Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497


https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-022-06345-3

RESEARCH ARTICLE

Motivation(s) from control: responseÿeffect


contingency and confrmation of sensorimotor predictions
reinforce different levels of selection

Eitan Hemed1 · Noam Karsh1,2 · Ilya MarkÿTavger1 · Baruch Eitam1

Received: 6 March 2021 / Accepted: 4 March 2022 / Published online: 22 March 2022
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany, part of Springer Nature 2022

Abstract
Humans and other animals live in dynamic environments. To reliably manipulate the environment and attain their goals they
would benefit from a constant modification of engine-responding based on responses' current effect on the current
environment. It is argued that this is exactly what is achieved by a mechanism that reinforces responses which have led to
accurate sensorimotor predictions. We further show that evaluations of a response's effectiveness can occur simultaneously,
driven by at least two different processes, each relying on different statistical properties of the feedback and affecting a
different level of responding. Specifically, we show the continuous effect of (a) a sensorimotor process sensitive only to the
conditional probability of effects given that the agent acted on the environment (ie, action-effects) and of (b) a more abstract
judgment or inference that is also sensitive to the conditional probabilities of occurrence of feedback given in the action by
the agent (ie, inaction-effects). The latter process seems to guide action selection (eg, should I act?) while the former the
manner of the action's execution. This study is the first to show that different evaluation processes of a response's
effectiveness infuence different levels of responding.

Keywords Sense of agency · Reward · Motivation · Action effectiveness

Introduction 1965). Consistent with this claim, some have argued that
executing control over the environment is itself reinforcing
Notwithstanding substantial scientific attention, how humans (Eitam et al. 2013; Higgins 2011, 2019; Hull 1943; Wen
establish a Sense of Agency (SOA)—whether detecting 2019; White 1959), possibly through similar neural path
which events were affected by their actions (Chambon and ways as “actual” tangible rewards (Redgrave et al. 2008;
Haggard 2013) or predicting which events will be so affected Redgrave and Gurney 2006).
(Gozli 2019) is an open question with multiple implications . Empirical work has accumulated to show that responses
An accurate SOA allows us to predict and evaluate the that lead to predictable, value-free perceptual changes (ie,
consequences of our actions and to behave in an effective action-effects) are reinforced, both in human infants as
manner to achieve our goals (eg, grabbing a piece of choco young as 2 months old (Hauf et al. 2004; Watanabe and
late). Reinforcing behavior that effectively controls the envi Taga 2006 , 2011; Zaadnoordijk et al. 2018, 2016) and
ronment, regardless of any desirable outcomes, can serve adults (Bakbani-Elkayam et al. 2019; Eder et al. 2017; Eitam et al.
as a strategy for maintaining a biological advantage (Skinner 2013; Hemed et al. 2019; Karsh and Eitam 2015a; Karsh et
al. 2016, 2020; Penton et al. 2018; Tanaka et al. 2021).
Given that previous work strongly suggests that SOA,
Communicated by Melvyn A. Goodale. indicating control over the environment might serve as a
reinforcer, the current work moves beyond to determine
* Eitan Hemed
what is the statistical evidence by which this process
Eitan.Hemed@gmail.com
determines when to reinforce a response.
1
Department of Psychology, University of Haifa, Haifa, Israel Note that unpacking the function by which this process
two

Department of Psychology, Academic College of Tel-Hai, operates is uniquely important to our basic understanding
Qiryat Shemona, Israel of reward processes. This is because that differing from

Vol.:(0123456789) 1 3
Machine Translated by Google

1472 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

other primary reinforcers, reinforcement from effectiveness Unlike sensorimotor driven SOA, conceptually driven
is solely computational. What we mean is that unlike any SOA has not been associated with a single mechanism.
other known primary reinforces, it lacks any robust hedonic Given this, a reasonable assumption is that judgments of
or experiential aspect such as sweetness, sexual pleasure, own agency are similar to other subjective judgments of
or pain (cf., Haggard 2005). This lack of a hedonic causality; or more generally, of whether events co-occur
component accompanied by reinforcing capacities is, among (Gozli 2019; Wegner and Wheatley 1999).
other things, strong evidence for the dissociation between
reinforcing and hedonic experience. Judgments of causality and coÿoccurrence

The statistics of reinforcement from effectiveness The co-occurrence of events has been termed contingency,
and describes the difference between the conditional prob
A model that explains how effective actions are reinforced, ability of an event (E; eg, reward) given a condition (R; eg,
must first account for how the brain, mind, or person rec instrumental response) and the conditional probability of
ognizes that an action is effective in changing the that event barring the condition("Contingency"; APA
environment and which of these can be shown to lead to reinforce dictionary, VandenBos 2007). Contingency in this sense
ment. Most modern accounts of the SOA state that there ranges between perfect positive contingency (1; when the
are two distinct (although possibly interconnected) types of reward appears only following the response) and perfect
SOA—conceptual and sensorimotor (also known as explicit negative contingency (ÿ1; when the reward is given only in
and implicit, or judgment of Agency vs. feeling of agency; the absence of the response). One of the term's main
Moore et al. 2009b; Saito et 2015 ; Synofzik et al. 2008; applications in psychological science is in the study of the
Wen and Haggard 2020; Wen et al. 2015; for a recent review effect of contingency on behavior and judgments of causality.
see Wen 2019). For example, the ÿP rule ('Delta-P'; [P(E|R) ÿ P(E| E|
The sensorimotor SOA is assumed to be generated by ¬R)]; Rescorla 1967). In the context of instrumental behavior,
an internal model that relies solely on sensorimotor input positive values of Delta-P describe a positive association
('Comparator'; Blakemore et al. 1998; Carruthers 2012; between a response and reward, were found to lead to
Haggard and Eitam 2015; Wolpert et al. 1995). Arguably, higher response frequencies while smaller (negative) values
the following sequence is activated once a motor program of Delta-P led to reduced response frequencies. This pattern
is produced: a forward model predicts the action's effect on has been established for non-human animals responding to
the environment and then a comparator component gain food or water (eg, Hammond 1980) and for humans
compares the sensorimotor prediction to the perceived responding to secondary reinforcers (eg, monetary gains;
action-effect. If the comparison yields little to no prediction Liljeholm et al. 2011; Shanks and Dickinson 1991; Vallée
error, agency over the specifc action effect is felt or judged. Tourangeau et al. 2005) .
It should be kept in mind that the 'comparator' itself only Even more pertinent to our current case is that the value
provides a sensory prediction error following an action. The of Delta-P has been found to correlate with judgments of
comparator itself does not entail knowledge about the causality (including self-causality; Liljeholm et al. 2011;
control an action gives one over the environment. However, O'Callaghan et al. 2019; Shanks and Dickinson 1991; Vaghi
as we elaborate below, this sensorimotor prediction can et al. 2019; Van Hamme and Wasserman 1994; Wasserman
serve in the evaluation of the effectiveness of an action—and drive its 1983)
et al. reinforcement.
and action-selection or operant learning (Elsner
Regardless of how the comparator can be used to and Hommel 2004; Hammond 1980; Liljeholm et al. 2011;
estimate control, in recent years doubts emerged regarding Shanks and Dickinson 1991).
the sensorimotor modularity of the comparator, or at least Given the above, Delta-P seems to be a very reasonable
about the sensorimotor modularity of the measures candidate for capturing the functional relationship between
hypothesized, sometimes tacitly, to be driven by its working environmental events and people's conceptual judgments
such as intention tional binding (Haggard et al. 2002) and of SOA or effectiveness (Moore et al. 2009a). These
sensory attenuation (Blakemore et al. 1998). These doubts judgments, as was shown for desired outcomes, should
are driven by multiple demonstrations that these behavioral affect action selection (frequency of responding) if SOA
measures are biased by high-level knowledge and cognitions indeed is reinforcing on that level of response selection.
that should not be available to the Comparator (Aarts et al. Another important outcome of utilizing Delta-P as a func
2012; Barlas and Obhi 2014; Berberian et al. 2012; Buehner tional description of the conceptual SOA is that it also leads
2015; Chris tensen et al., 2019; Desantis et al., 2011, 2012; Dogge
to anet interesting
al. prediction of dissociation between the
2012; Gentsch et al. 2015; Haering and Kiesel 2012; Lynn statistics that underlie the conceptual and sensorimotor SOA's.
et al. 2014; Moore et al. 2009a, b; Pfster et al. 2014; Preston Specifically, committing to the above functional relation
and Newport 2010; Takahata et al. 2012). constrains the candidate algorithms (or mental mechanisms)

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1473

and effectively rules out the operation of a sensorimotor key. Pending experimental condition, responses to
mechanism such as the comparator described above (De imperative cues lead to either no visual change, to a value-
Houwer and Moors 2015). This is because the comparator's free action-effects, or a similar yet lagged action effect. In
prediction-efect-comparison sequence described above is that study, the responses of participants in the immediate
initiated if and only if a motor-program is sent to production action effect condition were the quickest, while participants
(ie, a forward model). As this does not occur in the case of in the no-feedback or lagged action-effect conditions were
inaction such a mechanism is incapable of tallying per (equally) slower. Although response speed was highest with
ceptual changes that follow inaction as it does not generate immediate action-effects, there was no difference in accuracy
a prediction when no engine program is sent to production between immediate, lagged or no action-effects conditions.
(for more on inactions, see the “General discussion ” ). Thus, It is important to keep in mind that both participated pants in
the functional relationship between the environmental input the immediate and lagged action-efects conditions receive
and sensorimotor SOA must be different. performance feedback (as they must respond cor rectly to
As we elaborate below, based both on our own work receive action-efects), still lagged action-efects resulted in
(Eitam et al. 2013; Hemed et al. 2020; Karsh and Eitam response speed that was as slow as that of the no-feedback
2015a; Karsh et al. 2016, 2020) and others' previous work condition. This comes to show that the facility
(Penton et al. 2018; Tanaka et al. 2021; Watanabe and Taga tation in response speed displayed in the task is not due to
2011) we argue that only the sensorimotor predictability of receiving performance feedback. In addition, another
the efects infuences the sensorimotor SOA. experiment in the above study had participants under all
More formally, in terms of contingency, if it indeed relies conditions also view a score counter, showing a sum that
on an eference copy the functional relationship between increased with correct responses; yet only participants that
sensorimotor SOA and the environmental input should fol received imme diate action-effects were faster to respond.
low the strength of the conditional probability of the occur Reaction time facilitation due to neutral own-action 'effects'
rence of an effect only given a motor response (ie, a was recently replicated by our group (Karsh et al. 2016;
sensorimotor prediction) or P(E|R). Consequently, the Experiment 1a) as well as others (Tanaka et al. 2021).
reinforcing effects of sensorimotor driven SOA, if such exist, Further studies provided additional evidence that the
should follow only P(E|R) and not contingency or Delta-P facilitation of response speed due to immediate action effects
(which is [P(E|R)ÿP(E|¬R)]) . does not depend on performance feedback, but most likely
While our previous conceptual and empirical work strongly on sensorimotor SOA driving reinforcement of actions. In
suggests that sensorimotor SOA is modular and hence these studies (Karsh et al. 2016, Experiments 2a–2b),
should infuence (reinforce) mostly the execution of motor participants performed the same task, but the location of the
programs and not the selection of actions; as another model action-effect was either spatially predictable or spatially
of SOA suggests that sensorimotor SOA may infu ence the unpredictable, surrounding the imperative cue.
more abstract level of action selection by indirectly affecting Spatially unpredictable action-effects led to response times
the postdictive or conceptual SOA (Synofzik et al. 2008) or that were as slow as those on the no action-effects condi
by some other phenomenal hedonic feeding experience into tion. This again shows that performance feedback is not
the conceptual SOA (eg, ' fuency'; Chambon and Haggard what facilitates response time in the task, as participants
2012). receiving spatially perturbed action-effects had to press the
The current study was designed to empirically test correct key to receive the action-effects, but they were still
whether the contribution of the different sources of SOA to slower compared to the participants in the spatially predictable condition .
response selection and execution can be dissociated based A replication of the above comparison between spatially
on the above functional relationships. predictable and unpredictable action-effects was recently
obtained (Hemed et al. 2020).
The current study Finally, additional evidence ruling out the possibility that
response time change in our task is due to performance feed
In the current study, participants performed a task previously back comes from a different task. In this task, participants
shown to reliably capture reinforcement from effectiveness viewed an imperative cue at the center of the screen and
on reaction time (presumably due to sensorimotor SOA; were required to pick a key at random on each trial, such
Hemed et al. 2019 ; Karsh et al. 2016) which we modified to that there are no correct or incorrect responses. Still,
also capture the potential effect of reinforcement on response response time decreased if responding to the cue resulted
frequency. The task is a variant of a choice reaction-time in immedi ate action-effects, compared with lagged or no
task introduced by Eitam and colleagues (Eitam et al. 2013), action-effect (Karsh and Eitam 2015a; Karsh et al. 2016, Experiment 1b).
where participants' viewed on each trial an imperative cue Given these findings, it is very likely that the facilitation
and were asked to respond with the spatially-mapped in response time in the task used here is due to

13
Machine Translated by Google

1474 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

changes in sensorimotor SOA, as found in previous studies The study consists of fve experiments that test the same
utilizing implicit measures of agency for spatial and temporal hypotheses using different experimental designs. To facilitate
perturbation (eg, Barlas and Kopp 2018). itate understanding of the findings, the pattern of results
Findings from explicit reports and judgments of agency across experiments is also depicted as a forest plot (see
from our previous studies also support the argument that Fig. 7, “General discussion”).
changes in response time comes from changes in
sensorimotor SOA (Eitam et al. 2013; Karsh et al. 2016).
In conditions in which the action-effects are lagged or Try 1
spatially-perturbed participants' subjective judgments of
agency (ie, conceptual SOA) are the same whether receiving Methods
immediate, spatially predictable or lagged action-effects.
Relatedly, participants usually maintain similar levels of Participants
response frequency regardless of temporal action-effect
delay (in a free-choice rather than cued task; Karsh and We recruited 65 students from Tel-Hai Academic College,
Eitam 2015a). The latter shows that conceptual SOA as to participate for either course credit or ~ 6$. 68% of them
termed above, might be mostly insensitive to spacial and were female, ages 19–33 (M=24.89, SD=2.39).
temporal features of feedback, when judging cau sality on Previous studies (Eitam et al. 2013; Karsh et al. 2016,
the person or deliberate-level. It should be noted that while 2020) found that contingent, immediate action-effects lead
delays could reduce response frequency (Karsh et al. 2021), to the facilitation of response speed compared with a
it is not fully clear how delays actually impact conceptual condition in which responses are never followed by action-
SOA (Wen 2019; see “General discussion”). effects. The most basic finding comes from a two-samples t-
Such a dissociation fts the differentiation between a test comparing the no action-effects condition and the
conceptual vs. sensorimotor SOA as well as their differential immediate action effects condition (Bakbani-Elkayam et al. 2019; Eitam et
infuence on levels of the response selection and execution 2013; Karsh et al. 2016, 2020). The standardized effect size
process. In the current study, we focus on this dissociation. for this comparison ranged between Cohen's d of 0.5 and
1.2, we estimate the population standardized effect size at
To systematically test this ostensibly different sensitivity 0.8. Yet here differing from previous studies, participants
we manipulated the presence of action-effects and inaction were instructed to select at random whether to respond or
effects (ie, effects occurring in the absence of a preceding not on each trial. Thus, due to the novelty of the task, no
action), using either a free operant procedure (Experiments power analysis was conducted before the collection of the
1 and 2a–2b) or a cued Go /No-Go task (Experiments 3a–3b). data, as this experiment served as sort of a pilot for the current study.
Given the above we predicted the following: Experiment 1 included four conditions. However, in terms
of power, we refer only to the two conditions that are most
(a) action-effects trigger the sequence that generates a similar to those from previous studies. In the current study,
sensorimotor SOA and consequently credits (ie, rein these are the action-effects present, inaction-effects present
forces) the effective motor-programs. (b) This form of condition and the action-effects absent, inaction-effects
reinforcement is argued to operate on a non-conceptual absent condition. Given that and with roughly 15 partici
level; therefore, (b1) it will be sensitive to the conditional pants per group (given random assignment), we had a
probability P(E|R) rather than to Delta-P, that also statistical post hoc power (1ÿÿ) of~0.7 for detecting a
involves P(E|¬R) and (b2) as this form of SOA credits Cohen's d of~0.8. Such an effect-size is consistent with
a specifc engine program it will affect only the very those found in previous studies. However, we should note
specific manner of execution here measured as that we did not opt for an effect size that is based on an
response speed and not the 'volitional aspects' of the ANOVA, for several reasons. First, previous comparisons
response (Brass and Haggard 2008), here measured between the two conditions described above (action-effects
as response frequency. (c) A conceptual, regularity- vs. no-action effects), provide us with a benchmark for pair-
detecting, mechanism of SOA will consider both action and wise comparisons between the action-effects present,
inaction-effects and hence inaction-effects absent condition and all others. Second,
will be captured by Delta-P. The conceptual mecha ANOVAs performed in previous studies were irrelevant as
nism is argued to be detached from the motor-system they were performed as a one-way analysis of differences in
(Wen and Haggard 2020; but see Synofzik et al. 2008), response time between several experimental conditions (eg,
so it can modulate actions through inputting to action immediate action effects, action-effects with short or long
selection processes—the “whether and what to do” temporal lags and no-action effects; Eitam et al. 2013). This
measured here as response frequency. sort of evidence would be meaningless as for a two-way analysis with an

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1475

Fig. 1 Method and predictions. A The four conditions and the feedback vs. orange and gray bars) but will not be affected by whether inaction-
scheme they received. B A depiction of an exemplary trial (dashed line not effects are present or absent (green and orange vs. blue and gray bars). In
shown to the participant and is included for illustration only). C The visual contrast, response frequency (left plot) is predicted to be facilitated by the
appearance of trials with no effects (left panel) or with action-/inaction- presence of action-effects compared with their absence (green and blue vs.
effects (right panel). D Idealized predicted pattern of results. We predict that orange and gray bars) and reduced by the presence of inaction-effects
response speed (left plot) will be facilitated by the presence of action-effects (green and orange vs. . blue and gray bars)
(green and blue

interaction. Finally, predicting a specific effect size based on the screen for 950 ms (the response window; see Fig.
on an ANOVA would be uninformative when testing the 1B and C), followed by an ITI of 1150 ms, and only then
difference between the baseline condition and the absent, the next cue appeared (on previous studies a response
inaction-effects present condition. Unrelated to the window of 850 ms and an ITI of 700 ms was used, similar
discussion above, we had no prediction about the effect to Experiments 2–3 in the current study). Participants were
size of the differences in response frequency, given the instructed to voluntarily decide whether to respond to the
lack of previous evidence. cue or with hold their response when the cue appeared,
and to take care to respond on 70% of the trials. No
design and task feedback was given to the participants about their actual
response frequency during the experiment. The instructions
Throughout the study, we manipulated the presence and did not mention the possibility of action- or inaction-effects
absence of action-efects and inaction-efects, yielding four at any point on any of the experiments.
experimental conditions (see Fig. 1A)—(a) action-efects Participants in the two action-effects present conditions
present, inaction-efects present, (b) action-efects present , received feedback if they responded correctly during the
inaction-effects absent, (c) action-effects absent, inaction response window. For subjects in the inaction-effects
efects present and (d) (a) action-effects absent, inaction present conditions, there was an 80% chance of receiving
efects absent. In Experiment 1, participants were randomly feedback if they did not respond. A correct response meant
assigned to one of these experimental conditions, pressing the spatially mapped key, either 'S', 'D', 'K' or
manipulated between subjects. 'L' (eg, 'S' and 'K' for the depictions in Fig. 1B and C, respectively) .
The task used was a four-alternative choice reaction Only the frst response was recorded, so participants were
time task, where on each trial an imperative cue appeared not able to correct their response if they frst responded
in one of four locations (with a 0.25 probability for the cue using an incorrect key. Feedback of consisting of the cue
to appear in any of the four locations). The cue moved down turning white for 100 ms and vanishing for the remainder of the

13
Machine Translated by Google

1476 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

response window (a 'fash'). Regardless of response time repeated on both fltered and unfltered data see Supplemen
and whether feedback was given or not, the duration of the tary Materials.
response window and ITI were kept constant. Trials were No-Response trials (18.71% of raw data; trials with no
deemed as No-Response trials if no response (either correct response or a response that is slower than the random time
or incorrect) was detected until a timepoint late in the point described above) were not analyzed. Response trials
response window (randomly sampled from a uniform were further labeled as valid or invalid based on several
distribution between 600 and 700 ms from cue onset). There criteria. A total of six outliers (±2SD) participants, in either
was no special alert (eg, error message) given an incorrect Response-Frequency (three participants, 4.6%) or Response
response, late, or no response. Based on our experience Time (four participants, ~ 6.2%) were filtered out (9.23% of
with the task, we predicted that very few trials will be slower N=65) . Out of the remaining subjects (90.77% of raw data),
than 600 ms—the typical mean RT in the task is within 400– incorrect responses (~ 3.6%; not the correct key was
500 ms with a standard deviation of 30–60 ms (Eitam et al. pressed), fast responses (0.02%; below 200 ms), and slow
2013 ; Karsh et al. 2016). responses (4.27%; above 700 ms) were also fltered out. All
filtration of invalid Response trials resulted in the loss of
16.25% of the raw data.
Procedure and apparatus

Participants signed an informed consent form, entered a data analyzes


soundproof dimly lit room, and were asked to decide on each
trial whether to respond or withhold their response while We defned response speed as the mean response time (RT)
maintaining a 70% response frequency across the experiment. elapsing from the presentation of the imperative cue until a
They were further instructed that if they do choose to respond keypress and response frequency (RF) as the percentage tri
then they should do as quickly and accurately as possible. als in which the participant responded (rather than with
They performed ten practice trials (during which the holding her response or responding later than the timepoint
experimenter gave verbal feedback on their performance) described above) out of the total number of experimental
followed by 240 task trials. The experiment ended with a self- block trials. For testing our two main hypotheses, we ran a
report questionnaire, followed by a demographics queries between-subject 2×2 ANOVA—action-effects (present,
and debriefng. absent) × inaction-effects (present, absent). We ran the
The experiment was programmed in PsychoPy 2 v.1.84 ANOVA for predicting RT and RF, separately. As post hoc
(Peirce 2007). Stimuli were presented on a Samsung tests we compared the action-effects present, inaction-effects
Syncmaster 943BM monitor with the refresh rate set to 60 Hz. absent condition to all other between-subject conditions. We
Responses were collected with a standard PC keyboard. selected this condition as the baseline for comparison given
previous studies used a variation of the same task. Due to
unequal variances (here and on Experiment 3a), the inde
Results pendent-samples t test was corrected using the Welch–Sat
terthwaite correction for degrees of freedom. The 95% CI for
Data were pre-processed with Stata (StataCorp 2015). the Cohen's d reported on the t tests were calculated using
Statistical analyzes were carried out in R through RPy2 the 'efsize' R package (Torchiano and Torchiano 2020), for
(Gau tier 2021, 2018), mainly using afex (Singmann et al. the between-subject and within-subject designs as
2015) and BayesFactor (Morey et al. 2018). Plots were recommended by Cohen (1988) and Gibbons et al . (1993),
generated using Python's Seaborn (Waskom 2018). respectively. Additionally, the frequentist analyzes were sup
plemented by comparable Bayesian t tests, which are crucial
data preprocessing given our null hypothesis that inaction-effects do not influence
RT. For the Bayesian tests, we selected an uninformed prior
Note that percentages of trials filtered by each screening (Cauchy ÿ0=0, ÿ=0.707) and sampled 10,000 observations
criterion overlap, as a trial can be classified as invalid based from the posterior distribution on each analysis. Note that all
on more than one criterion such as when a response is both of the individual contrasts specified below are also plotted as
slow and incorrect. Similarly, a participant can be an outlier standardized effect sizes in Fig. 7 in the “General discussion”.
both in terms of response speed and response frequency. For group descriptive statistics of response and frequency,
The screening criteria were based on previous studies (Eitam see Fig. 2A and B below, for response accuracy see
et al. 2013; Hemed et al. 2019; Karsh et al. 2016). supplementary materials.
Crucially screening did not change the qualitative pattern of First, we analyzed RT data (see Fig. 2A and C). As
results—for a side-by-side comparison of the analyzes predicted, presence of action-effects facilitated RT (with a
large effect size) [F(1, 55)=21.35, p<0.0001, Partial-ÿ2=0.280],

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1477

Fig. 2 Experiment 1. Response speed increases with the presence of action- of response time (A) and response frequency (B). Error bars indicate 95%
effect but is insensitive to the presence or absence of inaction-effects (A– CI of estimated marginal means. Dashed lines indicate the grand average.
C). Response frequency on the other hand, is weakly facilitated by the C and D) Bayesian Estimation of the contrasts between the action-effects
presence of action-effects and inhibited by the presence of inaction-effects present, inaction-effects absent condition, and all other conditions.
(B–D). A and B Individual and group means Horizontal lines indicate 95% HDI

while neither inaction-effects [F(1, 55)=0.19, p=0.660, (ÿ 0.74, 0.76), BF 1:0 = 0.34].1 Compared to baseline,
Partial-ÿ2=0.003], nor the interaction term [F(1, RT was significantly slower on the action-effects absent
55)=0.21, p = 0.650, Partial-ÿ2= 0.004] had any
significant effect on RT. We continued by comparing
the baseline condition (action-effects present, inaction- 1
A Bayes Factor greater than 3 or smaller than 0.33 is considered by
effects absent) to all other conditions. For the key convention to be the minimal conclusive ratio (See Jefreys 1998; Kruschke
comparison, and in accord with our expectations, there and Liddell 2018); a Bayes factor of 3 means that the alter native hypothesis
is three times more likely than the null hypothesis given the data (for support
was no difference in RT between the two action-effects
in the null, simply use the inverse of the Bayes factor ratio).
present conditions [Two tail—t(28) = 0.02, p = 0.983, Cohen's d = 0.01, 95% CI

13
Machine Translated by Google

1478 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

conditions—regardless of whether inaction-effects were that participants did not receive feedback regarding their
present [Upper-tail—t(19)=2.96, p=0.004, Cohen's d=1.21, response frequency and responded on a greater proportion
95% CI (0.32, 2.10), BF 1:0 =15.75] or inaction -effects were of trials than they were asked to (>80%, instead of ~70%).
absent [Upper-tail—t(30)=3.79, p<0.001, Cohen's d=1.28, Therefore, in Experiment 2a, we aimed to better control the
95% CI (0.50, 2.06), BF 1:0=66.73]. ratio of required Response and No-Response trials. The
Regarding RF (response-frequency; see Fig. 2B and D, second concern was that inaction-effects (No-response trials
an identical two-way between-subject ANOVA found an on inaction-effects present conditions) appeared at random
insignificant infuence on response frequency by action- timing but also relatively late in the response window. The
effects [F(1, 55)=2.96, p=0.090, Partial -ÿ2=0.050], with a late ness of the inaction-effects could have helped
significant influence of inaction-effects [F(1, 55)=7.69, participants differentiate between own-action effects and
p=0.008, Partial-ÿ2=0.120] and no interaction between the spontaneously occurring, inaction-effects, and possibly for
two [F(1, 55)=1.16 , p =0.290, Partial - ÿ2=0.020 ] . higher that reason inaction-effects did not infuence response
on the base line condition, with an insignifcant difference speed. However, that would not explain why we found
(Bayesian: insensitive result) [Lower-tail—t(28)=ÿ1.43, evidence for an influence of inaction-effects on response frequency.
p=0.082, Cohen's d=ÿ0.52, 95% CI (ÿ1.28, 0.24), BF Finally, it could also be the case that inaction-effects
1:0=1.31]. would have affected RT if they were less delayed and such
a fnding would seriously challenge our explanation of our
basic fnding here and in previous studies (Eitam et al. 2013)
—facilitation of RT . This is because our current explanation
We found that response frequency was signifcantly higher is that RT is facilitated by reinforcement of a specifc motor
on the baseline condition compared with the action-efects program that is credited—using the comparator's
absent, inaction-efects present condition [Lower-tail— t(16) (sensormotor SOA) output as its input—with causing the
= ÿ 2.61, p = 0.010, Cohen's d = ÿ 1.11, 95% CI (ÿ1.99, perceptual effect. If it would have been consistently found
ÿ0.23), BF 1:0=10.05], but not signifcantly different than the that RT is facilitated in inaction-effects present conditions
condition in which both action-effects and this explanation would be falsified.
inaction-effects were absent [Lower-tail—t(31)=ÿ0.53, As such in Experiment 2a we sought to equate the timing
p=0.299, Cohen's d=ÿ0.18, 95% CI (ÿ0.9, 0.53), BF 1:0=0.50]. of action- and inaction-effects by titration inaction-effects to
participants' response speed. Finally, given the large indi
vidual differences found in Experiment 1, we opted for using
a more sensitive, repeated-measures design.
Try 2a
Methods
The results of Experiment 1 supported the notion that action-
effects facilitate response speed, but inaction-effects do not. Participants
Crucially, the Bayesian analysis supported the null
hypothesis for no difference between both conditions in Twenty-fve naïve students from the University of Haifa were
which action-effects were present (see Fig. 2C). Regarding recruited, 88% female, ages 21–29 (M =24.4, SD =0.42).
our hypothesis that a calculation that considers both action- As we had no experience with the current task in a within
effects and inaction-effects could facilitate response subject design, we estimated that the effect would be like
frequency, we found support for infuence from inaction the one found on between-subject designs in previous stud
effects, but the pattern is not as clear as with response speed. ies (Cohen's d=0.8) when comparing conditions similar to
The pattern may not match our prediction that both action the inaction-effects absent conditions in the current study.
effects and inaction-effects infuence response frequency; The sample allowed us to detect a similar effect in a within
Regarding response frequency, the pattern we found is that subject design with a power of~0.98.
inaction-effects robustly reduce response frequency, and
that action-effects facilitates response frequency but to a design and task
lesser degree (see the ANOVA analysis above). Most
importantly for our theoretical purposes, the data do clearly The experiment included the same four experimental
show that differing from response speed—inaction effects conditions as in Experiment 1 (see Fig. 1), but for Experiment
are infuen tial for response frequency (sometimes exclusively 2 we used a within-subject design, and each condition was
so; see Fig. 7 for comparison of all effect sizes on the study). blocked (the block order was random for each participant to
There were two specific caveats that we wanted to cancel out order effects). Each block was 200-trials long (4
address in the following experiments. The first being cue locations×50 repetitions, in random order).

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1479

As in Experiment 1, if no response was given up to a certain response speed—we found a signifcant efect for action effects
timepoint, the trial was considered a No-Response trial. [F(1, 17)=6.4, p=0.020, Partial-ÿ2=0.270] but no infuence of
Here, the timepoint was initially set to 500 ms. However, inaction-effects [F(1, 17)=0.62, p= 0.440, Partial-ÿ2 = 0.040] or
following the first correct response, the timepoint was an interaction [F(1, 17) = 1.30, p=0.270, Partial-ÿ2=0.070]. We
recalculated on each additional trial to be the 75th percentile followed by comparing the baseline condition (action-effects
plus 1 standard deviation of all previous correct response times. present, inaction effects absent) to all other conditions. As
This gave participants enough time to respond, without predicted, we found no difference between the baseline
arbitrarily truncating the RTs distribution's right tail and condition or the action-effects present, inaction-effects present
signifcantly blurred the difference in timing of action- and condition [Two-tail—t(17)=0.12, p=0.904, Cohen's d=0.02, 95%
inaction-effects. On the inaction-efect present conditions, the CI (ÿ0.35 , 0.40), BF 1:0=0.24]. In contrast to our prediction, in
probability of an inaction-efect was 1 and not 0.8 as in this experiment we did not fnd that RTs were faster in this
Experiment 1. Additionally, participants were instructed to condition compared with action-efects absent, inaction-efects
respond on 50% of the trials, the ITI was 700 ms and the present [Upper-tail—t(17)=0.93, p=0.182, Cohen's d =0.17,
number of repetitions for each cue location was equal. 95% CI (ÿ0.200, 0.54), BF 1:0=0.57].

Procedure and apparatus Finally, we found the predicted slower RT on the condition
where both action-effects and inaction-effects were absent
The instructions were read to the participants who then compared [Upper-tail—t(17) = 2.50, p = 0.011, Cohen's d=0.39,
proceeded to complete four experimental blocks, separated by 95% CI (0.06, 0.73), BF 1:0=5.31].
self-paced breaks. During the break, participants were noti fed A two-way repeated-measures ANOVA was used to test the
of their cumulative response frequency by an on-screen effect of action-effects and inaction-effects on response
message and were reminded to maintain a 50% response frequency (see Fig. 3B–D). It showed that the efect of action-
frequency. The equipment was identical to Experiment 1 except effects on response frequency is signifcant [F(1, 17)=14.96,
those stimuli were now presented on a BENQ XL2420T p=0.001, Partial-ÿ2=0.470], but the efect of inaction-effects was
screen. not [F(1, 17 ) = 0.12, p = 0.730, Partial-ÿ2=0.007] and neither
was the interaction [F(1, 17) = 2.86, p = 0.110, Partial-ÿ2=
Results 0.140]. We continued by comparing the action-effects present,
inaction-effects absent condition to all others. We found that
Data pre-processing response frequency was nominally lower when both action-
efect and inaction-effects were present, but the comparison
No-Response trials (53.47% of raw data; trials in which par was not signifcant and insensitive by Bayesian terms [Lower-tail
participants did not respond or responded later than the time — t(17)=ÿ1.47, p=0.080, Cohen 's d=ÿ0.52, 95% CI (ÿ1.28,
point described above) were not analyzed. We filtered out 7 0.24), BF 1:0=1.10]. As predicted, we found lower response
(28% of N=25) participants, all of whom had less than 20 valid frequency when only inaction-effects were present [Lower tail—
trials on at least one experimental condition which precluded t(17)=ÿ2.93, p=0.005, Cohen's d=ÿ0.94, 95% CI (ÿ1.73, ÿ0.16),
calculating a reliable estimate of their RT (Sim mons et al. BF 1 :0=11.08] or when both action- or inaction-effects were
2011) . One of these was also an outlier (±2SD) in both absent [Lower-tail—t(17)= ÿ3.73, p=0.001, Cohen's d=ÿ1.27,
response speed and frequency. For the remaining subjects 95% CI (ÿ2.2, ÿ0.34), BF 1:0=47.64].
(72% of raw data), we fltered incorrect responses (~4.89%),
and fast responses (0.4%; below 200 ms). Filtration of invalid
response trials (both complete participants and individual trials)
resulted in a loss of 31.59% of the data.
Applying these flters did not modify the pattern of results (see Experiment 2b
Supplementary Materials section).
The results of Experiment 2a were similar to those of
data analyzes Experiment 1 while controlling for the difference in the timing of
the inaction-effects and variance in response frequency. An
We used a repeated-measures ANOVA and paired t tests, in unexpected finding in Experiment 2a was that the action effects
line with Experiment 2a's design. First, we analyzed RT data absent, inaction-effects present condition was as fast as the
(plotted in Fig. 2A and C). For the ANOVA, we used the baseline, action effects only, condition. If found to be robust
Greenhouse–Geisser correction for sphericity (here and in the this finding would falsify our theoretical position that the
following within-subject experiments). A two-way within-subject facilitation of response speed stems from a sensorimo tor
ANOVA matched our prediction regarding process based on an eferent copy (ie, Comparator),

13
Machine Translated by Google

1480 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

Fig. 3 Experiment 2a. Response speed increases with the presence of (B). Error bars indicate 95% CI of estimated marginal means. Dashed lines
action-effect but is practically insensitive to the presence or absence of indicate the grand average. C and D Bayesian Estimation of the contrasts
inaction-effects (A–C). Response frequency is facilitated by the presence between the action-effects present, inaction-effects absent condition, and
of action-effects, and nominally lowered by the presence of inaction-effects all other conditions. Horizontal lines indicate 95% HDI
(a non-significant interaction; B–D). A and B Individual and group means of
response time (A) and response frequency

as such a process must be indifferent to events that are control by instructing subjects not to balance their response
not preceded by an action. Crucially, an inspection of the frequency across blocks (see below). Experiment 2b served
forest plot depicted in Fig. 7 shows that this result is an another purpose that is not directly related to the current
oddball suggesting that it is a statistical fuke. work and hence these parts are discussed only in the
In Experiment 2b, we aimed to replicate Experiment 2a Supplementary materials section. Experiment 2b was
while timing inaction-effects more in line with that used in similar to Experiment 2a but included two additional
Experiment 1 (ie, a random timepoint not titrated to the between-subject conditions in which instead of value-free
participant). Additionally, we increased experimental feedback par participants received feedback indicating attainment of eith

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1481

negligible or substantial sums of money. We did so initially to block independently. As in Experiment 2a, block order was
allow a comparison of value-free feedback to studies in which randomized for each participant to avoid order effects.
a similar free-operant procedure with tangible outcomes was
used (O'Callaghan et al. 2019; Shanks and Dickinson 1991; Results
Vaghi et al. 2019). As this discussion is not directly relevant
to the model underlying 'pure' effectiveness, which is the data preprocessing
focus of the current study, only the value-free feedback is
presented in the main text, with the additional between- No-Response trials (45.41% of raw data) were not analyzed.
subject conditions appearing in the Sup supplementary We fltered out in total fve outliers (12.2% of N=41) which
materials. Experiment 2b was pre-registered on OSF (Hemed were either extreme (± 2 SD) in RF (three participants, 4.3%)
et al. 2017).2 and in RT (two participants, 5.38%) or had less than 50% of
correct responses on Response-Trials (one partici pant, ~
Methods 1.1%; which was also one of the RT-outlier partici pants). Out
of the remaining subjects (87.8% of raw data) we fltered out
Participants incorrect responses (~5.55%), fast (0.02%; below 200 ms)
and slow responses (0.07%; above 700 ms). Filtration (both
Forty-One naïve students from the University of Haifa were complete participants and individual response trials) resulted
recruited. 77% of which were female, ages 23–27 (M=24.43, in the loss of ~17% of the data.
SD=3.85). We did not conduct an a-priori power analysis, but
the current sample (41) and design allows to detect of an data analyzes
effect size of ~0.4 (as found on the action-effects present,
inaction-effects absent vs. action-effects absent , inaction We used a repeated-measures ANOVA and paired t-tests,
effects absent contrast of Experiment 2a, for the RT data) as in Experiment 2a. First, we analyzed RT data (plotted in
with a power of ~0.85. We indicate the effect size found on Fig. 4A–C). A two-way within-subject ANOVA matched our
Experiment 2a as this was the frst time we used the current predictions—showing significant effect of action effects [F(1,
task in a within-subject design. 35)=11.60, p=0.002, Partial-ÿ2=0.250] and no influence of
inaction-effects [F(1, 35)=2.75, p=0.11, Partial-ÿ2=0.070] or
Task, procedure, and apparatus the interaction term [F(1, 35)=0.35, p=0.56, Partial-ÿ2=0.010].
We followed by comparing the baseline condition (action-
Excluding the monetary-gain conditions mentioned above, effects present, inaction-effects absent) to all other conditions.
Experiment 2b was identical to Experiment 2a save for two As predicted, we found no difference between the action-
further changes. First, the timepoint for determining whether effects present, inaction-effects absent condition or the action-
the current trial is a No-Response trial was sampled from a effects present, inaction efects present condition [Two-tail—
pre generated normal distribution of 200 values (ÿ=650 ms, t(35)=1.33, p=0.191, Cohen's d=0.19 , 95% CI (ÿ0.1, 0.49),
ÿ=40; based on the results of Experiment 2a and designed BF 1:0=0.40]. In line with our prediction, we found faster RT
to ensure that the timing of inaction-effects was (a) not late for the action efects present, inaction-efects absent condition,
in the trial and (b) would not truncate the response win dow). compared with the action-efects absent, inaction-efects
Second, between blocks participants were informed of the present condi tion [Upper-tail—t(35)=3.40, p= 0.001, Cohen's
percentage of trials in which they responded during the recent d=0.51, 95% CI (0.19, 0.82), BF 1:0=39.700] and the action-
block (rather than the cumulative percentage as in Experiment effects absent, inaction-effects absent condition t [Upper-tail
3) and were reminded to maintain a rate of 50% throughout — t(35) = 3.02, p = 0.002, Cohen's d =0.29, 95% CI (0.09,
the coming block. The purpose of this modification was to 0.49), BF 1:0=16.32].
ensure that participants would not try to balance their
responses across blocks but would treat each We used a two-way repeated-measures ANOVA to
analyze the RF data (see Fig. 4B–D). We found no effect of
action-effects on response frequency [F(1, 35) = 0.05, p=0.82,
Partial-ÿ2=0.002], a signifcant effect of inaction effects [F(1,
two

The experiment was pre-registered on OSF (Hemed et al. 2017) and we


35)=5.07, p= 0.03, Partial-ÿ2=0.130] and no interaction [F(1,
present it with all its conditions for the sake of completion (see Supplementary 35)=0.12, p=0.73, Partial-ÿ2=0.004].
materials); yet in a recently published series of experiments (Karsh et al. We compared the action-effects present, inaction-effects
2020) we rather frmly established that adding monetary value to a neutral absent condition to all other conditions and found that as
efect a response has on the environment does not facilitate response times
more than merely adding such an efect.
predicted, response frequency was significantly lower when
both action-effect and inaction-effects were present (yet

13
Machine Translated by Google

1482 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

Fig. 4 Experiment 2b. Response speed increases with the presence of response time (A) and response frequency (B). Error bars indicate 95% CI
action-effect but is insensitive to the presence or absence of inaction effects of estimated marginal means. Dashed lines indicate the grand average. C
(A–C). Response frequency, on the other hand, is not influenced by the and D Bayesian estimation of the contrasts between the action-effects
presence of action-effects and lowered by the presence of inaction-effects present, inaction-effects absent condition, and all other conditions.
(B–D). A and B Individual and group means of Horizontal lines indicate 95% HDI

Bayesian analysis shows that the current data is insensitive) [Lower-tail—t(35)=ÿ0.43, p=0.336, Cohen's d=ÿ0.10, 95%
[Lower-tail—t(35)=ÿ1.87, p=0.035, Cohen's d=ÿ0.41, 95% CI (ÿ0.57, 0.37), BF 1:0=0.26].
CI (ÿ0.86, 0.04), BF 1:0=1.65]. We also found lower
response frequency for the contrast with action-effects
absent, inaction-effects present [Lower-tail—t(35)=ÿ1.96, Try 3a
p=0.029, Cohen's d=ÿ0.46, 95% CI (ÿ0.96, 0.03 ), BF
1:0=1.90]. In contrast to our predictions, we found no In Experiments 1 and 2a–2b, in line with our hypothesis, we
signifcant difference between the baseline condition and the found that action-effects decreased response speed, but
action-effects absent, inaction-effects absent condition inaction-effects did not (and there was no interaction

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1483

between the two). Another, seemingly stable pattern, is an the experimenter gave them vocal feedback on their
asymmetry between the robust reduction of response performance, but they did not receive any action-effects or
frequency by inaction-effects and the weaker influence (at inaction-effects regardless of the experimental condition.
best) action-effects have on facilitating response frequency. They then completed the three experimental blocks (120
This pattern for response frequency was not predicted based trials each), separated by self-paced breaks. Following the
on previous work on 'Delta-P' (eg, Vaghi et al. 2019) as well task they completed a debriefng questionnaire and the SOA
as our work on control feedback (Karsh and Eitam 2015a, scale (Tapal et al. 2017). Responses were collected using a
b). In Experiment 3a, we aimed at replicating the facilitating response box (Empirisoft, DirectIN High-Speed Button Box).
effect of action effects using a more controlled, cued task Sounds were played through standard PC speakers.
rather than a free operant procedure, given the noisiness of
the response frequency measure. Results
Methods
data preprocessing

Participants
No-response trials (50.82% of the raw data; trials in which
participants did not respond, regardless of the auditory cue
One hundred and twenty-one students at the University of
or the response accuracy) were not analyzed. We fltered out
Haifa were recruited, 66% were females, ages 18–39 (M
eight (6.61% of N=121) outlier (±2SD) participants in either
=24.96, SD =3.47). None of them participated in our previous
Response Frequency (fve participants, ~ 4.1%) or Response-
experiments. We did not conduct a-priori power analysis, but
Time (three participants, ~2.5%) or had less than 50% of
about 30 participants per group would allow us to detect a
correct responses on Response Trials (three participant
Cohen's d of 0.8 with a statistical power ( 1ÿÿ) of~0.92 (for
pants, ~2.5%). Out of the remaining subjects (93.39% of raw
the RT data contrast of action-effects present, inaction-
data) we removed incorrect responses (~1.8%), fast (0.44%;
effects absent vs. action-effects absent, inaction efects
below 200 ms) and slow responses (0.5%; above 700 ms).
absent; see Experiment 1 “Participants”).
Filtration of invalid Response trials (both complete participant
task pants and individual trials) resulted in loss of 8.83% of the
raw data.

The trials on Experiment 3a were identical to Experiments


2a–2b, except that each trial was preceded by a 500 ms data analyzes
Respond/Do not respond auditory cue (a 440 or 196 HZ
tone, respectively), followed by a 200 ms ISI and only then Like Experiment 1 we used the Welch–Satterthwaite cor
by the imperative cue and the response window. recction for degrees of freedom for independent samples t
Participants were randomly allocated to one of the test. First, we analyzed RT data (see Fig. 5A–C). As
experimental conditions (manipulated between subjects) predicted, a two-way between-subject ANOVA showed that
and performed only this condition throughout all experimental action-effects signifcantly infuenced RT [F(1, 109)=7.3, p =
blocks (three blocks, each consisting of 120 trials, 50% 0.008, Partial-ÿ2 = 0.060], but inaction-effects did not [F( 1,
Respond cue trials, 30 repetitions of each cue location in 109) = 0.24, p = 0.62, Partial-ÿ2 = 0.002] and neither did the
random order ). A commission error (responding on a Do not interaction [F(1, 109) = 0.57, p = 0.45, Partial-ÿ2=0.005]. We
respond cue trial or an omission error (no response on a continued to compare the action effect present, inaction-
Respond cue) trial did not lead to action-effects or inaction- effects absent condition to all other conditions. In line with
effects, regardless of the experimental condition. Additionally, our predictions, we found no difference in RT when both
given the auditory cue, we had substantial control regarding action-effects and inaction-effects were present [Two-tail—
whether a participant would respond to a cue or forgo the t(56)=ÿ0.20, p=0.842, Cohen's d=ÿ0.05, 95% CI (ÿ0.58,
trial.Therefore, we titrated the timing of inaction efects to the 0.47), BF 1:0=0.27]. Addition ally, as predicted RT was
participants' response speed, set to the median of all correct signifcantly slower on the action effects absent, inaction-
responses on previous Response trials, includ ing the effects present condition compared with the baseline
practice block (see below). condition [Upper-tail—t(54.48)=2.27, p = 0.014, Cohen's d =
0.60, 95% CI ( 0.06, 1.14), BF 1:0=4.28], but only nominally
Procedure and apparatus slower on the action-effects absent, inaction-effects absent
[Upper-tail—t(52.63)=1.35, p = 0.092, Cohen's d = 0.36, 95
Participants were familiarized with the auditory cues and %CI (ÿ0.18, 0.9), BF 1:0=1.02].
completed a short training block (32 trials) during which

13
Machine Translated by Google

1484 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

Fig. 5 Experiment 3a. Response speed increases with the presence of (A) and response frequency (B). Error bars indicate 95% CI of estimated
action-effect but is practically insensitive to the presence or absence of marginal means. Dashed lines indicate the grand average. C and D
inaction-effects (A–C). Response frequency was not influenced by the Bayesian Estimation of the contrasts between the action-effects present,
presence of either action-effects or inaction-effects, or their interaction (B– inaction-effects absent condition, and all other conditions.
D). A and B Individual and group means of response time Horizontal lines indicate 95% HDI

Second, we analyzed RF data (see Fig. 5B–D). A were present, response frequency was significantly
two-way between-subject ANOVA did not fnd a significant higher [Lower-tail—t(38)=ÿ1.96, p=0.029, Cohen's
effect of action-effects [F(1, 109) = 0.01, p = 0.92, Partial- d=ÿ0.52, 95% CI (ÿ1.05, 0.02), BF 1:0=2.500].
ÿ2 = 0.000], inaction-effects [F(1, 109) = 0.58, p=0.45, Additionally, we did not fnd the predicted lower response
Partial-ÿ2=0.005] or the interaction term [F(1, 109)=2.38, frequency when action-effects were absent, regardless
p=0.13, Partial-ÿ2=0.020]. We continued to compare of whether inaction effects were present [Lower-tail—
the action-effect present, inaction-effects absent t(52)=0.50, p=0.689, Cohen's d = 0.13, 95 % CI ( ÿ 0.4,
condition to all others. In contrast to our prediction, we 0.66), BF 1:0 = 0.19] or absent [Lower-tail—t(53) = 1.17, p = 0.876, C
found that when both action-effects and inaction-effects

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1485

d=0.31, 95% CI (ÿ0.23, 0.85), BF 1:0=0.14], both with we found in previous studies, and the same (with less cer
Bayesian support for the null hypothesis. tainty to the nosier measurement) for response frequency.4

Methods
Experiment 3b
Participants
In Experiment 3a, the pattern of response speed found in
Experiments 1 and 2a–2b was replicated. However, the pat Eighty-eight naïve students from the University of Haifa
tern of results for the response frequency measure was in were recruited. 67% of which were female, ages 19–34 (M
contrast to the one predicted nor was it consistent with the =24.21, SD=2.92). To circumvent issues of the sensitivity
unpredicted pattern that was found in the other experiments of the data, our stopping rule for data collection was that all
in this study. It is possible that the tightly controlled nature hypotheses reach a conclusive BF10 (<0.33 or>3),
of the task (using auditory cues, rather than free operant regardless of whether the pattern of results fts our
procedure) minimized the (albeit, limited) ability of action predictions or not. See pre-registration on the OSF project
effects and inaction-effects to infuence response frequency, for more details (Hemed et al. 2017). On Experiments 2a
even though participants still displayed a similar pattern of and 2b (both also with a within-subject design), we found
RT to that seen in all previous experiments. an effect size of Cohen's d~0.35 for the RT contrast of
Our interim conclusion regarding the facilitating effect of action-effects present, inaction-effects absent vs. Inaction
value-free effects on response frequency is weak as it is Effects absent. We did not conduct a priori power analysis,
highly sensitive to participants' interpretation of the task, but given the sample obtained using the Bayesian analysis
their interpretation of the relevance and informativeness of stopping rule, our sample had a posteriori statistical power
the perceptual effects in relation to the task's goals, their (1ÿÿ) of~0.95 to detect a similar effect.
interest in the task and so on. In hindsight, this volatility is
consistent with the theoretical framework suggested by us task and design
elsewhere (Karsh and Eitam 2015b) which specifies that
action-selection (eg, how and how much to respond) As in Experiment 3a, we used Respond and Do not respond
depends on participants' current high-level cognitions of auditory cues (here we used tones with the frequency of
which Delta- P is only a small and potentially not key 440 and 1046 Hz to make them easily distinguishable). If a
determinant. participant responded before a randomly selected time
The volatility of the effect of own-action effects on point, the trial was considered a response trial, and if they
response frequency is very different from the robustness of did not—a no-response trial. The timepoints were sampled
the effect of (predictable and immediate) own action effects from a random distribution, with the same parameters as in
on response time which also attests to the modular nature Experiment 2b. Action-effects and inaction-effects were
of the mechanism producing them. independent of the auditory cues and depended solely on
This current experiment aimed to alleviate a concern the experimental condition. During the practice block, no
raised by a previous reviewer of the paper3 that in action-effects or inaction-effects were shown, and no
Experiment 3a participants were able to fully disambiguate audition cues were played (ie, a trial included only the 850
action-effects and inaction-effects using the auditory cues ms response window and 700 ms ITI). The experiment had
they received; thus they could have disregarded the inaction a within-subject design, where the experimental conditions
effects occurring on No-Response trials as irrelevant to
their behavior (although their timing was titrated, see
Experiment 2a), and that is allegedly, the reason inaction-
effects did not infuence response speed. Note that this 4
It should be noted that we previously attempted to run this experiment
alternative explanation is not likely given that we observed
dissociating between tones and the result of actions and inactions (using
a similar pattern of response speed when using a free- only the two conditions where action-effects are present, manipulated
response task (Experiments 1 and 2a–2b) and a cued- between-subjects). However, due to a faw design the results of the
response task (Experiment 3a). Yet to alleviate this concern, experiment provided mixed results (we found the predicted difference in
response frequency between the two conditions and a difference in RT
we aimed to dissociate the auditory cues and action-effects,
between the conditions). The faw was that we used the mean RT of previous
hypothesizing that we would still fnd the pattern of results for response
valid trialsspeed that for deeming trial as No-Response (see Experiment
as timepoint
2a) and as a result the partici pants were gradually pushed to respond
faster and faster as the time window shortened with their improved
performance, resulting in truncated distribution of RTs. The current design
3
We would like to thank Dr. Jan De-Houwer for raising this possibility. bypasses this faw and is more like the Experiments presented in the current
study.

13
Machine Translated by Google

1486 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

used in the study were manipulated in separate blocks and found that action-effects significantly influenced RF [F(1, 80)
in a random order, as in Experiments 2a–2b. = 24.69, p < 0.0001, Partial-ÿ2 = 0.240], but inaction-effects
did not [F(1, 80) = 1.72, p = 0.190, Partial -ÿ2 = 0.020], with
Procedure and apparatus a marginally significant interaction between the two [F(1, 80)
= 3.64, p = 0.060, Partial-ÿ2 = 0.040]. We continued to
Participants first performed a practice block (32 trials), compare all conditions to the baseline condition (action-
during which they received feedback from the experimenter. effects present, inaction-effects absent). In contrast to our
Then, they were familiarized with the Respond/Do not predictions, we did not find significantly lower response
respond tones and completed the four experimental frequency when both inaction-effects and action-effects were
conditions in four separate experimental blocks, in a random present [Lower-tail—t(80) = ÿ 0.48, p = 0.318, Cohen's d = ÿ
order (200 trials each, 50% Response-tone trials), as in 0.06, 95 %CI (ÿ0.32, 0.19), BF 1:0 = 0.19]. As ever, we did
Experiments 2a–2b . The equipment used was identical to confirm our prediction that response frequency is higher on
Experiment 2b. the baseline condition (action-effects present, inaction-
effects absent) compared with the condition where only
Results inaction-effects are present [Lower tail—t(80) = ÿ 2.72, p =
0.004, Cohen's d = ÿ 0.35, 95% CI (ÿ 0.62, ÿ 0.09), BF 1:0 =
Data pre-processing 7.58] or when both action effects and inaction-effects are
absent [Lower-tail— t( 80 ) = ÿ 4.85, p < 0.001, Cohen's d =
Two participants were excluded before any pre-processing ÿ 0.65, 95% CI (ÿ 0.93, ÿ 0.36), BF 1:0 = 5525.65].
as they failed to understand the instructions, requiring a 2nd
run of the practice block. No-Response trials (51.25% of raw
data) were not analyzed. We filtered out seven participants
(~8% of N=88), which were outliers (±2 SD) in response
frequency (two participants;~2.28%) or response speed (fve
participants; ~5.68). Out of the remaining subjects (92% of General discussion
raw data) we fltered incorrect trials (~ 2.63%), fast or slow
responses (0.02% and 0.03%; respectively). Filtration of The past decade or so of study converged on the position
invalid Response-trials (both complete participants and that SOA can be parsed as originating from conceptual or
individual trials) resulted in the loss of 10.4% of the data. from sensorimotor sources (Dewey and Knoblich 2014;
Moore 2016; Moore et al. 2009b; Synofzik et al. 2008; Wen
data analysis and Haggard 2020) .
The current study adds to this growing consensus by
As in Experiments 2a–2b, we used paired samples t tests to disassociating between sensorimotor and conceptual SOA
compare between the different conditions. First, we analyzed based on their functional (input–output) behavior and their
the response time data (see Fig. 6A–C). As predicted, a two down stream reinforcing effects. Specifically, conceptual
way within-subject ANOVA revealed that action-effects had SOA is, among other infuences, also driven by a general-
a signifcant infuence on RT [F(1, 80)=49.07, p<0.0001, purpose judgment of contingency (which we initially predicted
Partial-ÿ2= 0.380], while inaction-effects did not [F (1, to follow the Delta-P rule, [P(E|R)—P(E|¬R)]) and reinforces
80)=1.17, p=0.280, Partial-ÿ2=0.010] or the interaction [F(1, volitional action. The effect of this infuence was weak and
80)=2.74, p=0.100, Partial-ÿ2=0.030]. We continued to inconsistent in our experiments potentially because there is
compare the action-effect present, inaction-effects absent more 'cognition' at play (and hence less experimental
condition to all others. As predicted, we found that when control) in situations where no tangible rewards are to be
both action-effects and inaction-effects were present, RT obtained (White 1959).
was not signifcantly different [Two-tail—t(80)=0.52, p=0.602, Conversely, sensorimotor SOA follows a simpler—
Cohen's d=0.04, 95% CI (ÿ0.12 , 0.21), BF 1:0=0.14]. conditional probability—function P(E|R) and reinforces
Also, as predicted we found that RT was slower when response execution or the specifc motor program that is
action effects were absent, regardless of whether inaction- credited with successfully predicting the effect; Empirically,
effects were present [Upper-tail—t(80)=4.82, p <0.001, this effect is more robust compared to the effect of 'Delta-P'
Cohen's d=0.41, 95% CI (0.24 , 0.59), BF 1:0=4910.21], or on response frequency.
absent [Upper-tail—t(80)=6.32, p<0.001, Cohen's d=0.56, Crucially, modulation of RT was found to be fully
95% CI (0.37, 0.74), BF 1:0=1,727,065.59 ]. indifference to the presence or absence of inaction-effects,
Second, we analyzed the response frequency data (see as predicted. This supports the assumption that this
Fig. 6B–D). A two-way repeated-measures ANOVA 'evaluation' of agency is available only following a motor action (Wolpert

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1487

Fig. 6 Experiment 3b. Response speed increases with the presence of frequency (B). Error bars indicate 95% CI of estimated marginal means.
action-effect but is insensitive to the presence or absence of inaction effects Dashed lines indicate the grand average. C and D Bayesian Estimation of
(A–C). Response frequency, on the other hand, is facilitated by the presence the contrasts between the action-effects present, inaction-effects absent
of action-effects, but is not affected by the presence of inaction-effects (with condition and all other conditions. Horizontal lines indicate 95% HDI
a non-significant interaction; B and D). A and B Individual and group means
of response time (A) and response

et al. 1995). We plot a summary of the findings of the Theoretical implications


current study in Fig. 7 below and continue by discussing the
theoretical implications of our findings, followed by several Some of us (Karsh and Eitam 2015b) proposed the Control
caveats of the current study. Based-Response-Selection-Framework (abbreviated CBRS)
as a framework interpreting the fndings that SOA reinforces

13
Machine Translated by Google

1488 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

Fig. 7 Forest plots of the study's findings. Response time (top row) is reinforced size reported on the results section for each of the contrasts per formed
by the presence of action-effects and insensitive to the presence or absence of between the 'baseline' experimental condition—action-effects present, inaction-
inaction-effects. In contrast, response frequency (bottom row) is weakly facilitated effects absent and each other experimental condition. The horizontal line is the
by action-effects but also weakly reduced by the presence of inaction-effects. corresponding 95% CI. The black dot indicates the average effect size across
The colored plus signs depict the Cohen's d effect size, the vertical line is the all experiments for this con
effect fret

effective actions as well as outlining the potential factors but only indirectly, potentially through interpreting sen
modulating such reinforcement. The model is composed of sations such as the fuency of responding (Chambon and
two levels, based on the different types of information they Haggard 2012; Synofzik et al. 2008; cf. Wen 2019). The
'consume'. One level of the model is based on a general second level of the model is modular, and based on
purpose cognitive process (ie, cognition) that forms the sensorimotor processes and is unaffected by higher
conceptual SOA—a causal judgment of action-outcome cognitions such as beliefs, desires or causality judgments
contingency such as Delta-P or based on applying explicit (eg, ones of the form of Delta-P). This level uses a
knowledge of the environment. This general purpose 'Comparator' (see introduction) that provides a sensorimotor
process influences action-selection at the consciously prediction of the consequences of (and only given) a motor response.
accessible, person-level (“Whether to act, or with which The function of this level is to evaluate the effectiveness of
effector”), here measured as response frequency. Our a motor program by testing its ability to predict the effect of
working hypothesis is that this level may also be affected by the that
motor-system
motor program on the environment–-utilizing the results

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1489

of the sensorimotor predictions tested by the comparator. Indeed, our study fnds that response frequency, is most
Responses are reinforced relatively to the degree they led certainly not infuenced only by a sensorimotor prediction.
to a confrmation of sensorimotor prediction/minimization of Which is in striking contrast with response speed. This
sensory prediction error (SPE)—by crediting the spec cifc peripheral effect of 'own-action effects' is also consistent
motor-program that is related to the recent prediction of the with CBRS which specifes that the selection of actions (ie,
Comparator. Thus, the sensorimotor level reinforces actions volitional action) is infuenced by multiple inputs of which the
on a sub-person, consciously inaccessible level (here judgment of one's SOA of perceived changes is but one and
measured as response latency). In other terms, the control not necessarily the most important. Other, potentially more
based-response-selection framework, argues that control infuential inputs may include abstract knowledge about the
over the environment reinforces action selection and action situation (eg, task instructions), one's attitudes towards the
execution—based on a sensorimotor and non-sensorimotor experimental situations, the inclination to explore the
evaluation of the control an action has over the environment. environment, degree of engagement with the task or mere
The current study provides direct support for the CBRS perception of how one's performing on the task . As none of
framework. As described above—the sensorimotor level the above (per CBRS) serve as inputs to the process
SOA (but not the conceptual SOA) can modulate response reinforcing the specifc motor program selected, they
speed. Here we fnd that modulation is sensitive only to the contribute to the dissociation between measures that are
presence or absence of action-effects, P(E|R) and not to the sensitive to only the modular elements of the motor-system
presence or absence of effects that occur when no motor (as is RT in the current experimental context) and ones that
response was produced, P(E|¬R), which is what is predicted are less modular being related to higher cognitions such as
if a comparator-like mechanism is involved. beliefs, etc.
As for modulation of action-selection (eg, whether to Here we would also like to address a possible criti cism
respond), our current results are mixed. On one hand, we of the current study. It was suggested by one of our reviewers
did not fnd a strong infuence of Delta-P—a functional that mere information about performance, or response
description that successfully captured people's (and other accuracy, drives response frequency, rather than information
animals) judgment of contingency, including the special case regarding control over the environment. There is no denying
of cau sality, on response frequency. On the other hand, we that in the task used in this study information regarding
found that response frequency was inhibited by the presence performance is confounded with information regarding control
of inaction-effects (contra to response speed) and, to a lesser —simply because participants are required to press the
degree, facilitated by action-effects (with no clear interaction correct key to receive action-effects.
between the two). As elaborated above, CBRS, our theoretical framework,
The latter does not provide strong evidence that Delta-P allows for information regarding expectations or perfor
is the prominent computation used by participants in the mance to infuence action-selection via conceptual SOA.
current study to select what to do or how much to do it which While in theory, information about performance and spec
is somewhat reasonable, given cases in which people some cifcally here, about response accuracy could have facilitated
times diverge from Delta- P even for causality judgments per response frequency, we fnd it unlikely that it did in the current
se (see Spellman 1996 for a review). It is not all that sur study, for the following reasons. First, by this interpretation
prising that on the effect of the conceptual SOA on response information about response accuracy should have been
frequency is less robust, given that both people's judgments positively correlated with response frequency. That is,
are infuenced by a myriad of factors that might not be well receiving feedback about being accurate should facilitate
understood yet (Wen 2019) and are not under sufficient further responses (ie increase response frequency). But in
experimental control and/or may vary between contexts. For the current study we find no consistent correlation between
example, evidence from a different paradigm indicates that accuracy (and hence, performance feedback) and frequency
low-level temporal delay could diminish response frequency of responding, undermining this hypothesis (see
in general, potentially by affecting sensorimotor processes supplementary materials section for the analyses). Second,
(Karsh et al. 2021). However, it is not clear whether the SPE success in our task is composed of not one, but three factors
related to the temporal delay reduced response frequency —responding using the correct key (accuracy), responding
directly or through conceptual SOA, and how it is weighted. prior to the end of the response window, and adhering to a
A second source of variability in response frequency is that specified response frequency over the long run (eg,
action selection (indexed here by response frequency) is responding on 50% of the trials).
itself affected by more factors (in comparison to execution). Regarding the speed of a response and selecting the correct
Hence, both the input (conceptual SOA) and output (action key, feedback about performance is readily available—if
selection) are 'noisier' and more multidetermined than sen participants did not respond accurately or quickly enough,
sorimotor processes and response execution. they did not receive action-effects. information regarding

13
Machine Translated by Google

1490 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

performance in terms of meeting the required response predictions predictions


frequency was given very sparsely (eg, every 200 trials
for experiments 2a–2b and 3-b). Although feedback on More broadly, the current study's findings are relevant for
response accuracy is readily available, as we write above a current debate on how does the mind integrate
it was not correlated with response frequency, so again, information to make predictions about upcoming events
there is no basis to the claim that it infuenced response (Dogge et al. 2019; Press et al. 2020; Yon and Frith 2021).
frequency. Third, participants across all conditions Dogge et al. (2019) argued that while sensorimotor-based
responded correctly to the cue—regardless of whether internal models (eg, the comparator) are ft to make
they received feedback about their response frequency at predictions regarding bodily-sensations (eg, being tickled
any point in time (ie, participants on the action-effect vs. tick ling oneself; Blakemore et al. 2000), they are a
absent groups, in experiments, 1 and 3a). Fourth, response poor ft for predicting extra-body effects (like the action-
frequency in the action-efect present, inaction-efect absent effects in our study). Specifically, they argue that in the
condition was greater than on the action-efect present, context of paradigms used to study the infuence of action-
inaction efect present condition—although both received effects on perception (like sensory attenuation or intentional
identical feedback on their response accuracy (see binding), sensorimotor mechanisms provide a poor
supplementary materials section for response accuracy explanation as there is evidence that effects that are
data) . Finally, in previous studies by our group (Karsh considered to be implicit measures of agency, such as
and Eitam 2015a; Karsh et al. 2016) as well as others intentional binding are sensitive to top-down influences like
(Penton et al. 2018) employed a free-choice version of the beliefs and explicit knowledge (see also the Introduction
task used here. In that version, participants are asked to section above). As an alternative they proposed a hybrid
respond by selecting, in each trial, a key at random in internal model (ie, comparator) with two alternative routes
response to a general imperative cue. The typical pattern —one uses an eference copy (a 'forward model' similar to
is that participants tend to choose the key that is associated the original Comparator model), while the other uses
with the highest probability of leading to an action-effect, conceptual information such as beliefs and causal reasoning.
at the expense of the other keys. This is in fact a Both models can make predictions regarding the perceived
demonstration of response frequency being associated effect of an action, but they are used in different
with poorer performance on the task, as it signals deviation circumstances stances. The lower-level process is used
from random responding (more strongly so as people's for overlearned and body-related effects (eg, sense of
perception of randomness is akin to probability matching; Bar-Hillel
beingand Wagenaar
tickled), 1991)
while the .
higher-level process is used in
In one of the above studies (Karsh and Eitam 2015a), no novel contexts and events that are related to the
association between participants' ratings of their intention environment (and possibly less with own- actions). Their
to cause an effect and their perceived success in model does not impose rigid constraints on whether the
responding randomly (the task goal) was found. If low- or high-level pro cesses can be used for a specifc
participants were to have mistakenly perceived the action- prediction, only indicates what might be the general
effects as feedback on successfully random—a positive function of each process. This model does share some similarity with C
correlation should have been detected, rather than no correlation
CBRSat all.
highlights the impact of the prediction process on
Note that all the above lies somewhat besides the key further action-selection and (b) in CBRS the two levels
point of the current study—which is that sensorimotor can share some information but make qualitatively different
information (here, the conditional probability of an effect predictions, regardless of whether a specifc contingency
given a response) reinforces response speed, but other is overlearned or novel (see our work on rapid updating of
types of information do not. Admittedly, the current study action's effectiveness in dynamic environments by what
can not completely rule out the possibility that information seems to be the low-level process; Hemed et al. 2020).
regarding performance or response accuracy specifcally, The current study moves this discussion forward by
facilitated response frequency, regardless of how unlikely dissociating between (a) the simultaneous operation of a
we think this explanation is. Future studies could answer purely (modular) sensorimotor forward model-based
this question using version of our task where information prediction diction and (b) a general-domain process like
regarding control and information on response accuracy causality judgments. While the former (ie, the Comparator)
are dissociated, for example using one of the free-choice rein forces motor programming when a sensorimotor
variations of our task (cf. Karsh and Eitam 2015a), one prediction is confrmed, (cf. Tanaka et al. 2021) the latter
similar to the task we used here where incorrect responses reinforces the action that is judged to be causally effective.
also lead to action-effects, or by having the action effects
fully inform you about correctness but to some degree
uncontrolled (eg, spatially unpredictable).

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1491

Predictions postdictions some hedonic attribute to control (and its loss; see
introduction), it is not yet clear what level of action-selection
The focus of CBRS is on the dissociation between the sense this applies to. Our previous findings (Hemed et al. 2020)
rimotor and conceptual types of SOA. However, there are have shown that loss of control inhibits action rather than
other ways to parse SOA, for example, by considering pro facilitates it, at least when the sensorimotor SOA is concerned
cesses that incorporate only prediction and ones that consider (measured by RT). Regarding the conceptual SOA, the
both prediction and 'postdiction', sometimes termed simple answer is that we are not sure. The current study was
retrospective and prospective SOA, respectively (Chambon not designed to answer how dynamically degrading action-
and Haggard 2013) . out as contingency would infuence response frequency (we
The utility of this dissociation can be demonstrated by review below a study by Penton et al. 2010that did test such
considering an intentional binding study (Moore et al. 2009a). dynamically changing contingencies). We speculate that it
Moore and colleagues manipulated the probability of receiving would reduce response frequency, as we found that lack of
action- and inaction-effects (ie, Delta-P). They found out that action-effects inhibits response frequency. Still, it could be
a high probability for action-effects led to intentional binding that a dynamic change in action-outcome contingency similar
effects regardless of Delta-P and even on trials in which no to what Gozli and Gao (2019) suggest would reinforce actions
effect followed the action. Conversely, when the conditional through other mechanisms that are not related to CBRS (eg,
probability of action-effects was low, intentional binding was explicit decision for exploration; Watanabe and Taga 2009;
found only following action-effects and only if Delta-P was Zaadnoordijk et al. 2018).
positive. The authors concluded that probability of action-
effects and Delta-P may be used by two different processes Subjective reports of SOA
to evaluate effectiveness, similarly to our point in this work.
Crucially though, they argue that the mechanism that is A final note refers to the current study's results regarding
sensitive only to the action-effect probability is a sensorimotor people's self-reported SOA. We do not present these findings
predictive process, (ie, the Comparator) that induces in full here (but see Supplementary Materials) as the
'prospective' SOA. On the other hand, Delta-P was attributed experimental designs in the current study were geared to
to a conceptual, 'postdictive' process, ie, causal inference, as dissociate between the infuence of factors shown to be
it occurred only following action-effects and was dependent associated with the infuence of the two 'types' of SOA on
on Delta-P. behavioral meas ures rather than to sensitively measure
While our findings relate to the dissociation found by Moore people's judgment of agency (conceptual SOA). More
et al.'s (2009a), they offer a different perspective on the specifically, three of the fve experiments in the current study
parsing of prospective and retrospective agency. used a within-subject design and regardless of the design,
First, Moore et al., used a measure of intentional binding subjective reports were always collected only at the end of
as a proxy for SOA, a measure that includes a deliberate each experiment rather than during the experimental blocks.
estimation of the time that elapsed between two events, Notwithstanding this caveat, it is interesting to note that
usually an own-action and a candidate action-effect. participants' subjective reports were not strongly associated
Importantly, the measure is de-facto retrospective and has with Delta-P. Generally, participants in conditions where
been shown to be also affected by 'cognitions' about the action-effects were present reported similar levels of feeling
situation (Desantis et al. 2011). of control over the environment regardless of the presence of inaction-effec
Second, as others have stated (Gozli 2019; cf. Gozli and This leads to the question of whether the causal judgment or
Dolcini 2018), associating sensorimotor processes with 'regularity detection' mechanism suggested by Wen and
prospective SOA and conceptual processes with retrospective Haggard (2020) is different from a subjective judgment of
SOA maybe misguided as both involve both prediction and agency. Importantly, two recent studies show that response
postdiction. Our proposal here is that motor programs are frequency, Delta-P and causality judgments are correlated, at
reinforced postdictively by a modular sensorimotor process. least in the context of obtaining desired outcomes. Both
Elsewhere, we have shown that sensorimotor SOA as studies used a free-operant task with varying probabilities of
measured by facilitation of reaction times is also highly action- and inaction-effects signaling monetary gains,
sensitive to the factors regarding prediction (eg, precision; (O'Callaghan et al. 2019; Vaghi et al. 2019).
Hemed et al. 2020). As an interim conclusion, we speculate that in the context
Relatedly, Gozli and Dolcini (2018) and Gozli and Gao of tangible outcomes (vs. value-free, action-effects) response
(2019) also suggested how the reinforcement of action (and frequency could follow a different computation, one where
specifcally exploration) can result from loss of control over response frequency is scaled by contingency and reward
the environment, in the context of hedonic stimuli (Gozli and outcome. Another possible explanation for this discrepancy
Dolcini 2018; Gozli and Gao 2019). While there seems to be may be found in a recent study by Yon et al. (2020). In the

13
Machine Translated by Google

1492 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

study, the conceptual component of agency was quantified inaction-effects, and somewhat in line with our findings, that
using several approaches, including signal detection, it was response frequency is weakly facilitated by action-effects
found- that explicit judgments of agency are biased upward and is more strongly inhibited by inaction-effects. However,
(“I am in control”), due to overweighting of action-effect they also found that response speed was influenced by the
occurrences (differently from the unbiased description of conditional probability of action-effects only when there was
causality suggested by Delta-P; Wasserman et al. 1983, but a low probability of inaction-effects, while we repeatedly
see Spellman 1996). Yet a third possibility for the discrepancy found that response speed was influenced strictly by the
between previous and current findings on the relation ship presence or absence of action-effects , regardless of the
between Delta-P and people's deliberate judgments of presence or absence of inaction-effects. The findings by
agency is that the link between the conceptual SOA and Penton and colleagues (Penton et al. 2018) regarding
behavior is itself context-specific (Tapal et al. 2017). This response frequency fit the CBRS framework's predictions—
may indeed be the case as humans tend to repeat the most the conceptual evaluation of effectiveness considers
effective actions (in the neutral sense of merely infuencing information both from own-action effects and externally
the environment) when exploring a novel environment, but generated effects. How ever, their data on response speed
may not tend to do so when they have a clear goal or an are different than ours (and, more importantly, conficts theoretically).
urgent need that requires fulfillment—when actions that are One possibility for the source of the apparent discrepancy
most conducive to the goal/need are selected (Nafcha et al. in results is that in Penton et al.'s study participants prepared
2016; White 1959). We contrast this with the fxed or their responses in advance and withheld them after planning
decontextualized relationship between behavior and rein their response. Unlike some of the previous studies using
forcement from a mere sensorimotor prediction error (ie, the the task, there was no attentional probe, so participants were
sensorimotor SOA). The lack of sensitivity to the context of always required to use only a specific set of responses (cf.
the latter form of reinforcement is also seemingly due to its Karsh and Eitam 2015a; Hemed et al. 2020).
modular nature and specifically, its lack of conceptual input In our study, it was impossible for participants to prepare a
(see Heald et al. 2021). response in advance and then decide not to execute it, as a
specific response was required per cue. However, in Penton
Actions and inactions et al.'s study participants were asked to first select at random
whether to respond or forgo the trial, and then select at
One caveat that we would like to note regarding the current random a key to respond with. Studies involving the
work, relates to an assumption we make regarding the measurement of scalp potentials (EEG), and specifcally a
rimotor sense SOA. Our predictions are premised on the specific evoked response potential (ERP) that has been
assumption that the sensorimotor evaluation of an action's effective
shown to refect the selection of a response (ie, which hand
ness relies on an eference copy, hence action-effects are to respond with), the Lateralized Readiness Potential (LRP)
meaningful to the sensorimotor SOA and inaction-effects are in the context of stop-signal tasks showed LRP's even when
meaningless. However, some might say that this is a responses were withheld (Huster et al. 2013; Li et al. 2008).
problematic assumption as there is evidence that there is an If this was indeed the case in Penton and colleagues' study
eference copy even for planned or imagined actions. Below an eference copy could have been generated even if the
we discuss other findings, from studies using experimental action was not eventually executed. This would be consistent
tasks and measures which are both similar and different than ours.with our theoretical proposal.
For additional theoretical and empirical comparisons other Another possibility is that Penton and colleagues detected
than the ones discussed below, please refer to the extended the infuence of inaction-effects on response speed due to
general discussion section in the supplemental materials. the comparative ease of their task—on response-trials, par
First, Penton and colleagues (Penton et al. 2018), tested participants were required to respond with any random key
the influence of action-effects and inaction-effects on out of the response set. Because they did not need to attend
response time and frequency, using a variant of our free any spatial cue as in the current study, their participants had
choice task (Karsh and Eitam 2015a). On each trial, their ample cognitive resources to evaluate the action-outcome
participants were asked to decide whether to respond or not, contingency of each block. Again, by this account, therefore
and if they did respond, they were asked to select a key at the knowledge of these probabilities infuenced response
random, out of four keys that were associated with different speed in their study and not in ours—simply because as it
action-effect probabilities (0, 0.3, 0.6 or 0.9). On different was not available to our participants, which were cognitively
blocks, the probability of inaction-effects was either 0, 0.3, taxed due to the cued-response task. This explanation is
0.6, or 0.9, each identified by a differently colored frame hard to accept as responding randomly is arguably a more
shown on the screen. Penton et al., found that response difficult task than cued responding (it is sometimes used as
frequency was modified by both action-effects and a manipulation of mental load) as one needs to hold and

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1493

update at least a partial tally of the different responses she of the experiment's conditions, it was found that responding
emitted. This alternative explanation can also be rejected with the previously associated, efect-compatible response
empirically as accuracy in our task was almost always was faster than responding with the efect-incompatible one.
above 90% (see supplementary materials), and participants' This is brought as empirical evidence for the hallmark of
mean response speeds were around half of the duration of ideomotor—a bidirectional sensorimotor association. This
the response window, showing that the task was quite easy congruence effect was found both when the conditional
for them. Thus, it is very unlikely that if we would have used probability of action-effect was high, but inaction-effects
a free-choice paradigm like Penton et al.'s, we would have were absent (Delta-P=0.6) and when the conditional
allowed our participants more cognitive resources, enabling probability of both action-effects and inaction-effects were
them to evaluate the inaction-effect probability and bias equally high (0.8; Delta-P=0). However, when the probability
their response speed. of action-effects was only slightly higher compared with that
Finally, another difference between the two studies that of inaction-effects (it was 0.80 and 0.50, respectively, ie,
could potentially explain the difference in results is the Delta-P=0.3), no facilitation of response speed was found.
existence of contextual cues. In Penton et al.'s, a colored Similarly, when the conditional probability of action-effects
frame surrounding the experimental window, uniquely was 0.5 or lower (and Delta-P was 0.0) no response speed
identified the probability of inaction-effects. Hypothetically, facilitation on association-compatible blocks was found.
subjects could have learned the mapping between colors The authors suggested that sensorimotor associations are
and probability values (there were only four colors and four acquired through two modes—Delta-P being positive and
probability values, see above) and could have used this high (ie, when inaction-effects were absent) or when Delta
information to predict when an inaction-effect is likely. If this P is naught but the probability for both action-effects and
sort of prediction infuenced their response speed, this inaction-effects is high.
comes as evidence against our point that response speed These findings are not fully compatible with our claim,
in our task is mostly sensitive to sensorimotor processes given the null findings that no sensorimotor associations
and that if our participants were only aware of the probability were formed when action-efect probability was high and
of inaction efects our pattern of results would have changed inaction-effect probability was moderate (ie, Delta-P=0.3).
(eg, slower RTs for the action-effect present, inaction-effect The most similar counterpart for this situation in our study
present condition). However, we believe that this explanation is the present action-effect, inaction-effect present condition
for the differences between the studies can also be rejected. in Experiment 1 (as they had a p=1 probability for action-
Contrary to the dynamically changing contingencies in effect given an action, and a p=0.8 probability for inaction-
Penton et al.'s study in our study the contingencies either effects given no-action). Which yields a slightly positive
did not change throughout the experiment (Experiments 1 value of Delta-P (with high frequency of action and inaction-
and 3a) or changed on separate (long) blocks, once every effects). The results in Experiment 1 are similar to those
200 trials (Experiments 2a– 2b and 3b). Both cases gave found on other experiments for this condition, although on
participants ample opportunity to consciously evaluate the Experiments 2–3 the conditional probability for both action-
action-effect and inaction-effect conditional probabilities. effects and inaction-effects is 1, making Delta-P exactly 0.
Although there are multiple procedural differences One could argue further that our results for the action-efect
between our study and Penton and colleagues', we suspect present, inaction-efect present stem from the high frequency
that the main reason for the ostensive differences between of action-efects and inaction-efects, as Els ner and Hommel
the results stems from the difference in sizes of the samples. found that high frequency of action- and inaction-efects can
The current study reports that data from more than 300 par drive sensorimotor associations when Delta -P is 0.
participants across several replications while Penton and
col leagues' results refect a single study with a ffth of our As in the current study we included only two conditions
total sample size. Thus, further studies are required to settlewhere Delta-P was 0, the action-effect present, inaction
the apparent discrepancy between the two studies, due to effect present and action-effect absent, inaction-effect
the relative similarity between the two tasks. absent. Exploring several other conditions where Delta-P is
Another study that is relevant to the current study's 0 (eg, like one where both action-effective probability and
findings is Elsner and Hommel (2004; Experiment 2). Elsner inaction-effect probability are 0.3) could have answered the
and Hommel used a Go/No-Go bidirectional association question of whether the facilitation we observed for response
acquisition task where participants frst learned action- and speed on the action-effect present, inaction-efect present
inaction-effect pairings between specifc keys and tones. In occurred from sheer frequency of feedback, as Elsner and
the next phase, the tones served as response-cues, and Hommel's study suggests or from high action-efect prob
participants were asked to respond either with the previously ability as we argue. If indeed sheer frequency or Delta-P
associated response, or with the alternative response. in some alone can drive sensorimotor processes, then our claim that

13
Machine Translated by Google

1494 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

sensorimotor SOA relies on action-effect probability alone (2020) also found that subjective agency reports were
will be undermined. infuenced by inaction-effects, similarly to our response
Although we have shown that facilitation in response frequency measure, which we believe to refect a conceptual
speed, which we attribute to sensorimotor processes alone, SOA more akin to a subjective agency report (but see above).
followed action-effects presence and was indifferent to the While it could be that our task was less sensitive, than theirs
presence or absence of inaction-effects one thing has to be in measuring response speed it does not seem likely given
considered in terms of the relevance of the results, which is we have found robust evidence for the lack of difference in
a difference in the methods used on the two studies. While response speed for the action-effect present conditions (by
Elsner and Hommel used an action-effect contingency recording the rather minute facilitation of response speed
learning phase on the 'test' phase, there were no action- observed in both conditions), regardless of the presence or
effects and inaction-effects present. Thus, their manipulation absence of inaction-effects. Finally, it is important to note
for testing the infuence of previously acquired sensorimotor that it is not at all clear whether intentional binding stems
associations was whether compatibility effects are found from a Comparator-like process (Suzuki et al. 2019) , so the
when action- and inaction-effects are removed. In a previous comparison between our results and Weller et al.'s may be
study we have shown that removing action-effects was not very informative .
immedi ately (ie, trial by trail) deleterious to response speed, Another interesting finding comes from a study which
let alone a long experimental block (Hemed et al. 2020 ). As used, sensory attenuation as a measure of 'implicit SOA'
the 'test' phase in Elsner and Hommel's study spanned many (Kilteni et al. 2018). In the study, a small motor applied
minutes and trials—this begs the question of how can the pressure to a participants' arm who were asked to match the
same sensorimotor process be responsible for both our fnd reference force by either pressing down on a button imaging
ings and theirs, when on one setting it is immune to or pressing it down (while their muscle activity was monitored
extinction, and on the other it is highly sensitive to extinctions. to make sure that they only imagined the action ).
We find that the difference in sensitivity to extinction Immediately after, they were asked to reproduce the force
potentially undermines the applicability of their finding to our applied to their arm by pressing down on a force sensor.
study, as it suggests that different mental processes are In both action and imagined-action conditions participants
probed by the two studies. showed sensory attenuation—the reproduced pressure that
On a more general note, regarding the task used by should have refected the reference pressure they received
Elsner and Hommel (2004). As elaborated above, this para was lower compared to a baseline condition, where partici
digm involves an extensive acquisition and test phase. A pants did not press the button nor imagined pressing it. The
'learning' phase which is then followed by a 'test' phase. In authors argued that the engine planning during imagery was
a recent paper, Sun and colleagues (In press), show that enough to provide an eference copy that arguably was fed
Elsner and Hommel's effects can in fact be created and to the comparator, yielding attenuation. It is important to
explained by what they term 'propositions' to mean explicit remember that in our task participants were not asked to
(conscious) causal inferences. That is, the results used by imagine the no-action to the imperative cue, and that Kilteni
Elsner and Hommel, that are argued to be evidence for the et al., gave their participants substantial motor-imagery
automatic creation and/or application of passively acquired training prior to testing, so it can be argued that our partici
associations can also be explained by people's explicit and pants simply did not imagine the movement as their partici
conscious understanding of action-effect relations. These pants did. A future study could potentially test our claims by
findings set Elsner and Hommel's study (and paradigm) recording the LRP in response to the cue and see whether
further apart than the current study and especially lowers participants did or did not imagine the actions spontaneously
the relevance of their results to the modular sensorimotor on inaction-trials. Also, explicitly asking our participants to
processes that we hypothesize underly the facilitation of imagine the actions on no-action trials could be an interest
response speed on our study. The findings by Sun and col ing control condition to our task.
leagues, however, are fully compatible with our key argument
that the effect of bona-fde sensorimotor processes on Conclusion
behavior is insensitive to inaction-effects (Sunet al. 2020).
Other studies have used different behavioral measures of We have shown that a response's effectiveness can be
sensorimotor and conceptual SOA, and found results which evaluated simultaneously by at least two different processes
only partially match ours. In a recent study, Weller et al. (at the least, as additional ones may be discovered) as
(2020) have shown that both explicit judgment of agency proposed in the Control-Based Response Selection
and intentional binding are increased when participants Framework (CBRS; Karsh and Eitam 2015b) and partially
receive inaction-effects, although to a lesser extent compared supported by a recent study (Wen and Haggard 2020). One
with actions lead to effects. Interestingly, Weller et al. such evaluation is based on sensorimotor-prediction and culminates in wh

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1495

believe is more than a sensorimotor prediction error— References


possibly a confrmation or disconfrmation of a sensorimotor
prediction following an action—which is directly informative Aarts H, Bijleveld E, Custers R, Dogge M, Deelder M, Schutter D, van
Haren NEM (2012) Positive priming and intentional binding: eye-blink
to the actual control a motor program has just aforded over
rate predicts reward information effects on the sense of agency. Soc
the environment. Here and elsewhere, we argue that the Neurosci 7(1):105–112 Bakbani-Elkayam S, Dolev-Amit T, Hemed E,
result of the sensorimotor prediction in turn infuences Zilcha-Mano S, Eitam B (2019) Intact motivation in major depression:
consciously inaccessible response-selection processes normative responsiveness to action-effectiveness demonstrated in a
clinical sam ple. SSRN. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3472084 Bar-
such as motor pro gramming. A different evaluation of
Hillel M, Wagenaar WA (1991) The perception of randomness.
action's effectiveness is non-sensorimotor, but conceptual
and is based on knowl edge, potentially infuencing Adv Appl Math 12(4):428–454
consciously accessible processes (eg, whether to respond Barlas Z, Kopp S (2018) Action choice and outcome congruency inde
pendently affect intentional binding and feeling of control judgments.
or withhold response). The effect of the latter judgment is
Front Hum Neurosci 12:137
far less robust because of at least two factors—frst, being Barlas Z, Obhi SS (2014) Cultural background influences implicit but not
cognitive it is highly sensitive to the far more variable mental explicit sense of agency for the production of musical tones.
state (ie, activated knowl edge) in a participant's mind—eg, Conscious Cogn 28:94–103
Berberian B, Sarrazin JC, Le Blaye P, Haggard P (2012) Automation
what they fnd interest ing in the task, their level of boredom,
technology and sense of control: a window on human agency.
the degree they judge a stimulus as being task relevant etc. PLoS ONE 7(3):e34075. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.
Second, this judgment is not the sole or even the most 0034075
important influence on selection of actions and is hence Blakemore SJ, Wolpert DM, Frith CD (1998) Central cancellation of self-
produced tickle sensation. Nat Neurosci. https://doi.org/10. 1038/2870
easily washed out by stronger influences (eg, opportunity
Blakemore SJ, Wolpert D, Frith C (2000) Why can't you tickle your
for reward). Notwithstanding the difference in complexity of self? NeuroReport. https://doi.org/10.1586/14737175.7.10.1337 Brass M,
the two processes, the current study is the first to document Haggard P (2008) The what, when, whether model of intentional
their differential influence on different aspects of response selection.
action. Neuroscientist 14(4):319–325. https://doi.org/10.
1177/1073858408317417
Supplementary Information The online version contains supplementary
Buehner MJ (2015) Awareness of voluntary and involuntary causal actions
material available at https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-022-06345-3.
and their outcomes. Psychol Conscious Theory Res Pract 2(3):237

Acknowledgments We would like to thank Prof. Jan De Houwer for his


Carruthers G (2012) The case for the comparator model as an explanation
insights on previous versions of the manuscript. We would like to thank
of the sense of agency and its breakdowns. Conscious Cogn. https://
Rotem Ellenbogen and Shiran Sharabi (Tel-Hai College) for their help in
doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2010.08.005 Chambon V, Haggard P
running Experiment 1, Lilach Yona, Amier Kardosh and Rivka Aviv
(2012) Sense of control depends on flu ency of action selection, not motor
(University of Haifa, Israel) for their help in running Experiments 2 through
performance. Cognition 125(3):441–451 Chambon V, Haggard P
4. (2013) Premotor or ldeomotor: how does the experience of action
come about?In: Prinz W, Beisert M, Herwig A (eds) Action Science:
Author contributions EH, NK and BE developed the study concept. Foundations of an Emerging Discipline Cambridge, MA:MIT Press,
All authors contributed to the experiments' design. EH, BE, NK, ITM, pp 359–380 Christensen JF, Di Costa S, Beck B, Haggard P (2019) I
performed data analysis. EH and BE wrote the paper; the others with just lost it!
minded and contributed to revisions. BE Supervised the study.
Fear and anger reduce the sense of agency: a study using intentional
Funding This research was supported by The Israel Science Foundation binding. Exp Brain Res 237(5):1205–1212 Cohen J (1988) Statistical
(ISF) grant number 339/16 and The Bi-national Science Foundation (BSF) power analysis for the behavioral sciences.
grant number 2016/299 to BE In: Statistical power analysis for the behavioral sciences
Desantis A, Roussel C, Waszak F (2011) On the influence of causal beliefs
Data availability The datasets analyzed during the current study are on the feeling of agency. Conscious Cogn 20(4):1211– 1220. https://
available from the corresponding author on reasonable request. doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2011.02.012 Desantis A, Weiss C, Schütz-
Bosbach S, Waszak F (2012) Believing and perceiving: authorship belief
modulates sensory attenuation.
Code availability The code used in current study is available from the
PLoS ONE. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0037959
corresponding author on reasonable request.
Dewey JA, Knoblich G (2014) Do implicit and explicit measures of the
sense of agency measure the same thing? PLoS ONE 9(10):e110118
Declarations De Houwer J, Moors A (2015) Levels of analysis in social psychology.

In: Gawronski B, Bodenhausen G (eds) Theory and explanation in


Conflict of interest The authors declared that they had no conficts of
social psychology, Guilford, pp 24–40 Dogge M, Schaap M, Custers
interest with respect to their authorship or the publication of this article.
R, Wegner DM, Aarts H (2012) When moving without volition: implied self-
causation enhances binding strength between involuntary actions
and effects. Conscious Cogn 21(1):501–506
Ethical approval The study was approved by the Ethics Committee,
Department of Psychology, University of Haifa (Approval No. 425/16).

13
Machine Translated by Google

1496 Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497

Dogge M, Custers R, Aarts H (2019) Moving forward: on the limits of motor- Karsh N, Eitam B (2015a) I control therefore I do: judgments of agency
based forward models. Trends Cogn Sci 23(9):743–753 Eder AB, influence action selection. Cognition. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.
Dignath D, Erle TM, Wiemer J (2017) Shocking action: facilitative effects of cognition.2015.02.002 Karsh N, Eitam B, Mark I, Higgins ET (2016)
punishing electric shocks on action control. J Exp Psychol Gen Bootstrapping agency: how control-relevant information affects motivation.
146(8):1204 Eitam B, Kennedy PM, Higgins ET (2013) Motivation J Exp Psychol Gen 145(10):1333–1350. https://doi.org/10.1037/
from control. xge00 00212
Exp Brain Res. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-012-3370-7 Elsner
B, Hommel B (2004) Contiguity and contingency in action effect learning. Karsh N, Hemed E, Nafcha O, Elkayam SB, Custers R, Eitam B (2020)
Psychol Res 68(2–3):138–154. https://doi.org/10.1007/ The differential impact of a response's effectiveness and its monetary
s00426-003-0151-8 Gautier L (2021) rpy2 - r in python [Computer value on response-selection. Sci Rep 10(1):1–12. https://doi.org/
Software]. https:// rpy2.github.io Gentsch A, Weiss C, Spengler S, Synofzik 10.1038/s41598-020-60385-9 Karsh N, Eitam B (2015b) Motivation
M, Schütz-Bosbach S (2015) Doing good or bad: how interactions from control: a response selection framework. In: The sense of agency.
between action and emotion expectations shape the sense of agency. Soc Oxford University Press, New York. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/
Neu rosci 10(4):418–430 Gibbons RD, Hedeker DR, Davis JM (1993) 97801 90267278.003
Estimation of effect size from a series of experiments involving paired
comparisons. J Educ Stat 18(3):271–279 Karsh N, Haklay I, Raijman N, Ruud Custers AL (2021) Control alters risk-
taking: the motivating impact of action-effectiveness in different risk
contexts. Motiv Sci. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/2021-97718-001
_
Gozli D (2019) Experimental psychology and human agency. Kilteni K, Andersson BJ, Houborg C, Ehrsson HH (2018) Motor imagery
Springer, New York involves predicting the sensory consequences of the imagined
Gozli DG, Dolcini N (2018) Reaching into the unknown: actions, goal movement. Nat Commun 9:1617 Kruschke JK, Liddell TM (2018)
hierarchies, and explorative agency. Front Psychol 9:266 Gozli DG, The Bayesian new statistics: hypoth esis testing, estimation, meta-analysis,
Gao CJ (2019) Hope, exploration, and balanced action and power analysis from a Bayesian perspective. Psychon Bull Rev
schemes. Behav Brain Sci 42:E41 25(1):178–206 Li C-SR, Yan P, Sinha R, Lee TW (2008) Subcortical
Haering C, Kiesel A (2012) Mine is earlier than yours: causal beliefs processes of motor response inhibition during a stop signal task. Neuroimage
influence the perceived time of action effects. Front Psychol 3:393 41(4):1352–1363

Haggard P (2005) Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends Cogn Liljeholm M, Tricomi E, O'Doherty JP, Balleine BW (2011) Neural correlates
Sci 9(6):290–295 Haggard P, Eitam B (2015) The sense of agency. of instrumental contingency learning: differential effects of action–
Social cognition and social neuroscience. Oxford University Press, New reward conjunction and disjunction. J Neuro sci 31(7):2474–2480
York Haggard P, Clark S, Kalogeras J (2002) Voluntary action and Lynn MT, Muhle-Karbe PS, Aarts H, Brass M (2014) Priming deter
conscious awareness. Nat Neurosci 5(4):382–385. https://doi.org/10.1038/ minist beliefs diminishes implicit (but not explicit) components of self-
nn827 _ Hammond LJ (1980) The effect of contingency upon the agency. Front Psychol 5:1483
appetite conditioning of free-operant behavior. J Exp Anal Behav
34(3):297–304 Hauf P, Elsner B, Aschersleben G (2004) The role of action Moore JW (2016) What is the sense of agency and why does it matter?
effects in Front Psychol 7:1272
Moore JW, Lagnado D, Deal DC, Haggard P (2009a) Feelings of control:
contingency determines experience of action. Cogni tion 110(2):279–
infants' action control. Psychol Res 68(2–3):115–125 Heald 283. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/ article/pii/
JB, Lengyel M, Wolpert DM (2021) Contextual inference underlies the S0010027708002771?casa_token=PQqmKJMSD_
learning of sensorimotor repertoires. Nature 600(7889):489–493 8AAAAA:Lxh2F7APr3-6IKn_t6DB3QFp274UvI37BklVJ6ggr
Hemed E, Karsh N, Mark-Tavger I, eitam, baruch (2017) The HMVlUh04onORztxuMJQRYHlkAf83BRjMe4 Moore JW, Wegner
effectiveness of actions. https://doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/YZH5B Hemed DM, Haggard P (2009b) Modulating the sense of agency with external cues.
E, Bakbani-Elkayam S, Teodorescu AR, Yona L, Eitam B (2019) Conscious Cogn 18(4):1056–1064. https://doi.org/10.1016/
Evaluation of an action's effectiveness by the motor system in a dynamic j.concog.2009.05.004 Morey RD, Rouder JN, Jamil T, Morey MRD
environment. Exp Psychol Gen 149(5):935–948 Hemed E, Bakbani- (2018) Bayesfactor.
Elkayam S, Teodorescu AR, Yona L, Eitam B (2020) Evaluation of Computation of Bayes Factors for common designs. R package
an action's effectiveness by the engine sys tem in a dynamic version 0.9. 12-4.2.
environment. J Exp Psychol Gen 149(5):935– 948. https://doi.org/10.1037/ Nafcha O, Higgins ET, Eitam B (2016) Control feedback as the motivational
xge0000692 Higgins ET (2011) Beyond pleasure and pain: how force behind habitual behavior. Progress in brain research, vol 229.
motivation works. Elsevier, New York, pp 49–68 O'Callaghan C, Vaghi MM, Brummerloh
B, Cardinal RN, Robbins TW (2019) Impaired awareness of action-outcome
contingency and causality during healthy ageing and following
Oxford University Press, Oxford. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof: oso/ ventromedial pre frontal cortex lesions. Neuropsychologia 128:282–
9780199765829.001.0001 289. https://doi.org/10.1016/J.NEUROPSYCHOLOGIA.2018.01.021
Higgins ET (2019) What reigns supreme: value, control, or truth? Peirce JW (2007) PsychoPy—psychophysics software in Python. J
Motiv Sci 5(3):185–201. https://doi.org/10.1037/mot0000150 Hull
CL (1943) Principles of behavior: an introduction to behavior theory. Neurosci Methods 162(1–2):8–13
Appleton-Century, New York Huster RJ, Enriquez-Geppert S, Lavallee Penton T, Wang X, Coll MP, Catmur C, Bird G (2018) The influence of
CF, Falkenstein M, Herrmann CS (2013) Electroencephalography of action–outcome contingency on motivation from control. Exp Brain
response inhibition tasks: functional networks and cognitive Res. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-018-5374-4
contributions. Int J Psycho physiol 87(3):217–233 Jeffreys H (1998) Pfster R, Obhi SS, Rieger M, Wenke D (2014) Action and perception in
Theory of probability. Clarendon Press, Oxford social contexts: intentional binding for social action effects.
Front Hum Neurosci 8:667

13
Machine Translated by Google

Experimental Brain Research (2022) 240:1471–1497 1497

Press C, Kok P, Yon D (2020) The perceptual prediction paradox. Van Hamme LJ, Wasserman EA (1994) Cue competition in causality
Trends Cogn Sci 24(1):13–24 judgments: the role of nonpresentation of compound stimulus
Preston C, Newport R (2010) Self-denial and the role of intentions in the elements. Learn Motiv. https://doi.org/10.1006/LMOT.1994. 1008
attribution of agency. Conscious Cogn 19(4):986–998 Redgrave P,
Gurney K (2006) The short-latency dopamine signal: a role in discovering VandenBos GR (2007) APA dictionary of psychology. American
novel actions? Nat Rev Neurosci 7(12):967–975 Redgrave P, Gurney Psychological Association Waskom M (2018) Seaborn: statistical
K, Reynolds J (2008) What is reinforced by phasic dopamine signals? Brain data visualization—Seaborn
Res Rev 58(2):322–339 Rescorla RA (1967) Pavlovian conditioning 0.9.0 Documentation. Sphinx 1.7.4
and its proper control pro Wasserman EA, Chatlosh DL, Neunaber DJ (1983) Perception of causal
cedures. Psychol Rev 74(1):71 relations in humans: factors affecting judgments of response-outcome
Saito N, Takahata K, Murai T, Takahashi H (2015) Discrepancy between contingencies under free-operant procedures.
explicit judgment of agency and implicit feeling of agency: implications Learn Motiv 14(4):406–432
for sense of agency and its disorders. Con scious Cogn 37:1–7 Watanabe H, Taga G (2006) General to specific development of movement
Shanks DR, Dickinson A (1991) Instrumental judgment and patterns and memory for contingency between actions and events in
performance under variations in action-outcome contingency and contiguity. young infants. Infant Behavior Dev. https://doi.org/10. 1016/
Mem Cognit. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03197139 Simmons JP, j.infbeh.2006.02.001
Nelson LD, Simonsohn U (2011) False-positive psychology: Watanabe H, Taga G (2009) Flexibility in infant actions during arm and leg-
undisclosed fexibility in data collection and analysis allows presenting based learning in a mobile paradigm. Infant Behav Dev 32(1):79–90.
anything as signifcant. Psychol Sci 22(11):1359–1366 Singmann H, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.infbeh.2008.10.003 Watanabe H, Taga G
Bolker B, Westfall J, Aust F (2015) afex: analysis of factorial (2011) Initial-state dependency of learning in young infants. Hum Mov Sci
experiments. R package version 0.13–145 Skinner BF (1965) Science and 30(1):125–142 Wegner DM, Wheatley T (1999) Apparent mental
human behavior (Issue 92904). Simon and Schuster, New York causation. Sources of the experience of will. Am Psychol 54(7):480–492
Spellman BA (1996) Acting as intuitive scientists: contingency judgments Weller L, Schwarz KA, Kunde W, Pfster R (2020) Something from
are made while controlling for alternative potential causes. nothing: agency for deliberate nonactions. Cognition 196:104136 Wen W
(2019) Does delay in feedback diminish sense of agency? The
review. Conscious Cogn 73:102759. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.
Psychol Sci 7(6):337–342 concog.2019.05.007 Wen W, Haggard P (2020) Prediction error and
StataCorp (2015) Stata statistical software: release 14. https://doi.org/ regularity detection underlie two dissociable mechanisms for
10.2307/2234838 computing the sense of agency. Cognition. https://doi.org/10.1016/
Sun D, Custers R, Marian H, Liefooghe B, Aarts H (In press) Examining j.cognition.2019. 104074
mechanistic explanations for ideomotor effects. J Exp Psy chol
Human Percept Perform Suzuki K, Lush P, Seth A, Roseboom W
(2019) Intentional binding without intentional action. Psychol Sci 30(6):842– Wen W, Yamashita A, Asama H (2015) The influence of action-out come
853 delay and arousal on sense of agency and the intentional binding
Synofzik M, Vosgerau G, Newen A (2008) Beyond the comparator model: effect. Conscious Cogn 36:87–95 White RW (1959) Motivation
a multifactorial two-step account of agency. Conscious Cogn reconsidered: the concept of competence.
17(1):219–239. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2007.03. 010 Psychol Rev 66(5):297
Wolpert DM, Ghahramani Z, Jordan MI (1995) An internal model for
Takahata K, Takahashi H, Maeda T, Umeda S, Suhara T, Mimura M, Kato sensorimotor integration. Sci AAAS Wkly Pap Ed 269(5232):1880–
M (2012) It's not my fault: postdictive modulation of intentional binding 1882 Yon D, Bunce C, Press C (2020) Illusions of control without
by monetary gains and losses. PLoS ONE 7(12):e53421 delusions
of grandeur. Cognition 205:104429
Tanaka T, Watanabe K, Tanaka K (2021) Immediate action efects motivate Yon D, Frith CD (2021) Precision and the Bayesian brain. Curr Biol
actions based on the stimulus–response relationship. 31(17):R1026–R1032 Zaadnoordijk L, Otworowska M, Kwisthout J,
Exp Brain Res 239(1):67–78 Hunnius S (2018) Can infants' sense of agency be found in their behavior?
Tapal A, Oren E, Dar R, Eitam B (2017) The sense of agency scale: a Insights from babybot simulations of the mobile-paradigm. Cognition.
measure of consciously perceived control over one's mind, body, and https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2018.07.006 _
the immediate environment. Front Psychol 8:1552. https://doi.org/
10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01552 Zaadnoordijk L, Otworowska M, Kwisthout J, Hunnius S, van Rooij I (2016)
Torchiano M, Torchiano MM (2020) Package 'effsize.' package The mobile-paradigm as measure of infants' sense of agency?
'Efsize.' Insights from babybot simulations. In: 2016 Joint IEEE international
Vaghi MM, Cardinal RN, Apergis-Schoute AM, Fineberg NA, Sule A, conference on development and learning and epi genetic robotics
Robbins TW (2019) Action-outcome knowledge dissociates from (ICDL-EpiRob), p 41–42
behavior in obsessive-compulsive disorder following con tingency
degradation. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroim aging 4(2):200– Publisher's Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to
209 Vallée-Tourangeau F, Murphy RA, Baker AG (2005) Contiguity jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional afflictions.
and the outcome density bias in action–outcome contingency judgments.
QJ Exp Psychol Sect B 58(2b):177–192

13

You might also like