyond (VI 233).3
me, since it is me? (‘‘Dialogue’’ 134) This concept of a ‘‘hollow’’ formed through
the mutual divergence of reversible sides of one
A response to this question – and, indeed, sole flesh helps to explain the sense in which the
a reformulation of the question itself – may be other may be ‘‘born’’ from my own embodied
found in Merleau-Ponty’s late reflections on the experience, without for that reason being con-
flesh as ‘‘the mother’’2 from which apparent stituted by consciousness. Already in my ordin-
oppositions such as vision and visibility, touch ary experience of the world there are different
and tangibility, or self and other are ‘‘born by perspectives from which to view an object. I can
segregation’’ (VI 136). Images of fecundity and walk around the table, look under it, stand on top
birth in The Visible and Invisible suggest not a of it . . . From each one of these perspectives,
miraculous parturition of the other from the self, certain aspects of the world become visible while
but rather a mutual fecundation of self and other, others are hidden; I cannot see the whole world
a divergence from one common flesh, such that at once; indeed, I cannot even see the whole of a
neither I nor the other can be designated as first simple object like a table all at once. And yet,
or second, active or passive. Rather than the self without this variability of perspectives, through
giving birth to the other, both emerge from an which one vantage point is lost, yet retained,
anonymous, impersonal flesh that generates while another is anticipated, I would not have an
differences within itself by folding or coiling experience of the object as a whole. Even the
over itself – ‘‘by dehiscence or fission of its own simplest experience already implies a multiplicity
mass’’ (VI 146) – such that differences do not of possible perspectives, each of which is a variant
emerge through opposition, but rather through of the others, and each of which could potentially
intensive self-relation and self-divergence. be filled by someone other than myself. This
Merleau-Ponty calls flesh ‘‘a pregnancy of simple experience implies a process of tempor-
possibles’’ (VI 250), where the possibilities alization – successive profiles lost and gained,
brought forth are not extinguished in their retained and anticipated – and a process of
actualization, but remain generative of new spatialization of the object as one and the same
possibilities. What sustains the flesh as a throughout all its successive profiles. But if this is
‘‘pregnancy of possibles’’ is a concept of the case, then my experience of the world ‘‘hooks
negativity which refers neither to a pure void into’’ the experience of others, whether or not

21
sexual difference

other viewers are factually there. Even when I am myself the possibility of becoming-other, altered
utterly alone, my perception is already brimming by a perspective that did not begin with me, but
or ‘‘pregnant’’ with other possible viewers. which implicates me as one who is seen and
This account of experience demonstrates touched as well as seeing and touching. Precisely
the implication of virtual others in one’s own because my body is reversible flesh, and because
perceptual experience, but it does not yet offer an no body contains the full sense of flesh within its
account that could stand up to the charge that own localized being, my body bears the alterity of
the phenomenological sense of ‘‘the other’’ is the other, not as a pure void, nor as a mystery
anything more than a variation on myself, the which resists my full comprehension, but as the
‘‘sprout’’ of a consciousness which remains firmly hollow that shapes my own existence. The sense
centered in its own experience. The late work of of the other emerges here ‘‘not as what contests
Merleau-Ponty diverges from standard phenom- my life but what forms it, not as another universe
enological accounts by articulating vision as a in which I would be alienated but as the preferred
reflective structure of seeing and being seen variant of a life that has never been my own’’
which cannot be completed by a single individual (VI 82 fn. 14).4 From this perspective, myself and
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

subject: ‘‘Here there is no problem of the alter the other are ‘‘extreme divergences of one same
ego because it is not I who sees, not he who sees, something’’ (VI 84). We are neither identical
because an anonymous visibility inhabits both of nor opposed, but rather variations of a common
us, a vision in general’’ (VI 142). To see and be flesh which articulates itself through the move-
seen is to be immersed in an anonymous structure ment of mutual divergence and co-implication.
of divergence and encroachment, where I am In contrast with the passages where others
always on the verge of catching up with the other appear as offspring and/or replicas of the
I might become, but never able to collapse the individual subject, Merleau-Ponty writes:
distance in between. Even when I look at myself
in the mirror, I can never quite see myself seeing. Take others at the moment they appear in the
I can see how a passing bird catches the eye of my world’s flesh . . . Before others are or can be
friend, without thereby knowing how it looks to subjected to my conditions of possibility and
reconstructed in my image, they must already
her, but I cannot quite catch myself in the act of
exist as outlines, deviations, and variants of a
perception. As in the example of the two hands
single Vision in which I too participate.
touching, there is a delay and divergence within For they are not fictions with which I might
my own self-relation. The seeing–seen and people my desert – offspring of my spirit
touching–touched bodies of others hook into and forever unactualized possibilities – but my
this hinge within myself, not by filling an empty twins or the flesh of my flesh. (VI 33)
gap but by prolonging my gaze and reflecting
it back to me. The other who looks at me is The other is ‘‘flesh of my flesh,’’ but only in the
therefore already prefigured in the reflective sense that ‘‘my’’ flesh is not mine alone, but
structure of my own perception, not only because already a divergent articulation of the anonymous
I spontaneously anticipate other ‘‘me’s’’ but flesh of the world. Elsewhere, in ‘‘The
because even my own self-relation implies a Philosopher and his Shadow,’’ Merleau-Ponty
relation to others who can see me in ways I cannot writes:
see myself.
If there is a break, it is not between me and the
Myself and the other, seeing and seen,
other person; it is between a primordial
touching and being touched, exist as mutually
generality we are intermingled in and the
implicative possibilities of a structure that precise system, myself–the others. What
belongs to neither of us: the chiasmatic structure ‘‘precedes’’ intersubjective life cannot be
of the flesh. To be pregnant with the other in this numerically distinguished from it, precisely
sense is not to project her perspective as one that because at this level there is neither individua-
might have been my own, had I only bothered to tion nor numerical distinction. The constitu-
walk around the table, but rather to bear within tion of others does not come after that of the

22
guenther
body; others and my body are born together generative flesh. While the concept of flesh
from the original ecstasy. (174) cannot be coherently understood as a ‘‘mother,’’
and while it should not be signified as feminine,
This ‘‘original ecstasy’’ of the flesh involves a
it nevertheless raises the possibility of an exciting
‘‘transitivity and confusion of self and other’’
account of sexual difference, and it does so
(174) in relation to which it is impossible to say
precisely to the extent that the flesh remains
which comes first; like the seer and the seen,
impersonal and anonymous.
self and other emerge as mutually implicating
Merleau-Ponty gives no clear indication of
variants of a single reversible structure.
whether he thinks sexual difference plays a part
While this radical reversibility complicates the
in the ‘‘birth’’ of self and other, but he does rely
Husserlian account of intersubjectivity in inter-
on the logic of sexual difference to explicate the
esting ways, it also draws Luce Irigaray’s
relation between self and other. In a working note
criticism – albeit for different reasons – in her
for The Visible and the Invisible, Merleau-Ponty
reading of the chiasm (127–53). If flesh is ‘‘the
writes:
mother,’’ and if it is an impersonal, anonymous
dimension, then where has the specifically
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

The I–other relation to be conceived (like


feminine mother disappeared to? Irigaray argues the intersexual relation, with its indefinite
that the logic of the chiasm appropriates the substitutions . . .) as complementary roles one
language of birth while distorting its irreversible of which cannot be occupied without the other
trajectory from mother to child, and neutralizing being also: masculinity implies femininity, etc.
the maternal-feminine into an unsexed, inexhaus- Fundamental polymorphism by reason of
tible, and fully reversible flesh. This logic which I do not have to constitute the other
excludes the mother by including her in a in face of the Ego: he is already there, and the
Ego is conquered from him. Describe the
closed circuit where she can only appear as the
pre-egology, the ‘‘syncretism,’’ indivision or
primordial condition for man’s self-relation, and
transitivism. What is it that there is at this
never emerge on her own terms as a subject or an level? There is the vertical or carnal universe
other. Irigaray’s critique raises an important and its polymorphic matrix. Absurdity of the
issue, and yet her resistance to the depersonaliza- tabula rasa on which cognitions would be
tion of the feminine mother seems to block an arranged: not that there be cognitions before
exploration of the feminist possibilities raised by cognitions, but because there is the field.
Merleau-Ponty’s concept of flesh. In her paper on The I–other problem: a Western problem.
ethics and sexual difference in Merleau-Ponty and (VI 220–21)
Irigaray, Judith Butler writes:
Just as masculinity implies femininity, the self
In [Irigaray’s] view, there is no masculine implies the other; neither side of these mutually
without a prior implication in the terms of the implicative relations can be properly understood
feminine, and there is no feminine without a on its own. Rather, both must be understood
prior implication in the terms of the mascu- in relation to the field, or ‘‘polymorphic matrix,’’
line; each term admits to its own internal or ‘‘vertical or carnal universe’’ which gives rise
impossibility through its relation to the Other. to the relation. Confusions arise when we attempt
The relation is not primarily that of an
to take one side of the relation as a starting point
encounter, but, rather, of a constitutive
for explaining the other, as when classical
intertwining, a dynamic differentiation in
proximity. (115) phenomenology attempts to explain the genesis
of the other in consciousness, rather than the
In what remains of this section, I argue that mutual divergence of self and other within the
Merleau-Ponty’s (admittedly brief) remarks on reflective structure of flesh. In this working note,
sexual difference in The Visible and the Invisible Merleau-Ponty seems to assume that the mascu-
suggest a similar reciprocity of masculine and line–feminine relation is straightforward enough
feminine, even though he develops this recipro- to explain the I–other relation without requiring
city in terms of an impersonal, anonymous, yet any special explanation of its own. But given that

23
sexual difference

he has described the I–other relation at greater masculine–feminine relation. The sense of mas-
length throughout his work, we may be able to culinity and femininity would arise equiprimor-
work backwards from the relation that Merleau- dially through a mutual divergence from one
Ponty finds necessary to explain towards the another, in the wake of whose double movement
relation he invokes without explanation. we discover a polymorphous flesh which both
In what sense does masculinity imply femi- connects and distinguishes between different
ninity? If sexual difference marks a basic cleavage forms of humanity. Like self and other, masculine
within humanity, such that all human beings are and feminine would be different but mutually
either men or women (bracketing for the moment implicated articulations of the flesh, where
all the various exceptions and complications of neither can be posited as the first or generic
this rule), then it is impossible to conceive of one form of the human. Rather, humanity would exist
without the other. One could no more posit men only as a zone of mutual divergence, a ‘‘poly-
without women than left without right, inside morphous matrix’’ which enables multiple forms
without outside, since these are relational terms of intersubjective and ‘‘intersexual’’ life. This
which only make sense in pairs.5 Throughout all zone would not be a blank slate or empty interval,
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

the ‘‘indefinite substitutions’’ of what Merleau- but rather a thickness of flesh which articulates
Ponty calls ‘‘the intersexual relation’’ – all the difference within the sameness of a ‘‘block
different ways in which men and women relate to of common life’’ (VI 12), a ‘‘common tissue’’
one another across the threshold of sexual (VI 203). Just as flesh cannot be separated from
difference – the terms masculine and feminine the movement of mutual divergence which gives
remain irreducible to each another, emerging birth to its various articulations, so too humanity
through mutual divergence from a polymorphous exists only through its variously sexed forms. The
field of being which is itself neither masculine nor ‘‘indivision or transitivism’’ that Merleau-Ponty
feminine. Already, this analysis provides the basis locates at the level of the flesh allows us to
for a critique of ontological localism with respect imagine a proliferation of different relations
to sexual difference; the sense of masculinity or between and among masculine and feminine
femininity must be found in the relation, rather articulations of humanity, while still confirming
than in bodies or parts of bodies from one side or that both must be in circulation, since (thus far,
the other. But what can we say about the genesis at least) sexual reproduction requires both sexes.
of this relation? Merleau-Ponty traces the relation This account seems promising to me, but
of I–other, and presumably of masculine– before we can run ahead with it we must note the
feminine, to a ‘‘fundamental polymorphism,’’ an ways in which the analogy between self–other
‘‘indivision or transitivity’’ from which both sides and masculine–feminine threatens to fall apart.
of the dual structure arise in tandem, mutually The relation of self and other is fully reversible,
shaping each other. One need not explain how the while masculine and feminine do not seem to be.
ego ‘‘constitutes’’ the other – indeed, it is a false In conversation, as in mutual looking and
question to pose – because one does not exist touching, the positions of self and other are
without the other; I become myself through my traded back and forth, sometimes so quickly that
encounters with others, and vice versa. Both sides the two become indistinguishable. Furthermore,
emerge as mutual divergences within a flesh that there is never just one self and one other, but
is impersonal and anonymous, that is neither a rather a multiplicity of seeing–seen or touching–
self nor an other, but a matrix of possibilities. To touched beings who occupy different shifting
the extent that Western ontologies overlook this positions in relation to one another. How could
radical transitivity of the flesh in order to posit we explain the full complexity of sexual differ-
self and other as discrete beings, the I–other ence, or of intersubjectivity for that matter,
problem may be, as Merleau-Ponty suggests, beginning from a notion of ‘‘complementary
‘‘a Western problem.’’ roles,’’ as if men and women were interlocking
It is tempting to transfer these insights pieces in the puzzle of humanity? Does not
immediately from the I–other relation to the the duality of these terms already foreclose the

24
guenther

possibility of articulating the full range of human And yet this brings us back to the question of
sexuation – androgynous, intersexed, transsexual irreversibility raised by Irigaray in her reading
bodies – as well as the different ways in which of Merleau-Ponty. Is it really anything more than
this sexuation is lived in relation to gender and a fantasy to imagine the masculine as ‘‘pregnant’’
sexuality? Merleau-Ponty may affirm a ‘‘funda- with the possibility of the feminine? In practice
mental polymorphism’’ at the level of the flesh, and in historical memory, isn’t it always the
but the flesh is not a being; it is an ontological feminine which is made to bear the masculine,
concept. Must polymorphic beings, like inter- along with the full weight of sexuate life?
sexed subjects, be understood in relation to the Merleau-Ponty’s image of the two pieces
basic duality of male and female? And if so, of wood that fit into each other as if by
has our phenomenological analysis come much ‘‘destination’’ seems to confirm this suspicion
further than the popular imagination, which by reducing the possibility of double divergence
circumscribes the sense of sexual difference to a complementary pairing in which two
within a male–female duality? mutually exclusive forms fit neatly together,
In another working note from The Visible and to the exclusion of all other possibilities.7
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

the Invisible, Merleau-Ponty further complicates In addition to reinforcing a normative duality


the issues I have raised by taking us a step back, of male and female, this view seems to sanction
and then a leap forward, within the same sentence. heterosexual pairing as an inevitable outcome,
In this passage, Merleau-Ponty relates ‘‘the male– as the only way for human beings to complete
female relation’’ to ‘‘two pieces of wood that themselves.8
children see fitting together of themselves, How might we make sense of Merleau-Ponty’s
irresistibly, because each is the possible of the provocative suggestion that ‘‘each [sex] is the
other’’ (VI 228). On one hand, we are brought possible of the other’’ without falling into the trap
back to the puzzle-piece theory of humanity, where of restricting the sense of sexual difference to
male and female bodies are destined for one a two-way street where male and female are
another like a lock and key.6 But on the other destined to fit together like pieces of a puzzle?
hand, the phrase ‘‘each is the possible of the The challenge for my project of developing a non-
other’’ suggests a way of developing our account of reductive, non-oppositional account of sexual
sexual difference in terms of a mutual divergence difference beginning from Merleau-Ponty’s onto-
of the flesh. On this reading, feminine and logical account of the flesh as a ‘‘pregnancy
masculine would not be the two basic forms of a of possibles’’ is to show how a polymorphous
more general human ‘‘type’’; rather, the feminine plurality – and not just a duality – may emerge
would exist as the possible of the masculine, through the mutual divergence of masculine and
and the masculine as the possible of the feminine. feminine. To develop this account, I draw on
The mutual divergence of these possibilities would Merleau-Ponty’s remarks on embryology in
create a porous zone of interpenetrating possibi- his Collège de France Lectures on Institution
lities in relation to which no single being could (1954–55) and Nature (1956–60).
posit itself as purely masculine or purely feminine,
since it also bears the possibility of the other. II the institution of sexual difference
This idea might fecundate a notion of humanity
which does not base itself on one (apparently The silliest notion has just crossed my
mind . . . Perhaps men are nothing but a
universal) standard, but rather facilitates a break-
freakish variety of women, or women only a
ing-forth of many different polymorphous forms freakish variety of men . . . (Diderot,
of sexuate life. If masculinity and femininity are ‘‘D’Alembert’s Dream’’ qtd in Laqueur 26)
considered not as separate terms but rather
as bearers of the ‘‘possible of the other,’’ then It may seem odd to discuss embryology in a
one might say that they are ‘‘pregnant’’ with phenomenological account of sexual difference.
each other, already anticipating and enabling After all, we do not experience our own
the difference of the other. embryological development as consciousness,

25
sexual difference

so what could an inquiry into embryology both rooted in a material past and oriented
possibly contribute to our sense of ourselves, or towards a future that calls and demands a
to the sense of sexual difference? But Merleau- response. Merleau-Ponty explains the temporality
Ponty’s distinctive approach to phenomenology, of institution in enigmatic, but suggestive, detail:
starting from the anonymous flesh rather than
from consciousness, and his late account of the Time is the very model of institution:9
passivity–activity, it continues, because it has
institution of a sense rather than its constitution
been instituted, it fuses, it cannot stop being,
in consciousness, suggest that we may reflect on it is total because it is partial, it is a field. One
biological patterns such as embryological devel- can speak of a quasi-eternity not by the
opment without leaving the realm of phenomen- escaping of instants towards the non-being of
ological ontology. We could reformulate this the future, but by the exchange of my times
claim in stronger terms: precisely because the lived between the instants, the identification
reflective structure of flesh is more fundamental between them, the interference and static of
than consciousness, our phenomenological reflec- the relations of filiation (cf. Guérin) (neither
tion on sexual difference should not confine itself an objective filiation nor the choice of the
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

to conscious experience, but should look to more ancestors). Lateral kinship of all the ‘‘nows’’
which makes for their confusion, their ‘‘gen-
fundamental patterns that cross the apparent line
erality,’’ a ‘‘transtemporality’’ of decline and
between body and mind, nature and culture.
decadence . . . Originary time is neither deca-
This is precisely what the concept of institu- dence (delay back upon itself) nor anticipation
tion seeks to do. Rather than developing two (advance forward upon itself), but is on time,
different vocabularies for the discussion of the time that it is. (IP 7)
biological and cultural phenomena – and without
reducing one realm to the other, as if culture Like the flesh, institution involves a ‘‘pregnancy
could be understood in biological terms or vice of possibles’’ (VI 250); it engenders a ‘‘lateral
versa – Merleau-Ponty develops a flexible concept kinship’’ of instants which are not simply
of the temporal process whereby a sense is arranged in a linear order from past to present
instituted in general: to future, but rather communicate with one
another to the point of confusion, generality or
[B]y institution we were intending those ‘‘transtemporality.’’10 This lateral kinship is not
events of an experience which endow the a cause/effect relation whereby a parent-instant
experience with durable dimensions, in rela- produces a child-instant; rather, as a pattern of
tion to which a whole series of other
transtemporality, it involves the cross-fertilization
experiences will make sense, and will form a
of different possibilities, in exchanges which are
thinkable sequel or a history – or again the
events which deposit in me a sense, not as neither active nor passive but passive–active.
something surviving or as a residue, but as a Through these exchanges, a meaningful pattern –
call to follow, the demand of a future. (IP 77) the ‘‘durable dimensions’’ of a sense – gradually
emerges, but this pattern remains open to
While in classical phenomenology the constitu- alteration, not only by future developments but
tion of sense is the work of intentional conscious- also by the pressure of past moments which retain
ness (such that the sense of the other, for their kinship with the present and future. When
example, arises within consciousness as the Merleau-Ponty says that originary time is ‘‘on
result of its own apperception, pairing and so time, the time that it is,’’ I take him to be saying,
forth), in Merleau-Ponty’s late lecture notes the contra Heidegger, that time is not ecstatic, that
institution of sense establishes the ‘‘durable the present is not merely an ‘‘Augenblick’’
dimensions’’ of a field within which both self between future and past, anticipation and repeti-
and other (to continue the same example) emerge tion. Rather, time spreads itself out like a tissue
in relation to each other. This field is not a static or field through which all moments are related
set of parameters, but rather a pattern which and may cross-fertilize one another in patterned,
is both repeatable and open to modifications, but also in unexpected, ways. Time is now;

26
guenther

its dynamism does not depend on a leap into is instituted through the temporal rhythms
the abyss, but rather on the fecundity of of genetic signals which spatialize their growth.
interconnections which hollow out a place for In this sense, we could say that the body is made
the emergence of both the familiar and the new. of space and time; its material structures emerge
Each emergence has the potential to make the in response to processes of temporalization and
entire past light up differently; near-forgotten spatialization regulated by the patterned circula-
elements may be brought forward to contribute to tion of genetic messages. Moreover, it is not
a sense which never existed before. This is not merely the content of these messages, but their
to say that time is a free-for-all, but rather elimination from certain domains and restriction
that there is a plasticity of originary time which to others, that makes possible the growth of a leg
both linear and ecstatic accounts of time fail in the appropriate place (Morris 82). Both
to grasp. the direction of embryonic development and the
The sense of time emerges for Merleau-Ponty burgeoning sense of the organism rely on spatio-
through transverse connections which gather and temporal processes whereby being is neither
repeat particulars in partially new, partially old localized in advance nor produced all at once.
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

ways. This approach to time suggests interesting Morris comments:


implications for our understanding of embryolo-
gical development, and in particular embryologi- [I]t is because there are intensive differences
cal sexuation. As an embryo develops in the of place and time, it is because being is not
womb, it gradually transforms from a fertilized all one that being is generative of
egg into a cluster of cells, and eventually into an sense . . . Being is not a plenum, it is emptied
out by intensive place and time differences;
organism with increasingly distinct and complex
but these differences, we must note, are not
structures. How and why does this development
even yet given as such, we must not think that
happen? Is the sense of the mature organism being is already emptied out, for this would
already contained in the fertilized egg cell, like a reduce negative differences to a positivity.
blueprint or a Platonic Form, such that it need (83–84)
only be unfolded or materialized? If so, then it
would hardly matter if the developing embryo Or, as Merleau-Ponty says in the Institution
were exposed to alcohol, cigarette smoke or Lectures:
radiation in the womb; we would not expect
contingent influences to alter the course of [T]he idea as field does not contain what will
be developed in it, and yet, the idea sends a
development. In his Nature: Course Notes,
teleology down a path. The development is not
Merleau-Ponty argues against the view that the
rectilinear, but its zig-zags are [a] develop-
sense of the organism is merely unpacked from a ment, for the rectilinear is Sinnentleerung,
ready-made ‘‘sack of possibles’’ (Nature 234), and the zig-zag resumes, reactivates in
suggesting rather that the organism develops a different way what has been founded.
in space and time through the elimination of (IP 98–99)
concrete alternatives (see Morris 71–75 for a more
detailed discussion). Or again, in a working note for The Visible and
In his discussion of Merleau-Ponty’s notes on the Invisible dated January 1960:
ontogenesis, David Morris explains that, while the
[T]he vortex of the embryogenesis suddenly
embryological growth of legs or antennae may be
centers itself upon the interior hollow it was
genetically prescribed, their precise locations do
preparing – A certain fundamental divergence,
not come already mapped out in extensive space; a certain constitutive dissonance emerges . . .
rather, these locations emerge gradually through It is in the universal structure ‘‘world’’ –
an overlapping of genetic signals which restrict encroachment of everything upon everything,
the growth of legs in one place and so allow it a being by promiscuity – that is found the
in another. The growth of legs does not merely reservoir whence proceeds this absolute new
happen ‘‘in’’ space and ‘‘in’’ time; rather, it life.11 (VI 233–34)

27
sexual difference

The unfolding of a new possibility, such as the continuum: females, ferms (female pseudoher-
possibility of growing legs, does not involve a maphrodites), herms, merms (male pseudoher-
simple transition from non-being to being, maphrodites) and males (‘‘Five Sexes’’).12 These
potential to actual, or plan to execution. Rather, terms do not refer to discrete ‘‘kinds’’ but rather
future events may open up new directions in to what we could now call, in the context of our
processes that are already underway, such that previous discussion of Merleau-Ponty, degrees
certain possibilities only appear as such in of mutual divergence. An organism with XY
retrospect, as details that have become significant chromosomes does not automatically become
only in light of later developments. The possibi- phenotypically male, as if determined in advance
lities of the organism, then, exist as much in by a genetic blueprint; rather, it develops in a
the past as in the present or future; any given male direction to a greater or lesser extent by
possibility is constantly modified by other limiting the possibilities inherent in its initial
emerging possibilities, which are in turn pluripotency. If a certain negativity is essential to
restricted by other processes of elimination and the process of embryonic growth – if restriction
restriction. and elimination condition the very possibility of
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

How might this approach to embryology as the growth, such that these possibilities are not
institution of a sense, or as a spatio-temporal merely unpacked ready-made from a sack,
process of possibilization within a field, affect but emerge in dynamic interrelation with past,
our understanding of the embryological develop- present and future events – then we might expect
ment of sex differences? Up until its sixth week to find a similar negativity also at work in the
of development, the human embryo does not yet process of sexual differentiation. When we
have sexually differentiated reproductive organs; consider the matter more closely, we find that
rather, it has what is called an ‘‘indifferent this negativity is even more complicated in the
gonad’’ with both proto-male (Wolffian) and case of sexual development. A leg may or may not
proto-female (Müllerian) ducts. At this point, the grow, and it may or may not grow in the usual
embryo’s sense – its meaning and its direction – place. But the process of human sexuation
remains open, pluripotent. Even if it has XX regularly produces at least two, and by some
chromosomes, and even if it is typical for an counts five or more, ways of being sexed, each of
embryo with XX chromosomes to develop which emerges in mutual divergence from the
ovaries, a uterus, a vagina, and so forth, a others, beginning from an ‘‘indifferent gonad’’
substantial increase in testosterone at this point with both proto-male and proto-female structures.
may orient the embryo towards the development The more determinate the sex of the embryo
of testes and/or a penis. As with the development becomes, the more it must eliminate other
of legs or antennae, chemical signals create directions for growth; sexuation entails a certain
certain possibilities for the organism by eliminat- loss for the individual organism, even for the
ing others; to the extent that sexuation is taken in hermaphrodite who develops both a penis and
one direction, the structures necessary for taking a vagina, for example, only by not developing a
the other direction wither away, and to the extent more extreme sexual determinacy in either
that neither direction is taken more than the direction. What is the sense of this loss, and
other, both sets of structures may develop to an what is its significance for sexual difference?
equal extent, eventually producing an infant body We could understand the loss of alternative
with a vagina and/or a penis, an ovary and/or directions as the blockage of a possibility that was
a testis, or a combined ovo-testis (see Fausto- not actualized, and has therefore ceased to be
Sterling, Myths of Gender 77–85, for a fuller possible. But this understanding would fall back
account of this process). into the ‘‘sack of possibles’’ theory of develop-
Given the range of different possibilities ment, reducing possibility to a potential presence
for human sexuation, Anne Fausto-Sterling that either remains in a state of non-being or
proposes a continuum model of sexual difference, exhausts itself in becoming actual. It would
identifying five points or clusters along this also commit the mistake of ontological localism,

28
guenther

as if the sense of sexual difference could be possibilities for the first time outside of myself, in
located in a single organism or in one of its parts. the bodies of others. This suggests that these
But if we want to understand sexual difference possibilities were never really lost, because they
phenomenologically, we cannot look to this or were never mine to begin with; they exist in the
that body or part, nor even to a collection of web of relationships between bodies who differ
bodies and parts. Rather, we must articulate the from one another within a field of mutual
field of being from which the sense of sexual divergence. This field forms the very texture of
difference emerges, and this means articulating our sexuate lives; it is not merely an abstract
the relations of mutual divergence which dis- ontological concept, but (also) the dimension
tribute sexual difference across differently sexed within which our sexed bodies make sense as
bodies through a temporalizing and spatializing nodes of possibility rather than fixed points
process that begins in the womb, but does not or destinations.
end there.13 Viewed from this perspective, the To translate this into the language that
loss of certain directions of sexual development Merleau-Ponty uses in The Visible and the
for one body does not extinguish the possibility Invisible, sexual difference forms a chiasm with
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

of different modes of sexuation, but rather intersubjectivity; the masculine–feminine relation


distributes this possibility across the field of not only mirrors the I–other relation, it forms a
intersubjective relations. I encounter the possibi- double relation of mutual implication with it.
lity of being sexed otherwise every day in my Sexuation makes sense across the terrain of
exchanges with parents, friends, sexual partners, intersubjectivity, where self and other encounter
colleagues, and even strangers who are sexed each other as ‘‘extreme divergences of one same
differently from me, and I also encounter it something’’ (VI 84), or as ‘‘the preferred variant
in those who have different ways of being the of a life that has never been my own’’ (VI 82 fn.
‘‘same’’ sex. The possibility of being sexed 14). Likewise, intersubjectivity makes sense not
otherwise, a possibility that was ‘‘mine’’ before merely in relation to the duality of masculine
I even had a sense of myself as consciousness, is and feminine, but in relation to the plurality of
not lost but rather encountered across a threshold mutually divergent sexuate forms, each of which
of intersubjective difference, or alterity. bears ‘‘the possible of the other’’ (VI 228). I insist
Where divergent forms are possible for an on plurality here, and not just a duality of man
organism, where it is not just a matter of having and woman, both in order to recognize the
or lacking certain parts, but of being differently, continuum of spontaneously occurring sexuate
the sense of this difference is not contained in any forms noted by Fausto-Sterling, and also in order
one being or form, but rather distributed across to emphasize the openness of sexed bodies to
the plurality of different beings who embody resignification and, in recent years, to re-sexua-
these forms.14 As with the seeing–seen relation, tion through surgical and hormonal therapies.
no single body can encapsulate the full sense of It is not merely the empirical occurrence of
sexual difference, since this sense is not deposited differently sexed bodies beyond the male–female
in the individual body, but rather distributed duality, but the political and cultural movements
across a range of different bodies whose develop- of intersex and transsexual communities reopen
ment takes different directions and produces the question of sexual difference, putting pres-
different sexuate forms. A zone of mutual sure on the presumed duality of sex.15 Like those
divergence and encroachment remains between contingent events in the development of an
these bodies, like a connective tissue or flesh organism that alter the sense of processes already
which both distinguishes bodies and orients them underway, contemporary intersex and transsexual
towards one another as the site of (their own movements create new possibilities for under-
eliminated possibilities for) sexual difference. standing the logic of sexual difference.16 In the
Precisely because there are others who embody specific context of this paper, these movements
the other forms in whose direction I could have, also open new ways of reading the texts of
but did not, develop, I discover my ‘‘lost’’ Merleau-Ponty, new possibilities provoked into

29
sexual difference

existence by emerging forms of sexuate identity and spatializing process which is both natural and
and community. historical, biological and ontological. And most
By approaching sexual difference in terms of importantly, it gives us a way of articulating the
intersubjectively distributed possibilities rather sense of sexual difference in terms of a possibility
than interlocking forms or types (as in Merleau- that does not extinguish itself in this or that
Ponty’s image of the two blocks of wood), we may actual form, but rather renews itself in our
grasp the temporality of sexual difference as both encounters with diverse others. Without shifting
a developmental process in which bodies become our attention from bodies or parts to the field of
sexed (and sometimes re-sexed) over time, and as being which generates their sense, we would miss
a social-historical process in which patterns the zone of mutual divergence and encroachment
of relation and exchange between sexed bodies which distinguishes the directionality of sexual
shift over time, altering the very sense of sexual development from a destination where the end is
difference. Sex is not destiny, not because already inscribed in the beginning. If sex were
nurture ultimately triumphs over nature, but destiny, then it would make perfect sense to read
because even in biological development, the sense back from the part to the whole, or from the end
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

of sexual difference emerges within a field of to the beginning, to understand being and
contingent intersubjective relationships, where becoming in terms of particular beings. But
each of us bears ‘‘the possible of the other’’ and given that each of us becomes who we are through
(re)discovers our own history of divergences a divergence from the possibility of the other(s),
in the bodies of others. Rather than opposing phenomenological reflection is required to dis-
nature to nurture, biology to culture, and so cern how these sexual differences are lived,
forth, we need to grasp the temporal processes by not just at an embryological level, but in a
which bodies materialize and become meaningful complex social and historical
in mutual divergence from one another. The world. Both the meaning and
patterns of exchange among variously sexed the direction, le sens, of our
bodies implicate each other in the possibility of sexuate lives are at stake in this
making sense of themselves and of others, in ways reflection.
that remain irreducible to a man–woman duality.
This possibility of making sense cannot be notes
actualized in the form of propositional statements
I would like to thank Bettina Bergo, David Morris,
because sense is generated from an open field
Noah Moss Brender and Shiloh Whitney for their
where patterns emerge through elimination and comments on a draft of this paper.
mutual divergence rather than through the
application of a rule or norm. For this reason, 1 See Levinas, Time and the Other and Totality
the sense of sexual difference cannot be articu- and Infinity.
lated in relation to types of bodies that either 2 ‘‘Do a psychoanalysis of Nature: it is the flesh,
embody or fail to embody a norm, nor even in the mother’’ (VI 267).
relation to a continuum of differences that would
3 Merleau-Ponty continues: ‘‘[T]he soul is the
again be structured around two ideal poles. hollow of the body, the body is the distension
Rather, we must take into account the way in of the soul’’ (VI 233). The relation between
which divergent forms of sexuation are distrib- body and soul ‘‘is to be understood as the
uted across an intersubjective field of different bond between the convex and the concave,
bodies, each with its own distinct but overlapping between the solid vault and the hollow it forms’’
history. (VI 231).
From this perspective, the trope of mutual 4 The encounter with an other is therefore an
divergence allows us to explain both the plurality ‘‘initiation to a symbolics and a typicality of others
of sexuate forms and their encroachment or of which the being for itself and the being for the
overlapping; it provides a non-oppositional logic other are reflective variants and not the essential
of difference as the effect of a temporalizing forms’’ (VI 82 fn.14).

30
guenther
5 Indeed, we could think of men and women as I have assumed that the ‘‘etc.’’ implies that feminin-
‘‘total parts’’ of humanity, where each expresses ity also implies masculinity, but the parallelism is
the totality of the human, but only in its partiality, clearly between I ^ other and masculine ^ feminine.
which in turn implies a reference to the other sex. The issues of sexual difference and temporality
SeeVI134, 216 ^17 for a discussion of ‘‘total parts.’’ raised by this biblical reference are so complex,
and yet so radically undeveloped in Merleau-
6 There may be a more generous way of reading
Ponty’s work, that I have bracketed them for the
this phrase in relation to Merleau-Ponty’s image of
purposes of this paper. I address these issues in a
a mutually defining surface between self and other.
different context in ‘‘Who Follows Whom?
This ‘‘surface of separation and of union . . . is the
Derrida, Animals and Women.’’
invisible hinge upon which my life and the life of
the others turn to rock into one another, the 9 Merleau-Ponty adds in the margin: ‘‘that which
inner framework of intersubjectivity’’ (VI 234). is and demands to be; it has to become what it is’’
But even this image implies a duality ^ self and (IP 80).
other, male and female ^ where the only
‘‘between’’ is the hinge of their mutual relation. 10 Merleau-Ponty explicitly compares institution
For this reason, its promise remains limited for to birth:
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

my project of opening up the logic of sexual differ-


[F]rom the moment of conception and still
ence to a plurality ^ unless the hinge is conceived
more after birth, there is an encroachment
as a zone of mutual divergence rather than a
towards a future which is made from itself,
simple point.
under certain given conditions, and which is
7 This image is reminiscent of Aristophanes’comic not the act of a Sinngebung. Birth [is not an
account of the genesis of sexual difference in act] of constitution but the institution of
Plato’s Symposium (189C^193d), where humans a future. Reciprocally, institution resides in
begin as double-sided beings who are then split the same genus of Being as birth and is not,
in half by Zeus, and so spend their whole lives any more than birth, an act. There will be
searching for the other half that will complete later decisionary institutions or contracts,
their wounded being. But to the extent that but they are to be understood on the basis
Merleau-Ponty grasps sexual difference in terms of birth and not the reverse. (IP 8)
of possibility rather than fixed forms, the encoun-
ter with the other need not be understood to fill From the perspective of institution, birth is the
in a gap in my own identity, because on the account emergence of someone to whom something can
of intersubjectivity I have given here there is no gap; happen; it is the opening of a future, not from
there is rather a hollow that makes determination nothing, but from a field of possibilities which is
possible, but does not seal off the possibilities itself shifting as some of these possibilities are
for further development in divergent directions. taken up and others left behind. The future of the
I elaborate this reading in the second section of one who is born encroaches; it is neither projected
this paper. nor mapped out in advance, but is made from the
one who is born and the situation into which s/he is
8 This interpretation is supported by another
born. Birth is an event, an emergence of the new
passing remark in The Visible and the Invisible: ‘‘The
from what was already there, but which will be
other is born from my side, by a sort of propaga-
altered in relation to that which is born.
tion by cuttings or by subdivisions, as the first
other, says Genesis, was made from a part of 11 See also Merleau-Ponty’s comments on
Adam’s body’’ (VI 59). Depending on whether one embryonic development in the chiasm chapter of
emphasizes ‘‘from my side’’ or ‘‘from a part of The Visible and the Invisible:
Adam’s body,’’ woman appears either as equal
or secondary. In any case, woman is aligned [A]s though, through all these channels,
with the other, and man/Adam with the self. all these prepared but unemployed circuits,
Note also the formulation of the passage the current that will traverse them was ren-
analyzed above: ‘‘The I^ other relation to be con- dered probable, in the long run inevitable:
ceived . . . as complementary roles one of which the current making of an embryo a newborn
cannot be occupied without the other being also: infant, of a visible a seer, and of a body a
masculinity implies femininity, etc.’’ (VI 220 ^21). mind, or at least a flesh. In spite of all our

31
sexual difference
substantialist ideas, the seer is being pre- 16 In the present paper, I do not have room to dis-
meditated in counterpoint in the embryonic cuss in detail the influence of trans and intersex
development; through a labour upon itself theory on my approach to sexual difference;
the visible body provides for the hollow a fuller discussion will be forthcoming in the next
whence a vision will come, inaugurates the stage of this project. For the time being, I can only
long maturation at whose term suddenly list the authors whose work has most influenced
it will see, that is, will be visible for itself, my thinking: Clare, Lane, Prosser, Salamon,
will institute the interminable gravitation, Shotwell, and Stone. For another component of
the indefatigable metamorphosis of the my own project, see ‘‘Other Fecundities.’’
seeing and the visible whose principle is
posed and which gets underway with the
first vision. What we are calling flesh,
this interiorly worked-over mass, has no bibliography
name in any philosophy . . . (VI147) Butler, Judith. ‘‘Sexual Difference as a Question
of Ethics: Alterities of the Flesh in Irigaray and
12 In ‘‘The Five Sexes, Revisited,’’ Fausto-Sterling
Merleau-Ponty.’’ Feminist Interpretations of Maurice
complicates this model of the continuum into a
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

Merleau-Ponty. Ed. Dorothea Olkowski and


multidimensional map which takes into account
Gail Weiss. University Park: Penn State UP, 2006.
differences at the chromosomal, hormonal,
107^26. Print.
and anatomical level, not to mention differences
in gender and sexuality. However, the concept Clare, Eli. Exile and Pride: Disability, Queerness, and
of sexual differences in degree rather than Liberation. Cambridge, MA: South End,1999. Print.
kind remains in this expanded version of the
model. Fausto-Sterling, Anne.‘‘The Five Sexes: Why Male
and Female Are Not Enough.’’ The Sciences 33.2
13 A second period of intense sexual development (1993): 20 ^24. Print.
occurs at puberty, and arguably continues
throughout adult life in more or less subtle Fausto-Sterling, Anne.‘‘The Five Sexes, Revisited.’’
ways. See IP 56 ^ 61 for a discussion of puberty. The Sciences 40.4 (2000):18 ^23. Print.
Transsexuals take up the possibility of diverging Fausto-Sterling, Anne. Myths of Gender: Biological
from one’s born sex through a combination of hor- Theories about Women and Men. New York: Basic,
mone therapy and sex reassignment surgery, both 1985. Print.
of which unfold over months and even years of
transitioning. See Prosser 99^134 for a discussion Guenther, Lisa. ‘‘Other Fecundities: Proust and
of the complex role that narrative plays in Irigaray on Sexual Difference.’’ Differences: A
this spatio-temporal process of changing sex. Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 21.2 (2010):
Needless to say, the transsexual does not merely 24 ^ 45. Print.
actualize the‘‘lost’’possibility of being sexed other- Guenther, Lisa. ‘‘Who Follows Whom? Derrida,
wise, thus canceling out the negativity involved Animals and Women.’’ Derrida Today 2.2 (2009):
in sexuation, but rather takes up this possibility 151^ 65. Print.
in a way that shifts the dynamics of the field,
underscoring the sense in which each body bears Husserl, Edmund. Cartesian Meditations: An
its own history of sexuation, and its own particular Introduction to Phenomenology. Trans. Dorion
relation to the modes of sexuation from which Cairns. New York: Springer,1997. Print.
it diverges.
Irigaray, Luce. ‘‘The Invisible of the Flesh: A
14 Arguably, this pertains not only to sexual Reading of Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the
difference but to other forms of embodied differ- Invisible, ‘The Intertwining ^ The Chiasm.’’’ An
ence, such as race and abilities. Ethics of Sexual Difference. Trans. Carolyn Burke
and Gillian C. Gill. London and New York:
15 See Laqueur for an historical account of shifts
Continuum, 2004.151^ 84. Print.
in biological accounts of sexual difference, from
the one-sex model of Aristotle and Galen to Lane, Riki.‘‘Trans as Bodily Becoming: Rethinking
the two-sex model of nineteenth- and twentieth- the Biological as Diversity, Not Dichotomy.’’
century biology. Hypatia 24.3 (2009): 136 ^57. Print.

32
guenther
Laqueur, Thomas. Making Sex: Body and Gender Stone, Alison. Luce Irigaray and the Philosophy
from the Greeks to Freud. Cambridge, MA: Harvard of Sexual Difference. Cambridge: Cambridge UP,
UP,1990. Print. 2006. Print.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Time and the Other. Trans.
Richard A. Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne UP, 1987.
Print.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on
Exteriority. Trans. Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne UP,1969. Print.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. ‘‘Dialogue and the
Perception of the Other.’’ The Prose of the World.
Trans. John O’Neill. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
UP,1973.131^ 46. Print.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Institution and Passivity:
Downloaded by [Lisa Guenther] at 07:54 09 August 2011

Course Notes from the Colle'ge de France (1954^1955).


[IP]. Trans. Leonard Lawlor and Heath Massey.
Evanston, IL: Northwestern UP, 2010. Print.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Nature: Course Notes
from the Colle'ge de France (1956^60). Trans. Robert
Vallier. Compiled and with notes by Dominique
Se¤glard. Evanston, IL: Northwestern UP, 2003.
Print.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice.‘‘The Philosopher and his
Shadow.’’ Signs. Trans. Richard C. McCleary.
Evanston,IL:Northwestern UP,1964.159^ 81.Print.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. The Visible and the
Invisible. [VI]. Trans. Alphonso Lingis. Evanston, IL:
Northwestern UP,1968. Print.
Morris, David. ‘‘The Time and Place of the
Organism: Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy in
Embryo.’’ Alter: Revue de phenomenology 16 (2008):
69^ 86. Print.
Plato ‘‘Symposium.’’ The Collected Dialogues of Plato.
Ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns.
Princeton: Princeton UP, 1961. 526 ^74. Print.
Prosser, Jay. Second Skins: The Body Narratives
of Transsexuality. New York: Columbia UP, 1998.
Print.
Salamon, Gayle. Assuming a Body: Transgender and
Rhetorics of Materiality. New York: Columbia UP,
2010. Print. Lisa Guenther
Shotwell, Alexis. ‘‘A Knowing that Resided
Department of Philosophy
in my Bones: Sensuous Embodiment and Vanderbilt University
Trans Social Movement.’’ Embodiment and Agency. 229 Furman Hall
Ed. Sue Campbell, Letitia Meynell and Nashville, TN 37240
Susan Sherwin. State College: Penn State UP, USA
2009. 58 ^75. Print. E-mail: lisa.guenther@vanderbilt.edu

You might also like