Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 29

DOI: 10.1111/nous.

12404

ARTICLE

The structure of analog representation

Andrew Y. Lee1 Joshua Myers2 Gabriel Oak Rabin3

1 University of Oslo
2 Abstract
New York University
3 New York University, Abu Dhabi
This paper develops a theory of analog representation.
We first argue that the mark of the analog is to be found
Correspondence in the nature of a representational system’s interpre-
Gabriel Oak Rabin, University of Oslo
Email: Gabriel.Oak.Rabin@gmail.com tation function, rather than in its vehicles or contents
Andrew Y. Lee, New York University alone. We then develop the rulebound structure theory
Email: andrew.yuan.lee@gmail.com
of analog representation, according to which analog sys-
Joshua Myers, New York University, Abu
Dhabi tems use interpretive rules that map syntactic structural
Email: joshualmyers@gmail.com features onto semantic structural features. The theory
involves three degree-theoretic measures that capture
Authors listed by alphabetical order of
surname. three independent ways in which a system can be more
or less analog. We explain how our theory improves
upon prior accounts of analog representation, provides
plausible diagnoses for novel challenge cases, extends
to hybrid systems that are partially analog and partially
symbolic, and accounts for some of the advantages and
disadvantages of representing analogically versus sym-
bolically.

1 INTRODUCTION

There is a commonly drawn distinction between analog and symbolic representation. Paradigms
of analog representation include mercury thermometers, hand-clocks, photographs, drawings,
line graphs, heat maps, and audio recordings. Paradigms of symbolic representation include dig-
ital thermometers, digital clocks, binary data, maritime signal flags, traffic lights, and words.
The distinction between the analog and the symbolic is appealed to across a diverse range of

This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs License, which permits
use and distribution in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited, the use is non-commercial and no modifications or
adaptations are made.
© 2022 The Authors. Noûs published by Wiley Periodicals LLC.

NOÛS. 2023;57:209–237. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/nous 209


14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
210 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

disciplines, both within philosophy and beyond.1 But while the difference between the analog
and the symbolic appears intuitive, there is a good deal of controversy over how to analyze the
distinction. What, exactly, is the mark of the analog?2
This paper develops what we call the rulebound structure theory of analog representation.
The central claim of the theory is that analog systems are those marked by the use of inter-
pretive rules that map syntactic structural features onto semantic structural features. Our
goal is to develop this idea into a systematic theory that yields plausible verdicts across a
spectrum of cases, including some novel cases that to our knowledge have never been dis-
cussed. We develop three degree-theoretic measures—analog mirroring, analog purity, and ana-
log mass—each of which captures a different way a system can be more or less analog. Along-
side these first-order claims, we also stake out a methodological position about where the
mark of the analog lies: namely, in the nature of a representational system’s interpretation
function.
The focus on structural features places the rulebound structure theory within the struc-
tural approach to analog representation. Theories within this approach can be thought of as
unified by the core idea that analog representation involves structure corresponding to struc-
ture. Other theories within the structural family include density theories (Goodman, 1968;
Haugeland, 1981; Schonbein, 2014), magnitude mirroring theories (Beck, 2019; Lewis, 1971;
Maley, 2011; Peacocke, 2019), and abstraction theories (Kulvicki, 2015). We will explain how
the rulebound structure theory handles a number of challenges facing these other views
and develops a more systematic analysis of what it means for structure to correspond to
structure.
§2 argues first that the mark of the analog lies in a system’s interpretation function (rather than
in its vehicles or contents), and then claims that interpretation functions are best thought of as
rules mapping inputs to outputs (rather than merely as sets of input-output pairs). §3 addresses
how the idea of isomorphism relates to analog representation and provides a basis for the develop-
ment of our positive theory. §4 and §5 contain the bulk of the rulebound structure theory, where
we develop three degree-theoretic measures of analogicity. §6 extends our theory to hybrid systems
that are partly analog and partly symbolic. §7 explains how our theory relates to and improves
upon extant theories of analog representation. §8 addresses objections. §9 discusses the advan-
tages and disadvantages of representing analogically versus symbolically.

2 FOUNDATIONS

We begin with some preliminary remarks on how to think about representational systems and
where to look for the mark of the analog.

1 References to analog representation occur in the philosophy of science (Papayannopoulos, 2020, Sterrett 2017, Trenholme

1994), philosophy of art (Goodman 1968, Lopes 2018, Thomson-Jones 2015), epistemology (Dretske 1981), philosophy of
perception (Beck 2019, Block forthcoming, Peacocke 1986), cognitive science (Dehaene 1997, Feigenson et al. 2002, Shagrir
2010), computer science (Siegelmann & Fishman 1998, Vergis et al. 1986, Xue 2016), and electrical engineering (Couch
2013).
2 The terms ‘iconic’, ‘pictorial’, and ‘imagistic’ are sometimes used instead of ‘analog’ and the terms ‘digital’ and ‘discursive’

are sometimes used instead of ‘symbolic’. Some (though certainly not all) uses of these terms aim at the same represen-
tational kind we seek to capture. We will remain neutral throughout the paper on any relationships between the analog,
the iconic, the pictorial, and the imagistic.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 211

2.1 The Interpretation Function

Every representational system has vehicles, contents, and an interpretation function. The vehi-
cles are the representers, the contents are the represented, and the interpretation function maps
vehicles to contents.3 Consider a digital clock (a paradigmatic symbolic system): the vehicles are
numeral displays, the contents are times of day, and the interpretation function maps ‘12:01′ to
one minute after noon. Or consider a mercury thermometer (a paradigmatic analog system): the
vehicles are thermometers individuated by mercury heights, the contents are temperatures, and
the interpretation function maps 6 cm of mercury to 30◦ C.
This paper is an investigation into what makes a representation analog. But first we must
ask: where should one look for the mark of the analog?4 The obvious options include looking
at a system’s vehicles, contents, or interpretation function. While methodological views about
where to look are rarely made explicit, vehicular rhetoric dominates the literature. For example,
Quilty-Dunn (2017: 61) states that “formats are general types of vehicular structures,” and Beck
(2019: 323) writes that he will “understand the thesis that perception is analog solely as a claim
about perception’s vehicles.” Others have favored alternative approaches: for example, Hauge-
land (1991) endorses a content approach and Goodman (1968) defends a hybrid vehicle-content
account.
We think that neither vehicle nor content approaches identify the true mark of analog repre-
sentation. As a preliminary argument, observe that it is possible for (1) the same contents to be
represented either analogically or symbolically and (2) the same vehicles to represent either ana-
logically or symbolically. To see the first dissociation, consider a digital clock versus a hand-clock.
Both systems represent times of day, so both have the same contents. But the digital clock is sym-
bolic while the hand-clock is analog. To see the second dissociation, consider a spy tapping on a
desk to send a message in Morse code versus a geologist tapping on a desk to describe a pattern of
seismic wave activity. Even if the two series of taps are indistinguishable, the spy’s taps represent
symbolically whereas the geologist’s taps represent analogically.5
Our view is that the mark of the analog is found in a system’s interpretation function, rather
than in its vehicles or contents alone. Call this the interpretation function approach.6 On this

3 We use the term ‘vehicles’ to refer to syntactically individuated vehicle types rather than vehicle tokens. A mercury
thermometer whose 6cm of mercury represents 30◦ C may be token-distinct but still type-identical to a second mercury
thermometer whose 6cm also represents 30◦ C. Note that syntactic types are usually more coarsely individuated than
physical types: even if the first thermometer contains one more atom of mercury than the second, that will probably not
suffice for a syntactic difference between the two.
4 Our talk of a search for the mark of the analog designates an investigation into the grounds, rather than the bearers, of
analogicity. We are primarily concerned with what makes something analog, rather than which entities bear the property
of being analog. Insofar as we have a view about bearers, we are inclined to think that the primary bearers of analogicity
are representational systems. But we also believe that one may permissibly talk of vehicles, contents, or interpretation
functions as being analog when they belong to a system that has what we take to be the mark of the analog: namely, the
use of rules that map syntactic structural features onto semantic structural features. Thanks to an anonymous referee for
helpful discussion of the grounds/bearers distinction.
5 One might seek to individuate vehicles in a way that permitted physically indistinguishable vehicles, such as the spy’s and

the geologist’s taps, to count as distinct kinds of vehicles. We will simply note that the examples preceding this footnote
are illustrative and preliminary. Our argument for the interpretation function, rather than vehicle or content, approach to
analog representation is largely supported by the usefulness of that methodology, which will be manifest over the course
of the paper.
6 Examples of interpretation function theorists include Barwise and Hammer (1996), Burge (2018), and Frigario, Giordani,

and Mari (2013), though they vary in the representational kinds targeted.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
212 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

view, analog representation is a matter of how vehicles represent contents, rather than what does
the representing or what is represented. As a corollary, analogicity is first and foremost a prop-
erty of representational systems (rather than individual representations). The examples above
of spies, geologists, and clocks are evidence in favor of the interpretation function approach.
Nevertheless, while our focus on the interpretation function is in some ways a departure from
prior vehicle (and content) approaches, this shift constitutes a less radical break from ortho-
doxy than it may initially appear. Many theorists who employ vehicular rhetoric clearly care
about interpretation functions. For example, Beck (2019: 334) argues that analogicity is a mat-
ter of vehicles covarying with contents, indicating he is committed to the interpretation func-
tion approach despite his aforementioned emphasis on vehicles. Given this, we think that the
interpretation function approach better captures what many theorists have had in mind all
along.

2.2 Rules

How are interpretation functions individuated? At minimum, any two interpretation functions
with distinct input-output pairs are not identical. The more interesting question is whether there
is more to the nature of an interpretation function than its inputs and outputs. In our view, inter-
pretation functions (and thus representational systems) are best individuated by how inputs are
mapped to outputs. In other words, we must look to the rules the system uses to map vehicles to
contents.
This idea can be illustrated via a debate from the history of mathematics about the nature of
mathematical functions: is a function any set of input-output pairs, or is it a rule for getting from
inputs to outputs?7 To illustrate, consider the following two functions:

𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝑥 2

𝑔 (𝑥) = (𝑥 2 + 3) (𝑥2 − 2) + (6 − 𝑥2 )

These functions yield the same output for any input, but they use different rules to move
from those inputs to those outputs. The prevailing convention in mathematics is extensionalist:
mathematical functions are individuated purely in terms of input-output pairings. But we think
that for the purpose of investigating representational systems, it is better to take a more fine-
grained intensionalist approach, where interpretation functions are individuated by the rules that
are used to map inputs to outputs.8 On this picture, every representational system has rules by
which it maps vehicles to contents, and even representational systems that have the exact same
input-output vehicle-content pairs can nevertheless be distinct in virtue of deploying different
rules.9

7 For example, Euler (1748) defined a function as a rule—an “analytic expression”—for generating outputs from inputs.

Schönfinkel (1924) was more liberal, permitting any arbitrary correspondence to count as a function as long as each input
generated only one output. For discussions of this debate, see Kleiner (2009) and Youschkevitch (1976).
8 The best example we know of a theory of analog representation that revolves around the rules of the interpretation
function is Frigario, Giordani, and Mari (2013).
9 Rules need not be systematic. For example, a brute assignment of each individual vehicle to its content still counts as a
rule. It is plausible that many symbolic systems rely on rules of this nature.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 213

To motivate the idea that the rules of the interpretation function matter when evaluating
whether a representational system is analog or symbolic, consider the following two systems:
__________________

Stipulated Population Map—Vehicles: 100 shades of red. Contents: 100 population densities.
Interpretation: Stipulated one-by-one assignment of shades of red to population densities.

Structural Population Map—Vehicles: 100 shades of red. Contents: 100 population densities.
Interpretation: If shade1 is darker than shade2 then the content of shade1 (a population density)
is denser than the content of shade2 .
__________________

These systems map all the same vehicles (inputs) to all the same contents (outputs), but they
do so using different rules. Stipulated Population Map assigns each red shade one-by-one to a
specific population density. Structural Population Map assigns contents using one simple rule:
“darker shades represent greater population density.” Even though the systems have identical
input-output structures, Stipulated Population Map seems symbolic while Structural Population
Map seems analog. We believe this felt difference corresponds to a real difference in represen-
tational kind.10 And we think the difference is best explained by the fact that the systems have
different interpretive rules. From this point forward, we will take as given that the nature of a
representational system depends not only on the input-output structure of a system, but also on
the rules that constitute its interpretation function.
We will remain largely neutral on the nature of rules. This is because we want our claims to be
compatible with a variety of views about the nature of interpretation functions and about repre-
sentation more generally. For example, rules need not be understood as linguistically expressible
sets of directions. Our use of the term ‘rules’ is intended merely to designate how an interpreta-
tion function maps vehicles to contents. Unless one is prepared to deny that there can be distinct
representational systems with the same inputs and outputs, and consequently deny that there
is any representationally relevant difference between Stipulated Population Map and Structural
Population Map, one is committed to the idea that interpretation functions have rules.
Our claims so far are as follows. When determining whether a representational system is ana-
log, one should look at the system’s interpretation function and not only at vehicles or contents.
Furthermore, one should look at the rules of the interpretation function. These claims are method-
ological, in the sense that they are claims about where to look for the mark of the analog rather
than claims about what to look for. §4 and §5 develop our positive theory of analog representation,
which explains what to look for.

3 ISOMORPHISM

The unifying theme behind the structural approach to analog representation is that analog rep-
resentation is a matter of structure corresponding to structure. For many readers, this idea will

10 For readers who are uncertain about our appeals to intuitions about which systems are more analog, we wish to empha-

size that this paper is not a conceptual analysis of the word ‘analog’ or the concept analog. Instead, we think there is
an important difference in representational kind between cases like Structural Population Map and Stipulated Population
Map, and we think the terms ‘analog’ and ‘symbolic’ work well for tracking this difference. When we say that one system
“seems more analog” than another, we seek to evoke the reader’s feeling for that difference. §7.3 discusses related issues.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
214 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

immediately evoke the notion of isomorphism. An isomorphism is, roughly put, a structure-
preserving bijective function. Though we do not think that isomorphism provides a satisfactory
criterion for analog representation, it will be useful to begin with a discussion of isomorphism
and develop our theory from that basis.
Although the term ‘isomorphism’ is common in the literature on analog representation, there
is a surprising lack of uniformity in what is meant by ‘isomorphism theory’.11 In some cases,
the intended idea is that a system is analog just in case there is an isomorphism between its
vehicles and its contents. We will argue shortly that such a claim is at best incomplete and
at worst false. In other cases, invocations of the term ‘isomorphism’ are simply intended to
express the general idea behind all structural approaches: that analog representation involves
similar structure between vehicles and contents. We think that such an idea is on the right
track. But a satisfying theory demands a more systematic analysis. This section aims to explain
more precisely what an isomorphism is, articulate what we take to be the best version of an
isomorphism theory of analog representation, and argue that such a theory is nevertheless
inadequate.
At first pass, it is natural to characterize the isomorphism theory as endorsing the following
criterion: a system is analog just in case there exists an isomorphism between its vehicles and
its contents. Consider how in Mercury Thermometer, there seems to be an isomorphism between
mercury heights and temperatures, whereas in the system for a digital thermometer, there does
not seem to be an isomorphism between numerals and temperatures. However, this criterion is
overly permissive. Consider the following systems:
__________________

Mercury Thermometer—Vehicles: 100 mercury heights. Contents: 100 temperatures. Interpre-


tation: If height1 is taller than height2 then the content of height1 (a temperature) is warmer than
the content of height2 .

Scrambled Thermometer—Vehicles: 100 mercury heights. Contents: 100 temperatures. Inter-


pretation: An unsystematic one-by-one bijective assignment of mercury heights to temperatures.
__________________

Mercury Thermometer and Scrambled Thermometer contain exactly the same vehicles
and exactly the same contents. Therefore, if there exists an isomorphism between the
vehicles and contents for Mercury Thermometer, then there also exists an isomorphism
between the vehicles and contents for Scrambled Thermometer. But Mercury Thermome-
ter is analog while Scrambled Thermometer is not. Therefore, whether there exists an iso-
morphism between vehicles and contents cannot be enough to decide whether a system is
analog.
A natural move at this point is to appeal to the fact that the systems map vehicles to contents dif-
ferently. More specifically, perhaps instead of asking whether there exists some function or other
that is an isomorphism between heights and temperatures, we should instead ask about a very spe-
cific function: the interpretation function.12 The interpretation function of Mercury Thermometer
always maps greater heights of mercury to warmer temperatures; the interpretation function of

11 SeeBeck (2015, 2019), Blachowicz (1997), Block (forthcoming), Frigario, Giordani, Mari (2013), Kulvicki (2015), Maley
(2011), and Shepard (1978). Haugeland (1991) calls the isomorphism account the “canonical account.”
12 The only extant account of analog representation we are aware of that requires that the interpretation function itself

must be an isomorphism is developed by Frigario, Giordani, and Mari (2013).


14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 215

Scrambled Thermometer does not. This strategy succeeds in delivering distinct verdicts on the
analogicity of Mercury Thermometer versus Scrambled Thermometer. However, the strategy works
only in cases where the two interpretation functions differ extensionally (i.e. with respect to which
inputs get mapped to which outputs). The following example illustrates how even systems with
extensionally equivalent interpretation functions can differ in analogicity (an idea already alluded
to in §2):

__________________

Lucky Scrambled Thermometer—Vehicles: 100 mercury heights. Contents: 100 temperatures.


Interpretation: A stipulative one-by-one bijective assignment of mercury heights to tempera-
tures, where by luck of the random assignment, each height happens to be assigned to the very
same temperature as in Mercury Thermometer.
__________________

If we consider only inputs and outputs, then the interpretation function of Mercury Ther-
mometer is indistinguishable from that of Lucky Scrambled Thermometer. But Lucky Scram-
bled Thermometer is intuitively not analog. This kind of problem arises for any view that
considers only the inputs and outputs of interpretation functions. Even when two systems
have interpretation functions with identical input-output structures, the way that they map
those inputs to outputs can matter for whether or not the systems are analog. In what fol-
lows, we explain how this idea—as well as the notion of isomorphism itself—can be made
precise.
Let a space be an ordered pair of a set of elements and a set of relations on those elements.13
Mercury heights paired with a taller-than relation is a space. Mercury heights paired with a twice-
the-height-of relation is another space. Let X = < DX , RX > and Y = < DY , RY > be spaces. A
function f from DX to DY is an isomorphism between X and Y just in case the following three
criteria are satisfied:

1. f is a bijection, meaning that f maps every element of DX to a unique element of DY and every
element of DY is the output f(x) for some x in DX .
2. RX and RY each contain at least one relation.
3. For every relation rX in RX , there is a relation rY in RY , such that for any elements x1 and x2 in
DX , rX (x1 , x2 ) if and only if rY (f(x1 ), f(x2 )), and for every rY in RY , there is an analogous rX in
RX .

The third criterion says that every relation in space X has a counterpart relation in space Y,
and every relation in Y has a counterpart in X, such that two elements of X bear that relation if
and only if their counterparts in Y bear the counterpart relation.14 If the third criterion is satis-
fied, then the function preserves the relevant relations. Note that while the function f is a func-
tion from the set DX to the set DY , f is an isomorphism between the space X and the space Y.
In total, there are three ways that there can be a failure of isomorphism: (1) if f is not a bijec-

13 The phrase “relations on those elements” requires that for each relation, some elements in the domain in fact bear that
relation.
14 These definitions are formulated in terms of binary relations, but they apply straightforwardly to relations of any adicity.

We assume the generalized formulation moving forward.


14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
216 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

tion, (2) if the spaces contain no relations, or (3) if f does not preserve the relations on the
spaces.15
Strictly speaking, it does not make sense to talk about isomorphism simpliciter between a set of
vehicles and a set of contents: isomorphism is a relation between structured spaces, rather than a
relation between unstructured sets. This means that when speaking of isomorphism, it is impor-
tant to specify the relations (or spaces) with respect to which the isomorphism holds. Even if a
function f is an isomorphism between set D1 paired with relation r1 to D2 paired with r2 , f may
nevertheless fail to be an isomorphism between D1 and D2 paired with other relations. For exam-
ple, even though f(x) = ex is an isomorphism from the real numbers under addition to the positive
reals under multiplication, it is not an isomorphism from the real numbers under addition to
the positive reals under addition. Though this may initially strike some as a technical detail, the
point matters for developing a theory of analog representation. Theorists often make claims about
isomorphism that leave implicit which relations structure the spaces. This underspecification is
problematic: since the physical world is replete with relations, it is easy to find isomorphisms
between any two domains. Because of this, the claim that there exists an isomorphism between a
system’s vehicles and its contents is almost trivial. Moreover, even the more specific claim that the
interpretation function itself is an isomorphism between the set of vehicles and the set of contents
is incomplete: the relevant relations on the vehicles and the contents must also be specified.
We now turn to a crucial issue. Supposing that isomorphism is important for analog repre-
sentation, what are the relations with respect to which the isomorphism must hold? Different
structural approaches to analog representation will answer this question differently. Some will
say magnitude relations, others dense relations, and yet others abstraction relations. By contrast,
the rulebound structure theory says that the relevant relations are whichever figure into the rules
of the interpretation function. Every system has an interpretation function that maps vehicles to
contents via certain rules. Those rules take into consideration certain relations and not others.
For example, Mercury Thermometer has a rule that says that taller heights represent warmer tem-
peratures. More precisely, let a system’s rulebound relations be the relations that are codified by
the rules of its interpretation function. Taller-than is rulebound in Mercury Thermometer; redder-
than is not. On our view, the relations that matter for isomorphism are the system’s rulebound
relations. This approach suggests the following criterion for analog representation:

The Isomorphism Criterion: The system’s interpretation function is an isomorphism


between the syntactic space and the semantic space.

The syntactic space is the space consisting of all the vehicles of the system paired with all the
rulebound relations on those vehicles. The semantic space is the space consisting of all the con-
tents of the systems paired with the rulebound relations on those contents. In order to satisfy the
isomorphism criterion, a system must have an interpretation function that is a bijection, that cod-
ifies at least one relation, and that preserves the relation(s) that it codifies. This makes the above
isomorphism criterion much more substantial than the earlier criterion (that there exists some
isomorphism between vehicles and contents). Mercury Thermometer satisfies the isomorphism

15 A mathematical example of isomorphism might help precisify these ideas. f(x) = ex is an isomorphism between the real
numbers ℝ under addition and the positive real numbers ℝ+ under multiplication. In this case, the domains are the real
numbers and the positive real numbers and the relations are addition and multiplication (understood as triadic relations).
The first criterion is satisfied because ex is a bijection from ℝ to ℝ+ . The second criterion is satisfied because the equality
ex + y = ex × ey ensures relation preservation: x + y = z iff f(x) × f(y) = f(z). Therefore, the spaces are isomorphic.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 217

criterion because its interpretation function is an isomorphism between its syntactic and seman-
tic spaces: taller-than and warmer-than are rulebound and the interpretation function preserves
them. By contrast, neither Scrambled Thermometer nor Lucky Scrambled Thermometer satisfy the
isomorphism criterion because neither system has rulebound relations that can be preserved in
the first place. These observations indicate that the isomorphism criterion provides a more accu-
rate, substantive, and precise distinction between the analog and the symbolic than prior accounts
that appeal more casually to the notion of isomorphism.
Nevertheless, we still think that the isomorphism criterion is inadequate as a general theory
of analog representation. The basic problem is that systems that nearly satisfy the isomorphism
criterion can still be highly analog. Consider the following examples:

__________________

Scrambled Population Map—Vehicles: 100 shades of red. Contents: 100 population densities.
Interpretation: A stipulative bijective mapping between shades of red and population density,
with no correspondence between darkness of shade and density.

Almost Isomorphic Population Map—Vehicles: 100 shades of red. Contents: 100 population den-
sities. Interpretation: A systematic bijective mapping between shades of red and population
density, with darker shades corresponding to greater densities, except that the darkest shade is
mapped to the second densest population and the second darkest shade is mapped to the densest.
__________________

Scrambled Population Map maps shades of red to population densities arbitrarily. Almost
Isomorphic Population Map maps shades of red to population densities systematically, with
exceptions for the two darkest shades and densest populations. Neither of these systems
satisfies the isomorphism criterion, since neither function preserves the rulebound rela-
tions in the mapping from the syntactic to the semantic space. Yet it is intuitive that
Almost Isomorphic Population Map is more analog than Scrambled Population Map. Our
diagnosis is that the difference is due to the fact that Almost Isomorphic Population Map
nearly satisfies the isomorphism criterion whereas Scrambled Population Map does not come
close.
The core problem is that isomorphism is all-or-nothing, whereas analogicity comes in degrees.
Consequently, the isomorphism criterion—at least by itself—is inadequate for capturing the
degreed aspects of analog representation. Still, we think that appeals to isomorphism are on the
right track. If analog representation is a matter of structure corresponding to structure, then iso-
morphism is a promising start towards developing that idea. The preceding discussion sets the
stage for our positive theory, where we will define a degree-theoretic variant of the isomorphism
criterion that captures a core dimension of analogicity.
Before moving forward, it is worth making a point about the kinds of systems that will
serve as our examples.16 We will focus on systems whose rulebound relations range over

16 Two simplifying assumptions are worth mentioning. First, we assume free recombination, meaning that a vehicle (or
content) that takes a value along one parameter (e.g. size) can take any value along a different parameter (e.g. color). Free
recombination prohibits a system in which each vehicle has both a height and either a red, blue, or green color, yet a green
vehicle of 10cm is not well-formed, even though vehicles with every other height and color combination are. Second, we
assume comparability, meaning that every pair of vehicles (or contents) is related by each relation. Comparability prohibits
a situation in which two vehicles are incommensurable along a parameter (e.g. size). Going forward, we assume that the
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
218 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

whole vehicles and whole contents (e.g. Mercury Thermometer’s taller-than relation), rather
than on systems whose rulebound relations range over parts of vehicles or parts of contents
(e.g. a photograph’s darker-than relation between individual pixels). We focus on the former
kinds of systems both because they are simpler and because we think the canonical exam-
ples of analog representation mostly fall within that class. However, our measures of analogic-
ity also apply to systems within the latter category. Our measures appeal to rulebound rela-
tions, and each measure applies whether those relations relate wholes to wholes or parts to
parts.

4 MIRRORING

Our theory consists of three degree-theoretic measures of analogicity. This section focuses
on the first and most central measure: analog mirroring. To set the stage, consider
again Scrambled Population Map (which maps shades of red to population densities arbi-
trarily) and Almost Isomorphic Population Map (which maps shades of red to popula-
tion densities systematically except for a mismatch between the two darkest shades and
two densest populations). Neither of these systems satisfies the isomorphism criterion.
Yet Almost Isomorphic Population Map seems more analog than Scrambled Population
Map.
A natural explanation for the difference is that it is easy to whittle down Almost Isomorphic
Population Map into a system that satisfies isomorphism: all one needs to do is remove a sin-
gle element from the syntactic space (e.g. the darkest shade of red) and a single element from
the semantic space (e.g. the second densest population). By contrast, turning Scrambled Pop-
ulation Map into a system that satisfies isomorphism is either difficult or impossible. These
observations hint at the basic idea behind analog mirroring: by counting how many elements
(vehicles and contents) must be eliminated before isomorphism is achieved, analog mirroring
measures how close the system is to satisfying the isomorphism criterion. Because Almost Iso-
morphic Population Map can be made to satisfy the criterion by eliminating a single vehicle
and a single content, that system has a very high, but not quite maximal, degree of analog
mirroring.
Let us say that a representational system S– is a subsystem of a system S just in case the syntactic
and semantic spaces of S– are subspaces of the syntactic and semantic spaces of S. For example,
a subsystem of Mercury Thermometer would be a system whose syntactic space includes mercury
heights 1−90 (cutting out 91–100), whose semantic space includes temperatures 1−90 (cutting out
91–100), and which retains the taller-than and warmer-than relations on the remaining heights
and temperatures. Intuitively, we can think of a subsystem as the original system with some vehi-
cles and contents removed.
Almost every system that has rulebound relations but that does not itself satisfy the isomor-
phism criterion will nevertheless have multiple subsystems that do.17 Some of these subsystems
will be larger than others. Some (perhaps only one) such system will be maximal: it will be as big
as or bigger than any other subsystem that satisfies the isomorphism criterion. Almost Isomorphic

systems we target satisfy both free recombination and comparability (on their syntactic and semantic domains). Although
we think that some oddball systems do not obey these principles, we do not think that the price of the extra complications
in the main presentation of our theory are worth the benefit of accommodating these cases.
17 Why “almost every system”? Since the definition of a space requires that each relation be instantiated, systems in
which the elimination procedure results in a single vehicle or single content (or less) will have an analog mirroring
score of 0.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 219

Population Map has two such subsystems: (1) the subsystem that cuts the darkest shade of red
and the second densest population, and (2) the subsystem that cuts the second darkest shade and
the densest population. Call any maximal subsystem that satisfies the isomorphism criterion a
mirrored subsystem of the original system.
A system’s analog mirroring score is the ratio of the size of its mirrored subsystem(s) to the size
of the system itself.18

size of mirrored subsystem


𝐀𝐧𝐚𝐥𝐨𝐠 𝐌𝐢𝐫𝐫𝐨𝐫𝐢𝐧𝐠 =
size of system

Analog mirroring measures how much of the representational system satisfies isomorphism.
This definition has some attractive formal features. Every system will have a mirroring score
between 0 and 1. The maximum value—1—occurs when no elements need to be eliminated
because the original system itself already satisfies the isomorphism criterion. The minimum
value—0—occurs when no subsystem satisfies isomorphism. To get a mirroring score above zero,
a system’s interpretation function must codify some relations. When a system has no rulebound
relations, it automatically gets a mirroring score of 0.
This formalization yields intuitive verdicts across a variety of cases. Structural Population Map,
which maps darker shades of red to denser populations with no exceptions, has a mirroring score
of exactly 1. Since only two elements need to be eliminated from Almost Isomorphic Population
Map, the mirrored subsystem of Almost Isomorphic Population Map is nearly as large as the orig-
inal system. Consequently, Almost Isomorphic Population Map has a mirroring score of nearly 1.
By contrast, Scrambled Population Map has a mirroring score of 0, since none of its subsystems
satisfies isomorphism.
In effect, our analog mirroring measure is a degreed version of isomorphism. We suspect that
such a measure can be useful not only for our theory, but also for research outside of analog
representation.19

5 PURITY AND MASS

Analog mirroring is a more nuanced measure of analogicity than the isomorphism criterion. Yet
it is still not enough to fully capture the respects in which systems can be more or less ana-
log. This section develops our two other measures: analog purity and analog mass. For clarity
of exposition, we assume that the systems discussed in this section have maximum analog mir-
roring. This assumption is harmless: on our account, a system with non-maximum mirroring
inherits its purity and mass values from its mirrored subsystem, which has maximum mirror-
ing by definition. Mirroring may thus be thought of as the gatekeeper to the realm of the ana-
log: without at least some mirroring, a system has no purity or mass, because it has no mirrored
subsystem.

18 Insystems whose spaces contain a finite number of elements, it is natural to measure size in terms of cardinality. In
systems whose spaces contain an infinite number of elements, we suggest appealing to the Lebesgue measure. See Tao
(2011) for more discussion of measures.
19 As an example, Shea (2014: 140) notes that it would be useful to have a notion of “approximate isomorphism” in devel-

oping a theory of mental content. This is exactly what our mirroring measure delivers.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
220 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

5.1 Analog purity

Consider the following system:

__________________

City Populations: Vehicles: 10 letters of the alphabet, each coming in three different sizes—big,
medium, and small. Contents: Populations for 10 different cities. Interpretation: Each letter
represents a different city (‘A’ represents Athens, ‘B’ represents Beijing, and so on). The size of
the letter represents the approximate population of the city: a big letter represents “more than 10
million people,” a medium letter represents “between and 1 and 10 million people,” and a small
letter represents “less than 1 million people.”
__________________

City Populations has maximum analog mirroring, since its interpretation function is a bijection
that preserves the larger-than relation on vehicles via the has-greater-population-than relation on
contents. However, the system seems less than maximally analog. Here is our diagnosis of this
intuition: although City Populations’ interpretation function preserves all of the system’s struc-
ture, the system does not utilize much structure to begin with.
Analog purity aims to capture this further dimension of analogicity by measuring the degree
to which the system’s elements are structurally distinct from each other. More precisely, two ele-
ments are structurally distinct whenever they have different structural profiles, where two ele-
ments have the same structural profile just in case they bear exactly the same rulebound relations
to every other element of the system. In City Populations, big-‘A’ and big-‘B’ have the same struc-
tural profile (and hence are not structurally distinct). This is because big-‘A’ and big-‘B’ bear the
larger-than relation to exactly the same elements. By contrast, big-‘A’ and small-‘A’ have distinct
structural profiles (and hence are structurally distinct): small-‘A’ bears the larger-than relation to
no other letters whereas big-‘A’ bears the larger-than relation to every small and medium letter.
Let us say that two elements have distinct nominal profiles just in case they are representa-
tionally distinct despite having the same structural profile. In City Populations, nominal profiles
correspond to letter types. Although big-‘A’ and big-‘B’ have the same structural profile, they are
still representationally distinct: big-‘A’ represents Athens while big-‘B’ represents Beijing. To illus-
trate further, big-‘A’ and small-‘B’ have distinct nominal and distinct structural profiles (different
letter, different size), whereas small-‘A’ and ‘big-‘A’ have identical nominal but distinct structural
profiles (same letter, different size). The nominal profiles can be counted by taking the total num-
ber of elements in the space and dividing by the number of structural profiles.
The purity of a system is determined by comparing the number of structural and nominal pro-
files:

number of structural profiles


𝐀𝐧𝐚𝐥𝐨𝐠 𝐏𝐮𝐫𝐢𝐭𝐲 =
number of structural profiles + number of nominal profiles

Analog purity is designed to capture the degree to which a system’s elements are structurally
distinct from each other. A system has maximum purity exactly when, in each of the syntactic
and semantic domains, every element is structurally distinct from every other element. In such a
system, each element has a unique structural profile. The more a system diverges from this ideal,
the lower its purity. In systems that fall short of maximum purity, some elements have the same
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 221

structural profile but different nominal profiles. These are exactly the elements that diminish a
system’s purity score.20
Purity is a degree-theoretic measure of analogicity. Like mirroring, it has a maximum value:
1. This maximum occurs for all and only systems in which each element has a unique structural
profile. Purity also has a minimum value: 0. This minimum occurs in systems that have no rule-
bound relations and thus no structural profiles. This minimum value also occurs for any systems
that have zero mirroring, since purity is defined over a representational system’s mirrored subsys-
tem.
A technical point is worth mentioning here. Because the subsystems under consideration have
maximum analog mirroring, the syntactic and semantic space are guaranteed to mirror each other
perfectly. As a result, there will always be the same number of structural profiles for both the
syntactic space and the semantic space. In City Populations, the semantic structural profiles cor-
respond to (represented) populations, and the syntactic structural profiles correspond to letter
sizes. Whether we count syntactically or semantically, we get the result that City Populations has
a purity score of 3/13, since on the syntactic side there are 3 letter sizes and 10 letters while on the
semantic side there are 3 populations and 10 cities.21
The unifying theme of the structural approach is that analog representation is a matter of struc-
ture corresponding to structure. In City Populations, all of the system’s structure corresponds to
structure, and as a result the system has maximum mirroring. However, the system does not have
much structure in the first place: most of the differences between City Population’s elements are
nominal, rather than structural. In other words, little of the representational work done by City
Populations is the result of structure corresponding to structure. By contrast, in Mercury Ther-
mometer each element has a unique structural profile. The syntactic profiles are generated by
height of mercury and the semantic profiles by temperature. As a result, Mercury Thermometer
has no nominal profiles, so Mercury Thermometer has maximum purity. This illustrates how the
purity measure captures the fact that City Populations is less analog, in at least one respect, than
Mercury Thermometer, despite the fact that both have maximum mirroring.
We can also make useful comparisons between systems that have less than maximum purity.
For example, consider a variant on City Populations that uses 10 letters coming in 10 sizes (instead
of 3) to represent 10 cities of 10 different populations (instead of 3). This system has a greater
number of structural profiles than City Populations but the same number of nominal profiles.
As a result, City Populations has less purity (3/13) than the expanded system (10/20). This is the
intuitively correct result.

20 In the special case where every element of a system has a unique structural profile, we take the system to have zero

nominal profiles. There is perhaps a sense in which a maximally pure system, where every element has a unique structural
profile, contains a single “nominal profile.” However, counting nominal profiles in this way would fail to serve its main
role: namely, gauging “the extent to which the system contains distinct elements that have the same structural profile.” In
fact, no system would ever have maximum purity under this approach. Since we use the term ‘nominal profile’ to denote
those non-structural features that make for a representational difference between elements, we do not count trivial features
that all syntactic or semantic elements share, such as “is a letter”, as nominal.
21 If there could be systems with infinitely many structural profiles but finitely many nominal profiles, then such systems

would count as maximally pure given our definition (for such systems, the proportion of structural profiles to total profiles
is 1). Nevertheless, some readers may have the intuition that such systems ought not count as maximally pure. In our view,
such systems reveal a divergence between two equally good ways of measuring purity: namely, (1) by counting structural
and nominal profiles (which is the measure we have defined), and (2) by counting structural and nominal features (such
as letter or size). We focus only on the first formulation because doing so greatly simplifies the technical exposition with
little loss. However, for those concerned about the kinds of infinitary systems described above, the second formulation
provides a natural extension of our theory that accommodates the desired intuition.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
222 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

5.2 Analog mass

The following pair of examples motivates the need for a third measure—analog mass—alongside
analog mirroring and analog purity.

__________________

Sparse Heat Map—Vehicles: 10 colors ranging from pure red to pure blue. Contents: 10 temper-
atures ranging from 0◦ C to 100◦ C. Interpretation: Redder colors map to warmer temperatures,
bluer colors map to colder temperatures.

Rich Heat Map—Vehicles: 1000 colors ranging from pure red to pure blue. Contents: 1000 tem-
peratures ranging from 0◦ C to 100◦ C. Interpretation: Redder colors map to warmer tempera-
tures, bluer colors map to colder temperatures.
__________________

These systems map redder colors to warmer temperatures and bluer colors to colder temper-
atures. Sparse Heat Map uses 10 colors to represent 10 temperatures; Rich Heat Map uses 1000
colors to represent 1000 temperatures. Since the redder-than relation on colors corresponds to the
warmer-than relation on temperatures, both systems have maximum mirroring. Since each ele-
ment of each system has a unique structural profile, both systems have maximum purity. Yet even
though the systems have identical mirroring and purity scores, there remains a way in which Rich
Heat Map is more analog than Sparse Heat Map.
Here is our diagnosis. Mirroring and purity both provide proportional measures of how much
of the system’s representational work is done by structure representing structure. But degree of
analogicity is also a function of the absolute amount of representational work done by structure
representing structure. Analog mass captures this idea:

𝐀𝐧𝐚𝐥𝐨𝐠 𝐌𝐚𝐬𝐬 = number of structural profiles

Mass is simply the numerator of purity. It can be calculated as outlined in the previous section.
To return to our example: Sparse Heat Map has 10 structural profiles; Rich Heat Map has 1000.22
Because of this, although the two systems are equivalent with respect to their mirroring and purity
scores, Rich Heat Map has greater analog mass than Sparse Heat Map. The mass measure allows
us to capture the respect in which the 1000-color map is more analog than the 10-color map.
Note that unlike mirroring and purity, mass has no maximum: there is no limit to the number of
structural profiles that a system can have.

5.3 The rulebound structure theory

The unifying theme of the structural approach is that analog representation is a matter of structure
corresponding to structure. We have developed and precisified this intuitive idea into three mea-

22 There is a way of counting profiles where Sparse Heat Map has 20 structural profiles: 10 syntactic structural profiles (col-

ors) and 10 semantic structural profiles (temperatures). However, because analog mass (as well as analog purity) applies
only to mirrored subsystems, the numbers of structural and nominal profiles will always be identical between the syntactic
and semantic spaces. We count in the way that yields 10 structural profiles because we find it simpler. Since each method
of counting generates the same comparative rankings between systems, nothing turns on this choice.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 223

sures: analog mirroring, analog purity, and analog mass. Each measure captures a distinct way
in which a system can live up to that core slogan. In particular, analog mirroring measures the
extent to which structure corresponds to structure, analog purity measures the proportion of the
representational work done by structure corresponding to structure, and analog mass measures
the absolute amount of representational work done by structure corresponding to structure.
Some readers might have intuitions that our measures are unable to capture. In our view, there
are many measures that can track intuitions about relative analogicity. Rather than trying to cap-
ture all intuitions expressible using the phrase ‘more analog’, we have focused on what we take to
be three fundamental, general, and joint-carving measures. Other readers may wonder how our
measures combine to yield a total analogicity score. But we wish to resist the idea that there is
any objective fact of the matter about how to weigh these measures against one another. Our view
is that these measures identify distinct dimensions along which representational systems can be
more or less analog, each of which can vary independently of the others. Each of these principles
tracks different families of intuitions about degree of analogicity. Relatedly, our principal focus is
on generating the right comparisons as to which systems are more or less analog along the relevant
dimensions, rather than on the absolute numbers outputted by the measures.
While some discussions of analog representation take analogicity to come in degrees, others
characterize it as a binary property. Our focus has been on the degreed aspects of analogicity,
but we can extract several binary conceptions of analogicity from our degree-theoretic measures.
First, both analog mirroring and analog purity have a maximum value. We can say that a sys-
tem is perfectly analog just in case it has both maximum mirroring and maximum purity. Nearly
all paradigms of analog representation, including mercury thermometers, hand clocks, and pho-
tographs, are perfectly analog. Second, mirroring, purity, and mass all have a minimum value. We
can say that a system is perfectly symbolic when it has minimum (i.e. zero) mirroring, and thus
zero purity and mass. Conversely, when a system has non-zero mirroring, purity, and mass, it is
not perfectly symbolic, and is thus at least somewhat analog.23

6 HYBRID SYSTEMS

This section explains how our framework can be used to analyze hybrid systems, an often over-
looked class of representations. A hybrid system is a representational system that has some features
that represent analogically and some features that represent symbolically. As an example, consider
Colored Thermometer, in which a colored column represents both temperature and cloud cover:
__________________

Colored Thermometer—Vehicles: Colored columns coming in 3 colors and 100 heights. Con-
tents: Combinations of temperature and cloud coverage. Interpretation: Taller columns rep-
resent warmer temperatures. Blue represents clear skies, yellow represents partly cloudy, and red
represents overcast.
__________________

Theories of analog representation tend to either deliver the wrong results for hybrid systems (by
classifying them as analog or symbolic simpliciter) or do not suggest any obvious way of handling

23 These ways of extracting binary measures avoid imposing arbitrary thresholds on our degreed measures. We believe
these binary measures carve the relevant representational kinds in a principled and intuitively satisfying way. Nevertheless,
those who disagree could still use our measures but adopt a different threshold marking what is required for a system to
count as analog.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
224 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

them (because the theory is not explicit enough to deliver a verdict). In contrast, our mirroring,
purity, and mass measures yield plausible verdicts when applied to hybrid systems. First, Col-
ored Thermometer has maximum mirroring, since the interpretation function is an isomorphism
under the relations codified by the rules of the system (the taller-than and warmer-than relations).
Second, Colored Thermometer has the same degree of mass as Mercury Thermometer, since both
systems have the same number of structural profiles. But third, Colored Thermometer suffers with
respect to purity because it has nominal profiles (colors and cloud coverages) while Mercury Ther-
mometer does not. Consequently, our theory predicts that Colored Thermometer is less analog than
Mercury Thermometer.
We believe these verdicts are correct, but there remains a further explanandum. Colored Ther-
mometer seems to represent temperature analogically (via height) and cloud coverage symboli-
cally (via color). Since our measures track degrees of analogicity for whole systems, our theory
is not yet sensitive to the fact that some features of a system can represent analogically while
other features represent symbolically. However, there is a natural way of extending our theory to
accommodate this datum. To forecast: our theory will claim that the degree to which a feature
represents analogically is determined by the degree of analogicity of the partial system generated
by partitioning according to that feature.
We start by introducing the notion of a partial system. Informally, partial systems result from
abstracting away from some of the original system’s representational distinctions. For example,
one partial system of Colored Thermometer groups columns by height and ignores color. A partial
system of a representational system is generated by partitioning each of the syntactic and semantic
spaces in a manner that retains the interpretation function. A partition of any set is a division
of that set’s elements into subsets—called cells—such that every element occurs in exactly one
subset. A partition retains the interpretation function if and only if any two vehicles of the original
syntactic space occupy the same cell in the partitioned syntactic space just in case their contents
(in the original system) also occupy the same cell (in the partitioned semantic space). Partitioning
and retainment ensure that the resulting partial system is a “partial version” of the original whole.
The elements of the partial system’s syntactic and semantic spaces are sets of syntactic or seman-
tic elements of the original system. For example, the set containing a blue, yellow, and red column
of 10 cm height is one syntactic element of the “color ignoring” partial system of Colored Ther-
mometer mentioned above. In order to apply our measures to the partial system, we need to define
the relations that structure it. Let us say that two cells A and B of the partial system bear relation r
to each other just in case every element in A bears r to every element in B. This definition entails
that the set containing blue, yellow, and red columns of 10 cm height bears the taller-than relation
to the set containing blue, yellow, and red columns of 8 cm height. In other words, the relations
that structure the original system are “exported” in the straightforward way to the partial system.
Importantly, we can apply our measures of analog mirroring, purity, and mass to partial systems
so defined.
Every representational system has many partial systems. But the interesting partial systems are
those that correspond to what we would intuitively call the features of the system. Colored Ther-
mometer has two features: color and height. First, when the system is partitioned according to
color (ignoring height), the result is a partial system with only three syntactic elements—blue,
yellow, and red—and three semantic elements—clear skies, partly cloudy, and overcast. Because
there are no rulebound relations between these elements, our theory predicts that this partial sys-
tem has zero analogicity. Second, when the system is partitioned according to height (ignoring
color), the result is a partial system that has as many syntactic elements as there are syntactically
distinct heights. In this partial system, each syntactic cell contains three elements: a blue, a yellow,
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 225

and a red column of identical height. When we apply our measures, the partial system receives
maximum mirroring and maximum purity. In the terminology introduced earlier, the height par-
tial system is perfectly analog and the color partial system perfectly symbolic. This entails that in
Colored Thermometer, height represents analogically and color symbolically, which is exactly the
verdict a theory should deliver.
This approach to partial systems generalizes in straightforward ways. Recall City Populations,
the system we used to motivate the analog purity measure. This system has two features: let-
ter character (representing city) and letter size (representing population). The size partial sys-
tem has maximum purity (and is perfectly analog), since each of its cells corresponds to a
distinct structural profile (though the system still has relatively low mass). The letter partial
system is perfectly symbolic, since its cells do not stand in any rulebound relations to each
other.
This way of thinking about partial systems allows the rulebound structure theory to answer
not only the question “Which representational systems are analog and to what degree?” but
also “Which features within a given system represent analogically and to what degree?” Both
questions are important. Our theory’s ability to answer both is evidence of its power and
flexibility.

7 OTHER THEORIES OF ANALOG REPRESENTATION

This section reviews how the rulebound structure theory relates to several prominent theories of
analog representation.

7.1 Density

According to density theories, a representational system is analog exactly when it is syntactically


and semantically dense.24 In brief, a syntactically dense system is one in which between any two
syntactically well-formed vehicles there is a third, while a semantically dense system is one in
which between any two contents there is a third. In the ensuing discussion, we will simply grant
that the density theorist has a principled way of characterizing what it is for one element to lie
“between” two other elements.
While we think there is an important grain of truth in density theories, we believe that they
are extensionally inadequate. First, density theories are too exclusive. Many non-dense systems
are analog. Consider again Structural Population Map, where 100 red shades represent 100 pop-
ulation densities and darker shades indicate higher population density. This system has only 100
red shades, meaning that there are no syntactically distinct shades in between (say) red34 and
red35 ; intermediate densities cannot be represented. Although this system is neither syntacti-
cally nor semantically dense, it is nevertheless intuitively analog. The rulebound structure the-
ory counts Structural Population Map as having maximum mirroring and purity: the interpreta-
tion function is an isomorphism and every representational difference arises from a structural
difference.

24 A density theory could also rely on either syntactic density or semantic density alone. The canonical density theory,
Goodman (1968), requires both, so we operate with that conception. The arguments we offer against such a theory gener-
alize easily to other density accounts. See Schonbein (2014) for a syntactic density account.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
226 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

Second, density accounts are too inclusive. They incorrectly count certain systems as analog.
Consider Scrambled Population Map:

__________________

Scrambled Population Map—Vehicles: Infinitely many shades of red. Contents: Infinitely many
population densities. Interpretation: Each shade of red is arbitrarily mapped to a different pop-
ulation density so that there is a non-structure-preserving bijection between shades of red and
population densities.
__________________

Suppose that the set of red shades is dense. Because each shade represents a different popula-
tion density, Scrambled Population Map is syntactically and semantically dense. But the mapping
between shades and population densities is completely arbitrary; no relation between population
density can be read off the relations between red shades. Therefore, density accounts incorrectly
count Scrambled Population Map as analog. By contrast, the rulebound structure theory provides
a diagnosis for why the system is not analog: in particular, the system fails to achieve even a low
degree of analog mirroring.
Though we have argued that density accounts are extensionally inadequate, we think that den-
sity accounts still track an important truth. In order for a dense system to be interpretable, it must
be analog in our sense. That is, dense systems must have interpretation functions that preserve
structure. Imagine trying to interpret Scrambled Population Map. Perhaps you think you see red42 ,
but might that be red42.1 or even red42.01 ? Since the system’s interpretation function does not pre-
serve structure, there are no constraints on how the structure of the vehicles maps to the structure
of the contents. It may be that red42 represents 670 people/km2 , red42.1 represents 11 people/km2 ,
and red42.01 represents 927 people/km2 . Since you cannot be sure whether you are seeing red42 or
instead one of the infinitely many nearby shades, you could easily be radically wrong about the
content. By contrast, if the interpretation function did preserve structure, then nearby shades of
red would represent nearby population densities. In such a scenario, even if you were unsure of
the exact identity of a vehicle, you could still be relatively confident of the content. These obser-
vations indicate that mirroring secures the interpretability of dense systems. As a result, dense
systems will tend to be analog.25

7.2 Magnitude mirroring

According to magnitude mirroring theories, analog representation is a matter of magnitudes of


the vehicle mapping to magnitudes of the content.26 For example, Peacocke (2019: 52) writes that
“analogue representation is representation of magnitudes, by magnitudes.” Examples of magni-
tudes include length, mass, temperature, and duration. The defining feature of magnitudes is that

25 Thisis similar to a feature that Kulvicki (2015) highlights: namely, that abstractions over syntax correspond to abstrac-
tions over semantic values. We agree with Kulvicki that density is a symptom (rather than the source) of analogicity. But
we also think that Kulvicki’s explanation (in terms of abstraction) can likewise be explained by a more fundamental the-
ory of analog representation. See Kulvicki (2015: §2–3) for an insightful discussion of the connection between density,
abstraction, and interpretation.
26 Magnitude mirroring theories include Beck (2015, 2019), Block (forthcoming), Lewis (1971), Maley (2011), and Peacocke

(2019).
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 227

they come in greater and lesser extents. For example, a temperature of 6◦ C is greater than 2◦ C but
less than 7◦ C.
In our view, magnitude mirroring theories are on the right track but cast too narrow a net. To
begin, observe that analog representation need not involve magnitudes. Consider hue: it does not
make sense to say that x is greater than y with respect to hue, so hue is not a magnitude. But it
is obvious that systems in which hue values of the vehicle map to hue values of the content (e.g.
photographs) ought to count as analog. The magnitude theorist could respond that magnitudes
need not be linearly ordered. To some extent, this is a verbal question about the term ‘magnitude’.
However, magnitudes are standardly defined in metaphysics and the philosophy of science as
coming in lesser or greater extents. As examples, Helmholtz (1887: 17) says that “a magnitude
is a quality of objects that is amenable to ordering from smaller to greater,” Kyburg (1997: 381)
writes that magnitudes are the values of “quantity function[s]” and “reflect the structure of the
real [numbers],” and Lewis (2009: 206) defines magnitudes as “properties that admit of degree.”
More importantly, even if one permits magnitudes to lack linear ordering, existing magnitude
accounts do not explain how magnitude mirroring works in these cases. For example, Beck (2019:
334) says that analog representation involves “the representation of one magnitude by a second
magnitude such that the second magnitude has the function of increasing or decreasing with the
first.” These accounts do not generalize in any straightforward way to non-linearly ordered struc-
tures, since those kinds of systems do not yield a meaningful notion of increasing or decreasing. By
contrast, the rulebound structure theory of analog representation applies just as straightforwardly
to systems without magnitudes as it does to systems with magnitudes.27
Finally, magnitude mirroring theories are usually all-or-nothing: either magnitudes represent
magnitudes or not. However, we have presented a number of cases illustrating how analog rep-
resentation comes in degrees. In City Populations the size magnitude represents the population
magnitude. The magnitude mirroring theorist must say that this system is analog simpliciter. But
City Populations (in which letters represent cities) does not seem as analog as, say, Mercury Ther-
mometer. Our theory captures this difference by generating the result that while both systems
have maximum mirroring, City Populations has relatively low purity and mass.

7.3 Abstraction

According to abstraction theories, analog representation is a matter of abstractions over vehicles


corresponding to abstractions over contents (Kulvicki 2015). For example, these theories con-
tend that Mercury Thermometer is analog because abstractions over vehicles (e.g. mercury heights
between 5cm and 6cm) correspond to abstractions over contents (e.g. temperatures between 25◦ C
and 30◦ C).
Though we believe abstraction theories are on the right track, we also think they identify a
symptom, rather than the source, of analog representation. A theory of analog representation
ought to explain why analog systems enable abstractions; the fact that a system yields these
abstractions is unlikely to be a brute feature of that system. Our view is that these abstractions are
possible because of the nature of the interpretation functions of analog systems. We have argued

27 Beck (2019) argues that Weber’s Law is best explained by taking perception to involve magnitude mirroring, and that
this result is evidence that perception is analog. We are sympathetic to Beck’s arguments. Since the rulebound structure
theory takes magnitude mirroring to be one way for a system to be analog, we agree that evidence of magnitude mirroring
is evidence of analogicity.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
228 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

that analog systems have interpretation functions that preserve the structure induced by their
rulebound relations. For example, Mercury Thermometer’s interpretation function maps taller-
than to warmer-than. Because of this, abstractions over height correspond to abstractions over
temperature. In other words, our account identifies the underlying feature of analog systems that
grounds the core component of abstraction theories.
There are also extensional differences between our theory and the abstraction theory. On the
abstraction theory, a system is analog to the extent that it enables the relevant abstractions. On
the rulebound structure theory, a system is analog to the extent that its interpretive rules map
syntactic structural features onto semantic structural features. Rulebound structure preservation
entails abstractability, but abstractability does not entail rulebound structure preservation. Con-
sider again Stipulated Population Map, which has 100 red shades mapping to 100 population den-
sities such that darker shades represent greater densities. For this system, abstractions over color
correspond to abstractions over population. However, Stipulated Population Map is not analog
on our account because its interpretation function does not operate on any rulebound relations.
Instead, the interpretation function stipulatively maps each red shade, one by one, to a specific
population density. Because of the lack of rulebound relations, the system has zero mirroring, and
by consequence fails to satisfy our criteria for analog representation. This difference between the
abstraction theory and the rulebound structure theory is due to how each theory deals with the
interpretation function. For the abstraction theory, all that matters are the inputs and outputs of
the interpretation function. Because of this, the abstraction theory is not sensitive to any inten-
sional differences between interpretation functions. By contrast, the rulebound structure theory
looks “inside” the interpretation function. As a result, it can distinguish between (for example)
Stipulated Population Map and Structural Population Map, which map the same inputs to the
same outputs but which use different rules.
For those with residual feelings that Stipulated Population Map is analog, there is a straight-
forward way of explaining away that intuition: Stipulated Population Map has a feature—namely,
abstraction—that is often a symptom of genuine analog representation. Moreover, if one is pre-
sented with only the input-output structure of Stipulated Population Map, it is natural to assume
that the system has the rules of Structural Population Map. However, we think that once one rec-
ognizes the difference between Stipulated Population Map and Structural Population Map, there
is clearly a respect in which the former is symbolic and the latter analog.

7.4 Surveying the structural approach

All of the theories we have discussed—density theories, magnitude mirroring theories, abstrac-
tion theories, as well as our own rulebound structure theory—fall under what we have called the
“structural approach” to analog representation. The unifying theme of the approach is that analog
representation is a matter of structure corresponding to structure.28 Now that we have discussed

28 Although theories of structural representation do not target analog representation, they also frequently appeal to the idea

of structure corresponding to structure. For example, Shea (2014: 123] writes that structural representation occurs when
“a relation between representational vehicles represents a relation between the entities they represent.” (See also Ramsey
(2007: 77-92), Shagrir (2012), and Swoyer (1991)). However, even setting aside the fact that they aim at different targets,
structural representation theories remain importantly different from structural theories of analog representation. First,
structural representation requires that the relevant relations serve as inputs to further processing. By contrast, the rule-
bound structure theory requires only that the relations occur in the rules of the interpretation function. Other structural
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 229

each of these theories individually, it is worth making some general remarks about the structural
approach. Any structural theory should answer the following two questions:

Structure Question: What counts as structure?


Correspondence Question: What counts as structure corresponding to structure?

To answer the structure question, most theories within the structural approach appeal to a cer-
tain kind of structure: density theories appeal to dense structure, magnitude mirroring theories
appeal to magnitudinal structure, and abstraction theories appeal to abstractability structure. We
have argued that the mark of the analog does not lie with any particular kind of structure. Instead,
we have adopted a liberal approach, where any kind of rulebound structure can be used to rep-
resent analogically. We provided a story of where this structure comes from: namely, from the
rules of the interpretation function. On our picture, the structure of a representational system is
determined by the relations codified by its interpretive rules.
To answer the correspondence question, most theories appeal to the idea of structure “mir-
roring” structure, where the notion of mirroring is either left intuitive or cashed out in terms
of isomorphism. We have argued that simple isomorphism accounts fail because isomorphism
is all-or-nothing while analogicity comes in degrees. In response, we have developed a precise
degree-theoretic mirroring measure, which we believe captures an intuitive sense of mirroring.
Furthermore, we have argued for the surprising conclusion that even systems with perfect mir-
roring can be more or less analog. For example, the syntactic structure of City Populations max-
imally mirrors its semantic structure. Yet the system remains less than perfectly analog because
many of its features represent symbolically. This claim holds not only for the technical analog mir-
roring measure we have developed, but also for pre-theoretical conceptions of mirroring. In light
of this, we think that an adequate answer to the correspondence question should not only explain
what is meant by “structure corresponding to structure,” but also provide a way of measuring the
proportion of and absolute amount of representational work done by structure corresponding to
structure. This is exactly what our analog purity and analog mass measures do. To our knowledge,
no other theory of analog representation has clearly identified these other aspects of analogicity.
It is worth noting that our answers to the structure and correspondence questions are somewhat
separable. While we favor the view that any rulebound structure can contribute to analogicity, it
is possible to reject our intensionalist framework but endorse our degree-theoretic measures. For
example, one could accept that mirroring, purity, and mass provide good answers to the correspon-
dence question yet still think that only magnitudinal structure matters for analog representation.
Conversely, while we favor mirroring, purity, and mass as measures of what it is for structure to
correspond to structure, it is possible to reject our measures yet endorse our intensionalist frame-
work and our rulebound account of structure. For example, one could accept that any rulebound
structure can contribute to analogicity yet still favor an isomorphism account of correspondence.
These considerations show how the components of the rulebound structure theory are relatively
modular. We believe the complete package yields an intuitive and satisfying theory of analog rep-

theories of analog representation do not require even that much. Second, analog representation and structural repre-
sentation are extensionally different: mercury thermometers are paradigms of analog representation, but do not count
as structural representations at all (since users do not normally interpret mercury thermometers by processing relations
between pairs of mercury heights). Third, the vehicles of structural representation must be complex: “some of the proper
parts of the structure that does the representing must themselves be representations” (Shea 2014: 135). By contrast, analog
representations have no such complexity requirement.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
230 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

resentation. But given the modularity of our view, those who diverge from us on some issues can
still adopt other components of our theory.

8 OBJECTIONS

We now consider objections.

8.1 The Gruesome structure objection

Consider Gruesome Thermometer, which has the same vehicles and contents as Mercury Ther-
mometer, but which maps vehicles to contents in a seemingly random way, with no correspon-
dence between taller-than and warmer-than. Intuitively, Gruesome Thermometer is not analog.
Yet Gruesome Thermometer can be understood in a way that forces the rulebound structure the-
ory to give the system high mirroring, purity, and mass scores.
Suppose the interpretation function for Gruesome Thermometer operates on the schwarmer-
than relation, where 92◦ C is schwarmer-than 70◦ C, which is schwarmer-than 80◦ C, and so on.
The schwarmer-than relation is gerrymandered so as to generate the result that Gruesome Ther-
mometer has maximum mirroring, maximum purity, and high mass. This makes Gruesome Ther-
mometer come out just as analog, on all the measures, as the more familiar Mercury Thermome-
ter.29 More generally, the rulebound structure theory may seem to classify as analog any represen-
tational system whose interpretation function codifies and preserves gruesome structural rela-
tions, no matter how symbolic such a system seems. The objection is that this classification is
incorrect.
We will provide two potential responses to the gruesome structure objection. Which response
one favors will depend on prior metaphysical and metasemantic commitments. Since addressing
those commitments in detail would take us too far astray, we will simply articulate the responses
without taking a stance on which is better.
The first option adopts a naturalness constraint, which says that only natural rulebound rela-
tions count toward analogicity. The idea behind naturalness is that some relations (e.g. warmer-
than) carve nature at its joints whereas others (e.g. schwarmer-than) do not. Though there is
disagreement on the nature of naturalness, there is usually agreement on which properties are
(and are not) natural. Under this first option, even if gruesome relations like schwarmer-than
can be codified by interpretation functions, they do not make a system more analog. On such an
approach, analog representation is not merely a matter of structure corresponding to structure,
but rather a matter of natural structure corresponding to natural structure. This option yields the
verdict that Gruesome Thermometer is not analog at all.30

29 Readers might notice that Gruesome Thermometer is similar to our earlier example Scrambled Thermometer. These sys-

tems have the same input-output structure, but they differ in their rules: Gruesome Thermometer has gruesome rulebound
relations while Scrambled Thermometer has no rulebound relations at all.
30 SeeLewis (1983) and Dorr and Hawthorne (2013) on what naturalness is. See Lewis (1984) and Williams (2015) for the
use of naturalness as a metasemantic constraint. The idea that something like naturalness divides the analog from the
symbolic (or digital) is endorsed by Lewis (1971), and is also a theme in work on the distinction that appeals to the notions
of convention and natural correspondence (see Giardino and Greenberg (2015, §1.1)). On these approaches, analog (or
iconic) representation involves natural correspondence, while symbolic representation is wholly conventional.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 231

The second option accepts that Gruesome Thermometer is analog and appeals to a metaseman-
tic error theory to explain why such a system strikes us as less analog than natural systems. The
basic idea motivating this response is that Gruesome Thermometer is just as analog as Mercury
Thermometer, but merely seems less analog to us because of the kinds of relations we humans
happen to use to carve up reality. Even if any relations whatsoever can in principle be codified by
interpretation functions to yield analog representational systems, it is plausible that only analog
systems that map natural relations to natural relations are amenable to creation and interpre-
tation by humans. If humans were to create a system whose inputs and outputs were identical
to Gruesome Thermometer’s, such a system would use purely stipulative rules rather than system-
atic rules operating over gruesome relations. Because of this, there is a danger that one’s intuitions
about Gruesome Thermometer are really tracking features of Stipulated Gruesome Thermometer,
a system that our theory would classify as symbolic. On the other hand, if there were gruesome
aliens who perceived the world in terms of the schwarmer-than relation, then those aliens may
well find Gruesome Thermometer more analog than Mercury Thermometer.

8.2 The small systems objection

Consider the following system:

__________________

Arrows—Vehicles: Arrows placed on trail signs. Arrows come in three sizes: Long, Medium,
and Short. Contents: Distances. Interpretation: A long arrow represents “more than 1 km,”
a medium arrow “200-1000 m,” and a short arrow “less than 200 m.”
__________________

Arrows uses arrows placed on wooden signs along a walking path to indicate how far the walker
is from the next landmark. Longer arrows represent greater distances. The rulebound structure
theory gives Arrows maximum mirroring and purity (but low mass). However, a perfect score on
two out of three measures may strike the reader as overly generous for a system that does not seem
very analog at all. More generally, the small systems objection says that our theory incorrectly
counts small systems as highly analog.
First, we think it is somewhat misleading to say that Arrows is highly analog. Though Arrows
scores highly on two out of three measures, the fact that it scores extremely low on the third mea-
sure is significant for assessing intuitions about analogicity. In fact, we think that ordinary ascrip-
tions of analogicity typically require relatively high scores on all three measures. Since Arrows has
low mass, we would expect most people to judge Arrows to be not particularly analog.
Second, there is an alternative way of precisifying how the Arrows system works, and this alter-
native precisification may confound intuitions about analogicity. On the stipulative precisification,
Arrows’ interpretation function assigns the contents “more than 1 km,” “200-1000 m,” and “less
than 200 m” to the long, medium, and short arrows directly. On the structural precisification,
Arrows’ interpretation function relies on a longer-than relation between the arrow symbols. Only
on the second precisification does Arrows count as having maximum mirroring and purity.
In fact, if one were told only the inputs and outputs of Arrows, the stipulative interpretation
would be the most natural way to understand how Arrows works. If tasked with assigning the
three arrows to their contents, most would take the easy route and simply stipulate which arrow
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
232 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

has which content. The alternative method of inventing rules that relate length relations between
arrows to distance relations between paths is more convoluted for systems as simple as Arrows.
Imagine going on a hike and encountering the trail signs of the Arrows system. Typically, such trail
signs include a key that captures the system’s interpretation function. The key is overwhelmingly
likely to simply list each vehicle next to its content. This is evidence that small systems like Arrows
will, in general, tend to be symbolic, and not use interpretative rules that rely on structure.

8.3 The verbal dispute objection

What exactly turns on which theory of analog representation is true? To some readers, it may seem
that there are many ways of precisifying the notion of analog representation and that nothing
significant turns on which notion we adopt. Perhaps the rulebound structure theory targets one
representational kind, magnitude mirroring theories target another, density accounts yet another,
and so on.
While we agree that some disputes about analog representation may be partly verbal, we also
think that theorists of analog representation have a common target. After all, no philosophers of
analog representation take their claims to be stipulatively true. If developing a theory of analog
representation were a matter of stipulation, then it would make little sense to appeal to intu-
itions about cases. Instead, philosophers develop theories that purport to identify what they take
to be an interesting representational kind and to explain the nature of that kind. It is easy to see
that not all representational kinds are equally interesting: the category “representations that are
accurate on Tuesdays” is far less interesting than the category “representations that involve mag-
nitude mirroring,” which (in our view) is less interesting still than the category “representations
whose interpretation functions map rulebound structure to rulebound structure.” In appealing to
intuitions about cases, we have sought to evoke intuitions about joints between representational
kinds rather than intuitions about the extension of the English word ‘analog’. Our theorizing is
thus better thought of as conceptually engineering the notion of the analog, rather than as trying
to capture its ordinary usage.
Moreover, we think the rulebound structure theory does a better job of capturing the target
representational kind than other theories. In some cases, existing theories of analog represen-
tation classify as symbolic systems that seem fundamentally similar to the systems they classify
as analog. For example, density theories classify dense mercury thermometers as analog while
classifying Mercury Thermometer, which has only 100 contents, as symbolic. In other cases, exist-
ing theories leave open how to apply their account to challenge cases. For example, it is unob-
vious how to make magnitude theories work for dimensions that lack ordinal structure (such as
hue). Moreover, as far as we know, no prior discussion of analog representation explains how
to deal with the lucky scrambled systems and hybrid systems discussed earlier. By contrast, the
rulebound structure theory provides intuitive and satisfying verdicts on all of these issues. For
these reasons, we believe the rulebound structure theory to be a genuine improvement over extant
theories.
Further evidence for the substantivity of these disputes comes from the observation that which
of these theories is correct will have downstream implications for formal semantics. There is
a budding field concerned with the project of developing formal semantics for non-symbolic,
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 233

non-language-like representational systems.31 Providing a formal semantics requires providing


an interpretation function. The rulebound structure theory identifies what form a formal seman-
tics for analog systems should take. In particular, the formal semantic apparatus should con-
sist of a set of rules that map syntactic relations between vehicles to semantic relations between
contents.
Finally, a virtue of the rulebound structure theory is that it explains some of the costs and ben-
efits of using analog versus symbolic systems. We turn to this issue next.

9 FECUNDITY AND FLEXIBILITY

The rulebound structure theory explains the fact that analog systems are more fecund but less
flexible than their symbolic counterparts. A representational system is semantically fecund to the
extent that it has high expressive power relative to the complexity of its interpretation function.
In other words, fecund systems generate greater expressive bang for their interpretive buck. To
illustrate, contrast Structural Population Map, which uses 100 vehicles (shades of red) to represent
100 contents (population densities) with Inkblots:

__________________

Inkblots—Vehicles: 100 random inkblots. Contents: 100 types of fruit. Interpretation: 100
rules, each of which maps a particular inkblot to a particular fruit.
__________________

Both systems map the same number of vehicles to the same number of contents. However, while
Structural Population Map achieves this mapping largely through a single simple rule (darker
shades represent denser populations), Inkblots has as many rules as it has vehicles, mapping each
vehicle to its content one by one. This gives Structural Population Map greater fecundity than
Inkblots. Although both systems map the same number of vehicles to the same number of con-
tents, Structural Population Map does so more efficiently.
Let us say that two systems are counterparts just in case exactly the same contents are express-
ible in each. Analog systems are more fecund than their symbolic counterparts.32 This is evident
when we observe that analog representations exhibit two of the main symptoms of fecundity:
they are easy to learn and easy to create. To learn Inkblots, you must memorize the content of
each inkblot individually. Knowing the content of one inkblot gives you no purchase on the con-
tent of any other. By contrast, learning Structural Population Map is comparatively easy. Once you
learn the contents of a few colors and that darker shades of greater represent greater population
densities, you have basically learned the system. Furthermore, creating an analog system such
as Structural Population is easier than creating a symbolic system such as Inkblots.33 If you were
tasked with assigning 100 inkblots to 100 fruits while your philosophical nemesis was tasked with
assigning 100 shades of red to 100 population densities, your nemesis would finish first every time.

31 See Casati and Varzi (1999), Cohn (2014), Cumming, Greenberg, and Kelly (2017), and Greenberg (2018) for some exam-

ples.
32 We suspect that the restriction to counterpart systems is unnecessary for systems without complex representations
involving multiple parts.
33 In small systems with very few vehicles and contents, it may sometimes be easier to stipulate contents one-by-one rather

than lay down rules capable of handling hundreds of contents. Arrows from §8.2 illustrates this situation.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
234 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

The rulebound structure theory explains why analog systems are fecund: namely, because their
interpretive rules take advantage of the structure of their vehicles and contents. Analog systems
use structure as a resource to assign many contents in one fell swoop. A single simple rule (e.g.
“darker shades represent greater densities”) can do a large amount of interpretative work, generat-
ing many, perhaps infinitely many, contents. By contrast, the interpretation functions of symbolic
systems become increasingly complex as more vehicles and contents are added. The core reason
for the ease of learning and ease of creation of analog systems is fundamentally the same: shades
of red and populations have analogous structures that are easy to exploit for representational pur-
poses. The learners and creators of an analog system can take advantage of this pre-existing struc-
ture; the metasemantic scaffolding is already in place.
If analog systems have all of these benefits, why use symbolic systems at all? In spite of their
virtues, analog systems have a significant flaw: they are less semantically flexible than symbolic
systems. This lack of flexibility manifests in two ways. First, analog systems are less modular than
symbolic systems. Symbolic systems tend to use separate rules to map each vehicle to its content,
whereas the rules of analog systems map many vehicles to contents all at once. This makes the
alteration and addition of content assignments in analog systems more difficult than in symbolic
systems. In Inkblots, any particular content assignment can be modified without changing the
rest of the system, and it is simple to add a new inkblot to represent kumquat. By contrast, in
Structural Population Map, it is difficult to change a particular assignment of color to population
density without massively altering many other assignments, and the most straightforward way
of extending the system would be to simply tack an extra symbolic rule onto the analog system.
Second, analog systems are less general than symbolic systems, in that analog systems are limited
in what we can use them to represent. For analog representation to be possible, the represen-
tational target must have some exploitable structure in the first place, and some vehicles with
analogous structure must be available to do the representing. Symbolic representation imposes
no such requirements.34
Fecundity and flexibility provide insight into where we should or should not expect to
encounter analog representation. Even when appropriately structured subject matter and vehi-
cles are available, there may still be advantages to constructing a symbolic system. If one wants
a flexible system with modular rules, a symbolic system is preferable. On the other hand, if one
wants a system that is easy to create and learn, then analog representation will likely work best.
These considerations apply not only to whole systems, but also to particular features of systems.
Imagine a scenario in which representation along one parameter (such as spatial location) has
exploitable structure, and where the designers of the system do not expect their representational
needs to change. That parameter would be best represented analogically. But suppose there is also
a second parameter (such as type of building) that does not have easily exploitable structure, or
for which the designers expect there to be future modifications of the system (such as new types
of buildings). That second parameter is best represented symbolically.

10 CONCLUSION

We began this paper with the question, “What is the mark of the analog?” We explained where
to look for that mark—in interpretation functions—as well as what to look for—rules that map
structure to structure.

34 See Camp (2007) for a related discussion of the trade-offs between different types of representational systems.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 235

On our view, interpretation functions should be understood as sets of rules that map vehicles
to contents, and not simply as vehicle-content pairs. A system’s structure is provided by the rela-
tions codified in the rules of its interpretation function. Analog systems are those marked by the
use of interpretive rules that map syntactic structural features onto semantic structural features.
Since systems can do better or worse in mapping structure onto structure, analogicity comes in
degrees. Furthermore, systems can do better or worse in at least three different ways, correspond-
ing to the measures we have called mirroring, purity, and mass. Mirroring measures the extent to
which the system’s structure is preserved by its interpretation function; purity measures the pro-
portion of representational distinctions that are due to structure; and mass measures the amount
of representational distinctions due to structure.
We have illustrated how the rulebound structure theory applies in a range of cases and com-
pares to its main rivals. We think our theory does better on a variety of counts, including giv-
ing satisfying verdicts on systems that alternative theories misclassify. The rulebound structure
theory’s three degree-theoretic measures allow considerable flexibility in accounting for which
systems are (or are not) analog and to what extent. To our knowledge, these fine-grained compar-
isons between representational systems, including hybrid systems that are partially analog and
partially symbolic, are not captured by any extant theory of analog representation. We have also
responded to what we take to be the main objections to the rulebound structure theory and used
the theory to explain why analog systems are fecund but inflexible.
Analog systems are those that take advantage of a very basic representational resource: namely,
the system’s structure. That structure is provided by the rules of its interpretation function. We
have explained how these simple ideas yield a systematic theory with greater predictive accuracy
and explanatory scope than its rivals. As a result, we believe the rulebound structure theory pro-
vides a better—and not merely different—theory of analog representation.35

ORCID
Andrew Y. Lee https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1899-0511
Joshua Myers https://orcid.org/0000-0002-2803-1939
Gabriel Oak Rabin https://orcid.org/0000-0003-0239-5328

REFERENCES
Barwise, J., & Hammer, E. (1996). Diagrams and the concept of logical system. In G. Allwein & J. Barwise (Eds.),
Logical reasoning with diagrams. Oxford University Press.
Beck, J. (2015). Analogue magnitude representations: A philosophical introduction. British Journal for the Philoso-
phy of Science, 66 (4), 829–855.
Beck, J. (2019). Perception is analog: The argument from weber’s law. Journal of Philosophy, 116 (6), 319–349.
Blachowicz, J. (1997). Analog representation beyond mental imagery. Journal of Philosophy, 94 (2), 55–84.
Block, N. (forthcoming). The border between seeing and thinking. MIT Press.
Burge, T. (2018). Iconic representation: Maps, pictures, and perception. In W. Shyam & F. A. Dorio (Eds.), The map
and the territory: Exploring the foundations of science, thought and reality. pp. 79–100. Springer.
Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21 (1), 145–182.
Casati, R., & Varzi, A. (1999). Parts and places: The structure of spatial representation. MIT Press.
Cohn, N. (2014). The visual language of comics. Bloomsbury.

35 acknowledgments: We are grateful for helpful comments from Nikola Andonovski, Gabriel Greenberg, John Kul-
vicki, Tamar Weber, Assaf Weksler, two anonymous referees for Noûs, and audiences at Dartmouth College, Tel-Hai Col-
lege, UAE University Al Ain, the University of Grenoble Centre for Philosophy of Memory, and the 2019 meeting of the
Anglo-German Picture Theory Group.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
236 LEE, MYERS, and RABIN

Couch, L. (2013). Digital and analog communication systems (8th ed.). Pearson.
Cumming, S., Greenberg, G., & Kelly, R. (2017). Conventions of viewpoint coherence in film. Philosopher’s Imprint,
17.
Dorr, C., & Hawthorne, J. (2013). Naturalness. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics:
Volume 8 (pp. 1). Oxford University Press.
Dretske, F. I. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press.
Euler, L. (1748). Introductio in analysin infinitorum.
Feigenson, L., Carey, S., & Hauser, M. D. (2002). The representations underlying infants’ choice of more: object
files vs. analog magnitudes. Psychological Science, 13, 150–156.
Frigerio, A., Giordani, A., & Mari, L. (2013). On Representing information: A characterization of the analog/digital
distinction. Dialectica, 67 (4), 455–483.
Giardino and Greenberg (2015). Introduction: Varieties of iconicity. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6 (1), 1–25.
Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art. Bobbs-Merrill.
Greenberg, G. (2018). Content and target in pictorial representation. Ergo, 5.
Haugeland, J. (1981). Analog and analog. Philosophical Topics, 12, 213–225.
Haugeland, J. (1991). “Representational Genera” from Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind, ed.
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Helmholtz, H. (1887). Counting and measuring, C.L. Bryan (trans.), New Jersey: D. Van Nostrand, 1930.
Kleiner, I. (2009). Evolution of the function concept: A brief survey. In M. Anderson, V. Katz, R. Wilson (Eds.),
Who gave you the epsilon?: And other tales of mathematical history (pp. 14–26). MAA.
Kulvicki, John (2015). Analog Representation and the Parts Principle. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 64 (1),
165–180.
Kyburg, H. (1997). Quantities, magnitudes, and numbers. Philosophy of Science, 64 (3), 377–410.
Lewis, D. (1971). Analog and digital. Nous, 5, 321–327.
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61 (4), 343–377.
Lewis, D. (1984). Putnam’s paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62 (3), 221–236.
Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosoph-
ical naturalism (pp. 203–222). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lopes, D. M. (2016). In the eye of the beholder. In J. Dodd (Ed.), Art, mind, and narrative: Themes from the work of
peter goldie (pp. 223–340). Oxford.
Maley, C. J. (2011). Analog and digital, continuous and discrete. Philosophical Studies, 155 (1), 117–131.
Papayannopoulos, P. (2020). Computing and modelling: Analog vs. Analogue. Studies in History and Philosophy of
Science Part A, 83, 103–120.
Peacocke, C. (1986). The inaugural address: Analogue content. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 60 (1),
1–17.
Peacocke, C. (2019). The primacy of metaphysics. Oxford University Press.
Quilty-Dunn, J. (2016). Iconicity and the format of perception. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23 (3-4), 255–263.
Quilty-Dunn, J. (2017). Syntax and Semantics of Perceptual Representation. Ph.D. dissertation, The Graduate Cen-
ter, City University of New York.
Quilty-Dunn, J. (2019). Perceptual pluralism. Noûs.
Schonbein, W. (2014). Varieties of analog and digital representation. Minds and Machines, 24(4), 415–438.
Schönfinkel, M. (1924). On the building blocks of mathematical logic. Reprinted in van Heijenoort, J. [1967]. (1976).
From Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931 (3rd ed.). Harvard University Press.
Shagrir, O. (2010). Brains as analog-model computers. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41 (3),
271–279.
Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63 (3),
519–545.
Shea, N. (2014). Exploitable isomorphism and structural representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114
(2), 123–144.
Shepard, R. N. (1978). The mental image. American Psychologist, 33, 125–137.
Siegelmann, H. T., & Fishman, S. (1998). Analog computation with dynamical systems. Physica D: Non- linear
Phenomena, 120(1–2), 214–235.
14680068, 2023, 1, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12404 by Cochrane Romania, Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
LEE, MYERS, and RABIN 237

Sterrett, S. G. (2017). Experimentation on analogue models. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook
of model-based science (pp. 857–878). Springer International Publishing.
Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87 (3), 449–508.
Tao, T. (2011). An introduction to measure theory Vol. 126. Amer Mathematical Society.
Thomson-Jones, K. (2015). Philosophy of digital art. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Trenholme, R. (1994). Analog simulation. Philosophy of Science, 61 (1), 115–131.
Vergis, A., Steiglitz, K., & Dickinson, B. (1986). The complexity of analog computation, Mathematics and Computers
in Simulation, 28(2), 91–113.
Williams, J. R. G. (2015). Lewis on reference and eligibility. In B. Loewer & J. Schaffer (Eds.), A companion to david
lewis (pp. 367–382). Wiley-Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical investigations (PI) (4th ed.). P.M.S. Hacker and J. Schulte (eds. and trans.),
Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Xue, Y. (2016). Recent development in analog computation: A brief overview. Analog Integrated Circuits and Signal
Processing, 86(2), 181–187.
Youschkevitch, A. P. (1976). The concept of function up to the middle of the 19th century. Archive for History of
Exact Sciences, 16(1), 37–85.

How to cite this article: Lee, A. Y., Myers, J., & Rabin, G. (2023). The structure of analog
representation. Noûs, 57, 209–237. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12404

You might also like