Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 52

John Locke and the Grounds for

Toleration 1st Edition Flavio Fontenelle


Loque
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/john-locke-and-the-grounds-for-toleration-1st-edition-f
lavio-fontenelle-loque/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

John Locke and Agrarian Capitalism Neal Wood

https://ebookmass.com/product/john-locke-and-agrarian-capitalism-
neal-wood/

The Grounds of the Novel 1st Edition Wright

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-grounds-of-the-novel-1st-
edition-wright/

An Essay Concerning Human Understanding John Locke

https://ebookmass.com/product/an-essay-concerning-human-
understanding-john-locke/

The Palgrave Handbook of Toleration 1st ed. 2022


Edition Mitja Sardo■ (Editor)

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-palgrave-handbook-of-
toleration-1st-ed-2022-edition-mitja-sardoc-editor/
Locke & Key - Mundo pequeño 1st Edition Joe Hill

https://ebookmass.com/product/locke-key-mundo-pequeno-1st-
edition-joe-hill/

Peruvian Cinema of the Twenty-First Century: Dynamic


and Unstable Grounds 1st ed. Edition Cynthia Vich

https://ebookmass.com/product/peruvian-cinema-of-the-twenty-
first-century-dynamic-and-unstable-grounds-1st-ed-edition-
cynthia-vich/

The Grounds of Political Legitimacy Fabienne Peter

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-grounds-of-political-
legitimacy-fabienne-peter/

America's Philosopher: John Locke in American


Intellectual Life Claire Rydell Arcenas

https://ebookmass.com/product/americas-philosopher-john-locke-in-
american-intellectual-life-claire-rydell-arcenas-2/

America's Philosopher. John Locke in American


Intellectual Life Claire Rydell Arcenas

https://ebookmass.com/product/americas-philosopher-john-locke-in-
american-intellectual-life-claire-rydell-arcenas/
International Archives of the History of Ideas 237
Archives internationales d'histoire des idees

Flavio Fontenelle Loque

ISBN 978-3-030-90362-6

I 11
9 783030 903626
~Springer
International Archives of the History of Ideas
Archives internationales d 'histoire des idees

Volume 237

Founding Directors
PaulDibon
Richard H. Popkin

Former Director
Sarah Hutton, University of York, York, UK

Director
Guido Giglioni, University of Macerata, Italy

Associate Director
John Christian Laursen, University of California, Riverside, CA, USA

Editorial Board Members


Michael J. B. Allen, University of California Los Angeles, Los Angeles, USA
Jean-Robert Armogathe, Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, Paris, France
Stephen Clucas, Birkbeck, University of London, London, UK
Javier Fernandez Sebastian, Universidad del Pais Vasco, Bilbao, Spain
Peter Harrison, The University of Queensland, Brisbane, Australia
John Henry, Science Studies Unit, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, UK
Jose R. Maia Neto, University of Belo Horizonte, Belo Horizonte, Brazil
Martin Mulsow, Universitat Erfurt, Gotha, Germany
Gianni Paganini, University of Eastern Piedmont, Vercelli, Italy
Jeremy Popkin, University of Kentucky, Lexington, KY, USA
John Robertson, Clare College, Cambridge, UK
G . A. J. Rogers, Keele University, Keele, UK
Ann Thomson, European University Institute (EUI), Florence, Italy
Theo Verbeek, Universiteit Utrecht, Utrecht, The Netherlands
Koen Vermeir, Paris Diderot University, Paris, France
International Archives of the History of Ideas/Archives intemationalt:1> <l'histoire Flavio Fontenelle Loque
des idees is a series which publishes scholarly works on the history of ideas in the
widest sense of the word. It covers history of philosophy, science, political and
religious thought and other areas in the domain of intellectual history. The
chronological scope of the series extends from the Renaissance to the Post-
Enlightenment. Founded in 1963 by R.H. Popkin and Paul Dibon, the International
Archives of the History of Ideas/Archives internationales d' histoire des idees
publishes, edits and translates sources that have been either unknown hitherto, or
unavailable, and publishes new research in intellectual history, and new approaches
within the field. The range of recent volumes in the series includes studies on
John Locke and the Grounds
skepticism, astrobiology in the early modem period, as well as translations and
editions of original texts, such as the Treatise of the Hypochondria ck and Hysterick for Toleration
Diseases ( 1730) by Bernard Mandeville.
All books to be published in this Series will be fully peer-reviewed before final
acceptance.

More information about this series at https://link.springer.comlbookseries/5640

~Springer
Flavio Fontenelle Loque G
Federal University of Lavras
Minas Gerais, Brazil

For my parents

ISSN 0066-6610 ISSN 2215-0307 (electronic)


International Archives of the History ofldeas Archives intemationales d' histoire des idees
ISBN 978-3-030-90362-6 ISBN 978-3-030-90363-3 (eBook)
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-90363-3

©The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland
AG2022
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar
or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the
editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
L'instant ou nous croyons avoir «tout »
compris nous prete l'apparence d'un
assassin.
E. Cioran
Acknowledgements

This book was originally written between 2016 and 2018, for my PhD dissertation,
which I defended in February 2019 before the Federal University of Minas Gerais
(Belo Horizonte, Brazil). The research on Locke was quite a challenge for me,
because in the previous decade my work had basically focused on the history of
early modem scepticism. I must say, though, that this challenge was rewarding. I
learnt a lot; Locke broadened my intellectual horizons and introduced me to new
people and places. After defending my dissertation, I turned to the more detailed
study of other authors, such as Pierre J urieu, and to some related issues, such as the
concept of lai"cite. Meanwhile, I have attempted to incorporate the works on Locke
and toleration, published in 2019 and 2020, into the present book.
Several people supported me in different ways on the long path that led to the
publication of this book. I am happy to take this opportunity to publicly acknowl-
edge them for their assistance and friendship.
First of all, I am grateful to Professor Jose Raimundo Maia Neto, my supervisor
since my time as an undergraduate. My PhD dissertation owes a lot to his knowl-
edge and erudition. I could always count on him, even in the years between my
Master's and my PhD, when we had no formal or institutional bonds. I deeply
admire not only his ability to focus on the main philosophical issues but also his
generosity and politeness. Rarely have I seen so remarkable an example of excel-
lence and simplicity.
I am also profoundly grateful to Professor Ian Harris, who advised me as a PhD
candidate when I was an exchange student at the University of Leicester in 2018.
We had several meetings to discuss Locke's philosophy. I owe a debt of gratitude to
him, not only for all that he taught me, through his incisive comments and his wit,
but also for his assistance in grappling with the practicalities of settling in a foreign
country. While in England, I had the honour of discussing my research with
Professor John Dunn, at his office in King's College, Cambridge, and with Professor
John Coffey at the University of Leicester. I thank Professor Timothy Stanton for
placing his trust in me, in sending me an advanced version of his transcription of
Locke'sA Defence of Nonconformity. I also mention Professor G. A. J. Rogers, who
was extremely kind to me, and I regret the fact that we were not able to meet. I thank

ix
x Acknowledgements

The Warburg Institute for giving me opportunity to conducl research lhere, which Contents
made a significant difference for my work.
The suggestions I received from the committee that evaluated my dissertation led
me to see some points that I was unable to perceive before. I am grateful to Professors
Eunice Ostrensky, Antonio Carlos dos Santos, Telma Birchal, Helton Adverse, and
Newton Bignotto for their attentive reading.
Throughout my research, especially in the initial years, I relied on several friends
in Germany, France, England, and Canada to send me articles and books lhat I was
unable to access in Brazil. I can hardly express how indebted I feel to them. I owe
my sincere gratitude to Daniel Arelli, Roberta Miquelanti, Pedro Vianna Faria, Luiz
Philipe de Caux, Julio Cesar Terra, Celso Neto, Sacha Kontic, and Joao Cortese. In
regard to access to bibliographical material, I also record my gratitude to Professors
Jose Raimundo Maia Neto and Ian Harris, who ordered books related to my research
for inclusion in the library archives of the Federal University of Minas Gerais and
the University of Leicester. 1 Introduction. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1
I am grateful to Fabio Fortes and Wellington Ferreira Lima for agreeing to trans- References. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9
late the Epistola de Tolerantia for the commented edition that I organised, and that
2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia . . . . . . . . 15
was published by Autentica Editora in November 2019. The technical revision I did
2.1 The Evangelical Argument. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
of the Latin translation was essential for my understanding of Locke.
2.2 The Argument from Commission . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
I thank the two reviewers who approved the manuscript of this book. Both were
2.3 The Argument of Unfitness of Force . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
very generous. I am also grateful to a group of people that, at various times and in
2.4 The Argument of Reductio ad Absurdum. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
different ways, helped me to improve my English. Writing in a foreign language is
2.5 Argumentative Synthesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
always a challenge, and Isabela Caixeta, Bennett Bullock, Fiona Stephenson, and
References. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56
Husain Bhana saved me from countless pitfalls.
To my family and close friends, I am grateful for all their support for this work, 3 The Locke and Proast Controversy. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63
but in their case, this is to say too little. My whole life has been shaped and moulded 3.1 The Argument of 'The Letter Concerning Toleration'
by them. Briefly Consider'd andAnswer'd................ .. .... . .... 65
3.2 Locke's Second Letter Concerning Toleration. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77
3.3 Proast's Third Letter Concerning Toleration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93
3.4 Locke' s Third Letter f or Toleration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106
3.5 Further Developments of the Controversy. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126
References. . ........ ... .. .............. . ... . . ...... ........ 133
4 Ethics of Belief. ... . ....... . .. ................ ... . . . ... . . ... 137
4.1 Obstinacy, Fallibility and Toleration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 138
4.2 Examination, Method and Probability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 153
4.3 Reason and Faith, Miracles and Enthusiasm ..... . . . .. . . . ..... 161
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180
5 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 185
References. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 192

References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195

Index....... .. . . .. ...... ... ... . . ... . ... . .. .. . . .... ...... .. . . . . 207

xi
List of Tables

Table 2.1 Synoptic table................................................................................. 55


Table 3.1 Thematic correspondence............................................................... 78

xiii
About the Author

Flavio Fontenelle Loque is associate professor at the Federal University of Lavras,


Brazil. His primary research interests are toleration and the history of scepticism.
He has published a work on fideism, Ceticismo e religiao no in{cio da modernidade
(Loyola, 2012), Scetticismo e religione all'inizio dell'eta moderna (Morcelliana,
2018), and a bilingual and commented edition of John Locke's Epistola de
Tolerantia (Autentica, 2019) in partnership with Fabio Fortes and Wellington
Ferreira Lima. His research interests include the notion of laicite and the translation
of modern authors, such as John Locke, Blaise Pascal, and Pierre Bayle.

xv
Abbreviations1

Arg. Proast, The Argument of the 'Letter concerning Toleration' briefly


consider'd and answer'd, ed. 1690
Cond. Locke, Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. P. Schuurman
Corr. Locke, The Correspondence of John Locke, ed. de Beer
DM Locke, A Discourse of Miracles, John Locke: writings on religion, ed.
V. Nuovo
DNC Locke, A Defence of Nonconformity, ed. Stanton (the quotations give the
page of the manuscript)
E Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. Nidditch
Epist. Locke, Epistola de Tolerantia, A Letter on Toleration, ed. Klibansky
and Gough
ET Locke, An Essay concerning Toleration, ed. Milton and Milton
FL Locke, Fourth Letter for Toleration, Posthumous Works, ed. 1706
Letter Augustine, Letters, ed. 1870-1873
Pol. Es. Locke, Political Essays, ed. Goldie
Popple Locke, A Letter concerning Toleration, ed. Montuori
RC Locke, The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. Higgins-Biddle
RLP The Reception of Locke's Politics, ed. Goldie, vol. 5: Long, The Letter for
Toleration deciper'd... ; Proast, The Argument... , A Third Letter. .. , A
Second Letter. ..
SL Locke, A Second Letter concerning Toleration, ed. 1690
SL-P Proast, A Second Letter to the author of the Three Letters for Toleration ,
ed. 1704
TL Locke, A Third Letter for Toleration, ed. 1692
TL-P Proast, A Third Letter concerning Toleration, ed. 1691
TTG Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Laslett
Works Locke, The Works of John Locke, ed. 1823

1 No changes have been made in order to modernise either the spelling or the punctuation of the

early modem English works, or of their critical editions.

xv ii
Chapter 1
Introduction

Abstract This chapter presents a brief overview on toleration in early modern


Europe. It then presents the purpose of this book, which consists of an effort to
understand, in detail, how Locke justified religious toleration in the Epistola de
Tolerantia, in the letters written as part of the controversy with Proast and in An
Essay concerning Human Understanding. The definition of toleration and the cen-
tral conceptual distinction between vertical and horizontal toleration are explained,
along with the two main questions that this book claims are at the core of Locke's
reasoning: why should the ends of State not be extended to include the care ofsouls?
and why should private persons tolerate each other?. The chapter ends with a brief
methodological remark and a summary of the structure of the book.

Religious intolerance is a common phenomenon, but it emerges with greater force


at certain times and places. Once such example occurred in early modern Europe,
when the Reformation divided Christianity, causing the coexistence of Christians to
become such a serious problem that it resulted in a series of wars. Due to these con-
flicts, the beginning of the modern age was also a period when the forms of coexis-
tence with the otherness were widely discussed. In general terms, we can say that
the initial attitude towards religious diversity among Christians was the quest for
concord. Especially in the sixteenth century, the ideal of reconciliation between
Catholics and Protestants was very much alive, and encompassed a political dimen-
sion (restoring peace) as well as a theological and ecclesiastical dimension (agree-
ment about the fundamental articles of faith and the communion of all men in the
same church). The unity that had been lost with the Reformation needed to be recov-
ered, and this was meant to happen with the reestablishment of uniformity through
consensus rather than through force. The hope was to achieve an agreement as to the
fundamentals of the faith - smoothing out all the most crucial differences - so that
only the so-called indifferent things would be left to the individual believer's discre-
tion. Therefore, the main ambition of those who yearned for concord was not really
the coexistence of different Christian denominations, but their reunification.
Accordingly, concord should not be confused with toleration, even though both

©The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature


Switzerland AG 2022
F. F. Loque, John Locke and the Grounds for Toleration , International Archives
of the History of Ideas Archives internationales d'histoire des idees 237,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-90363-3_1
2 1 Introduction Introduction 3

conl:t:pls reject the use of force in religious matters, for toleration presupposes that With regard to toleration in early modem Europe, we must also take into account
diversity is insurmountable. 1 the fact that political stability was traditionally associated with religious uniformity,
The contrast between these two concepts is illuminating, as it reveals that tolera- i.e. dissidence was seen as politically disruptive. The threat to social order raised by
tion holds as permanent the coexistence with the otherness or, strictly speaking, sedition was a justification for intolerance - a justification of a political nature to
with a relevant otherness (i) of which we make a pejorative judgment and (ii) to which others were added, notably those of a theological nature, as we shall see. In
which we have power to make opposition. By definition, the adjective 'tolerant' this respect, it is interesting to remember the case of France, whose history illus-
refers to an institution or a person that does not make opposition to what is taken as trates this line of thought very well. In that country, where the adage une Joi, une Loi,
bad or false, 2 although he has the power to do so. Without these two features, we un roi clearly depicts the association between religious uniformity and political
should not speak of toleration, but of indifference (when there is no pejorative judg- stability, the disturbances caused by the civil wars were so damaging that they led
ment) or acquiescence (when there is no superiority of power). 3 Consequently, in its the State to concede toleration to dissenters at the end of the sixteenth century (those
more immediate sense, toleration consists in a coexistence with an otherness that we who defended toleration in these pragmatic terms became known as politiques).
do not have a good opinion of, but that we choose not to combat. This is the reason Nevertheless, almost a century later, France turned to its old conception of itself as
why toleration is commonly conceived as concession. an exclusively Catholic country, and the religious persecutions reached new heights
In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the notion of toleration as concession with the revocation of the Edict of Nantes in 1685.5
was prevalent and it had a characteristic that needs to be emphasised: it was always In fact, and not only in France, the pragmatic defence of toleration rests on a
a concession of the State towards religious dissenters. The emphasis on this charac- constellation of political forces. As it is a concession, there is nothing to prevent it
teristic is important because it helps us to delineate a polysemy that is intrinsic to being revoked in the future. If its value is merely instrumental, as a means of ensur-
the notion: toleration can describe either the vertical relationship between the State ing peace, it is clear that a social or institutional rearrangement might lead to the
and its citizens, or the horizontal relationship between private persons or groups.4 subsequent conclusion that toleration can be discarded. All that would be required,
Historically speaking, the Edict of Nantes (1598) and the Declarations oflndulgence for instance, would be for the State to gain enough power to suppress dissidence. If
of Charles 11 (1672) and James II (1687) instance the vertical relationship, whereas one does not bring into question the association between religious uniformity and
the Augsburg Peace Treaty (1555) instances the horizontal one. As we can see, tol- political stability, it is impossible to assign to toleration a value in and of itself.
eration as concession springs from a power asymmetry, and is properly exemplified However, aside from this politically based justification for intolerance, there are
by the institutional acts of France and England, countries already very centralised in also those of a theological nature, whose central aspect rests on the need to correct
early modem Europe. In the absence of such an asymmetry, toleration can no longer the people that are in error and guide them to truth and salvation. Throughout the
be conceived as concession, for it refers to a horizontal relation between similar modem age, opposition to these two types of justification for intolerance repre-
forces, as in the case of the Holy Roman Empire, where political dispersion and sented the main philosophical advancement with regard to toleration. Therefore, in
independence led to an accord among reasonably equal parts that allowed different order to decisively establish the concept of toleration in principle (and not merely in
regions to have different religions, as the maxim cuius regio, eius religio shows. pragmatic terms), it was necessary to show that religious diversity does not impinge
on the social order, and that each person must be free to search for salvation in what-
ever way he deems most suitable.
1
0n the notions of concord and toleration, see Turchetti (199la, b), Bejan (2017, 20-49) and There are several concepts and arguments that can be deployed in the philosophi-
Guggisberg ( 1983, 37-39). As Laursen (1999, 4) points out, "the basic idea of concordance was cal drive to underpin toleration,6 but it is not the intention of this book to discuss all
the proto-Haberrnasian idea that we can all agree in the long run; the basic idea of tolerance is that
of them. The aim here is to analyse the reflection of one of the most important and
we will continue to disagree and dislike one another". For a broad view of research on toleration
in early modem Europe and its main interpretative lines since the end of the nineteenth century, see influential thinkers on this theme, John Locke ( 1632-1704), in order to understand,
Walsham (2006, 6-13). in more detail, how he justified religious toleration. More precisely, this book aims
2
This pejorative valence of the concept is found in the Latin origin of the word, but it is also found to elaborate an interpretation of his mature works, reconstructing his arguments and
in the Greek words to which it goes back. A s tntoµovf] and µaKpo0oµia , tolerantia describes the highlighting some of their political, ethical, theological, and epistemological
capacity to suffer an evil (both Greek terms occur in the New Testament and were translated as aspects. While it is well known that to achieve religious toleration the ends of the
patientia and longanimitas, cf. Harris 201 3, 82-83). In some vernacular languages, the negative
State must be circumscribed to the preservation and advancement of civil goods and
valence is conveyed in the synonymous of the verb to tolerate: souffrir and Leiden. On the negative
tone of toleration and its medieval heritage, see Bejczy ( 1997).
3 5 0n
For a good view of the concept of toleration in its more abstract and broader aspects, see Forst the history of toleration in France, besides Lecler (1994, 400-554), see Garrisson ( 1985),
(2003), Horton ( 1996, 2011 ) and Galeotti (2015). Labrousse ( 1990), Armogathe (1985) and Negroni (2014).
4 6 For a broad view of different approaches to toleration, see Nederrnan and Laursen ( 1996) and
On the difference between the vertical and horizontal dimensions of toleration, see Williams and
Waldron (2008, 5). Laursen and Nederrnan (1998).
4 I Introduction I Introduction 5

must never extend lU the salvation uf souls, we cannot say that the reasons for reli- the ~ame standpoint, although his writings on this theme more presuppose than
gious toleration, and the correlation of these reasons, are well-established. Moreover, exhibit it. Accordingly, since it is impossible to disentangle theology from politics,
the distinction between the secular ends of the State and the saving ends of the ethics and even epistemology, the present book points out their relations, but it
Church cover just one of the dimensions of Locke's treatment of toleration: the nonetheless emphasises the problem of truth, as we just said.8 It is important to
vertical one. But a thorough interpretation of his thought must also encompass the remember, though, that Locke himself was never a sceptic, but that he neatly saw
reasons why private persons should not impose their opinions on others in the hori- the limits of human understanding as well as the frequent misuse of truth as a justi-
zontal relationship, i.e. between themselves. Indeed, as we shall see, Locke's fication (indeed, as a pretext) for persecution.9
treatment of toleration is primarily concerned with the question why should the ends With regard to toleration, the period in which Locke lived was a troubled one.
of State not be extended to include the care of souls? But he is also interested in Born in 1632 and dying in 1704, 10 he lived through some very important events,
answering another question: why should private persons tolerate each other? With such as the end of the Thirty Years War with the Peace of Westphalia ( 1648) and the
regard to his main writings, the first question is the core of the Epistola de Tolerantia above-mentioned revocation of the Edict of Nantes by Louis XIV in October 1685.
whereas the second is touched upon in a crucial section of An Essay concerning With respect to the history of England, Locke saw the civil wars of the 1640s, the
Human Understanding. In An Essay concerning Human Understanding, though, regicide of Charles I (1649), Cromwell's Protectorate (1653-1659), the Restoration
Locke deals still with a third question: Why does a person become impositional? of Monarchy (1660) and the Glorious Revolution (1688-1689), to quote just the
Throughout the present book, issues related to epistemology will receive particu- great historical landmarks. Although it is very difficult to establish precisely how
lar attention because we believe it is necessary to disentangle three arguments that these events may have influenced Locke's treatment of toleration, it is reasonable to
are often confused, especially in the readings of the Epistola. As we shall see below, say that at one stage the entanglement of politics and religion was seen by Locke as
all of these arguments deal with the problem of truth, but they are based on different a target of attack through the distinction between the ends of State and Church and
concepts - fallibility, reciprocity and distinction between belief and knowledge - to the criticism of private persons who impose their beliefs on others, or who make
explain why the care of souls should not belong to the State, or the magistrate, as their own beliefs a pretext to violate civil laws.
Locke prefers to call it. Without clarifying these arguments, it is impossible to per- In early modem Europe, the most evident entanglement of politics and religion
ceive clearly the moral implications of the duty to examine, which, according to consisted in the statement that the State should promote salvation, and, ergo, that the
Locke, is incumbent upon human beings as rational creatures, i.e. it is impossible to use of force by the State to convert souls was legitimate. Thus, not only a civil func-
ascertain the horizontal dimension of toleration in contrast to the vertical one. By tion, the conservation of political stability, but also pastoral and ecclesiastical ones
way of introduction, we submit that the interpretation proposed here is that in the were assigned to the magistrate, since force was supposed to help guide erroneous
Epistola, the arguments of fallibility and reciprocity are politically framed because persons to communion into the only true church. As we shall see below, this view
they are related to the institution of the ends of the State (the vertical dimension of was shared and underpinned by Locke's most important critic, Jonas Proast (c.
toleration) whereas, in An Essay concerning Human Understanding , these two 1642-1710), but its origins goes back to Augustine (354-430), in particular to his
arguments are formulated and deployed with a moral purpose: to demonstrate that
private persons should not impose their opinions on others (the horizontal dimen-
sion of toleration). Meanwhile, the argument of the distinction between belief and Locke's religious worldview and the interpretations of his philosophy, see Ashcraft (1996) and
knowledge, whose locus classicus is An Essay concerning Human Understanding, Sigmund (2005).
8
is explicitly adduced in Locke's treatment of toleration only in A Third Letter, as a The present work occupies a sort of intennediary position between two groups of interpretations:
rejoinder to an important objection to the argument of reciprocity, as we shall on the one hand, the group devoted to the religious worldview that underlies Locke's treatment of
toleration, such as Stanton (2006) and Harris (2013); on the other, the group that focuses on par-
explain.
ticular explicit topics on the texts, especially the discussion of usefulness of force, such as
It must be noted, however, that the distinction between secular and sacred ends Waldron ( 1988).
related to State and Church never implied that ethics and politics could be conceived 9 Although Locke was not a sceptic and never defended toleration based on scepticism, it is conve-
without taking into account God's existence and designs. From Locke's perspective, nient to remark that there is a common view according to which there is a necessary conjunction
human life (individually and socially) is inconceivable without God's designs. between scepticism and toleration. This common view, however, is far from true. From a philo-
Therefore, it is no exaggeration to affirm that Locke's philosophy is immersed in a sophical perspective, toleration would be a straightforward issue if it could be treated in such linear
tenns. In this respect, see Popkin (1998), who discusses two branches in the modem defence of
religious worldview. 7 Inevitably, his arguments in favour of toleration also assume
toleration, the one sceptical, the other dogmatic; and Tuck (1988), who shows how scepticism can
entail intolerance. For a synthesis of this issue, see Coffey (2006).
7 1
As Harris (2002, 181) points out, "in agreement with most of his contemporaries, Locke acknowl- °For Locke's life, see Cranston ( 1985) and Woolhouse (2007), along with Le Clerc ( 1732), Coste
edged that God wanted there to be a civil government and thought that God was the moral law- ( 1735), King (1830) and Fox Bourne ( 1876). There are also excellent biographical syntheses writ-
maker". On this topic, see Dunn (1969, 1989, 1990), Waldron (2002) and Nuovo (201 1). On ten by Goldie (2010) and Milton (2011).
6 1 Introduction Introduction 7

writings concerning the Donatists, 11 where several biblical passages are seen as toleration - after all, political decisions are not based on ideology alone, but also on
authorising the use of force to correct heretics and schismatics. Compelle intrare, an circumstantial considerations. 16 Clearly a mere concession, the so-called Toleration
imperative found in Luke's version of the parable of the great banquet (14:23), is the Act ( 1689)17 suspended the penalties of part of the legislation against the Trinitarian
emblematic expression of this tradition to which Locke opposed himself, and dissenters and authorised them to worship in public. That is why it is often seen as
against which an open attack was launched by Pierre Bayle (1647-1706) in his an advancement, even if, on the one hand, nothing was conceded to Anti-Trinitarians
Philosophical Commentary on these words of the Gospel, 'Compel them to come in, and to Catholics and, on the other, the Test Act ( 1673) remained untouched.
that my house may be full ' (1686-1688)_12 In Locke's case, the opposition to In England, to sum up, the institutional debate about toleration was dualistic. The
Augustine consists not of an express rebuttal of the injunction compel them to come debate centred around what should be (r) the conduct of the State regarding those
in, but essentially of a discussion of the notions of charity in the Epistola and obsti- who do not profess the established religion (dissenters and Catholics) and (11) the
nacy in An Essay concerning Human Understanding. degree of dogmatic, disciplinary and ceremonial rigidity of the Anglican Church. In
After the Restoration of Monarchy, especially when the reestablishment of the the former case, the issue was civil toleration while, in the latter, it was ecclesiasti-
Anglican Church was at issue, this view was the main justification for the adoption cal toleration. These two branches must be demarcated because there is no neces-
of persecuting laws for dissenters and Catholics. 13 In spite of the discussions about sary bond between them. It was perfectly possible, for instance, to claim ecclesiastical
comprehension and indulgence, 14 what really took place in the aftennath of Charles toleration (as did the latitudinarians) without claiming civil toleration. 18 With respect
II's enthronement was the institution of laws 15 aimed at preserving the structure of to Locke, the defence of the distinction between the ends of State and Church falls
the Anglican Church and restricting the religious exercise of dissenters and into the field of civil toleration, but he was also in favour of ecclesiastical
Catholics. Later, after the Glorious Revolution, the same view concerning the func- toleration. 19
tions of the State still prevailed, but even so, small advances were made towards An uncertain issue with respect to Locke is the extent to which the distinction
between State and Church should be pursued. It is not clear whether the distinction
between the ends of these two societies required a real separation of them.20 It
11
Of Augustine's writings on the Donatists, the most important are Letters 93 (to Vicentius, dated
408) and 185 (to Boniface, dated 417). For a list of all Augustine's writings in the Donatist contro-
16
versy (letters, sermons and treatises). see Monceaux (1923, 275-292). There is a good synthesis of ln England, the most important circumstantial element was anti-Catholicism, which influenced
Augustine's position in Lecler (1994, 83-88) and Zagorin (2003, 24-33). On the Donatist contro- the Glorious Revolution and the so-called Toleration Act ( 1689). For a broad view of Restoration,
versy and the development of Augustine's thought on coercion, see Evers (2002~. Brown (1964) Glorious Revolution and the debate on comprehension and indulgence, see Beddard ( 1979), Spurr
and Gaddis (2005, 131- 150). For a detailed analysis of the revival of Augustine during the ( 1989), Schochet (1996) and, in particular, Coffey (2000).
Restoration, see Goldie (199 1). On intolerance at the end of the seventeenth century in several 17
Although this act is known as Toleration Act, the word 'toleration' never appears in the text of the
countries of Europe, see Marshall (2006). official document, not even in the resume of its content: "an act for exempting their majesties'
12
0n the third volume of A Philosophical Commentary, published in 1687, Bayle openly discusses Protestant subjects dissenting from the Church of England from the penalties of certain laws" (cf.
Augustine's letters: the two most important ones, letters 93 and 185, but also, on the final chapters, Browing 1953, v. VIII, 400). On the Toleration Act and its meaning, see Wykes (1990).
other letters against the Donatists. For a list of these other letters, see Bayle (2002, 21-22, n. 1). 18
ln An Essay concerning Toleration, Locke defines latitudinarianism as the amplification of the
For a comparison of Locke and Bayle, see, for example, Dunn ( 1996), Jenkinson ( 1996), Almeida terms of church communion: "few & large" articles in speculative opinions and "few & easy"
(2010) and Savonius-Wroth (2012). ceremonies in worship (cf. ET, 302). However, as we pointed out, latitudinariani sm is not neces-
13
In general, the word 'dissenter' describes those who do not follow the established religion of sarily linked with toleration; in this respect, see Ashcraft (1992). For the context of the concept,
their country. In France, the term refers to Protestants as a whole. In England, however, it refers and a general overview of the similarities and differences between Locke and other authors on lati-
only to the non-Anglican Protestants (also called non-conformists). For this reason, it is necessary tudinarianism, see Spurr (1988), Marshall (1992) and Simonutti (2003).
to point out the 'Catholics' in the universe of those who are not in the Anglican communion. 19
According to Coffey (2000, 11-13, 2006, 630), besides the civil and ecclesiastical branches of
" In a letter to Philip van Limborch ( 1633-1712) of 12 March 1689 (cf. Corr, v. III, 1120), when toleration, there are two others: a social and a polemical one. The social branch of toleration refers
once again Parliament debated comprehension and indulgence, Locke explains these notions as to the actual coexistence of private persons, usually in villages and local communities, a coexis-
follows: "the question of toleration has now been taken up in parliament under a twofold title, tence that may be hostile or courteous regardless of the legal status of dissenters and Catholics. On
namely Comprehension and Indulgence. The former signifies extension of the boundaries of the this topic, see, for instance, Bossy (1991) and Walsham (2006, 269-280). The polemical branch of
Church, with a view to including greater numbers by the removal of part of the ceremonies. The toleration, in its tum, describes the civility or incivility of the public debates and corresponds to a
latter signifies toleration of those who are either unwilling or unable to unite themselves to the reflection on the persecution of the tongue. For a reading of Locke with an emphasis on this last
Church of England on the terms offered to them". branch, see Wilhelm ( 1999) and, in particular, Bejan (20 17).
20
llTuese laws constitute the famous Clarendon Code, composed by the Corporation Act (1661 ), Act According to Goldie in his introduction to the edition of A Letter concerning Toleration and
of Uniformity (1662), Five Miles Act (1665) and Conventicle Act (1670), which were followed by Other Writings, "it is unclear if Locke was a categorical separationist. ... If we assume that Locke
two versions of the Test Act (1673). All this legislation, as well as other relevant documents on was a categorical separationist, then it is not to Britain that one would look for a modern Lockean
toleration from 1660 to 1714, is gathered in English Historical Documents, see Browing (1953, state, but to the United States, where the argument of Locke's Letter found futfillment in Thomas
v. VIll). Jefferson's Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom ( 1779), or to France, with its secular republican
8 l Introduction References 9

seems that the Stale could have an established religion as long as it did not discrimi- and their correlation. In this analysis we shall reson to some of Locke's already
nate among its citizens based on religious motives, i.e. as long as it assured equal published manuscripts, to Two Treatises of Government and to The Reasonableness
civil rights for all. At any rate, this is not a question that the present book seeks to of Christianity. In the third chapter, our task is to scrutinise the controversy between
answer. Similarly, the aim here is not to reconstruct Locke's treatment of toleration Locke and Proast, an adversary against whom Locke composed other three letters
from a chronological perspective in which, in broad terms, toleration was initially concerning toleration (the last of which remained unfinished). In the fourth chapter,
refused and later supported by him, as is commonly said when Locke's major writ- based on An Essay concerning Human Understanding, and also on the writings Of
ings on toleration are compared: on the one hand, his two speeches, one in English the Conduct of the Understanding, A Discourse of Miracles and An Essay for the
(1660), the other in Latin (c. 1662), known nowadays as Two Tracts on Government; Understanding of St Paul's Epistles by consulting St Paul himself, we discuss how
and on the other, An Essay concerning Toleration ( 1667),A Defence ofNonconformity the due examination of truth is associated with toleration. We then analyse Locke 's
(1681-82) and the Epistola de Tolerantia (1689). 21 As we said above, the present broader reflection concerning the duty to examine that is incumbent upon the human
book seeks to analyse Locke's mature reflection in order to understand, in as much being as a rational creature. From a conceptual perspective, Chaps. 2 and 3 discuss
detail as possible, how he sustains religious toleration and how he does so with the grounds for toleration concerning the relationship between State and citizens,
regard not only to the vertical relationship between State and citizens, but also to the while Chap. 4 develops the grounds for toleration with regard to the relationship
horizontal relationship between private persons. From a methodological standpoint, between private persons.
the interpretation proposed here is focused chiefly on the concepts and arguments At the end of this book, we hope to convey a coherent and comprehensive view
adduced by Locke, i.e. on the objective of identifying, defining and assessing them of Locke's mature treatment of toleration, in which we see clearly the two dimen-
by giving precedence to the texts themselves. Evidently, there are other possible sions of toleration and their grounding reasons. We also hope that this book will
approaches to Locke's writings (as well as to any other author's writings). There are provide elements for reflecting on our contemporary world, in which religious
methodological choices that emphasise the historical and political context or that fanaticism has prompted urgent discussion on the ends of State and Church, and
seek to ascertain the sources of his thought but, although relevant and fruitful, these reflection about the duties of private persons one to another.
are research itineraries that will not be adopted in this book. 22
The interpretation that will be developed here encompasses three chapters,
besides the introduction (Chap. 1) and the conclusion (Chap. 5). In the second chap-
ter, we shall examine the Epistola de Tolerantia in order to establish its arguments References

tradition of lai'cite" (Locke 2010, xiv). In this respect, see also McCabe (1997) and Pritchard Primary Sources
(2014). According to Coffey (2000, 12), Locke was a radical tolerationist who defended "the natu-
ral right or entitlement of religious dissenters to worship freely and enjoy civil equality. The most Augustine. 1870-1873. <Euvres Completes de Saint Augustin, traduites en frarn;:ais et annotees
radical tolerationists went a stage further and advocated what was later called 'disestablishment', par MM. Peronne, Vincent, Ecalle et Barreau, vol. 4 (lettres I a CV), vol. 5 (lettres CVI a
or 'the separation of church and state', a development that we tend to associate with the American CLXXXIX), vol. 6 (lettres CXC aCCLV). Paris: Librairie de Louis Vives.
and French Revolutions, but one which has never taken place in England itself'. For a contempo- - - . 2019. Retratar;oes Tr. A. Belmonte. Sao Paulo: Paulus.
rary discussion of toleration and of the so-called separation of church and state, see Maclure and Bayle, Pierre. 2002. Supplement du Commentaire Philosophique, ed. M. Pecharman. In Les
Taylor (2010), Baub6rot and Milot (2001), Laegaard (2011) and Taylor (2014). Fondements Philosophiques de la Tolerance, ed. Y.C. Zarka, F. Lessay and J. Rogers, vol. 3.
21We indicate here the dates of composition, except in the case of the Epistola, written in the
Paris: PUF.
European winter of 1685-86 and published in 1689. OfLocke's main writings on toleration, apart - - . 2014. De la Tolerance - Commentaire Philosophique, ed. J.-M. Gros. Paris: Honore
from the publication of excerpts, A Defence of Nonconformity remains unpublished. There is, Champion.
though, a transcription of the manuscript in Stanton (2003). An Essay concerni11g Toleration was Browing, Andrew. 1953. English Historical Documents 1660-1714, ed. A. Browing, vol. 8.
published for the first time in 1876 in the Life of Joh11 Locke by Fox Bourne; the Two Tracts 011 London: Eyre & Spottiswoode.
Government were originally published in 1961 by Viano (both of Locke's works received a critical Coste, Pierre. 1735. Eloge de M. Locke. In Locke, John. Essai Philosophique concernant
edition in 2006 and 1967, respectively). Of the uncountable articles and books that reconstruct and l'Entendement Humain, tr. P. Coste, trosieme edition revue, corrigee et augmentee de quelques
analyse Locke's treatment of toleration, see Gough (1973), Cranston (1987), Cay6n (1996), additions importantes de !'auteur qui n'ont paru qu'apres sa mort & de quelques remarques du
Sommerville (2004), Tate (2016) and, above all, Stanton (2013), besides the more comprehensive traducteur. Amsterdam: chez Pierre Mortier.
research of Harris ( 1998), Marshall (1994) and Collins (2020). Le Clerc, Jean. 1732. Eloge Historique de feu Mr. Locke. In Locke, J. <Euvres Diversesde M. Locke,
22 For examples of other methodological approaches, see Ashcraft ( 1986), whose research focuses tr. J. Le Clerc et al., nouvelle edition considfrablement augmentee, vol. I. Amsterdam: chez
on the historical and political context of Locke's political philosophy, and Loconte (2014), who Jean Frederic Bernard.
seeks to ascertain the sources of Locke's conception of toleration. For a discussion of methodology Locke, John. 1823. The Works of John Locke, 10 vol. London: Printed for Thomas Tegg et al.
and of the interpretations of Locke's philosophy, with an emphasis on the liberal and Marxist read- - - . 1961. John Locke - Scritti Editi e lnediti sulla Tolleranza, ed. C.A. Viano. Torino: Taylor.
ings as well as on the reading of the so-called Cambridge school, see Santos (2017). - - . 1967. Two Tracts on Government, ed. P. Abrams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
10 Introduction References 11

- - - . 1968. Epistola de tolerantia, ed. R. Klibansky and J.W. Gough. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Coffey, John. 2000. Persecution and 'JOLeration in Protestant t:ngland 1558-1689. Edinburgh:
- - - . 1976-1989. The Correspondence of John Locke, ed. E.S. de Beer, 8 vols. Oxford: Longman.
Clarendon Press. - - - . 2006. Scepticism, Dogmatism and Toleration in the Seventeenth-Century England. In
- - - . 1999. The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. J.C. Higgins-Biddle. Oxford: Persecution and Pluralism: Calvinists and Religious Minorities in Early Modern Europe
Clarendon Press. 1550-1700, ed. R. Bonney and D.J.B. Trim, 149- 176. Bern: Peter Lang.
- - -. 2000. Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. P. Schuurman. PhD dissertation, Collins, Jeffrey R. 2020. In the Shadow of Leviathan: John Locke and the Politics of Conscience.
University of Keele. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- - - . 2002. John Locke: Political Essays, ed. M. Goldie. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cranston, Maurice. 1985. John Locke: A Biography. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- - -. 2003. A Denfence of Nonconformity, Transcription T. Stanton. In Stanton, Timothy. - - - . 1987. John Locke and the Case for Toleration. In On Toleration, ed. S. Mendus and
John Locke, Edward Stillingfieet and Toleration, PhD dissertation, Appendix, University of D. Edwards, 101-121. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Leicester. Dunn, John. 1969. The Political Thought of John Locke. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- - - . 2006. An Essay Concerning Toleration and Other Writings on Law and Politics, - - - . 1989. 'Bright Enough for All Our Purposes': John Locke's Conception of a Civilized
1667- 1683, ed. J.R. Milton and P. Milton. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Society. Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 43: 133-153.
- - - . 2010. A Letter Concerning Toleration and Other Writings, ed. M. Goldie. Indianapolis: - - - . 1990. What ls Living and What Is Dead in the Political Theory of John Locke?
Liberty Fund. In Interpreting Political Responsibility: Essays 1981-1989, ed. J. Dunn, 9-25. Oxford:
- - - . 2011. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. Nidditch. Oxford: Polity Press.
Clarendon Press. - - - . 1996. The Claim of Freedom of Conscience: Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Thought,
- - -. 2015. Two Treatises of Government, ed. P. Laslett, 26 ed. Cambridge: Cambridge Freedom of Worship? In The History of Political Theory and Other Essays, ed. J. Dunn,
University Press. 100-120. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Original: Dunn, John. 1991. In From
Proast, Jonas. 1999. The Argument of the Letter Concerning Toleration Briefly consider'd and Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England, ed. O.P. Grell,
answer'd; A Third Letter Concerning Toleration: In Defense of the Argument of the Letter J.I. Israel, and N. Tyache. Oxford: Clarendon University Press.].
Concerning Toleration Briefly consider'd and answer'd; A Second Letter to the Author of the Evers, Alexander. 2002. Augustine on Church (Against the Donatists). In A Companion to
Three Letters for Toleration In The Reception of Locke 's Politics, ed. M. Goldie, vol. 5, 23-128. Augustine, ed. M. Vessey, 375-385. Malden: Blackwell.
London: Pickering & Chatto. Forst, Rainer. 2003. Toleration, Justice, Reason. In The Culture of Toleration in Diverse Societies:
Reasonable Tolerance, ed. C. McKinnon and D. Castiglione, 7 1-85. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Fox Bourne, H.R. 1876. The Life of John Locke, 2 vols. London: Henry S King.
Secondary Sources Gaddis, Michael. 2005. There ls No Crime for Those Who Ha ve Christ: Religious Violence in the
Christian Roman Empire. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Almeida, Maria C.P. 2010. A toleriincia e sua medida em John Locke e Pierre Bayle. Princfpios Galeotti, Anna E. 2015. The Range of Toleration: From Toleration as Recognition Back to
17: 31-52. Disrespectful Tolerance. Philosophy and Social Criticism 41: 93-110.
Arrnogathe, Jean-Robert. 1985. Croire en Liberti: L'Eglise catholique et la revocation de l'Edit Garrisson, Janine. 1985. L'Edit de Nantes et sa revocation: Histoire d'une intolerance. Paris:
de Nantes. Paris: O.E.l.L. Editions du Seuil.
Ashcraft, Richard. 1986. Revolutionary Politics and Locke's 'Two Treatises of Government'. Goldie, Mark. 1991. The Theory of Religious Intolerance in Restoration England. In From
Princeton: Princeton University Press. Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England, ed. O.P. Grell,
- - - . 1992. Latitudinarianism and Toleration: Historical Myth Versus Political History. J.I. Israel, and N. Tyache, 331-368. Oxford: Clarendon University Press.
In Philosophy, Science and Religion in England, 1640-1700, ed. R. Kroll et al., 151-177. - - - . 2010. The Life of John Locke. In Th e Continuum Companion to Locke, ed. S.-J. Savonious-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wroth, P. Schuurman, and J. Walmsley, 1-36. London: Continuum.
- - - . 1996. Religion and Lockean Natural Rights. In Religious Diversity and Human Rights, ed. Gough, J.W. 1973. The Development of Locke's Belief in Toleration. In John Locke 's Political
I. Bloom, J.P. Martin, and W.L. Proudfoot, 195-21 2. New York: Columbia University Press. Philosophy, ed. J.W. Gough, 2nd ed., 193-220. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bauberot, Jean, and Micheline Milot. 2001. l..ai'citis sans Frontieres. Paris: Seuil. Guggisberg, Hans R. 1983. The Defence of Religious Toleration and Religious Liberty in Early
Beddard, Robert A. 1979. The Restoration Church. In The Restored Monarchy 1660-1688, ed. Modem Europe: Arguments, Pressures, and Some Consequences. History of Eumpean Ideas
J.R. Jones, 155-175. London: Macmillan. 4: 35-50.
Bejan, Teresa M. 2017. Mere Civility: Disagreement and the Limits of Toleration. Harvard: Harris, Ian. 1998. The Mind of John Locke. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Harvard University Press. - - -. 2002. Tolerance, Eglise et Etat chez Locke Tr. M.-A. Solasse. In Les fondements philos-
Bejczy, Istvan. 1997. Tolerantia: A Medieval Concept. Journal ofthe History of Ideas 58: 365-384. ophiques de la tolerance, ed. Y.C. Zarka, F. Lessay, and J. Rogers, vol. 1, 175-218. Paris: PUF.
Bossy, John. 1991. English Catholics After 1688. In From Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious - - - . 2013. John Locke and Natural Law: Free Worship and Toleration. In Natural Law and
Revolution and Religion in England, ed. O.P. Grell, J.I. Israel, and N. Tyache, 369-387. Oxford: Toleration in the Early Enlightenment, ed. J. Parkin and T. Stanton, 59-105. Oxford: Oxford
Clarendon University Press. University Press. (Proceedings of the British Academy n. 186).
Brown, Peter. 1964. St Augustine's Attitude to Religious Coercion. The Journal of Roman Studies Horton, John. 1996. Toleration as a Virtue. In Toleration: An Elusive Virtue, ed. D. Heyd, 28-43.
54: 107-116. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Cay6n, Jose. 1996. La teoria de la tolerancia en John Locke. Madrid: Editorial Dykinson. - - -. 2011. Why the Traditional Conception of Toleration Still Matters. Critical Review of
international Social and Political Philosophy 14: 289-305.
12 Introduction References 13

Jenkinson, Sally L. 1996. Two Concepts of Tolerance: Or why Bayle Is Not Locke. The Journal of Simonutti, Luisa. 2003. Scepticism and the Theory of Toleration: Human Fallibiliry and adi-
Political Philosophy 4: 302-321. aphora. In The Return of Skepticism from Hobbes and Descartes to Bayle, ed. G. Paganini,
King, Peter. 1830. The life of John Locke with Extracts from His Correspondence, Joumals and 283-302. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Commonplace Books. New Edition with Considerable Additions in Two Volumes. London: Sommerville, Johann. 2004. Conscience, Law, and Things Indifferent: Arguments on Toleration
Henry Colburn and Richard Bentley. from the Vestiarian Controversy to Hobbes and Locke. In Contexts of Conscience in Early
Labrousse, Elisabeth. I 990. la revocation de l'Edit de Nantes: uneJoi, une loi, un roi? Paris: Payot. Modem Europe, 1500-1700, ed. H. Braun and E. Vallance, 166-1 79. Basingstoke: Palgrave
Laegaard, Sune. 2011. Religious Neutrality, Toleration and Recognition in Moderate Secular Macmillan.
States: The Case of Denmark. Les ateliers de l 'erhique, The Ethics Forum 6: 85-106. Spurr, John. 1988. 'Latitudinarianism' and the Restoration Church. The Historical Journal
Laursen, John C. 1999. Orientation: Clarifying the Conceptual Issues. In Religious Toleration: 31: 6 1-82.
"The Variety of Rites" from Cyrus to Defoe, ed. J.C. Laursen, 1-11. Scranton: Macmilliam. - - - . 1989. The Church of England, Comprehension, and the Toleration Act of 1689. The
Laursen, John C., and Nedennan, Cary J. 1998. Beyond the Persecuting Society: Religious English Historical Review I 04: 927-946.
Toleration Before the Enlightenment, ed. J.C. Laursen and C.J. Nedennan. Philadelphia: Stanton, Timothy. 2006. Locke and the Politics and Theology of Toleration. Political Studies
University of Pennsylvania Press. 54: 84-102.
Lecler, Joseph. 1994. Histoire de la tolerance au siecle de la Reforme. Paris: Albin Michel. - - - . 2013. Natural Law, Nonconformity, and Toleration: Two Stages on Locke's Way. In
Loconte, Joseph. 2014. God, Locke and Liberty: The Struggle for Religious Freedom in the West. Natural law and Toleration in the Early Enlightenment, ed. J. Parkin and T. Stanton, 35-57.
New York: Lexington Books. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Proceedings of the British Academy n. 186).
Maclure, Jocelyn, and Charles Taylor. 2010. lai'cite et liberte de conscience. Montreal: Boreal. Tate, John W. 2016. Liberty, Toleration and Equality: John Locke, Jonas Proast and the letters
Marshall, John. 1992. John Locke and Latitudinarianism. In Philosophy, Science and Religion in Concerning Toleration. New York: Routledge.
England, 1640-1700, ed. Kroll et al., 253-282. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, Charles. 2014. How to Define Secularism. In Boundaries of Toleration, ed. A. Stepan and
- - - . 1994. John Locke: Resistance, Religion and Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge C. Taylor, 59-78. New York: Columbia University Press.
University Press. Tuck, Richard. 1988. Scepticism and Toleration in the Seventeenth Century. In Justifying
- - - . 2006. John Locke, Toleration and Early Enlightenment Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives, ed. S. Mendus, 21-35. New York:
University Press. Cambridge University Press.
McCabe, David. 1997. John Locke and the Argument Against Strict Separation. The Review of Turchetti, Mario. 199la. Religious Concord and Political Tolerance in Sixteenth- and Seventeenth-
Politics 59: 233-258. Century France. The Sixteenth Century Journal 22: 15-25.
Milton, J.R. 201 1. A vida ea epoca de Locke In Locke, ed. V. Chappell and tr. G. Rodrigues Neto, - - - . 1991b. Une question mal posee: Erasme et la tolerance. L'idee de sygkatabasis.
17-40. Campinas: ldeias & Letras. [Original: Milton, J.R. 1999. The Cambridge Companion Bibliotheque d'Humanisme et Renaissance 53: 379-395.
to Locke, ed. V. Chappell, 5-25. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.] Waldron , Jeremy. 1988. Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution. In Justifying
Monceaux, Paul. 1923. Histoire litteraire de l'Afrique Chretienne depuis les origines ajusqu'a Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives, ed. S. Mendus, 61-86. Cambridge:
/'invasion arabe. Vol. 7. Paris: Editions Ernest Leroux. Cambridge University Press.
Nederman, Cary J., and Laursen, John C. 1996. Difference and Dissent: Theories of Toleration in - - - . 2002. God, Locke and Equality: Christian Foundations of John Locke's Political Thought.
Medieval and Early Modem Europe, ed. C.J. Nederman and J.C. Laursen. New York: Rowman Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
& Littlefield Publishers. Walsham, Alexandra. 2006. Charitable Hatred: Tolerance and Intolerance in England, 1500-1700.
Negroni, Barbara de. 2014. Intolerances: catho/iques et protestants en France, 1560-1787. Paris: Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Artheme Fayard. Wilhelm, Anthony G. 1999. Good Fences and Good Neighbors: John Locke's Positive Doctrine of
Nuovo, Victor. 201 1. Locke's Religious Thinking and His Politics. In Christianity, Antiquity and Toleration. Political Research Quarterly 52: 145- 166.
Enlightenment: Interpretations of Locke, 235-246. New York: Springer. Williams, Melissa S., and Jeremy Waldron. 2008. Introduction. In Toleration and Its Limits, ed.
Popkin, Richard. 1998. Skepticism About Religion and Millenarian Dogmatism: Two Sources of M.S. Williams and J. Waldron, 1-27. New York: New York University Press. (Nomos XLVIIO.
Toleration in the Seventeenth Century. In Beyond the Persecuting Society: Religious Toleration Woolhouse, Roger. 2007. Locke: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Before the Enlightenment, ed. J.C. Laursen and C.J. Nederman, 232-250. Philadelphia: Wykes, David L. 1990. The Tricentenary of the Toleration Act of 1689: A Cause for Celebration?
University of Pennsylvania Press. In Truth and Tolerance, ed. E.J. Furcha, 60-82. Montreal: Faculty of Religious studies, McGill
Pritchard, Elizabeth A. 2014. Religion in Public: Locke's Political Theology. Stanford: Stanford University.
University Press. Zagorin, Perez. 2003. How the Idea of Religious Toleration Came to the West. Princeton: Princeton
Santos, Antonio C. 2017. John Locke ea diversidade de interpreta~oes. Sapere Aude 8: 469-491. University Press.
Savonius-Wroth, S.J. 2012. 'Lovers of Truth' in Pierre Bayle's and John Locke's Thought. In
The Intellectual Consequences of Religious Heterodoxy /600-I 750, ed. S. Mortimer and
J. Robertson, 155-180. Leiden: Brill.
Schochet, Gordon J. 1996. The Act of Toleration and the Failure of Comprehension: Persecution,
Nonconformity, and Religious Indifference. In The World of William and Mary: Anglo-Dutch
Perspectives on the Revolution of I688-89, ed. D. Hoak and M. Feingold, 165-187. Stanford:
Stanford University Press.
Sigmund, Paul E. 2005. Jeremy Waldron and the Religious Turn in Locke Scholarship. The Review
of Politics 67: 407-418.
Chapter 2
The Argumentative Structure
of the Epistola de Tolerantia

Abstract This chapter aims to identify and analyse the argumentative structure of
the Epistola de Tolerantia. The interpretation developed here argues that there are
two dimensions of toleration in Locke's reasoning-a vertical one (State-to-citizens)
and a horizontal one (citizen-to-citizen)- and that, when considering his arguments,
both dimensions should be taken into account. Vertical toleration relates to the so-
called three considerations and other important arguments. Deeply intertwined, they
constitute the core of the Epistola de Tolerantia, whose central purpose is to dem-
onstrate that the ends of the Commonwealth cannot be extended to the care of souls,
i.e. that the magistrate has no commission to use force in religious matters.
Horizontal toleration, meanwhile, is fonned by a single argument built on the
notions of meekness and charity. Its aim is to show that no Christian shall compel
his neighbour in religious matters, because force is incompatible with Christ's life
and teachings.

Toleration is the abstention from force as a means to convert souls (cf. SL, 2, 6,
Works, 62, 67). 1 Formulated in 1690, approximately one year after the publication
of the Epistola de Tolerantia, Locke's definition presents, in a few words, a duty that
private persons, churches, clergymen and the magistrate should respect. The great
challenge, though, is to substantiate this. Why should one not compel others to sal-
vation when one has the power to do so and believes that he has the truth? Why

1 In his Second Letter, Locke addresses Proast as follows: "Force, you allow, is improper to convert

Men to any Religion. Toleration is but the removing that Force" (SL, p. 2, Works, p. 62); "The
purpose of the Letter is plainly to defend Toleration, exempt from all Force; especially Civil Force,
or the Force of the Magistrate" (SL, p. 6, Works, p. 66). ln A Defence of Noncofonnity, Locke
defines toleration as follows: "taking off the power of the Magistrate from restraining any differ-
ences amongst Christians" (DNC, 7), and, in the same vein, "takeing off the Magistrates hand from
holding men close to uniformity" (DNC, 42). In a similar fashion, this straightforward definition is
also adopted by Bayle. In a letter to David Constant de Rebecque (1638-1733) from 16/26 July
1690, he says that toleration (in his own words, "political toleration") "is nothing but the exemp-
tion from the penal laws" (Bayle 1737, 645).

© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature 15


Switzerland AG 2022
F. F. Loque, John Locke and the Grounds for Toleration, International Archives
of the History ofideas Archives intemationales d'histoire des idees 237,
https://doi.org/l 0.1007/978-3-030-90363-3_2
16 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de To/erantia 17

should one accept religious diversity? In the Epistola, the most famous arguments advancement of civil goods (cf. Epist., 64.27-28).5 It is in this context - the effon to
to support toleration can be easily found (cf. Epist., 66.19-70.17). They are what define the ends of the Commonwealth and hence its legitimate sphere of action -
Popple's translation2 designates three considerations, but besides not comprising all that the three considerations are introduced. In political terms, the defence of tolera-
of Locke's arguments, neither their interpretation nor their value is consensual. tion requires a distinction to be made between the ends of Church and State, so that
The first and foremost expression of this lack of consensus about Locke's argu- the care for the salvation of souls should be left exclusively to private persons and
ments is Proast's The Argument of the 'Letter concerning Toleration' briefly the religious societies they enter into, each one of these societies searching to pro-
consider'd and answer'd, since he judged that there was just one argument in cure salvation through its own way. To put it crudely, the distinction between the
Locke's reasoning (cf. Arg., 3-4, RLP, 26-27). 3 Nonetheless, at the beginning of A ends of Church and State means that each person should be allowed to search for his
Second Letter (cf. SL, 6, Works, 67), Locke presents a metaphor to contest this read- own salvation in the church he deems most appropriate, i.e. that the magistrate
ing: from his perspective, the house he has built is supported by several beams, not should not legislate - in other words, prescribe penalties - concerning religion.
just one. If one of them were removed, the others would hold it up. This analogy is If a person is to be punished when he professes his religion, this must never be
not enough to prove the insufficiency, maybe even the error, of Proast's reading (a done for religious reasons, only for political ones, as the sole obligation of the civil
metaphor is not an argument), but it is an excellent illustration of the way Locke power is to maintain public order. The magistrate must be guided by political rea-
himself conceived the Epistola, and a significant indication of the difficulty of inter- sons, as we see in Locke's exposition of intolerable practical beliefs (cf. Epist.,
preting it, especially if we take into account the historical recurrence of readings 130.12-134.21) and in his example of the prohibition of the slaughter of calves (cf.
like that of Proast.4 If Locke makes so blunt an opposition to his main critic's read- Epist., 108.23-110.26). In summary, it is incumbent upon the civil power to punish
ing, and it continues to be formulated centuries later, we shall conclude that his case crimes, not heresies, schisms or sins. The distinction between the ends of Church
for toleration is more intricate than he imagines. and State sustained in the Epistola implies that the magistrate has no duty regarding
As for the metaphor, it is important to emphasise two conclusions that may be beliefs and ways of worship as such, but solely regarding the consequences these
drawn from it: firstly, there are different arguments to support toleration; secondly, may have to civil society. Only their political dimension must concern the magis-
they are independent of each other, each capable of supporting the whole building trate, not their religious dimension.
by itself. Nevertheless, when Locke explains the metaphor and sets out the argu- In this sense, Locke's main arguments - i.e. the three considerations - are
ments that he describes as the beams of his case for toleration, they do not corre- intended to support the thesis that the magistrate's jurisdiction must be concerned
spond exactly to the famous three considerations found in the Epistola. It is puzzling "only" (unice) with the civil goods, that the right and dominion of the civil power
that Locke does not follow literally that exposition enumerated by the adverbs must be circumscribed and limited "solely" (so/is) by the care and advancement of
primo, secundo, tertio which seemed to contain the central points of his reasoning. these goods, and that the magistrate's jurisdiction neither can nor ought "in any
Hence, we may ask (1) what, precisely, the arguments to support toleration are and manner" (ullo modo) comprise the salvation of souls (cf. Epist., 66.14- 18).6 Locke's
(n) how they relate to each other. Without answering these questions, it is impossi- case for toleration, therefore, is essentially focused on the restriction of the ends of
ble to understand the controversy with Proast and assess the grounds for religious the State, i.e. on the vertical dimension of toleration. In A Second Letter, referring
toleration proposed by Locke. to the author of the Epistola as a third person, Locke sums up his purpose as fol-
Nonetheless, before analysing Locke's arguments and the relationship between lows: "all that he endeavours, is to show the bounds of Civil Power; and that in
them, we must have a clear idea of what it means to support religious toleration in punishing others for Religion, the Magistrate misapplies the Force he has in his
the seventeenth century. As the Epistola shows, the duty to tolerate relates to private hands, and so goes beyond Right, beyond the limits of his Power" (SL, 66,
persons, churches, clergymen and the magistrate (cf. Epist., 78.lss). None of them Works, 135).
are permitted to use force in religious matters, but Locke stresses the role of the
magistrate, whose jurisdiction must be circumscribed to the preservation and
5 Locke writes " ... ad bona civilia conservanda promovendaque", which Popple translates as

" ... for the procuring, preserving and advancing their own civil interests" (Popple, 15).
2 0n Popple's life and thought, see Robbins (1967) and Simonutti (1998). 6 As Spitz (2002, 114) says, "Locke does not take the right to liberty of conscience as a starting
3 It
is the argument of unfitness of force, as we shall see below. In The Argument edited by Vernon point in order to show, then, that all legitimate government ought to respect this right and so abstain
(Proast 2010, 55), there is a mistake in the passage referred to here: one should read single argu- from all persecution. Rather, he meditates on the possible governmental functions in order to show
ment and not.final argument. that compelling consciences is not one of them". Accordingly, it seems inadequate to divide
4
Undoubtedly, Waldron (1988) is the greatest contemporary example of a reading of the Epistola Locke's defence of toleration into two branches, civil and religious, as Silva (2013) does. Although
focused on the argument of unfitness of force. Concerning this topic, see also Spitz (2002) and the duty to tolerate regards churches and clergymen (besides private persons and the magistrate),
Bou-Habib (2003). For a critical assessment of this reading, see Schwartzman (2005) and Chen this does not amount to two different types of toleration, a civil toleration based on the first consid-
(2006), but in particular Stanton (2006) and Harris (2013). eration and a religious toleration based on the second consideration.
18 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.1 The Evangelical Argument 19

From Locke's perspective, although it is necessary to distinguish between the scriptural and non-scriptural arguments should cause no wonder either, given that
ends of Church and State, the magistrate is not supposed to abandon altogether the toleration is "agreeable" (consona) to the Gospel and to reason (cf. Epist., 64.10-12).
care of the salvation of souls. Indeed, he is required not to seek this goal by the use In either case, nevertheless, it is important to note the sense and the limits ofLocke's
of force - that is, by the use of his power as magistrate to prescribe laws and thereby reasoning. Hence, considering Locke's reasoning as a whole, we may say that the
resort to coercion. 7 However, the magistrate is not forbidden to resort to discourses, Epistola displays four arguments: the three considerations and the argument con-
as any private person, clergyman or church. He is not forbidden to teach, admonish, cerning charity, with which we shall begin our analysis.
and persuade. There is a crucial distinction between two types of care: cura authori-
tativa, based on authority, and cura charitativa, based on charity (cf. Epist., 90.6-7):
"in teaching, instructing, and correcting the erroneous by arguments, he certainly
does what it becomes any good man to do; the magistrate is not obliged to put off 2.1 The Evangelical Argument
either humanity or Christianity" (Epist., 68.12-15). Locke's purpose is to remove
from the magistrate just one of the means by which the conversion of souls can sup- Of all the arguments displayed in the Epistola, the first is the one concerning charity.
posedly be wrought. All the others - that amount to discourse but also to the exam- As we have seen, this argument is based on Scripture, particularly the New
ple of a good life - are preserved. Testament, and for that reason it is described here as confessional. This argument -
There is no doubt that by establishing the distinction between magisterial and which we shall call the evangelical argument - is found especially in the prologue
charitable care, Locke wishes to stress that the use of force cannot be conceived as (cf. Epist., 58.1-64.26). 10 It is grounded on a conception of Christianity as conform-
a charitable act and, thereupon, that Christians must abstain from it as a means to ing to the example of Christ, the Prince of Peace, according to Locke (cf. Epist.,
save souls. If charitable admonitions and endeavours to refute errors "are indeed a 64. l; Isaiah 9:6). In his own words, "if the Gospel and the Apostles are to be
Christian's greatest duties (maxima ... officia)" (Epist., 124.9-10),8 their accom- believed, no man can be a Christian without charity (sine charitate), and without the
plishment must necessarily be exempt from force. "We pray every day for their faith which worketh, not by force, but by love" (Epist., 58.25-26; cf. Galatians 5:6).
Conversion, and I think it is our Duty so to do", Locke says in reference to Pagans, In the opening pages of the Epistola, some passages of the New Testament are
Muslims, and Jews when he replies Proast's critique concerning the extension of expressly mentioned: Luke 22, Romans 1, Galatians 5, and some others are alluded
toleration proposed in the Epistola, "but it will, I fear, hardly be believed that we to, such as Mathew 11, Luke l 4, 2 Corinthians 10. 11 Nevertheless, it is the reference
pray in earnest, if we exclude them from the other ordinary and probable means of to Galatians 5, in particular to Galatians 5:6, that is the most important point to
Conversion, either by driving them from, or persecuting them when they are amongst highlight, because it is based on this passage that Locke not only sustains the bold
us" (SL, 2, Works, 62). opposition between love and force, but also emphasises action over belief. In The
According to Locke, there is a Christian duty to evangelise, 9 a duty that Proast Reasonableness of Christianity, Locke quotes the same passage when he speaks of
also acknowledges (cf. TL-P, 2, RLP, 42), but the use of force as a means to lead the obedience to Christ's laws, and again he stresses the role of love and action. In The
erroneous to salvation is incompatible with Christianity: coercion affronts charity, Reasonableness of Christianity, Locke reiterates his interpretation, citing the sec-
the main Christian principle. This incompatibility between force and charity consti- ond chapter of the Epistle of James, whose predominant theme is faith and works
tutes, then, an argument to support religious toleration, but it is distinct from the
three considerations in two aspects, as we shall see below: firstly, given its theologi-
cal and moral character, it corresponds to the horizontal toleration (whereas the
three considerations have a political character and so correspond to the vertical tol-
10
eration); secondly, since it is based on Scripture it has a confessional nature (while The expression evangelical argument was inspired by Goldie and Popkin (2006, 102), who speak
the three considerations tend to have no appeal to Scripture and so have a secular of an "evangelical case for toleration". However, the sense we give to this expression is different
from that of Goldie and Popkin. Here, evangelical argument is the name given to a specific argu-
nature). These differences are not a problem, however. It is no wonder that Locke ment concerning charity or love and Christ's example, which corresponds to just one conceptual
sustains toleration in its vertical and horizontal dimensions. Moreover, his use of strand explored in the evangelical case.
11
When Locke gives the references of his quotations in the prologue of the Epistola, he mentions
7
the chapters, but not the verses. The complete references are as follows: Luke 22:25-26, 22: 32,
Evidently, it means here physical force or the threat to use it. However, in the Epistola there are Romans I: 19, Galatians 5: 19-21 (the first edition of Popple's translation interpolated a quotation
metaphors relating the notion of force to persuasion, as Walker (1996) shows.
from 2 Timothy 2: 19: "let every one that nameth the name of Christ depart from iniquity"). As for
8 Translation slightly altered.
the allusions, we fi nd Matthew 11 :29-30, 26:52-53, Luke 14:26, 2 Corinthians 10:4, Ephesians
9
For an interpretation of the modem debate on toleration and the duty to evangelise, see Goldie and 6:10-18, Hebrews 2:10, besides the important allusion to Isaiah 9:6. In the case of Galatians
Popkin (2006, 99-104). See also Goldie's introduction to his edition of A Letter (Locke, 2010, 5: 19-21 , Locke does not mention "heresies" as one of the "works of the flesh", as Wolfson (2010,
xi- xii) and Marshall (1994, 179). 85-91) points out.
20 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2. 1 The Evangelical Argument 21

(cf. RC, 118, §§ 210-211; Epistle ofJames 2:14-26). 12 ln a manuscript of uncertain religiosity in practice, towards other Christians and towards the followers of other
date 13 entitled Tolerantia Pro, Locke lists a series of biblical passages in favour of religions. 17
toleration 14 and presents the same perspective: all the verses extracted from the New Ultimately, Locke gives prominence to the way people live, to the obedience to
Testament are concerned with love and its practice, as well as the persecution of Christ's example, "the great pattern for our imitation" (Pol. Es., Pacific Christians,
Christ's followers; the verses taken from the Old Testament explore the treatment § 6, 305); metaphorically, what really matters is to "tread in his steps" (Epist., 64.1 ).
given to foreigners. 15 For Locke, therefore, the core of Christianity is a faith that This is why Locke insists on the centrality either of meekness, charity and benevo-
consists in love and charitable actions, a faith, then, that is incompatible with the use lence, or of sanctity of life, chastity of custom and goodness. There cannot be a
force, i.e. with intolerance. better way to follow Christ than to engage in the struggle against vices and the cul-
According to Locke, toleration should be understood as a way to follow Christ's tivation of virtues, particularly the greatest one of all: charity. Any conscientious
example. Persecution of supposed heretics or schismatics is contrary to the evan- conviction, "even though erroneous" (quam erronea), 18 or any abstention of out-
gelical laws, to the precepts of charity (cf. Epist., 146.4-5). Hence, when Locke ward worship, if accompanied by an innocent life, is not so contrary to God as a
responds to the question about mutual toleration among Christians in the opening vicious life (cf. Epist., 60.15-17). What is the point of searching to rectify the dog-
paragraph of the Epistola, he states that toleration is "the chief distinguishing mark mas of a so-called heterodox person, to correct his ceremonies, if the one who per-
(praecipuum ... criterium) of a true church" (Epist., 58.3). The explanation is sim- secutes does not extirpate his own vices, if he is negligent with the moral errors of
ple: intolerance is contrary to Christ's example. Other criteria may be cited as dis- his own close friends and relatives? As we see in the post scriptum to the Epistola,
tinguishing marks of a true church, for instance, the antiquity of places and names, Locke rejects the zeal devoted to subtle questions, to things that surpass the com-
the splendour of ritual, the reformation of teaching, or the orthodoxy of faith, but mon human grasp. To him, there is no doubt that this "zeal" (zelus) serves as a pre-
these can hardly be taken as "signs" (notae) of the church of Christ. Rather, they are text to cover non-religious interests, especially when the "fanatics" (zelotae) make
probably signs of a desire for power and empire. Thus, nothing more clearly distin- use of force or violence against the supposed heterodox believers.
guishes a true church (and a true Christian) than toleration, which is tantamount to In the manuscript Toleration A (c. 1675), there is a severe criticism of clergymen
saying that no intolerant church (or person) can be considered Christian. 16 who do not use "the meekness and tender methods of the Gospel" to attract more
Nonetheless, the incompatibility between Christianity and intolerance has two fea- members to their congregations. 19 When force is used to increase the number of
tures that need to be highlighted: the first, as we read in the prologue to the Epistola, church members, we can suspect, as Locke says, "that 'tis not the feeding of the
concerns the relationship between Christians and Christian churches; the second, as sheep, but the benefit of the fleece that makes these men endeavour by such methods
Locke says in the conclusion of the Epistola (cf. Epist., 142.32-144.3) and in A to enlarge their fold" (Pol. Es., Toleration A, 231 ). In A Defence of Nonconformity,
Third Letter (cf. TL, 183, Works, 354), concerns the attitude of Christians and we find a similar remark when Locke points out that "it is no wonder they should
Christian churches towards other religions and their followers. In summary, Locke contend for the largnesse of their flocks since they have the more to milk, & shear
contends that the use of force in religious matters is incompatible with Christianity, & have often the selling of them" (cf. DNC, 5", 15). Strictly speaking, Locke reveals
and that nobody can be called a Christian if he does not show his charitable an enormous lack of confidence in, sometimes even contempt towards clergymen,

12 The relevance of works - and not only of faith - is a point Locke also stresses in his Paraphrase
"Marshall (1994, 367) affirms that in the Epistola there is "the unequivocal statement that it was
and Notes on the Epistles of St Paul, as Russo (2019, 129) singles out: "the task Locke set for a duty of Christianity to tolerate others" and, along the same lines, Marshall (1994, 104) states that
himself in his last essay was precisely the attempt to "save works" on a Scriptural, Pauline basis, "persuasion ... had been Christ's method". According to Harris (2013, 84), "tolerantia is a product
ground the need for doing good squarely in the Bible, and oppose those interpretations of Christian of love". As Curley (2017) shows, it is radically different from Augustine's position. Marshall
faith that would lead to an ethically anarchical world incomprehensible to reason". (1994, 119-121 , 367) points out that, in a draft on Galatians 5 :6 among Locke's manuscripts,
13 Goldie (Locke 2010, xl) estimates that the manuscript was written between 1676 and 1690 whilst
which he dates from January 1667 and thinks unlikely to be from Locke himself, one of its pas-
Marshall (2006, 367) considers that it is from 1688. sages speaks of "evangelick charity" and states that it is "not confined to those of our opinion, or
14 party, or brotherhood, but is extended far and wide".
"Matthew 5:43-48, 7:24-27, Luke 6:27-28, Romans J 2: J4, 20-21, 1 Peter 3:9, Luke 23:34, Acts
7:60, 1 Corinthians 4:12-13, Galatians 5:9-10, Deuteronomy 14:21, 15:3, 23:19-20, 28:43, 18
Translation slightly altered.
Exodus 22:2 1, 33:9,Leviticus 19:10, Jeremiah 7:6, 22:3, 'Zachariah 7: 10, Malachi 3:5, Deuteronomy 19
It would not be amiss to observe that, in the article 87 [97) of The Fundamental Constitutions of
10:18, 21:14" (cf. Locke 2010, 189). Caroline, where there is an express mention of "diversity of opinions", the conversion of heathens,
is In the Epistola, there is one reference to the New Testament concerning foreigners, 1 Corinthians Jews and dissenters is supposed to be wrought "by good usage and persuasion, and all those con-
5: 12-13, which aims to demonstrate that the church does not desire their exclusion from the vincing methods of gentleness and meekness suitable to the rules and design of the Gospel" (cf.
Commonwealth (cf. Epist., 144.4). Pol. Es., The Fundamental..., 178). Likewise, in A Defence of Nonconfonnity Locke states that the
16 This reasoning supposes that Christianity is the true religion. In A Second Letter, this supposition ways Christ authorises are "those wayes of meeknesse, & gentlenesse preaching of the gospell in
is openly admitted (SL, 2, Works, 63). simplicity, & exemplarinesse of life in conversation" (DNC, 110).
22 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.1 The Evangelical Argument 23

given the fact that the zeal for a church, "combined with love of dominion" (cum tion, but, as soon as they become superior due to the magistrate's favour, they trans-
amore dominandi conjunctus),20 can "easily" (commode) degenerate into a pretext gress peace and Christian charity. Is it not interesting that when they are inferior in
for rapine and ambition (cf. Epist. , 112.28-114.3). In the conclusion of the Epistola, power, they make no effort to refute the errors that are pleasing to the magistrate and
Locke expresses his mistrust even more directly, when he states that the cause of to the court? (cf. Epist. , 82.25-84.11).
religious disputes and wars does not lie in the "diversity of opinions" (opinionum There are yet three other points in this historical reading of the ascension of
diversitas), but in the refusal of toleration, and when he accuses church leaders of Christianity in the manuscript Toleration A: (d) princes favoured those who pro-
inciting both the magistrate and the people against the supposed heterodoxies "due moted their authority, (e) the magistrate began to judge religious dissension danger-
to their avarice and will for dominion" (avaritia et dominandi libidine) (cf. Epist., ous and assumed the duty to punish those who, according to the clergy, were
144.24-146.7). 21 heretics, schismatics and fanatics, and (f) people fonned confederacies and combi-
In The Reasonableness of Christianity, Locke employs, for the first time in his nations to protect themselves when they realized that they could be harmed for
writings, the word 'priestcraft' (RC, 162, § 286) to indicate the clergymen's inclina- worshipping God in their own way, so that the clash between the oppressor and
tion to dominion and the political and religious distortions that it implies.22 However, people's desire of religious freedom often resulted in persecution and war. These
this critique had been formulated by him many years earlier, at least since An Essay three points can be found in the Epistola in almost the same words. The third one is
concerning Toleration, where he states that compulsion as a means to convert has explored in a long section in which Locke discusses the popular view of assemblies
nothing to do with the expansion of truth, but with interest and dominion (cf. ET, as seditious and factional (cf. Epist., 134.22-140.27). At any rate, what is essential
296). In the manuscript Toleration A , written almost a decade after An Essay con- here is to note that the conflation of Church and State stems from the clergymen's
cerning Toleration , the same critique appears, but with more detail, some of which vicious conduct. Instead of seeking virtue and guiding themselves by charity, they
is restated in the Epistola. In this text composed around 1675, Locke imagines that resort to religion as a pretext to gain power. In the name of faith, they try to achieve
throughout history the magistrates of different Commonwealths abstained from their desire for dominion by imposing beliefs and ways of worships, i.e. by perse-
meddling with indifferent things in religion because once these things enter a cult, cuting dissenters.
they cease to be indifferent to this or that devotee, who considers that they are pleas- As we can see, Locke's conception of Christianity has a moral nature. Locke
ing to God. However, there was a change when Christianity became the established stresses the importance of action and life compared to belief and worship. So great
religion. Since then, "affecting dominion" (Pol. Es., Toleration A, 233), clergymen is his emphasis on the moral nature of the Christian religion that in the manuscript
started to vindicate an independent power from the civil government, so that (a), Error (1698) he uses the expression "saving orthodoxy" as exempt from any refer-
when the magistrate was more powerful than they were, they pretended that their ence to beliefs and ceremonies: "I lay it down as a principle of Christianity, that the
own power was only spiritual, but yet pressed him to persecute those they disliked, right and only way to saving orthodoxy, is the sincere and steady purpose of a good
and when that happened, they made an apology of the divine right of monarchy, but life" (Pol. Es., Error, 347). In another manuscript from 1698, Sacerdos, in which
(b) when the magistrate was not serviceable to them, they were the first to question Locke points out the reunion of religion and morality in Christ, branches that in
his authority and to disturb the government; finally, (c) when they could not con- Antiquity were split between priests and philosophers, he states that, "for the obtain-
front the prince, they were liberals. In this sense, Locke remarks in the Epistola that ing the favour and forgiveness of the deity, the chief part of what man could do
the great combatants for truth rarely manifest their zeal when the magistrate is not consisted in a holy life, and little or nothing at all was left to outward ceremony"
on their side. When the magistrate is not on their side, they encourage mutual tolera- (Pol. Es., Sacerdos, 344-5). Around the same time, Locke wrote in one of his bibles:
"the reforming our lives is the way to believe the Gospel".23 In this sense, it is clear
how much this conception of Christianity reduces the relevance of disputes con-
20
Translation slightly altered. cerning doctrines and rituals, and how it states the centrality of the imitation of
21Translation slightly altered. According to Ashcraft (2009, 60), "Locke's position in the Letter
Christ, who persecuted nobody and asked his disciples to convert souls through
concerning Toleration expresses a radical anticlericalism ... While Locke's discussion in the Letter
centres on the magi strate's use of force - because he is the only authority that can legitimately
exemplary conduct and evangelical lessons - never through the use of force. As
employ force for any purpose - Locke has no doubt that the real force driving religious persecution Locke notes, "the Gospel frequently declares that the true disciples of Christ must
is the clergy". When Locke unveils the clergy's interest, he presents what can be called, according expect and suffer persecution; but that the true church of Christ should persecute or
to Tarcov ( 1999), the psychological foundations of intolerance. In the present book, we shall give censure others, or compel them by force, by sword and fire, to embrace her faith and
a different meaning to what we shall call psychological justification for intolerance. doctrines, I do not remember to have read anywhere in the New Testament" (Epist.,
22Jn his introduction to A Letter concerning Toleration and Other Writings, Goldie notes that the
word priestcraft "became fashionable in the 1690s" and that "it denoted a general theory of the
23
propensities of all priesthoods to pervert religion in pursuit of earthly domination" (Locke 2010, This note is mentioned by MarshalJ (1994, 373) and Marshall (1990, 997-998), who explains
xxii). On priestcraft, see also Goldie (2018) and Lancaster (2018). For a broader treatment of the that it summarises Locke and Benjamin Whichcote's (1609-1683) views of faith and represents
issue, see Lancaster and McKenzie-McHarg (2018). "the later soteriology of Locke himselr'.
24 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.1 The Evangelical Argument 25

76.4-9). In the manuscript Pacific Christians (1688), a sort of catalogue of princi- accomplished (cf. Letters, 87.8, 88.l l , 93.5.18, 105.2.5-6, 204.4; Psalms 2:2,
ples for a religious society,24 Locke not only subscribes to the same position, but 10-11, 72:11), penalties can be imposed on those who refuse the unity of the
also relates it to the problem of the unity among Christians and acknowledges the Church. If persuasion was, originally, the only means to restore those who divided
impossibility of avoiding difference of opinions: the Church, then afterwards, another means became available: force. In Augustine's
Nothing being so opposite, or having proved so fatal to unity, love and charity, the first and
reading of the parable of the great banquet, these two epochs and means correspond
great characteristical duties of Christianity, as men's fondness of their own opinions, and to the two actions of the man who laid on the great feast. When his originally invited
their endeavours to set them up and have them followed, instead of the Gospel of peace; to guests made excuses not to come, he asked his servant to "conduct" (adducere) 27 to
prevent these seeds of dissention and division, and maintain unity in the difference of opin- his house the poor, the maimed, the halt and the blind, but finding that there was still
ions which we know cannot be avoided, if anyone appears contentious, abounding in his room, he then asked the servant to go into the "highways and hedges" and to "com-
own sense rather than in love, and desirous to draw followers after himself, with destruction
or opposition to others, we judge him not to have learned Christ as he ought, and therefore
pel" (cogere) them come in, hence the distinction between "gently" (leniter) con-
not fit to be a teacher of others (Pol. Es., Paci.fie Christians,§ 8, 305-306). ducting and compelling (Letter, 185.6.24). For Augustine, the great banquet
represents the Church, and the highways and hedges are a figure for heresies and
Although Locke never literally states it, his line of thought may have led him to schisms. Pointing out that some erroneous people are not corrected through persua-
the express statement that Christ is tolerant. Nevertheless, even without a literal sion, that they resist the "evident" (Letters, 88.9, 185.10.47) and "most manifest"
statement as such, it is clear that his conception of Christianity contradicts the domi- truth (Letters, 128.4, 141.2, 141.13, 144.1 ), Augustine infers that their correction
nant one of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, i.e. the conception inspired by requires coercion. Being too hardened, "they cannot be corrected with words" (ver-
Augustine's epistles written in the Donatist controversy. It is strange that Locke bis emendari non potest), but they can be corrected "with a bit of severity of the
never mentioned it, given that he cannot be supposed not to know it. It was ubiqui- discipline" (aliquantula severitate disciplinae) (Letter, 185.7 .26), as Augustine says
tous in the modem debate on toleration. 25 In the work The 'Letter for Toleration' euphemistically. This "hardness" (duritia) that makes force necessary to conversion
deciphrer'd, and the absurd and impiety of an absolute toleration demonstrated, the is, so to speak, a psychological justification for intolerance. Augustine also describes
very first critique of the Epistola, Thomas Long (1621-1707) refers to the Donatist it in other terms - obstinacy (cf. Letters, 43.1.1, 53.3.7, 89.1, 89.3, 139.1, 185.10.47),
controversy and cites De Correctione Donatistarum that Augustine addressed to perversity (cf. Letters, 43.1.1, 53.3.7, 56.2, 87.9, 89.2-3, 93.3.10, 97.4, 105.2.6,
Boniface. Proast himself acknowledges that his method, which Locke sarcastically 139.1, 185.1.1 ) and animosity (cf. Letters, 33.5, 43.1.l, 82.2. 93.3.10, 93.5.17) -
describes, several times, as "new" in A Second Letter (e.g., SL, 24, 30, 42, Works, and seems to associate it with the notion of habit (cf. Letters, 52.4, 56.2, 89.6, 89.7,
87, 93, 107), was "at least as old as St. Austin" (TL-P, 43, Works, 82). 93.1.1-2, 141.13, 142.4, 185.7.29). Metaphorically speaking, the erroneous people
Certainly, we must admit that Christianity may be conceived in different ways. who resist conversion through words alone are seen as frenetics and lethargies that
As we can see by Augustine's position, it is possible that these different conceptions must be refrained or awaked for their own health (cf. Letters, 89.6, 93.2.4) and as
have scriptural basis besides the emblematic compelle intrare found in the parable children whose parents, for the love of them, must not spare the rod (cf. Letters,
of the great banquet in Luke 14:23. 26 The gist of Augustine's view is that since the 133.2, 185.6.21, 173.3; Proverbs 13:24, 23:14, 29:19, Ecclesiasticus 30:12). For
prophecies concerning the submission of the secular power to God were Augustine, the point at stake is not that they are coerced, but to what they are
coerced (cf. Letters, 93.5.16, 185.6.24). Correcting such people is a "duty of char-
24 Jn England, after his exile in the Netherlands, Locke founded a society of virtuosi with edifying ity" (officium caritatis) (Letter, 43.1.1) whilst toleration is a "false indulgence"
ends, but also concerned with political and philosophical issues, the Dry Club. If we take into (Letter, 105.2.6), a "freedom for error" (Letter, 105.2.10), a "false and cruel meek-
account Pierre Des Maizeaux's ( 167213-1745) remark in the dedication of A Collection ofSeveral ness" (Letter, 185.2.7). In short, as Augustine affirms, referring to Proverbs 27 :6, "it
Pieces of Mr. John Locke, this kind of society had always pleased Locke. For more details on this is better to love with severity than to deceive with leniency" (melius est cum severi-
topic, see Simonutti (2001 and 2008).
25 According to Goldie (1993, 169), "Locke knew well enough that both Anglicans and French
tate diligere, quam cum lenitate decipere) (Letter 93.2.4, cf. Letter 151.7). 28
papists drew their arguments from St Augustine's teaching, and that one of the most influential
versions of the Augustinian case amongst Anglican divines had been produced by Thomas Long
27
[The History of the Donatists, of 1677]." Referring to Luke 14:21, Augustine uses the verb adducere (in the Vulgate, the verb is introdu-
26 Besides Luke 14:23 (cf. Letters, 93.2.5, 173.10, 185.6.24), Augustine employs other biblical cere). In her English translation, Atkins chose to invite, but this does not seen to be a good alterna-
sources in his letters to Vincentius and Boniface, such as the conversion of Paul in Acts 9:4 (cf. tive (cf. Augustine 2001, 188). As we read in a sermon devoted to the parable of the great banquet,
Letters, 93.2.5; 185.6.22), the domain of Sarah over Hagar in Genesis 16:6 and Galatians 4:26, 29 Augustine thinks that there are three groups of people: those who were invited (or called), those
(cf. Letters, 93.2.6; 185.2.9-11 ), the conversion of Nebuchadnezzar in Daniel 3:24-30 (cf. Le//ers, who were conducted and those who were compelled to come in (cf. Sermon, 112. l ).
28
93.3.9; 185.2.8). The statement of the necessity to bring to the church those that are in error is As Goldie ( 1991, 348) summarises, "when the mind in bondage is lost to Christian truth, and an
based on Ezekiel 34:4 (cf. Letters, 185.7.31 ) On Augustine's justification of intolerance, see Joly eternal soul is at stake, then coercive discipline by the magistrate in the service of the Christian
(1955) and Scalise (1996). pastor is an act of the greatest charity. Indulgence is a 'mistaken kindness' and penal laws are an
26 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.1 The Evangelical Argument 27

It is no accident, therefore, that one of the points at stake in the modem debate (cf. RC, 23, § 26), and to some concomitant articles (cf. RC, 164, 169, §§ 291, 301;
on toleration concerns the notion of charity - and it concerns the notion of charity Locke, 2016, 21 , § 28, 49, 162- 163, §§ 25, 306-308): "these two, Faith and
not only from a moral point of view, as we see in the evangelical argument, but also Repentance; i.e., believing Jesus to be the Messiah, and a good Life; are the indis-
from a political one, as we shall see in the following chapter concerning the Locke pensable Conditions of the New Covenant to be performed by all those, who would
and Proast controversy. In both cases, however, the main issue remains the same: obtain Eternal Life" (RC, 112, § 199). To obtain eternal life, Christ gave teachings
can force be compatible with love? For Locke, there is no doubt that force and char- concerning "faith and manners" (cf. Epist., 116.21-22: quafide, quibus moribus ... ),
ity are incompatible, as we just saw in his emphasis on the faith that works "not by so that each person has duties related to "believing" (crede) and "acting" (agere):
force, but by love" (Galatians 5:6, Epist., 58.25). As he states in An Essay concern- everyone is supposed "to investigate" (investigare) and "to perform" (peragere) the
ing Toleration, "I ... am much indebted to the man that takes care I should be happy things necessary to salvation (cf. Epist. , 122.27-124.1).32 In a manuscript written in
but tis hard to thinke that that comes from charity to my soule which brings such ill 1694, Locke sustains the same position when he lists "what one must believe to be
usage to my body" (ET, 296). Locke's position is centred in Christ's meekness, 29 the saved" (quae credenda ad salutem) and "what one must do to be saved" (quae
major expression of which is seen in the Sermon on the Mountain, and is sum- agenda ad salutem) (Adversaria Theologica 94, § 5). 33 Therefore, the opposition
marised in the Golden Rule (cf. RC, 123, § 219). This rule was described in An between notional science and rule of righteousness is not intended to cast doubt on
Essay concerning Human Understanding as "that most unshaken Rule of Morality, the need to believe, but to condemn the speculative excess that ends up serving as a
and Foundation of all social Virtue" (E, I.iii.4). 30 When Locke composed The pretext for clerical dominion. Hence, in the prologue to the Epistola, there are allu-
Reasonableness of Christianity, he restated his conception of Christianity, citing sions to the so-called indifferent things to salvation. The imposition of indifferent
Christ's answer to Pilate, according to which his kingdom is not of this world things concerning either doctrine or ways of worship is a characteristic procedure of
because, if it were, his followers would have struggled for it, since they were not those who distort religion to suit their own interests. In A Third Letter, Locke refers
few and were forward to consider him king; if force should be used, Christ would to "those generous Principles of the Gospel, which so much recommend and incul-
have ordered it (cf. RC, 84-85, §§ 144-145; John 18: 33-37). In the Epistola, we cate universal Charity, and a Freedom from the Inventions and Impositions of Men
find the same statement when Locke says, ironically, that if infidels should be con- in the things of God" (TL, 349, Works , 544-545). Naturally, Locke's conception of
verted by constraint, an army of heavenly legions would be much more adequate Christianity is very conciliatory and may be easily linked with his defence of tolera-
than the troops of any patron of the church (cf. Epist., 64-7-9). tion, because it reduces the dogmatic and ceremonial dimensions of religion to a
The purpose of Christianity is "to institute a life with righteousness and piety" minimum. 34 As Locke states in A Second Vindication of the Reasonableness of
(ad vitam recte pieque instituendam), 31 so that all people that neglect virtue and are Christianity, his conception of Christianity "tends to Peace and Union amongst
inclined to vice attribute "in vain" (jrustra) to themselves the name of Christian (cf. Christians" (Locke 2016, 37, § A3'). Indeed, for him "charity [is] a Vertue much
Epist., 58.15-19). Christianity is more a rule of righteousness towards good life, more necessary than the attaining of the Knowledge of obscure Truths, that are not
"the great business of true religion", than a notional science (Pol. Es. , Pacific easie to be found; and probably, therefore, not necessary to be known" (Locke 2016,
Christians,§ 6, 305). As we can see in The Reasonableness of Christianity, the good 232, § 479).35
life, i.e. the sincere effort to obey Christ's law (cf. RC, 112, § 198) is a grounding Locke focuses on the moral development of individuals (an aspect with which no
notion of Locke's conception of the Christian religion, but it does not exempt the Christian would disagree), rather than addressing abstruse discussions (that are so
believers from giving assent to an essential dogma, that Jesus Christ is the Messiah
32
Translation slightly altered.
act of love. It may be better to win by gentle persuasion, but amongst the stubborn there is a 'hard- 33
The manuscript, Adversaria Theologia 94, is quoted here according to Nuovo's edition and trans-
ness of heart that cannot be softened by such words'." lation (cf. Locke 2002b, 23).
29 In A Second Letter, however, Locke acknowledges that on one occasion - the expelling of mer- 34
This is the so-called latitudinarianism. Bejan (2015, n. 13) refers to The Reasonableness of
chants from the temple (cf. John 2:13-25) - Christ used force (cf. SL, 49, Works, 115). When Christianity as an "an exercise in latitudinarian theology". This perspective of Christianity was
Augustine justified his change of attitude regarding the coercion of Donatists, he used this Biblical shared by the Dutch Remonstrants with whom Locke lived in exile. On Locke's friendly relations
passage (cf. Augustine 2019, I, 13, 6). in the Netherlands, see Simonutti (1999).
30 Being easy and plain, this rule may be used in the instruction of children (cf. Locke 1989, 213, § 35
Similarly, in A Third Letter, Locke wrote: "An Agreement in Truths necessary to Salvation, and
159). In Of the Conduct of the Understaruling (§ 43 (84)), Locke affirms that "our Saviours great the maintaining of Charity and brotherly Kindness with the Diversity of Opinions in other things,
rule [is) that we should love our neighbour as our selves" as he did in Of Ethic in General(§ 11): is that which will very well consist with Christian Unity, and is all possibly to be had in this World,
"this rule of our actions set us by our lawmaker is conversant about, and ultimately terminates in, in such an incurable Weakness and Difference of Mens Understandings" (TL, 82, Works, 237). In
those simple ideas before mentioned; viz. thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself' (Pol. Es. , Of the same vein, we read in A Defence ofNonconformity that '"tis want of joyneing in peace, & char-
Ethic... , 303). ity, and not in all the circumstances of outward worship that causes our eviUs" (DNC, 1, cf.
31 DNC, 107).
Translation slightly altered.
28 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.2 The Argument from Commission 29

liable to hide the ulterior motives). It is little wonder, therefore, that in the manu- At any rate, despite the simplicity of the argument, which can be put in the logi-
script Error he criticises the churches "in which, as one may observe, opinions are cal form of a valid categorical syllogism (i) 'C is EC'; (ii) 'EC is ML'; (iii) 'Hence,
preferred to life and orthodoxy is that which they are concerned for, and not morals" C is ML', it is not difficult to perceive the great moral consequences of it, even
(Pol. Es., Error, 346). More broadly, in the manuscript Civil and Ecclesiastical though they are restricted to those who identify themselves as Christians, i.e. to
Power, written in 1674, Locke states that "all things tending to the attainment of those who accept its scriptural basis. In light of the evangelical argument, we can
future bliss ... are of three sorts": credenda, cultus religiosus and moralia. He then say that no Christian can enforce his beliefs and ways of worship upon other per-
points out that those things one needs to do to be saved are twofold: some of them sons, which corresponds to an approach to toleration in its horizontal dimension, as
concern "the ways of expressing our honour and adoration of the deity, and of mentioned above. From Locke's perspective, in short, the use of force in religious
address to him for the obtaining any good from him" (cu/tus religiosus), others matters is a betrayal of charity, which is the "Spirit of the Gospel" (RC, 3, § A2v).
concern "the right management of our actions in respect of ourselves and others" Charity, if it is not to become an empty word, must be understood as "an effectual
(moralia) (Pol. Es., Civil... , 217). 36 A few years later, in 1681-82, in A Defence of forbearance 39 and good will" (Pol. Es., Pacific Christians, § 5, 305).
Nonconformity, Locke would formulate a definition of religion that comprises
"those opinions, & actions alone which I entertaine, & performe, onely to please
God, & such as have no concemement at all with my neighbour or the interest, or
affaires of this world" - a definition that seems to exclude moralia from religion. 2.2 The Argument from Commission
However, this definition of religion is certainly framed in a restrictive fashion, as
Locke asserts that morality is "acknowledged ... to be a great part of that wherein As we have seen previously, the other three arguments to support toleration appear
God may be offended or pleased with us" (DNC, 76). in the section of the Epistola that defines the Commonwealth as "a society of men
Specifically formulated against the use of force in religious matters, the evan- constituted only (solummodo) for preserving and advancing their civil goods"
gelical argument may thus be settled in the following terms: (i) 'Being a Christian
is to follow Christ's example'; (ii) 'Christ's example is to act virtuously with meek-
ness and charity'; (iii) 'Hence, being a Christian is to act virtuously with meekness Marshall (2016, 656-{)57) makes this point very clearly. In this sense, it is important to remember
and charity'. As the first premise is evident to all Christians, there is no doubt that that, in the reviews of the Epistola in the Bibliotheque Universe lie et Historique and in the Histoire
des Ouvrages des Sfavans, there is an emphasis on the "cruel and ridicule charity that consists in
the biblical passages to which Locke resorts are intended to support the second
oppressing or beheading one's neighbour for the sake of converting him" (Basnage de Beauval
premise. 37 It must be noted, however, that the Augustinian reading of compel/e 1721, 22) and a clear assertion that "without toleration there can be no charity, because we cannot
intrare in Luke 14:23 clearly contradicts the second premise, at least from Locke's say that dishonouring people, preventing them from keeping their lives, persecuting them, taking
perspective. Yet, in the Epistola, and also in the works and manuscripts explored away their goods, and killing them, as those who have no toleration towards those who do not share
above, Locke never openly compares his conception of Christianity with other con- their beliefs, are actions compatible with charity" (Le Clerc 1689, 403). On the reviews and on the
immediate reception of the Epistola, see Soulard (2019) and Loque (2020). Likewise, in his cor-
ceptions, particularly the Augustinian one. He only does so indirectly, when he
respondence with Locke, Limborch asserts that the Epistola proves, "on grounds never hitherto so
describes the violence to which the supposed heretics were exposed - they were set forth, that all religious persecution is contrary both to the spirit of religion and to the law of
mutilated, despoiled and killed, to mention nothing more (cf. Epist., 60.1) - and nature" (Corr., v. III, 1131). As Loconte (2014) demonstrates, the emphasis on the incompatibility
above all, when he opposes religious coercion to the faith acting through love (cf. of the example of Christ and intolerance represents an influence of Christian humanism on Locke.
Galatians 5:6, Epist., 58.25).38 From this perspective, contrary to what Nuovo (2011, 242) affirms, we cannot say that the equation
of toleration and the "Christian virtue of charity" seems to be "purely rhetorical". Lamb and
Thompson (2009, 239) also consider that in the Epistola there is an "intermarriage of charity and
36 For a discussion on whether the cultus religious, understood as public worship, and affiliation toleration", but they focus on the meaning of charity related to Locke's notion of property and
with a church are required for salvation, see Lucci (2020, 196-197). We should bear in mind, justice (cf. TTG I § 42).
39
though, that at the time Locke composed A Defence of Nonconformity, he believed that "since the In Locke's index to An Essay concerning Human Understanding, there is an entry for toleration
actions of a private solitary life cannot reach to all the instances & purposes of religion in its full with only one remission to the work, specifically to E, IV.xvi.4, the title of which is "the right use
extent therefore men find themselves obliged, when they embrace any religion, to associate, & of it Uudgement] is mutual Charity and Forbearance". Since forbearance has the sense of abstain-
joyne in Communion with some society, wherein that religion is professed" (DNC, 19, cf. DNC, ing from, it appears that Locke is considering it synonymous of toleration, which he defines liter-
23, 30, 39, 76-77). ally as the removal of force (cf. SL, 2, 6, Works, 62, 67), as we saw above. In this respect, it is
37 This is why, contrary to Goldie and Popkin (2006), we have shortened the scope of the evangeli- noteworthy that Pierre Coste (1668-1747) chose 'toleration' when he translated this passage (cf.
cal argument here. The latitudinarian position regarding indifferent things, even though very Locke 1735, 548). In an earlier stage, though, Locke seems to have conceived forbearance in a
important, does not have a scriptural basis like the statement of Christian meekness and charity. different way. In A Defence of Nonconfonnity, Locke also associates charity and forbearance (cf.
38
DNC, 7 , 110, 112, 151, 154), but apparently, he believes (referring to Romans 14, in particular, to
Goldie (1991) shows how Locke confronted the Augustinian legacy in the controversy with
Romans 14:13: "Let us not therefore judge one another any more") that forbearance is the action
Proast, but he does not explore Locke's rebuttal of Augustine (focused on charity) in the Epistola. of not judging others (cf. DNC, 142).
Goldie and Popkin (2006, 102), Bejan (2015) and Vernon (1997, 9) touch upon this issue whereas
30 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.2 The Argument from Commission 31

(Epist., 64.27-28). These arguments correspond to what Popple calls three consid- verb committere, and also accepts the sense of to trust. The issue is always a conces-
erations, and, for the sake of clarity, we shall call them here the argument from sion made in confidence, with a determined end. The emphasis on the substantive
commission, the argument of unfitness of force, and the argument of reductio ad commission, however, helps to show that the task to be performed by the magistrate
absurdum. Given their political nature and their secular character, all these argu- corresponds to an end entrusted to him. Ultimately, as we see in the Two Treatises
ments are independent of the evangelical argument, which has a theological and of Government, legislative power is "only a Fiduciary Power" (TTG, II§ 149). 42 The
moral nature, and a confessional character. However, taken as a whole, these three magistrate cannot do whatever he wants, because he has a trust that restricts what he
arguments are interconnected, as we shall see. can legitimately do.
In order to understand the structure and the interconnection between these three Therefore, regardless of the translation chosen for demand.are and its cognate
arguments, we shall start with the first one. It is condensed in one paragraph in forms, it is important to note that by focusing the discussion on the notion of com-
which Locke begins his exposition of the proofs "to demonstrate" (demonstrare) mission or trust, Locke is indicating that the functions of the Commonwealth are not
why the magistrate's jurisdiction must be limited exclusively to civil matters. evident: his aim is, precisely, to determine them. For Locke, it is necessary to estab-
First, because the care of souls is not committed to the civil magistrate, any more than to lish which mandate should be entrusted lo the magistrate. In other words, it is neces-
other men. It is not committed to him by God; because it does not appear that God ever gave sary to explain why it should not include the care of souls. Since there are two ways
any such authority to one man over another as to compel other men to embrace his religion. whereby power may be committed to the magistrate, Locke discusses each one
Nor can any such power be vested in the magi strate by men, because no man can so far separately, as he did in the First Tract on Government and in An Essay concerning
abandon the care of his own eternal salvation as to embrace under compul sion a worship or
Toleration.
faith prescribed by someone else, be he prince or subject. For no man, even if he would, can
beLieve at another's dictation. It is faith that gives force and efficacy to the true religion that The first way regards God, but, according to Locke, it seems that God has never -
brings salvation. For whatever profession you make, to whatever outward worship you con- literally, "nowhere" (nusquam)43 - given to one man over another the authority to
form, if you are not fully persuaded in your own mind that it is both true and well pleasing compel others to embrace his religion. In the Epistola, this is Locke's claim for
to God, far from being any furtherance, it is an obstacle to salvation. For in this way, instead denying to the magistrate the commission that could be given to him by God. As we
of expiating your other sins by the exercise of religion, in offering to God Almighty a wor-
can see, a modest (ironic, even?) tone is lent to the claim by the expression apparet,
ship which you believe to be displeasing to him you add to the number of your sins those of
hypocrisy and contempt of his Divine Majesty (Epist., 66.19-68.2). but its most important feature is its scriptural basis. Locke clearly presupposes that
the Scripture contains God's will, and affirms that nowhere in the Revelation does
Broadly speaking, this is the argument: (iv) 'God has not committed the care of God concede, to the magistrate, the care of souls. Given the absence of any explicit
souls to the civil magistrate'; (v) 'Men have not committed the care of souls to the concession of this commission to the magistrate, we must conclude that he does
civil magistrate'; (vi) 'Hence, the care of souls has not been committed to the civil possess it or, at least, that he does not possess it as a divine concession. In A Second
magistrate', which is tantamount to saying that his jurisdiction must be confined to Letter, Locke quotes some biblical passages, such as I Peter 2: 13, to support his
civil matters.40 The argument is straightforward, but its premises are not evident. position (which he says is coherent with Richard Hooker (1554-1600)) on the
They do not support the thesis without further grounding. Why have neither God nor restriction of the magistrate's jurisdiction: Commonwealths or civil societies or
men committed the care of souls to the civil magistrate? Moreover, what does Locke governments are nothing but an "all0pro7tiVTJ K-ricnc;;", "the contrivance and
mean by 'committing' the care of souls to the civil magistrate?
Locke employs the verb demandare (cf. Epist., 66.20) to refer to the care of souls 42
For the sake of clarity, it is worth quoting this passage in full: "Though in a Constituted
committed to the magistrate. Literally, it means to trust and corresponds to the verb Commonwealth, standing upon its own Basis, and acting according to its own Nature, that is, act-
to entrust, often used in the Two Treatises of Government. 41 In the Locke and Proast ing for the preservation of the Community, there can be but one Supream Power, which is the
controversy, developed in English, it is discussed whether or not, in religious mat- Legislative, to which all the rest are and must be subordinate, yet the Legislative being only a
ters, the magistrate has authority or commission, a word that comes from the Latin Fiduciary Power to act for certain ends, there remains still in the People a Supream Power to
remove or alter the Legislative, when they find the Legislative act contrary to the trust reposed in
them. For all Power given with trust for the attaining an end, being limited by that end, whenever
40
In fact, this argument is an enthymeme. In order to be valid, the reasoning requires another prem- that end is manifestly neglected, or opposed, the trust must necessarily be forfeitecf' (TTG,
ise: the commission to take care of souls may be committed to the magistrate either by God or by TI§ 149).
men. It seems that Locke has always worked with this disjunction. It is found in the First Tract on 43
Some translators, starting with Popple, give a temporal sense to nusquam when its meaning is
Government (cf. Locke 1967, 126) and reappears in An Essay concerning Toleration (ET, 270). locative, as we see in two analogous passages: in A Second Letter, Locke says that "I do not find
41
When we compare Locke's Latin and English writings, notably the Two Tracts on Government, any where that. .. " (SL, 54, Works, 12 1); and in the manuscript Toleration D, which will be dis-
it seems that the Latin verb demandare may be doubled in English: to commission and to entrust. cussed below, where Locke states that "God has nowhere given such power to any man or soci-
Compare: "whether you suppose him [magistrate) immediately commissioned by God and by him ety ... " (Pol. Es, Toleration D, 276). In the review of the Epistola published in the Bibliotheque
entrusted with the care of the society ... " (Locke 1967, 126) and "verum cum magistratui a deo Universe/le et Historique, which was based on the Latin edition, nusquam is interpreted in the
societatis cura demandatur ..." (Locke 1967, 194). locative sense: "Dieu n'a dit nulle part qu'il entendoit. .. " (Le Clerc 1689, 404).
32 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.2 The Argument from Commission 33

institution of man", whose end is "the Punishment of evil-doers, and the praise of states that the care and power over all these things "are committed to the magistrates
them that do well" (SL, 54, Works, 121). 44 by the society" (a societate magistratibus demandata est). According to Locke, this
It must be stressed, however, that some passages of the Old Testament, such as is the "origin" (origo) of the legislative power and this power, which is supreme,
Isaiah 49:23, are traditionally employed to vest the magistrate with the care of souls must be circumscribed in a manner that reflects its origin. The public good in secu-
(cf. TL-P, 10, RLP, 49). Locke never mentions them in the Epistola. This silence lar matters is the "sole reason and the sole end" (unicum ... argumentum unicusque...
may be due to his understanding of the Jewish State: it was a theocracy (cf. Epist., finis) of the constitution of the Commonwealth (cf. Epist., 126.1-16).47
116.10). According to Locke, it is clear that the law of Moses implied a unity of the In the Epistola, Locke does not develop his reasoning to the extent of making
ecclesiastical and the civil orders, but this unity was broken by Christ: among the explicit that there are two stages in the constitution of the Commonwealth. In the
Jews, there could not be, "as is the case after the birth of Christ, ... any distinction first stage, given the inconveniences of the state of nature, men enter and constitute
between the church and the Commonwealth" (Epist., 116.11-12). Of the law of a political body. InLocke's words, this stage corresponds to a " Voluntary Agreement"
Moses, which was divided into moral, judicial and ceremonial, Christ kept only the (TTG, II § 173), hence the recurring notions of consent and compact in the Two
moral part (cf. Epist., 114.31; RC, 19-21, §§ 19-22), so that "there is absolutely no Treatises of Government. In the second stage, in which Locke generally no longer
such thing under the Gospel as a Christian commonwealth" (Epist., 116.18-19).45 speaks of consent, but of trust (cf. e.g. TTG, II § 22), men entrust the constituted
Therefore, to prove that God committed the care of souls to the magistrate, it would power with the mandate of preserving their lives, liberties and estates or, generally
be necessary to show a saying of Christ authorizing him to use force in religious speaking, of preserving their property (cf. TTG, II §§ 123-124). It is in this second
matters, but no such saying appears to exist. stage, as we have said above in the explanation of demandare, that political power
As we pointed out earlier, since the premises of the argument from commission is entrusted to the magistrate as a commission or mandate. The main difference
are not evident, they need to be proved. In the Epistola, each premise is given its between the two stages lies in the fact that consent refers to the powers that men give
own justification and becomes the conclusion of an additional argument. 46 Hence, up - the powers to punish others and of self-preservation (the latter is only partially
with regard to the first way whereby the magistrate's commission may be instituted, relinquished) - in order to confer them on the legislative (cf. TTG, II§§ 128-13 1;
it is clear that premise (iv) 'God has not committed the care of souls to the civil TL, 62, Works, 214). Trust, however, has to do with the ends of the constituted com-
magistrate' is backed up by the following proposition: (a) 'It seems that nowhere in mon power (cf. TTG, II § 222). 48 In other words, in the first case, the issue is the
the Scripture has God committed the care of souls to the civil magistrate'. Locke concession of power; in the other, it is the scope and the admissible employment of
does not give this additional argument a name; for the sake of clarity, we shall call the constituted common power.49 Hence, one can say, in analytical terms, that firstly,
it the political scriptural argument, given that it has a scriptural basis, as does the the community or political body is formed and, secondly, the government is formed.
evangelical argument. This is why the dissolution of government does not necessarily entail the dissolution
The other way whereby the care of souls can be committed to the magistrate is of society (cf. TTG, II§ 211).
through the trust of men. Although at this point of the Epistola Locke does not say It must be stressed, however, that the magistrate's commission is not chosen by
explicitly that he presupposes the transition from the state of nature to the constitu- men. It is derived from the human natural condition, as divine creation, and in
tion of a Commonwealth, he does have this transition in mind. His reasoning is cast
in similar terms when compared to the Two Treatises of Government (TTG, II §§ 47
Translation slightly altered.
4-21, 95-99, 123-131), as we see in another section of the Epistola, where he 48
In A Third Letter, Locke reasserts the difference between consent and trust when he explains the
describes the necessity that humankind has to work in order to survive and the threat two senses of power: "the natural Force of all the Members of any Society, or of those who by the
to property represented by dishonest men. Locke then refers to the "mutual com- Society can be procured to assist it, is in one Sense called the Power of that Society. This Power or
pacts" (pacta ... mutua) among men to defend the things of this life, and clearly Force is generally put into some one or few Persons' Hands with Direction and Authority how to
use it; and this in another Sense is called also the Power of the Society.. .. The Power therefore of
any Society in this Sense, is nothing but the Authority and Direction given to those that have the
Management of the Force or natural Power of the Society, how and to what Ends to use it, by which
44
1 Peter 2: 13 also occurs in the Two Treatises of Government (TTG, I § 6) and in the Second Tract Commission the Ends of Societies are known and distinguished" (TL, 65, Works, 217-218).
on Government (Locke, 1967, 228). In the case of the latter, however, it is mentioned in order to 49
As Laslett sums up in his introduction to the Two Treatises of Government (TTG, 114), Locke
prove that the magistrate may legislate about indifferent things, what entails a much larger jurisdic- "divides off the process of compact, which creates a community, from the further process by which
tion compared to that sustained by Locke in his later works. the community entrusts political power to a government; although they may take place at the same
45 As Coffey (2000, 63) points out, "by treating Israel as a pennanent model for Christians, propo-
time, these two are distinct. This puts his system amongst those which distinguish the 'contract of
nents of uniformity were confusing the Law and the Gospel and revealing their failure to compre- society' from the 'contract of government' , though in Locke this second process is not a contract
hend the great transformation that had occurred with the coming of Christ". at all. And this may be his second point; to underline the fact that the relation between government
46
For a comprehensive view of the structure of Locke's arguments in the Epistola, see the Synoptic and governed is not contractual, for a trust is not a contract." In broad terms, Tuckness (2002b) fits
Table in the final section of this chapter. these concepts into what he calls contractual and legislative consent.
34 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.2 The Argument from Commission 35

particular from the duty of self-preservation. The ends of the Commonwealth are istrate. What sense could this concession have, if the means in the magistrate's
determined by the necessity to obey the law of nature and, at the same time, to rem- hands - the laws and their corresponding penalties - are unable to reach the
edy the inconveniences of the state of nature (cf. TIO, II § 135).5° From this per- understanding?
spective, the Two Treatises of Government could have plainly supported toleration, This is the very same reasoning that constitutes the argument of unfitness of
had this work discussed the possible extension of civil power to the care of souls (in force, so that there is an interconnection between Locke's first two considerations
this work, there are only two incidental references to religion, cf. TTG, II §§ made to defend the restriction of the magistrate's jurisdiction to civil goods. 53 In the
209-210). 51 After all, if the end of the Commonwealth is the preservation of prop- second consideration, there is nothing more at stake than the relationship between
erty, then the imposition of beliefs and ways of worship by the magistrate is hardly force and faith; consequently, it is more appropriate to examine this relationship in
conceivable. As we shall see in the next chapter, Locke openly resorts to the notion the discussion of the argument of unfitness of force. For now, it is more important
of state of nature in A Second Letter and, in particular, in A Third Letter to show that to note that there is, in the Epistola, another reason why people would not commit
religious imposition is an injury to be remedied by civil society, i.e. that the liberty the care of souls to the magistrate. It is this reason that appears in the metaphor of
to believe and to worship God as each one thinks most appropriate is one of the beams in A Second Letter, when Locke states that the argument of unfitness of force
liberties to be protected by the Commonwealth. In sum, therefore, when Locke is not the only argument to support the view that the magistrate does not have the
develops his reasoning on toleration, he applies his conception of the constitution of commission to promote salvation (cf. SL, 6, Works, 67). This second reason to sup-
the Commonwealth to the specific issue of religion in order to demonstrate that the port the view that men would not commit the care of souls to the magistrate is the
jurisdiction of the civil power "neither can nor ought in any way to be extended argument of fallibility. This argument is referred to often in the Locke and Proast
(nee ... extendi) to the salvation of souls" (Epist., 66.16-17). However, one may still controversy, but it had been adduced years earlier, in the manuscript Toleration D
ask: what exactly would prevent people from extending the magistrate's jurisdiction (1679),54 when it received an enlightening formulation:
beyond secular matters? No man has power to prescribe to another what he should believe or do in order to the sav-
In response to this question, Locke sustains that nobody can abandon the care of ing of his own soul, because it is only his own private interest, and concerns not another
his own salvation, because it is impossible for anyone to believe by prescription. man. God has nowhere given such power to any man or society, nor can man possibly be
Even if a person wanted to, he could not embrace a doctrine or a way of worship supposed to give it [to] another over him absolutely.
(I) Because man in all states being liable to error, as well governors as those under
prescribed by others. If a person is not convinced "in his heart" (in corde) that his
them, doctors or scholars, it would be unreasonable to be put under the absolute direction
belief is true and his way of worship pleasing to God, the mere outward profession of those who may err in a matter of that concemment, eternal concemment, wherein if they
and performance are worthless to salvation. Furthermore, this outward profession misguide us they can make us no reparation.
and performance without the "conscientious conviction" (Epist., 60.16: conscien- (2) ... because no compulsion can make a man believe against his present light and
tiae persuasio)52 is an obstacle to salvation. It is hypocrisy, and implies contempt for persuasion, be it what it will, though it may make him profess indeed. But profession with-
God. Without a "conscientious conviction", nobody can be saved: outward profes- out sincerity will little set a man forwards in his way to any place but that where he is to
have his share with hypocrites, and to do anything in the worship of God which a man
sion and performance do not suffice, even if they are done on behalf of true religion. judges in his own conscience not to be that worship he requires and will accept, is so far
Locke conceives faith as inner persuasion and contends that it is inaccessible to the from serving or pleasing God in it, that such a worshipper affronts God only to please men
magistrate's commands. The understanding cannot be moved by force. This is (Pol. Es., Toleration D , 276).
Locke's justification to deny that people would commit the care of souls to the mag-

53
Given that these two arguments are intertwined, we cannot agree with Tate (2016, 204, 225), who
50 On this topic, see Dunn (1980, 1996) and the debate between Stanton (2011, 2012, 2017) and claims that they are "categorically distinct". It is surprising that he states, moreover, that the argu-
Tate (2012, 2013, 2017), besides Harris (2013), who analyses the constitution of the Commonwealth ment from commission "is not only categorically distinct" from the argument of unfitness of force,
taking into account the natural duty to worship God mentioned by Locke in the fourth and seventh "but also inconsistent with it" (Tate 2016, 138).
of the Essays on the Law of Nature (cf. Locke 1954, 156.16-22, 194.11-12). 54
The argument of fallibility occurs in writings earlier than Toleration D, as An Essay concerning
51 According to Milton and Milton in their introduction to An Essay concerning Toleration, "both
Toleration (ET, 272-273), but never so clearly associated with the argument from commission and
refer to covert royal support for popery, not to disputes between the Church of England and the argument of unfitness of force. Locke discussed infallibility, but focused on papal infallibility
Protestant dissenters" (ET, 39, n. 1). However, it is interesting to note that, in the preface to the in a Latin manuscript dated 1661, which is sometimes called by scholars "Essay on infallibility"
French translation of the Second Treatise of Government, Jean Le C lerc (1657-1736) makes a (cf. Biddle 1977); in another manuscript entitled "Catholic Infallibility" (cf. Pol. Es., Catholic... ,
plain reference to the religious persecution in France as an illegitimate excess that deserves to be 226-230), and in a letter to Henry Stubbe of circa September 1659 (cf. Corr., v. I, 75). Jolley
resisted (cf. Locke 1691, 3-4). On the first translations of Locke's works into French, see Soulard (2016, 117) acknowledges the contractualist dimension of the argument of fallibility, but he con-
(2011). Specifically on the French translation of the Second Treatise of Government, see siders that it is more noticeable in Locke's replies to Proast. It is unclear why he thinks so, given
Savonius (2004). that the first consideration is boldly structured from the perspective of men when they enter the
52 Translation slightly altered. Commonwealth.
36 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.2 The Argument from Commission 37

As we can see, in Lhe introductory paragraph of this manuscripl, there is a refer- that each person is especially concerned wilh his own salvation. As we can see,
ence to the first way whereby the care of souls may be committed to the magistrate: Locke associates the notions of fallibility and concern, so that, all people being
the divine concession. Once again, Locke denies that it constitutes a ground for the equally apt to take care of their own souls, each person would take care of his own
magistrate's spiritual authority, because nowhere has God given him this power (it salvation better than anyone else, since nobody would put so much effort in it as
is the political scriptural argument almost in the same terms found in the Epistola). himself. From this perspective, it is the individual "effort" (studium) that makes the
However, the substantive part of Toleration D deals not with the divine, but with the difference, all the more so when we consider that there are few beliefs necessary to
human concession, so to speak. This is clear from the enumerated exposition of two salvation and that consequently, the study of religious matters need not be exhaus-
arguments, aimed at justifying why people do not commit the care of souls to the tive: "one day of seven besides other days of rest in the Christian world allows time
magistrate. The second of these arguments is the argument of unfitness of force, enough for this" (Cond., § 8 (28)). 56 In the Epistola, nevertheless, there is no explicit
which we shall examine below; the first is the argument of fallibility, which is struc- statement that each person would take care of his own salvation better than the mag-
tured as follows: (p) 'all men, regardless of their position or status, are liable to istrate. In order to prove that men would not commit the care of souls to the magis-
error'; (y) 'if a person misguides other with regard to salvation, he can make no trate when they leave the state of nature, it is enough to sustain the equal capacity
reparation', (v) 'Hence, men have not committed the care of souls to the civil mag- between the magistrate and their subjects or citizens, i.e. that they are equally liable
istrate'. Why would men commit the care of souls to the magistrate, a matter of to error. Why would a person abstain from the care of his own soul if he knew that
eternal concernment, if he is as liable to error as any other person, and cannot repair he ran the risk of losing salvation? Or to put it another way, why would a person
his citizens' loss of salvation due to his spiritual misguidance? entrust the care of his own soul to another person if he believed himself to be equally
In the Epistola, it is also in these terms that the argument of fallibility is framed. capable of gaining it57 and more concerned in this endeavour?
It appears in the section in which Locke discusses the magistrate's duties regarding Premise CP) 'all men, regardless of their position or status, are liable to error' is
toleration and, more accurately, in a passage in which Locke criticises fanatics by enough to support the proposition that (v) 'men have not committed the care of
affirming that there is no consensus as to the right way to salvation. Given that the souls to the civil magistrate' , but, as we see in the manuscript Toleration D, Locke
right way is "controversial" (cf. Epist., 92.19-20: de recta ambiguitur), could the strengthens his position with a second proof: (y) 'if a person misguides other with
magistrate choose it for others? Locke's answer is negative. The magistrate could regard to salvation, he can make no reparation'. In the Epistola, the second premise
not do so because "neither the care of the commonwealth, nor the right of enacting (y) can also be found in the section that deals with the magistrate's duties concern-
laws, reveals the way that leads to heaven more certainly (certius) to the magistrate ing toleration, and seems to imply another feature of fallibility. The magistrate is
than a private man's study reveals it to himself' (Epist., 92.20-22). By the same fallible for being as liable to error as anyone else (power does not make a person
token, but using other words, Locke states that "the one and only narrow way that more cognitively apt), but also for not being able to repair the harm caused by his
leads to heaven is no better known to the magistrate (magistratui non magis notam) misguidance, in case someone loses salvation because of him.
than to private persons, and therefore I cannot safely follow him as my guide who In fact, Locke's reasoning is more audacious in the Epistola than in Toleration D,
may probably be as ignorant (aeque ignarus) of the way as I am, and who certainly because he makes a clear argumentative concession: "but let us grant that the way to
must be less concerned for my salvation than I am myself' (Epist., 96.1-5). eternal life is probably better known to a prince than to his subjects, or at least that
The central point of this reasoning is clear: the magistrate is as fallible as anyone
else. His superiority in power does not make him more apt to discover and embrace
the true religion. Therefore, he is virtually as ignorant about religious matters as all 56
This perspective is also found in An Essay concerning Human Understanding: "no Man is wholly
other people. As Locke says in An Essay concerning Toleration, in a clear recourse taken up with the Attendance on the Means of Living, as to have no spare Time at all to think of his
to the notion of fallibility, the magistrate has "noe more certain or more infallible Soul, and inform himself in Matters of Religion" (E, IV.xx.3). Accordingly, Locke affirms in The
knowledge" of the way to salvation; he is not "made infallible in reference to others, Reasonableness of Christianity that "the written Word of God" is "a Collection of Writings
designed by God for the Instruction of the illiterate bulk of Mankind in the way to Salvation" (RC,
by being made a governor over them" (ET, 273, 277). In the idiom of the Two 6, § 2); see also RC (157-158, 169, §§ 279, 302) and A Vindication of the Reasonableness of
Treatises of Government, it means that all people, being equal, are born to "the use Christianity (cf. Locke 2016, 22, § 30). To Rogers (2002, 111), "Locke's religious position is
of the same faculties" (TTG, II§ 4). 55 Even the absolute monarchs, as Locke reminds grounded on the axiom that we all have sufficient understanding of the way the world functions,
the reader, "are but Men" (TTG, II § 13). Power does not influence nature, which and sufficient capacity to reason in order to identify our duty. This allows us to assure our salvation
remains the same in all mortals (cf. Epist., 94.2-5). Furthermore, Locke observes without the intervention of others (including the clergy of all churches)".
57
Criticising Waldron (1988), Stanton (2006, 95-96) considers that "the assumption of people's
natural adequacy to self-direction" is central to Locke's case for the distinction between the ends
55
Equal endowment does not mean that everyone has the same excellence of parts or ability (cf. of Church and State. For a more detailed discussion of this point, see Harris (1998, 170-179).
TTG, II§ 54, E, IV.xx.5, Cond., § 2 (4)). However, the real difference among people is due not to Inspired by Waldron (2002, 83-107), Loconte (2014, 190-195) discusses this topic under the title
their endowment, but to the use or exercise of their natural capacities (Cond., § 4 (7)). of "democratic conscience".
38 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.3 The Argument of Unfitness of Force 39

in such uncertainty it is safer and more convenient to follow his dictates" (Epist., plays a central role in his case. Why is this argument so important? And what is the
94.7-10). Under these conditions, would men commit the care of souls to the mag- inflection it represents? Basically, the issue at stake is a change of target: in the
istrate? Again, the answer is negative, but not only because, although he may be second consideration, Locke aims to prove that the "care of souls cannot belong"
more apt, the magistrate may still err, but because the harm resulting from his error (cura animarum non potest pertinere) to the magistrate (Epist., 68.3). 58 This is dif-
will be imputed totally upon others. If the magistrate commanded a person to live ferent from proving, as Locke did in the argument from commission, that the care
by commerce to become rich, as Locke exemplifies, the person could obey the mag- of souls "is not committed" (non demandatur) to him. Now, Locke's aim is not to
istrate because he could be repaired if he did not become rich. However, with regard demonstrate that this care has not been given to the magistrate and, therefore, that it
to eternal life, what can the magistrate do to repair the harm? In the search for the is not under his jurisdiction (something/actual, so to speak, in the sense that neither
kingdom of heaven, the magistrate can offer no "security" (sponsio) (cf. Epist. , God, in His revelation, nor men, when they left the state of nature, vested him with
94.20). As Locke wrote in An Essay concerning Toleration , "if he force me to a this mandate). From this point on, Locke's main purpose is to defend the view that
wrong religion, he can make me noe reparation in the other world" (ET, 272). religious coercion is irrational, as force is inapt to produce beliefs, and, as a conse-
Still reasoning in a concessive vein, Locke makes a second concession: he sup- quence, the care of souls not only is not, but cannot be committed to the magistrate.
poses, now, that "the magistrate's opinion in religion is sound, and the way that he As formulated in the second consideration, the argument of unfitness of force is
directs truly evangelical" (Epist., 98.21 -23), i.e. that the magistrate is not cogni- wider in scope and perhaps, for this reason, it is emphasised by Locke in a specific
tively fallible and, consequently, that the question of reparation has disappeared, consideration.
since there is no more risk of error. In this case, would men commit the care of souls It is noteworthy, however, that the argument of unfitness of force is intended to
to the magistrate? The answer, once again, is negative. But this time Locke resorts prove the irrationality of the imposition of beliefs, providing an explanation for why
to the argument of unfitness of force. Therefore, Locke's reasoning develops gradu- men would restrict the ends of the Commonwealth to civil goods. This point must
ally: firstly, the magistrate is considered as fallible as any other person; then, the be clarified because the argument can be read in another way, as seeking to convince
magistrate is considered less fallible, but unable to repair the harm caused by his the magistrate of the irrationality of the use of force to produce beliefs. 59 The differ-
error; finally, the magistrate is supposed to be infallible, so that, at this last level, ence is remarkable: in the former perspective, the argument has an explanatory
only through another proof could the care of souls be denied to him. character, it clarifies the commission that men entrusted to the magistrate when they
Taking the argument from commission as a whole, we can conclude that there entered civil society (and justifies their restriction of the magistrate's functions); in
are different arguments associated with it: on the one hand, the political scriptural the latter perspective, the argument has a performative character, it is addressed to
argument (forming the basis of the premise related to the divine concession of the the magistrate and is aimed at convincing him that it is not incumbent on him to
care of souls), and on the other, the arguments of fallibility and unfitness of force meddle with religious matters (it aims to lead him, by himself, to restrict his own
(forming the basis of the premise related to the human concession of the care of functions).
souls). In this reasoning, the argument of unfitness of force plays a central role. In The imposition of beliefs is irrational from both perspectives, but Locke's rea-
the paragraph that contains the first consideration, it is the argument explicitly soning always presupposes the first one, as we see in Toleration D and in the incon-
adduced by Locke to justify the second premise (the argument of fallibility appears testable presence of the argument of unfitness of force in the composition of the
in other passages of the Epistola), but its central role has another motive. The argu- argument from commission.6() Even Proast adopts this perspective, as he attempts to
ment of unfitness of force represents an inflection in the argumentative structure of
Locke's reasoning, as we shall see. It is no accident that although present in the first
58
consideration, this argument is also formulated in a consideration by itself. It is important to note that this way of setting out the issue echoes (or maybe rehearses) some of
Augustine's letters in the Donatist con1roversy, in particular letter 88 from the Clergy of Hippo
Regius to Januarius, where Augustine asks "si ad imperatores christianos haec cura pertinere non
debet" (Letter, 88.5), and Letter 155 from Augustine to Macedonius, where he discusses the.finis
that should peninere to the secular power (cf. Letter, 155.3.10).
2.3 The Argument of Unfitness of Force 59
It is from this second perspective that Waldron (1988) develops his influential thesis or, more
accurately, the first part of his thesis. According to Waldron, (a) Locke's purpose is to show that
In the Epistola, Locke makes concessions in his reasoning several times, and admits religious persecution is irrational, since force acts upon the will and not upon the understanding,
as non-demonstrated what had already been demonstrated. We see this, for instance, but (b) yet the magistrate could promote salvation, as Proast states, as long as the magislrate resorts
to "the epistemic apparatus that surrounds and supports belief - the apparatus of selection, atten-
in the discussion of the magistrate's fallibility. Using this procedure, Locke seeks to tion, concentration and so on - which, although it does not generate belief directly, nevertheless
strengthen the position he is criticising in order to oblige himself to find more con- plays a sufficienl role in its genesis to provide a point o f leverage" (Waldron 1988, 82).
sistent and cogent arguments. Hence, we can say that in his defence of toleration the 60 It is Spitz (2002) who develops the distinction between these two perspectives, but like Waldron

argument of unfitness of force represents an inflection and, consequently, that it ( 1988), he also claims that the argument of unfitness of force is aimed at convincing the persecu-
40 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.3 The Argument of Unfitness of Force 41

show not only that religious coercion may be useful, but also that, given its useful- In the second place, the care of souls cannot belong to the civil magistrate, because his
power consists wholly in compulsion. But the true and saving religion consists in the inward
ness and necessity (hence, its rationality), "it is every man's true Interest, not to be
faith of the mind, without which nothing has any value with God; and such is the nature of
left wholly to himself in this matter" (Arg., 22, RLP, 35). According to Proast, men human understanding, that it cannot be compelled by any outward force. Confiscate a man's
would commit the care of souls to the magistrate, i.e. his major critique of the g~s, imp~son or torture his body: such punishments will be in vain, if you hope that they
Epistola is not intended to prove that the mere usefulness of coercion would autho- will make him change his inward judgement of things (Epist., 68.4-9). 63
rise the magistrate to use force in religious matters. Proast would not need to resort
As we can see, Locke's first statement regards the magistrate's power, which
to the notion of interest (in his Third Letter, he reiterates the expression "every
consists in nothing but compulsion. Evidently, the magistrate may employ other
man's true Interest", cf. TL-P, 78, RLP, 114), if the argument of unfitness of force
means to propagate religion: he can admonish, exhort, convince; for none of these
were addressed exclusively to the magistrate, because in this case only the notions
means is illegitimate (cf. Epist., 68.l(}-18). But there is something characteristic
of means and end are at stake. Therefore, it is due to Proast's recognition of the
and intrinsic to the magistrate's role: "it is proper to the magistrate (magistratus
explanatory character of the argument of unfitness of force that his objection to
proprium) to give orders by decree and compel with the sword" (Epist., 68.19-20). 64
Locke culminates in the attempt to demonstrate that it is men's interest to commit
It is this difference that grounds the distinction between the two types of care men-
the care of souls to the magistrate and to enlarge the ends of the Commonwealth.61
tioned above, one based on authority, the other on charity. There is nothing obscure
As we pointed out above, the argument of unfitness of force has different meanings,
about this way of putting things; rather, it is straightforward: on the one hand, the
depending on whether an explanatory or performative reading is given to it, but we
magistrate is conceived as being entrusted with the civil power; on the other, as
shall explore this point later on, when we examine the Locke and Proast contro-
Christian. In this sense, it should be emphasised that force, his proper means to act,
versy. For now, it is important to note that, in either case, the structure of the argu-
manifests itself either as punishments stemming from a failure to respect some law
ment does not vary, given that in both cases the demonstration of the irrationality of
or decree, or as rewards for obedience (cf. Pol. Es., Law, 270). As long as it is con-
coercion to produce beliefs is grounded on the same statements concerning human
fined to the ends commissioned by the individuals, political power is "a Right of
understanding, faith and force.
making Laws with Penalties of Death, and consequently all less Penalties" (TTG, II
The second consideration, as well as the first, is synthesized in a short paragraph
§ 3), as Locke says in the Two Treatises of Government. It makes no sense to imag-
in the section in which Locke defines the State. However, unlike the first consider-
ine that laws can dispense with some sort of penalty (for, if they did, how can we
ation, it contains just one argument: the argument of unfitness of force, as we know.
suppose they would be obeyed?). Even ecclesiastical laws cannot dispense with
Moreover, it is formulated in a way that is compatible with its other occurrences
penalties, but these penalties must not compromise the civil goods of church mem-
throughout the Epistola62 :
bers (cf. Epist., 72.13-26).
Strictly speaking, churches have no right to coerce, if by that we mean the use of
force that results in harm to the transgressors' estates, liberty or life. However, obe-
tors and, therefore, is addressed to the magistrate. According to Wootton (1993, 102), "what
dience is an issue in religious as well as civil societies. Therefore, churches must
Waldron fails to notice is that it is precisely this complex argument about the proper functions of have some form of influencing their members' conduct when the fear of losing
government, looked at from the point of view of the interests of the citizen, that Locke is concerned eternal happiness is not sufficient inducement (cf. Pol. Es., Civil and Ecclesiastical
with, and that he returns to again and again in his dispute with Proast". In this same sense, Vernon Power, 218). Given that it is illegitimate for them to cause harm to property, the
( 1997, 71) affirms: "the argument is not brought to bear on the acts of a constituted State: it is maximum ecclesiastical sanction is excommunication. As Lockes says in A Defence
brought to bear in the constitution of the State". Pevinic (2009) questions the position supported by
Waldron (1988) and tries to fit Locke's defence of toleration into the perspective of men, but he of Nonconformity, "the onely meanes to keep in order their particular members is
does so through the Two Treatises of Government and does not to show how this perspective is admonition & reproof & if these will not doe, their utmost power is onely expulsion
found in the Epistola, or in the Locke and Proast controversy. Which in this sort of societyes is termed Excommunication" (DNC, 21). By defini-
61 If we take into account the explanatory and performative dimensions (the former corresponding tion, the magistrate's power is inevitably the only incumbent to compel. 65 Hence, by
to the perspective of men ; the latter to the magistrate's), we can understand why Waldron (1988) making a paraphrase of the Epistola, we can formulate the first premise of the argu-
sn:esses the distinction between the functionalist and modal conceptions of the State, and why he
thinks that Locke sustains the latter. Like Spitz (2002), Waldron ( 1988) does not realise that Proast
himself employs the notion of interest in his objection to Locke, and that the controversy is not
63
limited to a discussion of the usefulness of force, i.e. to a discussion of the adequacy between Translation slightly altered.
64 Translation slightly altered.
means and ends. Why would the notion of interest be introduced if the discussion were solely about
what the magistrate is apt to do? Ultimately, it is the perspective of men that is at stake in the argu- 6i As Pritchard (2014, 7) sums up, "Locke is adamant that the difference between church and state

ment of unfitness of force, not the magistrate's perspective. is a difference in power. But for Locke this is not a case of powerlessness and powerful; rather, it
62 And with its other occurrences in Locke's writings as a whole, even when his aim was not to is about types of power. For Locke church, public, and state employ persuasive power; the state
support toleration (cf. Locke 1967, 127-128). alone employs punitive power".
42 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.3 The Argument of Unfitness of Force 43

ment of unfitness of force as follows: (vii) 'The magistrate's power consists in coer- (cf. Locke, 1967, 127-128). This is why Locke considered, at that time of his intel-
cion', understanding by that the magistrate's power qua magistrate (not qua lectual development, that the necessity to obey and the liberty of conscience could
Christian), which power corresponds to his exclusive right to make coercive laws. be harmonized: obedience presupposes the "assent of the will" (assensum volunta-
After the explanation of the magistrate's proper way of acting, Locke makes a tis) and not "assent of the judgement" (iudicii) (cf. Locke, 1967, 207/239).
second statement. He reiterates that faith has an inner dimension (what we saw in Therefore, it is the centrality of interiority and involuntariness of faith that allows
the formula "conscientious conviction", cf. Epist., 60.16) and that it is indispensable Locke to show the gap between understanding and force as means to form beliefs.
to salvation. If a person wants to gain eternal happiness, outward conformity and lip In the short paragraph containing the second consideration, Locke does not resort
service to God are not enough. In the section in which Locke discusses the magis- explicitly to the distinction between will and judgement, although he mentions the
trate's duties concerning toleration, he notes that the true religion, even if professed latter notion. Nevertheless, it is this distinction that underpins his reasoning, as we
by the magistrate, will not bring his subjects or citizens to salvation if they are not see in the Two Tracts on Government, and also in the restatement of the argument in
convinced "in their souls" (ex anima) (cf. Epist., 98.23). A few lines later, more the section of the Epistola dedicated to speculative opinions: "to believe this or that
emphatically, Locke says that "no way that I walk in against my conscience will to be true is not within the scope of our will" (in nostra voluntate situm non est)
ever lead me to the mansions of the blessed.. .. It is useless for an unbeliever to (Epist., 120.17-18). Regardless of the degrees and length of punishments, it is
assume the outward appearance of morality; to please God he needs faith and inward impossible for force to produce sincere religious belief. Thus, we may say the third
sincerity" (Epist., 98.24-25, 28-29). and final premise of the argument of unfitness of force is that (ix) 'Human under-
In the Epistola, there is an unquestionable association between faith and con- standing cannot be compelled by outward force', which is tantamount to saying that
science (or soul), between belief and interiority, without which the requirements for by compelling the will, the magistrate cannot oblige a person to change his assent
salvation cannot be understood. This is why the second premise of the argument of from what appears true to that person to what seems false to him.
unfitness of force may be resumed in the proposition (viii) 'Salvation requires inner It must be added, however, that Locke's view on the relationship between belief
faith'. Purposely, it is not specified here whether salvation requires only inner faith and will is not as straightforward as the Epistola seems to suggest. Although Locke
(as though sincerity were a sufficient condition) or whether it requires inner faith as urges that "to believe this or that to be true is not within the scope of our will", in
well (as though sincerity were a necessary condition). In order for a person to be other works he states that at least sometimes belief can be voluntary. In the Draft A
saved, besides the duties concerning manners, must he have a sincere belief, or a he writes: "and were not faith at least sometimes a voluntary act I doe not see how
sincere and true belief? In the Epistola, there seems to be no passage that sheds light infidelity could be a sin" (Locke 1990, § 42). Evidently, it is possible to suppose that
on Locke's position. 66 We shall touch on this issue in the fourth chapter, when we this statement, made in 1671, adduces a view that Locke would have rejected when
analyse An Essay concerning Human Understanding. For now, we simply note that he wrote the Epistola in 1685. After all, if belief were voluntary, coercion (by acting
the sense of the argument of unfitness of force does not change if we choose one or upon the will) could make a person change his belief. Nonetheless, this evolutionist
the other alternative. interpretation of Locke's thought is unsatisfactory because it does not resolve the
In his reasoning in the Epistola, Locke only needs to sustain that faith (or a sin- theological problem concerning the involuntariness of belief pointed out in Draft A:
cere religious belief) is essential to salvation, regardless of whether it is a sufficient if infidels are not responsible for their beliefs, would it be just to condemn them?
or necessary condition to salvation. In other words, it is enough for Locke to sustain Apparently, it turns out to be a dilemma: on the one hand, we can state the involun-
the value of interiority in order to show the functioning of the understanding, i.e. the tariness of belief and reject coercion, but it raises a theological problem; on the
limits of external influence in the production of beliefs. In fact, Locke aims to dem- other, we can avoid the theological problem by assuming that belief can be volun-
onstrate the irrationality in the employment of a means incompatible with the tary, but then it impinges on the rejection of coercion. As we shall see, this is a false
intended end. To make this demonstration, it is enough to show that force is inca- dilemma, but in order to clarify the issue we need to analyse the relationship between
pable of bringing a person to believe sincerely, thus, Locke does not need to support belief and will in more detail. We need, then, to have recourse to An Essay concern-
any polemic thesis regarding salvation, as it is beside the point. If sincerity is suffi- ing Human Understanding:
cient or necessary to salvation, it does not matter for the sake of the argument of Our Knowledge, as in other Things, so in this, has a great Conformity with our Sight, that it
unfitness of force. From the time of the Two Tracts on Government it was clear for is neither wholly necessary, nor wholly voluntary. .. . Just thus is it with our Understanding,
Locke that force can influence a person's actions, but that it does not reach his judg- all that is voluntary in our Knowledge, is the employing, or with-holding any of our
ment: God has not "entrusted man with a liberty at pleasure to believe or reject'', Faculties from this or that sort of Objects, and a more, or less accurate survey of them: But
they being employed, our Will hath no Power to determine the Knowledge of the Mind one
whereof the opposition between "internal persuasion" and "outward conformity"
way or other; that is done only by the Objects themselves, as far as they are clearly discov-
ered (E, IV.xiii.1-2).

66 For a reading of the Epistola that considers sincerity sufficient for salvation , see Kraynak (1980).
44 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.3 The Argument of Unfitness of Force 45

When the Agreement of any two Ideas appears to our Minds, whether immediately, or by assent as Jong as a belief seems true to him. As we shall see in the next chapter, the
the Assistance of Reason, I can no more refuse to perceive, no more avoid knowing it, than existence of a voluntary dimension of belief gives rise to an important objection to
I can avoid seei ng those Objects, which I turn my Eyes to, and look on in day-light: And
what upon full Examination I find the most probable, I cannot deny my Assent to. But
the refusal of the use of force in religious matters. In the Epistola, Locke does not
though we cannot hinder our Knowledge, where the Agreement is once perceived; nor our foresee this objection. He develops his reflection on the process of investigation
Assent, where the Probability manifestly appears upon due Consideration of all the only in An Essay concerning Human Understanding and, later, in Of the Conduct of
Measures of it: Yet we can hinder both Knowledge and Assent, by stopping our Enquiry, the Understanding. Hence, in the Epistola, with regard to premise (ix) of the argu-
and not imploying our Faculties in the search of any Truth. If it were not so, Ignorance, ment of unfitness of force, his reasoning privileges the involuntariness of belief. The
Error, or Infidelity could not in any Case be a Fault (E., IV.xx. 16).
reason for this is simple: it is this dimension that allows him to assert that the use of
Locke weaves together two conceptions of the relationship between belief and force to produce beliefs is irrational, given that it is useless, due to the inadequacy
wi11 67 : on the one hand, the will can influence belief, because belief depends on the between means and end.
employment of the human faculties; on the other, the will cannot influence belief, However, from a practical point of view, coercion is useless in the best hypoth-
because, once the human faculties are employed, the will is unable to refuse what esis, for it tends to be counterproductive in most cases. In a context in which indi-
appears true to the understanding. However subtle, it is not difficult to see the con- viduals are liable to punishment for not professing the established religion, what
trast Locke attempts to draw. In the first case, he stresses the process of investiga- should we expect? Naturally, as Locke states several times, we should expect that
tion: if the ideas available to the understanding depend on the will, it is clear, then, many people would conform outwardly in order to avoid the legal penalties imposed
that the will influences belief (so we can say that belief has a voluntary dimension); to dissenters. Hence, it is not surprising that the notions of hypocrisy and dissimula-
in the second case, he stresses the assent: once a judgement is made based on the tion figure in the Epistola, and that they are restated in the controversy with Proast.
ideas available to the understanding in a certain moment, it is impossible that, by When the argument of unfitness of force is at stake, it is not surprising to find refer-
will, a person can transfer his assent from what appears true to what does not (hence ences to hypocrisy, as in An Essay concerning Toleration (cf. ET, 278) and in A
the involuntariness of belief). Locke does not explain this distinction as clearly in Defence of Nonconformity (cf. DNC, 15). Nevertheless, the use of force in religious
the Epistola as he does in An Essay concerning Human Understanding, but it cannot matters is counterproductive because it produces insincere conformity, but also
be denied that Locke does use the distinction. Indeed, in the Epistola, we see a fluc- because many people who suffer violent punishments, or who see the suffering
tuation between the two possible meanings of the relationship between belief and caused to dissenters refuse the religion in whose name these punishments are meted
will: when Locke says that force cannot act upon the understanding, he presupposes out, as Proast himself would acknowledge (cf. Arg., 13-14, RLP, 30-31).68
the involuntariness of belief (a person can only assent to what seems true to him), So, the structure of the argument of unfitness of force is as follows : (vii) 'The
but, when he says that arguments can act upon the understanding, he presupposes magistrate's power consists in coercion', (viii) ' Salvation requires inner faith', (ix)
the voluntary dimension of belief (a person is free to employ his faculties in order 'Human understanding cannot be compelled by outward force', (x) 'Hence, the care
to reconsider his views, and in so doing, he might conclude that what seemed true of souls cannot belong to the civil magistrate'. But if the care of souls cannot belong
to him is not so). to the magistrate, to whom it should belong? Inevitably, each person must be incum-
Given this distinction, we can see why the dilemma mentioned above is false. bent upon his own salvation, and it implies that each person "must be left to himself
Similarly, we can see, in detail, what dimension of the relationship between belief and to his own conscience" (Epist., 100.10-11). There can be no other outcome of
and will Locke emphasises in the argument of unfitness of force. When Locke says Locke's reasoning, all the more if we consider that all people are equally apt or are
that, if faith is not voluntary, it is difficult to imagine how infidelity can be a sin, he equally fallible in the search for salvation. In other passages of the Epistola, Locke
resorts to the process of investigation and points out the individual responsibility - reiterates his position that each person should "be left" to himself and to his own
and duty - to examine religious matters. Depending on a person's effort, he may conscience (the Latin verb is relinquere, literally, to be left, to abandon, cf. Epist.,
never come to the true religion and, from this perspective, it is his own fault.
Conversely, when Locke says that "to believe this or that to be true is not within the 68
Con Li (2015) develops this aspect of the argument of unfitness of force. He stresses that Waldron's
scope of our will", he means that coercion is incapable of making a person shift his ( 1988) analysis is incomplete due to its focus on the categorical dimension of the argument (the
contrast between belief and will) and its contempt for the empirical dimension: the aversion caused
by force in the victims and by-standers is also a proof of the irrationality of the use of force in
67
The quotations from An Essay concerning Human Understanding make it clear that belief and religious matters. In a certain sense, Conti (2015) demonstrates how Locke's reasoning resorts to
will as well as knowledge and will hold a similar relation, but for the sake of simplicity we shall the perspective of men, but he does so without noticing that the recourse to the notion of aversion
speak here only of belief and will. On this topic, the so-called "ethics of belief', the main interpre- is not enough to call into question Waldron's (1988) thesis, i.e. Conti does not cast doubt on the
tations are Passmore (1978), Wolterstorff (1996) and Corneanu (2011, 141-168), but see also perfonnative perspective Waldron adopts. Pevinic (2009) also explores the empirical dimension of
Ayers (2005, v. I, 90--97, 127-131), Tully (1988), Losonsky (2001, 72-104), Savonius-Wroth the argument and says that the use of force, even if it followed Proast's proposal, would be coun-
(2012), Harnou (20 18), Green (2019) and Kilcullen (1988, 136-174). terproductive for another reason: it would create resistance and could lead to disorder.
46 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.4 The Argument of Reductio ad Absurdum 47

100.10, 112.14, 124.28), but he also introduces an important element: the religious 2.4 The Argument of Reductio ad Absurdum
pursuit of a person, even if erroneous, is "inoffensive" (innocuus) to others (cf.
Epist., 80. l). Even if a person loses his salvation, this loss does not cause "harm"
Here, once again, Locke reasons in a concessive vein. Having already proven that
(damnum) to his neighbour (cf. Epist., 124.30). Nobody takes any "prejudice" (det-
the care of souls is not committed to the magistrate, and that the use of force cannot
rimentum) when other people search their salvation following their own judgement
belong to the civil power because coercion is incapable of producing beliefs, he sup-
(cf. Epist., 124.16) because religion, "whether true or false, does no injury (nu/lam
poses, in the third consideration, that force can act on the understanding and, conse-
facit ... injuriam) to the rest of the citizens in their worldly affairs" (Epist.,
quently, that the care of souls belongs to the magistrate. This is Locke's last
128.14-15). As Locke points out in A Defence of Nonconformity, "the faults, &
consideration and, as in the other two, it is condensed into a single paragraph in the
miscarriages of one man hinders not anothers right, no not his owne right" (DNC,
section of the Epistola where Locke defines the ends of the Commonwealth:
3). From Locke's standpoint, a person's error (in ecclesiastical terms, the multiplic-
ity of sects) does not represent a risk to others. It is not a poison or a plague to be In the third place, the care of the salvation of souls can by no means belong to the civil
attacked by the magistrate.69 It is only according to the intolerants that the spreading magistrate ; because, even if the authority of laws and the force of penalties were capable of
converting men's minds, yet this would not help at all in the salvation of their souls. For
of a putative error is an evil to be prevented by law, as Long states in his book there being but one true religion, one way to heaven, what hope is there that most men
against the Epistola: "I believe it is the Duty of Magistrates to keep Men from would reach it, if mortals were obliged to ignore the dictates of their own reason and con-
infecting the Souls of their Subjects with destroying Errors, if he may lawfully shut science, and blindly accept the doctrines imposed by their prince, and worship God in the
up a Man that hath the Plague on his Body, why not him that hath the Plague of manner laid down by the laws of the country? Amid all the variety of opinions that different
Heresie on his Soul?" (Long, 1689, 9, RLP, 13). As the intolerants in general, among princes hold about religion, the narrow way and the strait gate that leads to heaven would
inevitably be open to very few, and they in one country only: and what would heighten the
which Proast, to whom men "cannot err, without dishonouring God, and endanger- absurdity and ill suit the notion of God, men would owe their eternal happiness or misery
ing their own and other Men's eternal Salvation" (TL-P, 2, RLP, 42), Long simply simply to the accident of their birth (Epist. , 70.3-17).
does not question the sharp distinction between orthodoxy and heterodoxy. He
assumes it to be obvious that his side has the truth without trying to explain how it The thesis to be demonstrated is that the care of souls cannot belong to the mag-
can be known. If Locke had answered him directly, he could have contested him in istrate. Here, Locke is slightly more emphatic than in his argument of unfitness of
the same terms as those he used when criticising Edward Stillingfleet (1635-1699) force, as he uses the expression "by no means" (nullo modo). As in the second con-
and Proast: he "supposes himself to be in the right" (DNC, p. 111), he resorts to a sideration, it is supposed that coercion is designed to convert a man's mind, and not
"lurking supposition" (SL, 4, Works, 65). to conform actions and manners, as in the Two Tracts on Government. However,
However, in the second consideration, Locke nowhere touches on the problem of according to Locke's description, this conversion is less a persuasion and more a
religious truth. His only aim was to show that coercion is incapable of producing submission, because it requires of each person that he "ignores" or "puts aside"
beliefs - and, in order to do so, it is indifferent whether these beliefs are true or false. (posthabere) the dictates of his own reason and conscience. A genuine conversion
As we read in A Defence of Nonconformity, the matter is not "whether the doctrine can spring only from the understanding as long as it is moved by the light of reason.
be in it self true, or false, but whether I doe beleive it" (DNC, 118). In fact, the At any rate, Locke now supposes that force is capable of producing beliefs. The
problem of religious truth emerges in the third consideration, which is formulated third consideration is built on this presupposition. Naturally, when Locke supposes
after a new concession. Locke has demonstrated that force cannot compel the under- that force can convert the understanding, he also supposes that the care of souls
standing and that, consequently, the care of souls cannot belong to the magistrate. belongs to the magistrate. But what does this imply? Would there be any gain in the
Yet, in the following stage of his reasoning, Locke concedes these two points. The salvation of souls? Locke thinks it would not promote salvation. If the care of souls
question that he then makes is this: what would happen if the care of souls belonged belonged to the magistrate, the outcome would be that people would obtain the
to the magistrate? future life according to their birthplaces - and that is nonsense. As we can see,
Locke's reasoning begins with a premise accepted by concession and amounts to an
unacceptable conclusion, whose content is universally rejected. The third consider-
ation is thus a reductio ad absurdum. However, in order to understand it in full, we
need to perceive its structure.
69 Marshall (2006, 440--466) explores the imaginary concerning intolerance in England. In his The first premise, the one to be demonstrated false, is (xi) 'Force is capable of
Third Letter, Proast speaks of a "mortal Infection" when he discusses the toleration of Pagans, converting the understanding and, consequently, the care of souls belongs to the
Jews, and Muslims (cf. TL-P, 3, RLP, 43). In The Mischief of Separation, Stillingfleet says that a magistrate' . There is no doubt that Locke does not agree with this proposition: it is
"general toleration" would have "dangerous consequences" and that it would give room for the
accepted as a hypothesis, in a concessive vein. Strictly speaking, Locke intends to
dissenter's folly, which is a "catching disease" (cf. Stillingfleet 1680, 58). On this topic, see also
Marshall (2006b). deny the causal relation presupposed in premise (xi) between (xi.a) the usefulness
48 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.4 The Argument of Reductio ad Absurdum 49

of force and (xi.b) the magistrate's commission lo take care of souls, so that, even if care of souls is incumbent upon the magistrate, all magistrates would impose their
we admit (xi.a), we do not come to (xi.b). The second premise is introduced by own religious beliefs, no matter how different they are, even though there is just one
Locke without further discussion: (xii) 'There is only one true religion'. Nowhere in true religion. If that is the case, people then would be saved depending on their
the Epistola does Locke seek to justify this proposition, because it is not a polemic birthplace. However, why would every magistrate impose his own religion? This
theological statement that requires proof. Rather, we could say that it was consid- would occur "for every man in what he beleives, has soe far this persuasion that he
ered evident. In A Third Letter, addressing Proast openly, Locke affirms: "I agree is in the right" (ET, 294). As Locke says in the Epistola, everyone - private person,
with you, that there is but one only true Religion" (TL, 160, Works, 326). By the church, prince - is orthodox to himself (cf. Epist. 58.6, 80.30, 112.2).70 To each one
same token, the third premise is presented as certain. It is an incontestable factual his own religion seems to be true, since nobody believes something that seems false
truth: (xiii) 'The princes of different countries profess different religions'. Given to him. Hence, given that (5) 'everyone is orthodox to himself', (xiii-i) 'if the care
these three premises, what is the conclusion? of souls belongs to the magistrate, different religions will be imposed around the
To Locke, there is no other conclusion but that (xiv) 'The salvation of soul world'. This is the proof of the implication (xiii-i) of premise (xiii), which proof will
depends on the chance of being born in the right place'. This conclusion is absurd be called here argument of reciprocity. All magistrates, as well as any private per-
for two reasons: firstly, because the association of birthplace and salvation implies son, profess a religion that is true to himself. If it were not so, we would fall into the
an ill conception of God; secondly, because the number of people saved would be nonsense that a person could believe something that seems false to him. Therefore,
very small, since there are several false religions and just one true one, i.e. since if the care of souls were an end of the Commonwealth, we must conclude that each
most religious beliefs imposed throughout the world would be false. Hence, if the magistrate would legislate according to the way to salvation which seems true
issue were to consider how the magistrate could contribute to the salvation of souls to him. 71
in the case that force were capable of producing beliefs, the upshot is that the mag- As for the argument of reciprocity, we must note that premise (o) is a matter of
istrate cannot be given this commission, even if force were useful. As there are fact and, as such, it does not need to be proven. In this argument, it is also important
countless false religions around the world, several false beliefs would be imposed. to note that Locke neither discusses the content or the grounds for the different reli-
Then, most people would lose eternal life simply for having been born in a country gious beliefs, nor does he debate the human cognitive capacity. In order to show that
whose prince professes a false religion. Civil power is "the same everywhere" and in religious matters everyone is orthodox to himself, he resorts neither to the distinc-
it would be lawful for each magistrate to require anything "to conform to a rule of tion between belief and knowledge (as he will later do in the controversy with
truth (ad normam veritatis) which he has invented for himself' (Epist., 112. l , 9-10). Proast), nor to the notion of fallibility (which in the Epistola is related only to the
Therefore, if Locke's reasoning is valid, the only way to avoid the conclusion is to first consideration).72 In other words, Locke does not assess the religious beliefs
reject one of the premises. Since it is impossible to reject either premise (xii), which based on their differences (if they are true or false, well or ill grounded), but on what
is a theological truth, or premise (xiii), which is factually true, the one to be rejected they have in common (the fact of being true to those who profess them). As we read
is premise (xi). As we can see, this rejection means that the care of souls cannot in An Essay concerning Human Understanding, when Locke asserts that "the
belong to the magistrate. strength of our Perswasions are no Evidence at all of their own rectitude", there is
Proast boldly refuses the third consideration, because the reductio ad absurdum nothing at stake but the fact that "crooked things may be as stiff and unftexible as
allows every magistrate to take care of souls and not only the one who professes the
true religion. Evidently, Proast does not deny the factual truth contained in premise
(xiii), what he denies is the implication that (xiii-i) 'if the care of souls belongs to
the magistrate, different religions will be imposed around the world'. From his per-
70 InA Second Vindication of the Reasonableness of Christianiry, Locke resorts to the same state-
spective, premise (xi) should not be contested. His point is that the care of souls
ment: "every one is Orthodox to himself' (Locke 2016, 193, § 382). In the same vein, he says in
belongs solely to whom professes the true religion. It is not only the usefulness of the Paraphrase and Notes on the Epistles of St Paul that "every Sect" is "perfectly Orthodox in its
force that would make people interested in committing to the magistrate the right to own Jugdment" (Locke 1987, v. I, 107).
take care of souls. Ultimately, it is the truth that authorises the magistrate to convert 71
Analysing another passage of the Epistola in which Locke adduces a similar reasoning (cf.
others: even if the commission to take care of souls were given to him, this right Epist., 152.26-154.3), Marshall (2016, 583) affirms that Locke applies "implicitly a rule of equity
could be exerted only on behalf of truth. This is a central point in the debate about or reciprocity" and turns the argument into a "reductio ad absurdum" .
72 The interpretation of this argument varies and several readings consider that the distinction
the ends of Church and State: it is not just the usefulness of force that is at stake.
Regardless of the terms in which the Locke and Proast controversy unfolded, to between belief and knowledge plays an important role here, e.g. that of Black (1998, 2007) and
Owen (2007). On the other hand, there are scholars who equate the third consideration to the argu-
which the next chapter shall be dedicated, it is important to perceive, here, that the ment of fallibility, such as Van der Schaar (2012), whereas others associate fallibility and distinc-
implication (xiii-i) of premise (xiii) needs to be proved. As we have already pointed tion between belief and knowledge, such as Tate (2016, 127-132). For a reading that singles out
out, if we admit that force is capable of producing beliefs and, consequently, that the the argument of reciprocity, see Goldie (Locke 2010, xv-xvi).
50 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.4 The Argument of Reductio ad Absurdum 51

streight: and Men may be as positive and peremptory in Error as in Truth" (E, for the truth in religion, Locke confines himself to saying that "the decision of that
IV.xix.11). 73 question belongs only to the Supreme Judge of all men" (Epist., 82.4-5).
In his Third Letter, Proast raises a significant objection to this reasoning, an As we saw in the argument of unfitness of force, one may ask to whom the argu-
objection that can, perhaps, be included in the charges of scepticism made against ment is addressed. Is the third consideration addressed to the magistrate or to men?
Locke (cf. TL-P, 35, RLP, 73). 74 As we have shown, however, the aim of the argu- Once again, it is to men that it is addressed. In the reductio ad absurdum, there is a
ment of reciprocity, in particular of its premise (o), is solely to shed light on the fact sort of calculus of consequence that makes sense only when we imagine that several
that for everyone his own religious belief is true; Locke does not want (nor does he religions could be imposed simultaneously. If it were addressed to the magistrate,
need) to question the truth of any religion, still less the truth of Christianity. By the the third consideration would be paradoxical. Since each magistrate believes his
same token, it is important to remark that the argument would not change, even if religion to be true, none of them could admit that others could impose their reli-
Locke had acknowledged (as he later does when addressing Proast directly) that the gions, unless he thought that they were also true (but this is theologically unaccept-
"true Religion and Christian Religion are, I suppose, to you and me, the same thing" able) or that their imposition would be beneficial to salvation (but this is a mistake).
(SL, 2, Works, 63) and that "that only true Religion is professed and held in the Thus, given the paradox that would follow if the third consideration were addressed
Church of England" (TL, 160, Works, 326). In sum, what is at stake is that it is to the magistrate, it is prudent to build an interpretation that makes it coherent. This
impossible for anyone to claim a right to himself to use force in religious matters is why we should read it as addressed to men, like the second consideration. Once
because he believes to have the truth without giving the same right to others. In A again, Locke squares his reasoning in a contractualist framework, and gives it an
Defence of Nonconformity, Locke makes it clear that the members of different reli- explanatory dimension, not a performative one. 77 When men leave the state of
gions think they are the " the sole deliverers of unmixed truth in doctrine & disci- nature, they have no assurance that the magistrate will really profess the only true
pline. This they all doe severally with the same confidence & zeale", that all of them religion. Uncertain about the religion they would be compelled to, they would run
are "Equall pretenders to say they are the true Church & must be beleived or have the risk of losing the future life if the care of souls were committed to the civil
the magistrate on their side & must be obeyd" (DNC, 86, 87). When two religious power. If we assume that there are several religions and only one is true, the chance
parties are opposed, none of them can claim a right that cannot be demanded by the of being coerced on behalf of error is greater than of being coerced on behalf of
other. If it is the truth (in fact, the putative truth) that ultimately forms the basis of truth. So it is unreasonable to commit the care of souls to the magistrate.
the magistrate's right to use force to take care of the souls, all magistrates may have This reasoning, which explores the consequences of the use of force in religious
the very same right, since all of them judge their own religion to be true. From each matters, is used by Locke in his reply to Proast. But unsurprisingly, we find it in the
one's perspective, the others are wrong. 75 Anyone who puts himself above others, Epistola (it had already appeared in the second consideration, when Locke con-
saying that his beliefs are certain, cannot do it but out of enthusiasm, as if his tenets tended that the use of force to promote conversion would be not only inefficient, but
were "divinely inspired" (pro theopneustis, cf. Epist., 152.21).76 In the Epistola, as counterproductive). In fact, it is because this consequentialist way of reasoning is

73 That the intensity of assent is not a criterion of truth seems to be an issue that Locke intended to
second of the Essays on the Law of Nature, inspiration is pictured as a kind of knowledge (cf.
tackle in the Essays on the Law of Nature. In a manuscript (MS. Locke e. 6) that contains a draft
Locke 1954, 122.23- 26). According to Locke in the preface to the Paraphrase and Notes on the
of some of these essays, he mentions a title of an essay that he never came to write: "if the firm Epistles of St Paul, Paul is the major example of a God-inspired man: "I remembered that St Paul
persuasion of the soul (firma animi persuasio) proves the law of nature" (cf. Long 1959, 31). was miraculously called to the Ministry of the Gospel, and declared to be a chosen Vessel; that he
74
0n Locke and scepticism, see Rogers (1998) and, in particular, Rogers (2003) and Sina (2015a, had the whole Doctrine of the Gospel from God by immediate Revelation" (Locke 1987, v. I, 110).
b).However, we must observe that most convictions of scepticism that Locke received came from On Paul and immediate revelation, see also E, IV.xviii.3 and Locke (1987, v. I, 306-308; cf.
those authors who raised objections against An Essay concerning Human Understanding, like John Corinthians 12: l-13).
Sergeant (1623-1707) and Henry Lee (t1713), as Yolton (1968) shows. In Proast's three letters, 77
There is no doubt that this framework may impose some limits to Locke's reflection on tolera-
there is one occurrence of the word (the one just quoted). Locke rejects emphatically the statement
tion, as Spitz (2002, 123- 124) states : "the argument [the third consideration] is valid from the
that the Epistola or A Second Letter promote scepticism (cf. TL, 237, Works, 415). For a broad subjects' point of view (it is contrary to the rational calculus to vest in a third person the power to
view of the revival of scepticism in the modern age, see Popkin (2003) and Schmitt (1 972). govern my belief), but it cannot serve to show to the persecutors that their conduct is not rational
75
This is why Tuckness (2008) stresses the notion of universality when he discusses this argument, because, strictly speaking, they are convinced that they have the truth. One might say, therefore,
but we must recall, in contrast with what the author says elsewhere (cf. Tuckness 2002a), that this that Locke's argumentation is deep and pertinent in the context of a political theory that affirms
argument is addressed to men, not to the magistrate. For an interpretation of this argument based that the civil magistrate does not have any powers except for those the subjects or citizens wanted
on the notion of "public reason", see Vernon (1997, 35-51 ). or could want to commit to him. Locke's argumentation is very cogent when we presuppose that
76
Locke is a well-known critic of enthusiasm, but he does not deny the possibility of genuine the citizens reflect on the power they could be j ustified in commitin g to those who govern them.
divine inspirations (cf. E, IV.xix.5). In the sixth of the Essays on the Law of Nature, he points out But it is no more cogent when Locke's theory of political power is not presupposed ... and when
that the divine will can be known by the light of nature or revealed " by God-inspired men or in one endeavours to elaborate a justification for toleration independent from any particular theory
some other manner" (vet per viros Beonvevarovi:; vel alio modo) (Locke 1954, 186.5-7). In the about the origin and end of political power".
52 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.5 Argumentative Synthesis 53

found in the Epistola that empirical concerns will be so recurrent in the controversy goods. As Locke says in An Essay concerning Toleration , "the magistrate hath noe
provoked by The Argument. To Locke, there has never been an interest to support thing with the good of mens soules or their concemments in an other life but is
toleration resorting only to the argument of unfitness of force (in other words, to the ordeind, & intrusted with his power, only for the quiet & comfortable liveing of men
opposition between will and understanding), as though his aim were simply to show in society one with an other" (ET, 281-282). It is noteworthy, however, that defend-
that, in principle, force cannot produce beliefs. As we saw in this chapter, there are ing the position that no magistrate, nowhere in the world, should use force to take
several arguments to support the restriction of the ends of the Commonwealth to care of souls is different from defending the position that everything in religion
civil goods. The last of these arguments, the reductio ad absurdum, is the culmina- should be accepted. Locke never supports the latter statement. On the contrary, he
tion of a development in three gradual stages: in the first moment, Locke aims to acknowledges the possibility of legal interventions in certain ways of worships for
show that the care of souls does not belong to the magistrate; in the second, that it political reasons and vindicates the exclusion of those who profess intolerable prac-
cannot belong to him; and in the third, that there would be dire consequences if it tical beliefs, as we mentioned in the introduction to this chapter.
belonged to him, since it would restrict salvation to few people and would imply an This observation is important because Locke's arguments are not intended to
offense to God. 78 In this sense, even if force could produce beliefs, as Proast sus- show that religious toleration is an inalienable individual right, if by that we mean
tains, there would be one reason not to institute the care of souls as an end of the that each person would have the right to profess and perform any beliefs or wor-
Commonwealth: the argument of reciprocity. It is, therefore, no accident that a good ships. It is an inalienable right as long as its enjoyment does not endanger civil
part of the Locke and Proast controversy turns to the debate about the true religion, society. 80 In fact, in all four of his letters on toleration, there is only one passage
as we shall see. where Locke associates toleration with the notion of individual right. He makes this
association in a context in which he discusses the transition from the state of nature
to civil society and in which it is clear that the statement "every Man has a right to
Toleration" entails no more than the right of not being coerced to someone else's
2.5 Argumentative Synthesis religion: the "Protection from such Injury is one of the Ends of a Commonwealth"
(TL, 61, Works, 212).81 In short, toleration is a negative right: the right of not being
In the Epistola, Locke deploys his three considerations in a contractualist frame- compelled to convert. It is gained (or kept, since it is a natural right) when the mag-
work. They have an explanatory character, rather than a perfonnative one, as men- istrate abstains from the use of force to impose or to forbid beliefs and ways of
tioned in the analysis of the arguments of unfitness of force and reductio ad worship on behalf of a putative truth. Political power has no business with salvation.
absurdum. 79 The considerations justify the restriction of the magistrate's mandate to In the Epistola, the defence of toleration is focused on the magistrate, even if private
civil goods or, in other words, they explain why the ends of the Commonwealth can- persons, churches and clergymen also have the duty to tolerate other religions and
not be extended beyond civil goods. However, one may ask whether these argu- their followers. Such is Locke's emphasis on the civil power and its ends that he
ments are able to move the intolerants, i.e. those who think that the magistrate has touches on the issue of active resistance. He admits that men may "defend, with the
the right to use force to promote the only true religion (and it so happens that the arms at their disposal, the rights which God and nature have granted them"; when
only true religion is always the one professed by each intolerant). It is not easy to the liberty of belief and worship is violated, "it is lawful to repel force with force"
answer this question, but an analysis of the Locke and Proast controversy may give (Epist., 146.15-17, cf. TTG, II§ 209). Active resistance is the last resort available
us some clues, as we shall see in the next chapter. When we consider the objections to men in defence of their right to take care of their own salvation, which is, accord-
raised against the Epistola and the way Locke's replies were received, it will shed ing to Locke, a "natural & Evangelical right" (DNC, 102). Active resistance is not,
light on the intolerants' way of reasoning. In fact, it will reveal that we should have however, a path to anarchy or confusion. As Locke states in the Two Treatises of
no hope that they will rethink their tenets.
Regardless of the possibility of convincing an intolerant (supposing that a dia-
logue with him is really feasible), Locke's defence of religious toleration entailed 80
Collins (2020, 234, 256) also speaks of an inalienable individual right. He argues that the Defence
the distinction between the ends of Church and State, i.e. that the ends of the of Nonconformity is the turning point for the case of "conscientious religious exercise" in Locke's
Commonwealth must be circumscribed to the preservation and advancement of civil intellectual progression from the Two Tracts on Government to the Epistola.
81
In Popple's translation, there is a passage that reads "that liberty of conscience is every man's
natural right" (Popple, 95), but it is not in the original. Compare: " .. . ut omnes ecclesiae teneremur
78 Lennon (1997, 188-189) also sees a development in the three considerations, but he puts it in the
docere et pro libertatis suaefundamento ponere" (Epist., 134.28-29) and " ... that all churches
following way: "the magistrate's control of religious belief would be inappropriate, anyhow were obliged to Jay down toleration as the foundation of their own liberty, and teach that liberty of
impossible, and, even if possible, improbable in achieving its intended effect". conscience is every man ' s natural right" (Popple, 93-95). In A Third Letter, the expression "right
79
Therefore, it cannot be said, as Tate (2016, 16) does, that Locke's first consideration takes prior- to toleration" occurs in another passage, but it refers to "those who deny Atheism (which takes
ity over the others. They are intertwined and should be read from a contractualist perspective. away all Religion) to have any Right to Toleration at all" (TL, 236, Works, 414 ).
54 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia 2.5 Argumentative Synthesis 55

Government, "Force is to be opposed to nothing, but to unjust and unlawful Force" 1'dblt! 2.1 Synoptic table
(TIG, II § 204, cf. TIG, II §§ 224-228).
Synoptic Table
Therefore, even if we cannot deny the relevance of the evangelical argument,
whose tenor is theological and moral, it is unquestionable that Locke's arguments Evangelical Argument
are mainly political. From this perspective, we can say that Locke aims to demon- (i) 'Being a Christian is to follow Christ's example'
strate that the magistrate has, and must have, a restricted authority,82 but also to (ii) 'Christ's example is to act virtuously with meekness and charity'
(iii) 'Hence, being a Christian is to act virtuously with meekness and charity'
prove that this jurisdiction of the political power is coherent with Christianity. This
endeavour is made through a cluster of arguments, whose relationship can now be
synoptically perceived (Table 2.1).
Political Scriptural Argument
Of all these arguments, the arguments of unfitness of force and of reciprocity are (a) 'It seems that nowhere in the Scripture
the most important, but we must stress that both of them fit into the contractualist has God committed the care of souls to
First Consideration the civil magistrate'
framework, i.e. both of them are explanatory and not performative. Of these two, the Argument from
argument of unfitness of force is the only one directly associated with the argument (iv) 'God has not committed the care of
Commission souls to the civil magistrate'
from commission (because it is literal in the first consideration), but the third con- (iv) 'God has not
sideration must also be associated with it. Furthermore, it is noteworthy that in the committed the care of souls
to the civil magistrate'
Epistola the argument of fallibility has a political character, whereas in a famous (v) 'Men have not
Argument of Fallibility
passage of An Essay concerning Human Understanding (cf. E, IV.xvi.4) it has a (~) 'all men, regardless of their position
committed the care of souls
or status, are liable to error'
moral character, as we shall see in the fourth chapter. In the Epistola, this argument to the civil magistrate'
(y) 'if a person misguides another with
is not intended to show that a man should tolerate another because both of them are (vi) 'Hence, the care of
regard to salvation, he can make no
souls has not been
liable to error, but to justify why people restrict the magistrate's jurisdiction to civil committed to the civil
reparation'
goods. Fallibility here acts as a political reason for toleration, because it justifies (v) 'Men have not committed the care of
magistrate'
souls to the civil magistrate'
men's refusal to commit the care of souls to the magistrate. It is not a moral reason
for toleration, because Locke extracts no eirenic implications from it. The issue, in
short, is the vertical, not the horizontal toleration. Fallibility may, no doubt, have a Argument of Unfitness of Force
moral implication, but it is not present in the Epistola, even in the section where
Locke discusses the duties in regard to toleration incumbent on private persons. In Second Consideration
that section, their duties to toleration are based exclusively on the statement that a Argument of Unfitness of Force
man's error is inoffensive to others (cf. Epist., pp. 78.30-80.1). (vii) 'The magistrate's power consists in coercion'
(viii) 'Salvation requires inner faith'
We may now understand precisely not only Locke's arguments in the Epistola, (ix) 'Human understanding cannot be compelled by outward force'
but also their interconnection. Locke started his reflection by exposing what seemed (x) 'Hence, the care of souls cannot belong to the civil magistrate'
to him to be the distinguishing mark of a true church, and attempting to prove that
Christians must tolerate others because love and meekness are the core of Christ's
Third Consideration
Argument of Reductio ad Absurdum
(xi) 'Force is capable of converting the
82 "Locke's argument, to put it simply, is not a defence of rights; it is a challenge to authority. What understanding and, consequently, the care Argument of
he proposes to demonstrate in the Letter concerning Toleration is that the claim for authority to use of souls belongs to the magistrate' Reciprocity
force to persecute individuals for their religious beliefs is not defensible on any ground .... Not (xii) 'There is only one true religion' (o) 'Everyone is
only has Locke put his opponents on the defensive, challenging them to produce a justification for (xiii) 'The princes of different countries orthodox to himself
authority which he denies exists, but also, it is obvious that without such a justification, the natural profess different religions' = (xiii-i) 'if the (xiii-i) 'Hence, if the
tight of individuals to worship freely is preserved" (Aschcraft 2009, 59-60). Nevertheless, it must care of souls belongs to the magistrate, care of souls belongs
be stressed that, even if the Epistola represents a challenge to political authority, it seems undeni- different religions will be imposed around to the magistrate,
able that it vindicates to each individual "the tights that are granted to other citizens" (concessa the world' different religions
aliis civibusjura) (Epist., 140.28-29). ln a letter to Limborch of 10 September 1689, Locke seems (xiv) 'Hence, the salvation of soul will be imposed
to express the same point when he speaks of "the establishment of equal liberty for all" (aequ/i depends on the chance of being born in around the world'.
omnibus... libertate) (Corr., v. III, 1182). Locke's purpose is not to propose a policy (that may be the tight place'
withdrawn if circumstances change), but a definition of the Commonwealth itself according to
which all citizens or subjects have the same tights (cf. Schochet 1992, 150-151 ).
56 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia References 57

example. As the Epistola develops, this theological and moral dimension is given Bayle, Pierre. 1737. <Euvres Diverses de Mr. Pierre Buyle, nouvelle edition considerabkment
less emphasis in favour of a political one. However, this theological and moral augmentee, vol. 4. Haye: par la Compagnie des Libraires.
Biddle, John C. 1977. John Locke's Essay on lnfalJibility: Introduction, Text and Translation.
dimension is never undermined. As we saw above, the relationship between force Journal of Church and State 19: 301-327.
and charity is an essential topic of the modem debate on toleration. Hence, if Le Clerc, Jean. 1689. Bibliotheque Universelle et Historique de l'annee M.D.C.LXXXIX, tome
Locke's metaphor in A Second Letter indicated that different beams sustain reli- quinzieme, seconde edition revOe et corrigee. Amsterdam: chez Jes heritiers d' Antoine Shelte.
gious toleration, we may say that the building is based, on the one hand, on the Locke, John. 1690. A Second Letter concerning Toleration. London: printed for Awnsham and
evangelical argument, and, on the other, on the three considerations, which com- John Churchill in Ave-Mary Lane Near Pater-Noster-Row.
- - - . I 691. Du Gouvernement Civil. Amsterdam: chez Abraham Wolfgang pres de la Bourse.
prise a cluster of arguments to explain and justify the restriction of the magistrate's - - - . 1692. A Third Letter for Toleration to the Author ofthe Third Letter Concerning Toleration
commission to the civil goods. Indeed, therefore, there are two beams that support London: printed for Awnsham and John Churchill at the Black Swan in Pater-Noster-Row.
the house built in the Epistola, but the second one is a reinforced beam, a threefold - - - . 1720. A Collection ofSeveral Pieces of Mr. John Locke never before printed or not extant
beam, since the three considerations are intertwined. It must be stressed, however, in his Works, ed. Pierre Des Maizeaux. London: printed by J. Bettenham for R. Francklin at
that each of these beams reflects different meanings of the notion of toleration: the the Sun in Fleetstreet.
- - - . 1735. Essai Philosophique concernant l'Entendement Humain, traduit de l'anglois par
evangelical argument turns to the relationship between private persons (the horizon- M. Coste, troisieme edition, revOe, corrigee & augmentee de quelques additions importantes de
tal dimension of toleration) whereas all the other arguments deal with the relation- !'auteur qui n'ont paru qu'apres sa mort & de quelques remarques du traducteur. Amsterdam:
ship between State and citizens or subjects (the vertical dimension). chez Pierre Mortier.
In A Second Letter, when Locke explains the metaphor of the beams, he is not - - - . 1823. The Works of Joh11 Locke, I 0 vol. London: printed for Thomas Tegg et al.
fair to his reasoning in the Epistola, as we shall see in the next chapter. In The - - - . 1954. Essays on the Law of Nature, ed. W. von Leyden. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- - - . 1963. A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. M. Montuori. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Argument, Proast perceived the contractualist framework of Locke's reasoning and - - - . 1967. Two Tracts on Government, ed. P. Abrams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
the centrality of the discussion of the magistrate's authority. As a result, his critique - - - . 1968. Epistola de tolerantia, ed. R. Klibansky and J. W. Gough. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
of Locke culminated in the statement that in religious matters "it is every man's true - - - . 1976-1989. The Correspondence of John Locke, ed. E. S. de Beer, 8 vols. Oxford:
Interest, not to be left wholly to himself' (Arg., 22, RLP, 35). Proast's main target is Clarendon Press.
the beam formed by the three considerations, but this does not prevent him from - - - . 1987. A Paraphrase and Notes on the Epistles of Saint Paul, ed. A. W. Wainwright, 2 vols.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
dealing with the evangelical argument (or, precisely, with the conception of - - - . 1989. Some Thoughts Concerning Education, ed. J. W. Yolton and J. S. Yolton. Oxford:
Christianity that underpins the argument), as we shall also see in the next chapter. Clarendon Press.
Ultimately, Locke and Proast attempt to assess the reasons why the ends of the - - - . 1990. Drafts for the Essay Co11cerning Human Understanding and Other Philosophical
Commonwealth should be instituted more restrictedly or largely, but they both also Writings, ed. P. Nidditch and G. A. J. Rogers, vol. I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
discuss whether or not force is compatible with Christianity. Having set forth - - - . 1999. The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. J. C. Higgins-Biddle. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Locke's arguments, we shall now analyse the objections raised against the Epistola, - - - . 2000. Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. P. Schuurman. Ph.D Dissertation,
and the controversy that unfolded. University of Keele.
- - - . 2002. John Locke: Political Essays, ed. M. Goldie. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- - -. 2002b. John Locke: Writings on Religion, ed. V. Nuovo. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
References - - - . 2003. A Denfence of Nonconfonnity, transcription T. Stanton In Stanton, Timothy.
John Locke, Edward Stillingfleet and Toleration , Ph.D Dissertation, Appendix, University of
Leicester.
Primary Sources - - - . 2006. An Essay Concerning Toleration and Other Writings on Law and Politics,
1667- 1683, ed. J. R. Milton and P. Milton. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- - - . 2010. A Letter Concerning Toleratio11 and Other Writings, ed. M. Goldie. Indianapolis:
Augustine. J870-1 873. CEuvres Completes de Saint Augustin, traduites en frani;:ais et annotees Liberty Fund.
par MM. Peronne, Vincent, Ecalle et Barreau, vol. 4 (lettres I a CV), vol. 5 (lettres CVI a - - - . 2011. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. Nidditch. Oxford:
CLXXXIX), vol. 6 (lettres CXC a CCLV). Paris: Librairie de Louis Vives. Clarendon Press.
- - - . 2001. Political Writings, ed. E. M. Atkins and R. J. Dodaro. Cambridge: Cambridge - - -. 2015. Two Treatises of Government, ed. P. Laslett, 26 ed. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. University Press.
- - - . 2019. Retrata~oes Tr. A. Belmonte Sao Paulo: Paulus. - - - . 2016. Vindications of the Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. V. Nuovo. Oxford:
- - - . Discorsi. Discorso 112. https://www.augustinus.it/italiano/discorsi/index2.htm. Accessed Clarendon Press.
8 Feb 2021.
Basnage de Beauval, Henri. 1721. Histoires des Ouvrages des S~avans Mois de SEPT. OCT. &c
jusqu'au mois d' AOUST 1690 inclus, tome VI. Amsterdam: chez Michel Charles Le Cene.
58 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia References 59

Long, Thomas. 1689. The Letter for Toleration decipher'd and the Absurdity and Impiety of an Dunn, John. 1980. Consent in the Political Theory of John Locke. In Political Obligation and in Its
Absolute Toleration demonstrated. London: printed by Freeman Collins and are to be sold by Historical Context, ed. J. Dunn, 29-52. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
R. Baldwin in the Old-Bay. - - - . 1996. Contractualism. In The History of Political Theory and other essays, ed. J. Dunn,
- - - . 1999. The Letter for Toleration Decipher'd and the Absurdity and Impiety of an Absolute 39-65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Toleration Demonstrated. 1n The Reception of Lccke's Politics, ed. M. Goldie, vol. 5, 1-21. Goldie, Mark. 1991. The theory of Religious Intolerance in Restoration England. In From
London: Pickering & Chatto. Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England, ed. O.P. Grell,
Proast, Jonas. 1690. The Argument of the Letter Concerning Toleration Briefly Consider'd and J.I. Israel, and N. Tyache, 331-368. Oxford: Clarendon University Press.
Answer'd. Oxford: printed at the Theatre, for George West and Henry Clements, Booksellers - - - . 1993. John Locke, Jonas Proast and Religious Toleration 1688-92. In The Church of
in Oxford. England c. 1688-c. 1833, ed. J. Walsh, C. Haydon, and S. Taylor, 143-171. Cambridge:
- - - . 169 I. A Third Letter concerning Toleration: in defense of tire Argument of the Letter con- Cambridge University Press.
cerning Toleration briefly consider'd and answer' d. Oxford: printed by L. Lichfield for George - - - . 2018. John Locke, the early Loc keans, and Priestcraft. Intellectual History Review 28:
West and Henry Clements. 125-144.
- - - . 1999. The Argument of the Letter concerning Toleration briefly consider'd and answer'd; Goldie, Mark, and Richard Popkin. 2006. Scepticism, Priestcraft, and Toleration. In The Cambridge
A Third Letter concerning Toleration: in defense of the Argument of the Letter concerning History of the Eighteenth-Century Political Thought, ed. M. Goldie and R. Wokler, 79-109.
Toleration briefly consider'd and answer'd; A Second Letter to the Author of the Three Letters Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
for Toleration In The Reception of Lccke's Politics, ed. M. Goldie, v. 5, 23-128. London: Green, Felicity. 2019. Freedom and Obligation in Locke's Account of Belief. British Journal for
Pickering & Chatto. the History of Philosophy 28: 69-89.
- - - . 20 I0. The Argument of the Letter concerning Toleration briefly consider'd and answer'd; Hamou, Philippe. 2018. Locke: "Aimer la Verite pour Elle Meme". Archives de Philosophie
A Third Letter for Toleration [selection]; A Second Letter to the Author of the Three Letters 81: 99-113.
for Toleration [selection] In Lccke on toleration, ed. R. Vernon, 54-66, 108-122, 164-169. Harris, Tan. 1998. The Mind of John Lccke. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. - - - . 2013. John Locke and Natural Law: Free Worship and Toleration. In Natural Law and
Stillingfleet, Edward. 1680. The Mischief ofSeparation. London: printed for Henry Mortlock at the Toleration in the Early Enlightenment, ed. J. Parkin and T. Stanton, 59-105. Oxford: Oxford
Phoenix in St Pauls Church-yard at the White Hart in Westminster Hall. University Press. (Proceedings of the British Academy n. 186).
Jolley, Nicholas. 2016. Toleration & Understanding in Lccke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Joly, Roben. 1955. Saint Augustin et !'intolerance religieuse. Revue beige de philologie et
d'histoire 33: 263-294.
Secondary Sources Kilcullen, John. 1988. Sincerity and Trwh: Essays on Arnauld, Bayle, and Toleration. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Kraynak, Roben. 1980. John Locke: From Absolutism to Toleration. The American Political
Ashcraft, Richard. 2009. Locke and the Problem of Toleration. In Discourses of Tolerance and
Science Review 74: 53-69.
intolerance in the European Enlightenment, ed. H.E. BOdeker and P.H. Reill, 53-72. Toronto:
Lamb, Roben, and Benjamin Thompson. 2009. The Meaning of Charity in Locke's Political
Toronto University Press.
Thought. European Journal of Political Theory 8: 229-252.
Ayers, Michael. 2005. Lccke. Vol. 2. New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis e-Library.
Lancaster, James A. 2018. From Matters of Faith to Matters of Fact: The Problem of Priestcraft in
Bejan, Teresa M. 2015. Evangelical Toleration. The Journal of Politics 77: 1103-1113.
Early Modern England. Intellectual History Review 28: 145-165.
Black, Sam. 1998. Toleration and the Skeptical Inquirer in Locke. Canadian Journal of Philosophy
Lancaster, James A., and Andrew McKenzie-McHarg. 2018. Priestcraft. Anatomizing the Anti-
28: 473-504. Clericalism of Early Modern Europe. Intellectual History Review 28: 7-22.
- - -. 2007. Locke and the Skeptical Argument for Toleration. Histo1y of Philosophy Quarterly
Lennon, Thomas. 1997. Bayle, Locke and the Metaphysics of Toleration. In Studies in Seventeenth-
24: 355-375.
Century European Philosophy, ed. M.A. Stewart, 177-195. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Oxford
Bou-Habib, Paul. 2003. Locke, Sincerity and the Rationality of Persecution. Political Studies 51:
Studies in the History of Philosophy II)
611-626.
Loconte, Joseph. 2014. God, Lccke and Liberry: The Struggle for Religious Freedom i11 the West.
Chen, Selina. 2006. Locke's Political Arguments for Toleration. In John Lccke: Critical Assessments
New York: Lexington Books.
of Leading Philosophers, Series 11, ed. P. Anstey, vol. I, 371-389. London: Routledge.
Long, P. 1959. A Summary Catalogue of the Leve/ace Collection of the Papers ofJohn Lccke in the
Coffey, John. 2000. Persecution and Toleration in Protestant England 1558-1689. Edinburgh:
Bodleian Library. Oxford: Oxford Bibliographical Society Publications.
Longman. Loque, Flavia F. 2020. A recep<;:1io da Carta sobre a Tolerancia de Locke. 0 que 11os faz pensar
Collins, Jeffrey R. 2020. Jn the Shadow of Leviathan: John Lccke and the politics of conscience.
29: 5-35.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Losonsky, Michael. 2001. Enlightenment and Action from Descartes to Kant: Passionate Thought.
Conti, Gregory. 2015. Lockean Toleration and the Victim's Perspective. European Journal of
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Political Theory 14: 76-97.
Lucci, Diego. 2020. John Lccke's Christianity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Comeanu, S. 2011. Regimens of the Mind: Boyle, Lccke and the Early Modern Cultura Animi
Marshall, John. 1990. John Locke's Religious, Educational and Moral Thought. The Historial
Tradition. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Journal 33: 993-1001.
Curley, Edwin. 20 I 7. From Augustine to Locke and Spinoza: Answering the Christian Case against
- - - . 1994. John Locke: Resistance, Religion and Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge
Religious Liberty. In Politics. Religion and Political Theology, ed. C.A. Speight and M. Zank,
University Press.
I9-37. Dordrecht: Springer.
60 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia References 61

- - - . 2006. John Locke, Tulerution und Early Enlightenment Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge modema ojferti a Antuniu Rotondo, ed. H. Mechoulan t:l al., vol. 2, 707-749. Firenze: Leu
University Press. S. Olschki.
- - - . 2006b. Defining and Redefining Heresy up to Locke's Letters concerning Toleration. - - - . 2008. Circles of Vinuosi and "Charity under Different Opinions": the crucible of Locke's
In Heresy, Literature, and Politics in Early Modem English Culture, ed. D. Loewenstein and last writings. In Studies on Locke: Sources, Contemporaries, and Legacy: in honour of
J. Marshall, 254-281. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. G. A. J. Rogers, ed. S. Hutton and P. Schuurman, 159-175. Dordrecht: Springer.
Nuovo, Victor. 2011. Locke's Religious Thinking and his Politics. In Christianity, Antiquity and Sina, Mario. 2015a. Rileggendo John Locke: la tolleranza, frutto di scetticismo? In Studi su John
Enlightenment: Interpretations of Locke, 235-246. New York: Springer. Locke e su altri pensatori cristiani agli albori del secolo dei lumi, 63-67. Milano: Vita e
Owen, J. Judd. 2007. Locke's Case for Religious Toleration: Its Neglected Foundation in the Essay Pensiero. [Original: L'Osseravtore Romano, 28 gennaio 1978, p. 3]
concerning Human Understanding. The Journal of Politics 69: 156--168. - - - . 2015b. Tolleranza religiosa e scetticismo. Riftessioni sull'«Epistola de Tolerantia» nel
Passmore, J.A. 1978. Locke and the Ethics of Belief. Proceedings of the British Academy 64: terzo centenario della sua pubblicazione. In Studi su John Locke e su altri pensatori cristiani
185-208. agli albori del secolo dei lumi, 123-134. Milano: Vitae Pensiero. [Original: Vitae Pensiero v.
Pevinic, Ryan. 2009. The Lockean Case for Religious Toleration: The Social Contract and the 72 n. 12 ( 1989) pp. 839-850]
Irrationality of Persecution. Political Studies 57: 846--865. Soulard, Delphine. 2011. L'<Euvre des premiers traducteurs frarn;ais de John L ocke: Jean Le Clerc,
Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford Pierre Coste et David Maze!. Dix-septieme Siecle 253: 739-762.
University Press. - - - . 2019. The Reception ofLocke's Politics: Locke in the Republique des Lettres. In Politics,
Pritchard, Elizabeth A. 2014. Religion in Public: Locke's Political Theology. Stanford: Stanford Religion and Ideas in Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-Century Britain: Essays in Honour ofMark
University Press. Goldie, ed. J. Champion, J. Coffey, T. Harris, and J. Marshall, 201-218. Nova York: Boydell
Robbins, Caroline. 1967. Absolute liberty: the life and thought of William Popple, 1638-1708. The and Brewer.
William and Mary Quarterly 24: 190-223. Spitz, Jean-Fabien. 2002. Quelques difficultes de la theorie lockienne de la tolerance. In Lesfonde-
Rogers, G.A.J. 1998. Locke and the Sceptical Challenge. In Locke 's Enlightenment: Aspects of ments philosophiques de la tolerance, ed. Y.C. Zarka, F. Lessay, and J. Rogers, vol. 1, 114-150.
the Origin, Nature, and Impact of his Philosophy, 33-48. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag. Paris: PUF.
[Original: Rogers, G. A. J. 1996. In The Philosophical Canon in the 17th and 18th Centuries: Stanton, Timothy. 2006. Locke and the Politics and Theology of Toleration. Political Studies
Essays in Honour ofJohn W. Yolton, G. A. J. Rogers, S. Tomaselli, 49-66. Rochester: University 54: 84-102.
of Rochester Press.]. - --. 2011. Authority and Freedom in the Interpretation of Locke's Political Philosophy.
- - - . 2002. Locke, Stillingfteet et la Tolerance Tr. M.-A. Solasse. In Les fondements philos- Political Theory 39: 6--30.
ophiques de la tolerance, ed. Y.C. Zarka, F. Lessay, and J. Rogers, vol. l, 91-113. Paris: PUF. - - - . 2012. On (Mis)interpreting Locke: A Reply to Tate. Political Theory 40: 229-236.
- -- . 2003. John Locke and the sceptics. In The Return of Scepticism from Hobbes and - - - . 2017. Natural Law, Judgement and Toleration in Locke. European Journey of Political
Descartes to Bayle, ed. G. Paganini, 37-53. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Theory 16: 128-135.
Russo, Raffaele. 2019. The Thread of Discourse: Primary and Secondary Paraphrase in Locke's Tarcov, Nathan. 1999. John Locke and the Foundations of Toleration. In Early Modern Skepticism
Hermeneutics. In Locke and Biblical Hermeneutics: Conscience and Scripture, ed. L. Simonutti, and the Origins of Toleration, ed. A. Levine, 179-195. Boston: Lexington Books.
121-141. Dordrecht: Springer. Tate, John W. 2012. Locke, God and Civil Society: Response to Stanton. Political Theory 40:
Savonius, S.-J. 2004. Locke in French: The Du Gouvernement Civil of 1691 and Its Readers. The 222-228.
Historical Journal 47: 47-79. - - - . 2013. Dividing Locke from God: The Limits ofTheology in Locke's Political Philosophy.
Savonius-Wroth, S.J. 2012. 'Lovers of truth' in Pierre Bayle's and John Locke's Thought. In Philosophy and Social Criticism 39: 133-164.
The intellectual Consequences of Religious Heterodoxy 1600-1750, ed. S. Mortimer and - - - . 2016. Liberty, Toleration and Equality: John Locke, Jonas Proast and the Letters
J. Robertson, 155-180. Leiden: Brill. Concerning Toleration. New York: Routledge.
Scalise, Charles J. 1996. Exegetical Warrants for Religious Persecution: Augustine vs the Donatists. - - -. 2017. Locke, Toleration and Natural Law: A Reassessment. European Journal of Political
Review & Expositor 93: 497-506. Theory 16: 109-121.
Schmitt, Charles B. 1972. Cicero Scepticus: A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Tuckness, Alex. 2002a. Rethinking the Intolerant Locke. American Journal of Political Science
Renaissance. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. 46: 288-298.
Schochet, Gordon J. 1992. John Locke and Religious Toleration. In The Revolution of 1688-1689: - - - . 2002b. Locke and the Legislative Point of View: Toleration, Contested Principles, and the
Changing Perspectives, ed. L.G. Schwoerer, 147-164. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Schwartzman, Micah. 2005. The Relevance of Locke's Religious Arguments for Toleration. - - - . 2008. Locke's Main Argument for Toleration. In Toleration and Its Limits, ed.
Political Theory 33: 678-705. M.S. Williams and J. Waldron, I 14-138. New York: New York University Press. (Nomos
Silva, Saulo H.S. 2013. Tolerancia Civil e Religiosa em John Locke. Sao Crist6vao: Editora UFS. XLVIII).
Simonutti, Luisa. 1998. Un acteur et temoin du debat sur Ja tolerance: William Popple, marchand, Tully, James. 1988. Governing Conduct. In Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe,
ecrivan et poete de la liberte. QI VIE I R IT Y 8: 267-272. ed. E. Leites, 12-71. Cambridge, Paris: Cambridge University Press, Maison des Sciences de
- - - . 1999. Religion, Philosophy, and Science: John Locke and Limborch's Circle in !'Homme.
Amsterdam. In Everything Connects: Jn Conference with Richard H. Popkin. Essays in His Van der Schaar, Maria. 2012. Locke on Judgement and Religious Toleration. British Journal for
Honour, ed. J.E. Force and D.S. Katz, 293-324. Leiden: Brill. the Histo ry of Philosophy 20: 41-68.
- - - . 2001. "Absolute, universal, equal and inviolable liberty of conscience" Popple, Locke e Vernon, Richard. 1997. The Career of Toleration - John Locke, Jonas Proast and After. Montreal:
ii "Dry Club". In La Formazione Storica dellaAlteritii: studi di storia del/a tolleranza nell'etii McGill Queen's University Press.
62 2 The Argumentative Structure of the Epistola de Tolerantia

Waldron, Jeremy. 1988. Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution. In Jusrifying Chapter 3
Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives, ed. S. Mendus, 61-86. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. The Locke and Proast Controversy
- - . 2002. God, Locke and Equality: Christian Foundations ofJohn Locke 's Political Thought.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Walker, William. 1996. Force, Metaphor, and Persuasion in Locke 's A Letter Concerning Toleration
In Difference and Dissent: Theories of Toleration in Medieval and Early Modern Europe, ed.
C.J. Nederman and J.C. Laursen, 205-229. New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Wolfson, Adam. 20 10. Persecution and Toleration: An Explanation of the Locke-Proast Quarrel,
1689- 1704. New York: Lexington Books.
Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1996. John Locke and the Ethics of Belief Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Wootton, David. 1993. Introduction. In Locke, John. Political Writings, ed. D. Wootton, 7-122.
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. Abstract This chapter attempts to reconstruct, in a synthetic and systematic way,
Yo lton, John. 1968. John Locke and the Way of Ideas. Oxford: Clarendon Press. the different argumentative strands of the Locke and Proast controversy. By analys-
ing separately each of the main letters written by the two authors, this chapter shows
the progression of objections and answers from Proast's The Argument to Locke's
Fourth letter, and determines why and when important reasonings were developed,
such as the argument of the distinction between belief and knowledge. The present
chapter demonstrates that the controversy has significant conceptual developments
when compared to the Epistola . The interpretation proposed here also aims to high-
light the importance of the notion of obstinacy as a justification for intolerance, and
to single out the more evident appropriations of Augustine.

In 1689, a few months after its publication, the Epistola received its first critique.
The 'letter for Toleration ' deciphrer'd, and the absurd and impiety of an absolute
toleration demonstrated was written by Thomas Long, a polemist of the 1670s and
1680s. In this book, Locke's evangelical argument and his three considerations are
never discussed, and several passages of the Epistola are simply described as "wild
freaks and excursions, the mention of them is a sufficient Confutation" (Long 1689,
3, RLP, 7). Although Long's tone is more defamatory than argumentative, which
might explain why Locke did not answer him directly, his work is interesting
because it reveals the intolerant zeal of some Anglicans, and unveils part of their
concerns, such as the fear that toleration would strengthen Catholicism (cf. Long
1689, 9, RLP, 13). However, this work is also interesting because it presupposes that
the defence of toleration was made by a dissenter (Long censures the Presbyterians
in particular, as they had refused mutual toleration in the 1640s, but now embraced
it). The supposed authorship of a dissenter deserves to be highlighted because it
tends to discard the possibility that Anglicans could contest the imposition of reli-
gious uniformity. Why could the defence of toleration be made only by dissenters?
Some supporters of toleration could very well be under the communion of the
Church of England, which was internally divided between those in favour of

©The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature 63


Switzerland AG 2022
F. F. Loque, John Locke and the Grounds for Toleration , International Archives
of the History of Ideas Archives intemationales d'histoire des idees 237,
https://doi.org/ l 0.10071978-3-030-90363-3_3
64 3 The Locke and Proast Controversy 3.1 The Argument of 'The letter Concerning Toleration' Briefly Consider'd... 65

persecution of nonconfonnists (broadly speaking, the High Church) and those (!.A) Locke, Epistula de Tolerantia (Gouda, 1689), anonymous;
inclined towards latitudinarianism (the Low Church). 1 lst ed. English translation by William Popple (London, 1689);
Given this division, when Locke replies to Proast, his main critic on toleration, 2nd ed. (revised) English translation by William Popple (London, 1690);
whose first book, The Argument of 'The Letter concerning Toleration' briefly (LB) Proast, The Argument of 'The Letter concerning Toleration' briefly consider'd
consider'd and answer'd, was published in 1690, both of them knew they were of and answer'd (Oxford, 1690), anonymous;
the same communion, but that they were on opposite sides from the ecclesiastical (11.A) Locke, A Second Letter concerning Toleration (London, 1690) by Philantropus;
and political standpoints. Proast was aligned with the High Church and the Tories, (n.B) Proast, A Third Letter concerning Toleration (Oxford, 1691), anonymous;
whereas Locke was aligned with the Low Church and the Whigs. In this sense, the (III.A) Locke, A Third Letter for Toleration (London, 1692) by Philantropus;
controversy between them may be conceived as part of a broader debate that (m.B) Proast, A Second Letter to the author of the Three Letters for Toleration
unfolded after the Glorious Revolution and that took place within the Church and (Oxford, 1704) by Philochristus;
Parliament. This debate covered topics such as comprehension, the Toleration Act (IV.A) Locke, A Fourth Letter for Toleration (London, 1706, Posthumous Works ).4
and the revocation of the Test and Corporation Acts. In some passages Locke gives
us glimpses into this debate, e. g. when he suspects that Proast's defence of punish-
ments for dissenters represents less a "care of the Salvation of Mens Souls" than a
"care of a Party" (SL, 35, Works, 99, cf. SL, 68, Works, 137) or when he mocks 3.1 The Argument of 'The Letter Concerning Toleration'
Proast's statement that God and the salvation of souls are the party he defends (cf. Briefly Consider'd and Answer'd
TL, 346-348, Works, 541-544).
While the controversy unfolded, other political issues gained weight, such as the The few pages of The Argument are clear and well written. In the critique of the
change of Archbishop of Canterbury,2 the accession of Queen Anne in 1702 and the Epistola, Proast displays the foundations of his defence of the imposition of the true
debate concerning occasional conformity, which Proast touches on in the post scrip- religion and deconstructs what appeared to him to be the only argument Locke had
tum of his Second Letter, written in 1704. Nonetheless, Locke and Proast rarely employed to refute the view that the care of souls belongs to the magistrate.
address these issues directly. The controversy was penned in the tenns set out in the However, as in a good review, Proast starts his analysis by establishing, precisely,
Epistola 3 and in The Argument, despite the influence of new works then published, the terms of the issue, in a summary of the position he intends to criticise. The dedi-
such as Gilbert Bumet's (1643-1715) A Discourse of Pastoral Care (1692) and cation aside,5 The Argument then gives a brief explanation of the notion of tolera-
Limborch's History of Inquisition (1692). At any rate, it is notable that in his strug- tion. For Proast, the extension of the toleration proposed by Locke is impressive.
gle to respond to Proast's objections and contest his apology for the use of force in Although Locke's reflection starts as a question about the differences among
religious matters, Locke did not display the contractualist framework of his line of Christians, it ends up including followers of other religions, as we read in a passage
reasoning and the interconnection between his three considerations as clearly as he of the conclusion of the Epistola quoted by Proast: "neither Pagan, nor Mahumetan,
did in the Epistola. Evidently, his main purpose remained the same, but the distinc- nor Jew ought to be excluded from the Civil Rights of the Commonwealth, because
tion between the ends of Church and State was underpinned, above all, by the metic- of his Religion" (Arg., 1, RLP, 25).6 This extension of toleration stems from the
ulous refutation of his adversary's proposal of religious coercion.
The Locke and Proast controversy comprises several works whose titles are mis-
leading. Hence, before we go on to analyse them, we shall first give an overview of 4
The Fourth letter, published in the Posthumous Works, later reproduced in the Works of John
the works to be analysed: Locke in 10 (1823) and 9 volumes (1824), lacks three short paragraphs which are crossed out in the
manuscript and were published by King in his biography of Locke (cf. 1830, v. II, 229-230).
Moreover, it is also worth noting that the last paragraph of the text in the Posthumous Works is not
1 Allhistorical information in this introductory section is based on Goldie (1993). in the manuscript. It probably indicates that the edition was based on another copy, as Long (1959,
2 When John Tillotson (1691-94) replaced William Sancroft (1677-90) as Archbishop of 33) points out.
5
Canterbury, Proast was directly affected, as the new archbishop postponed the answer to Proast's Proast does not say to whom he addresses the dedication, but, according to Thomas Hearne, anti-
claim to be restored as chaplain of All Souls College in Oxford and to be paid retroactively from quarian and Jacobite, one of his closest friends in Oxford, the "very worthy Friend" is Arthur
1688, when he was expelled by Leopold Finch. On Proast's claim, see Goldie (1993, 148-153) and Charlett, also from Oxford and aligned with the High Church (cf. Goldie 1993, 154).
the summaries given by Vernon (1997, 9-14) and Spitz (2010). 6
Proast used Popple's translation, which reads "civil rights of the commonwealth" and not simply
3 Here, it is worth mentioning, as Tate (2016, 148) does in his criticism of Goldie (1993), that the "commonwealth" (respublica) as in the original (Epist., 144.2-3). The imprimatur of The Argument
Locke and Proast controversy cannot be placed entirely within the post-Glorious Revolution dis- is dated 9 April 1690 and the dedication was signed on 27 March 1690. Proast could hardly have
putes between the High and Low Church, or the Tories and Whigs, given that the Epistola was used the second and revised edition of A letter concerning Toleration, which was published in
written in the European winter of 1685-1686. For an overview of the debate sparked by the March 1690. However, in order to clarify the issue, an advertisement after the dedication states that
Epistola, see Sell (1997, 173-184). "the Edition of the letter conceming Toleration, here cited, it that in Quarto". As we read in the
66 3 The Locke and Proast Controversy 3. 1 The Argument of 'The Letter Concerning To lera tion' Briefly Consider'd... 67

requirements (certainly inadequate, from Proast's perspective) for a person to qual- In the first pages of 1he Argument, Proast gives his own formulation of the prem-
ify for it: nobody is excluded, except atheists, those who transgress civil laws, and ises and the conclusion of the argument of unfitness of force. He divides the argu-
those who do not acknowledge and teach the duty to tolerate. Quoting from Popple's ment in five propositions about which there is not complete disagreement. The first
preface, Proast thus concludes that all sects and religions ought "to enjoy an Equal two premises are acknowledged by both Locke and Proast: (Jst) that there is only
and Impartial liberty", as long as they do not hold beliefs contrary to civil society one true religion; (2nd) in which men must believe to be saved. Proast shows further
and are "ready to tolerate each other" (Arg., 2, RLP, 26). Proast never goes into the agreement with Locke when he acknowledges that (3rd) reason and argument are
details concerning the intolerable practical beliefs (cf. Epist., 130.12-134.21). the proper means to produce belief and, consequently, that the understanding cannot
After these initial remarks, Proast then expresses his assessment: considering the be coerced to believe by an outward force. To employ Proast's own words: "Force
experiments of more restricted toleration that have been made (he does not say is very improper to be used to that end instead of Reason and Arguments" (Arg., 4,
which experiments he refers to, but they seem to concern the interregnum of RLP, 27). Notwithstanding this inadequacy, it does not mean that (4th) force is
1649- 1660, cf. TL-P, 13, RLP, 52), one cannot expect that the toleration supported "utterly of no use for the promoting True Religion" (Arg., 3, RLP, 26). Force cannot
by Locke be beneficial to the true religion, even if it contributes to trade and com- act directly in the production of beliefs, instead of reason, but it can perfectly act
merce. 7 Proast stresses that he does not believe the Epistola intended to cause preju- "indirectly and at a distance" (Arg., 5, RLP, 27). It is his disagreement concerning
dice to any religion or to Christianity in particular, which is tantamount to saying the fourth proposition that leads Proast to refute Locke's conclusion that (5th)
that the author of the Epistola was mistaken about the fruits of the toleration pro- nobody has the right to use force in religious matters (Arg. , 4-5, RLP, 27).
posed. In The Argument, Proast is assertive in this forecast concerning toleration, Proast draws a distinction in the use of force that Locke does not explore in the
but he limits himself to the statement that it seems difficult to conceive how tolera- Epistola. Proast contends that there is a sort of duplicity in the use of force: its direct
tion could be serviceable to true religion or its followers. At the beginning of his and immediate or indirect and distant character. He employs this distinction to con-
Third Letter, however, he clearly affirms that toleration would not be serviceable to test the fourth premise of the argument of unfitness of force and so destroy the
true religion; rather, that toleration could ruin it (cf. TL-P, 2-4, RLP, 42-44). In this conceptual house built in the Epistola. 8 If force were "utterly useless", as Proast
second critique of Locke, Proast' s reasons are then set out, as we shall see below. In reiterates (Arg., 27, RLP, 37), it would be impossible to employ it to promote the
The Argument, Proast states that his purpose is not to assess the value of the tolera- true religion. However, if one acknowledges that it might be serviceable, its use in
tion defended by Locke, but to examine the proofs offered to sustain it. favour of the salvation of souls cannot, in principle, be discarded. Taken as a whole,
For Proast, there is just one argument to support toleration: the argument of unfit- the line of reasoning developed in The Argument has two stages, the first being to
ness of force. Why does Proast affirm that there is just one argument? How is it demonstrate that force may be serviceable. As we shall see below, Proast initially
possible when at least three arguments were clearly adduced: the so-called three proves that the right to compel on behalf of true religion can belong to the magis-
considerations? The reason is simple. For Proast, the argument from commission trate, then argues that this right ought to belong to him. In the first stage, the central
begs the question of the distinction between the ends of Church and State (and, concept is that of the utility of force; in the second, it is the necessity of force, as
being invalid, it should not be considered a real argument) while the argument of Locke himself acknowledged (cf. TL, 18-19, Works, 164) when he corrected his
reductio ad absurdum is ill-formulated (according to Proast, what is at stake is the misinterpretation of The Argument (in A Second Letter, Locke considered the utility
possibility of the magistrate imposing the true religion, and never his own, even if of force sufficient to justify the magistrate's commission to take care of souls, cf.
the latter appears true to him). As we saw in the second chapter, in the Epistola there SL, 47, Works, 113). According to Proast, Locke should have proven that force has
is still the evangelical argument, which Proast seeks to reject by resorting to a con- no utility at all to produce belief in order to successfully defend toleration, but the
ception of Christianity that allows the possibility of a charitable use of force. Thus, Epistola is nothing more than a declamation (the allusion to rhetoric has a pejorative
despite stating that there is only one argument in the Epistola, Proast ends up connotation) for the impossibility of promoting religion by force and for the inhu-
responding to all of Locke's arguments. manity of compelling with fire, sword and capital punishments (cf. Arg., 28, RLP,
37). But how can force be useful ? What does Proast mean when he says that it can
be useful indirectly and at a distance? According to his own reconstruction of the
argument of unfitness of force, how does Proast demonstrate that the fourth premise
bibliographical descriptions of Locke's works, the first edition of Popple 's translation was in 4° is false?
while the second was in 12° (cf. Yolton 1998, 4-6, items 3-4; Attig 1985, 14, items 51-52).
7 In the Epistola, Locke does not present the contributions to trade and commerce as an argument

for toleration, but this is touched on in An Essay concerning Toleration (cf. ET, 301) and in the
manuscript Trade of 1674 (cf. Pol. Es., Trade, 222). For a study of the relationship between com- 8 Inthe Philosophical Commentary, Bayle also deals with the objection concerning indirect and at
merce and toleration, see Santos (2013). For a broad overview of this issue, at least in the late a distance use of force (cf. Bayle 2014, 97-101). This objection was a commonplace among the
1680s, see Ashcraft (1986, 506--511). On toleration in the Interregnum, see Worden (1984). intolerants, contrary to Locke's ironic remark that Proast 's method is new (e.g., SL, 24, Wo rks, 87).
68 3 The Locke and Proast Controversy 3.1 The Argument of 'The Letter Concerning Toleration' Briefly Consider'd ... 69

The indirect usefulness of force is manifest when private persons do not inform the due examination is often not properly conducted and explains why he presup-
themselves about the true religion due to carelessness and negligence as well as poses that anyone can discover the way to salvation:
when they reject it at once as an error due to prejudice. In these cases, Proast con- Now here I grant, that if all men were but so faithful to their own Souls, as to seek the way
tends that force can "bring men to consider those Reasons and Arguments which are of Saving them, with such Care and Diligence as the Importance of the matter deserves, and
proper and sufficient to convince them, but which, without being forced, they would with Minds free from Prejudice and Passion; there could be no need of Force to compell any
not consider" (Arg., 5, RLP, 27). Thus, force cannot make a person withhold his man to do, what in that case every man would be sure to do voluntarily, an of his own
assent to a belief while it appears true to him, in order to assent to another one that accord. But then it must be granted withal, That if this were the case; as there is indeed but
one true Religion, so there could be no other Religion but that in the world, John 7: 17.
appears false to him. Proast never doubts the involuntary nature of belief when the Because (if we believe the Scriptures) no Man can fail of finding the way of Salvation, who
relationship between belief and will is viewed from the perspective of assent (hence seeks it as he ought; Psalms 25:9, 12, 14, Proverbs 2:1-5; and in this case all Men are sup-
the agreement concerning the third premise). On the contrary, his critique of Locke posed so to seek it. And yet there is nothing more notorious, than that Men have sought out
explores the voluntary nature of belief when it comes to the process of investigation. many Inventions, and contrived a great variety of Religions to themselves: so that there is
In a nutshell, force acts upon the will, but in order to make a person take into account nothing about which the World is more divided, then it is about the way that leads to Eternal
Blessedness. Which is an evident demonstration, that all Men have not sought the Truth in
arguments he had previously refused to consider, i.e. to make him enrich the infor- this matter, with that application of mind, and that freedom of Judgement, which was req-
mation available to his understanding. According to Proast, this would entail a reas- uisite to assure their finding it (Arg., 6-7, RLP, 28).
sessment of his beliefs and, consequently, a shift of assent. Therefore, this shift of
assent springs from the new truth value of the beliefs, so that one can speak of the Initially, we see that Proast, once again, resorts to the notions of care and preju-
indirect, distant and mediated usefulness of force. When Proast states that force has dice, but this time he associates them with the notions of diligence and passions. It
an indirect usefulness, he is claiming that it can lead those who had previously is not his purpose to define them precisely, but to indicate the motives that hinder the
refused to consider the proofs that are apt to convince them to finally consider them. search for the true religion (passions and prejudices are frequently mentioned) and
Proast is in no doubt that there are "proper and sufficient" arguments in favour of the their implications on the examination (carelessness and negligence). Repeatedly,
true religion, and that those arguments, if duly considered, cannot fail to convince and not only in The Argument, Proast seems to make the following distinction: on
all those who give them a fair hearing. As we read in his Third Letter, "no man who the one hand, he points out the obstacles to the search for truth; and on the other, he
rejects Truth necessary to his Salvation, has consider'd already, as he ought to con- describes how these obstacles affect the examination, which may then be said to be
sider" (TL-P, 28, RLP, 67). Apart from the "desperately perverse and obstinate" careless or negligent. In different passages of The Argument, Proast mentions
(Arg., 14, RLP, 31), all other men should bow to this "instruction" offered them "for "lusts", "foolish humours'', and "crafty Seducer" (Arg., 7, 20-21, 27, RLP, 28, 34,
the enlightening their minds and discovering the Truth to them" (Arg., 13, RLP, 31 ). 37), as well as the "Impressions of Education, the Reverence and Admiration of
Metaphorically speaking, force obliges a person to tum to the arguments he had Persons, Wordly respects, and the like incompetent Motives", all of which, accord-
insisted on ignoring; it acts as a means to "balance the weight" of prejudices (Arg., ing to him, "determine far greater numbers, than Reason, or such Considerations as
11, RLP, 30). Coercion does not convince by itself, directly, by acting upon the are apt and proper to manifest the Truth of things" (Arg., 8, RLP, 28). Proast does
assent, but indirectly, as it leads a person to consider what he had put aside. If a not use these notions rigorously, nor does he need to do so, for what he is seeking to
person has not yet embraced the true religion, this will certainly happen as soon as demonstrate by these confluent terms is clear: people are liable to be influenced by
he is exposed to the truth. The fact of being instructed by force is not problematic: factors that affect the search for truth (the most prominent of which are passions and
religious truth is no less true for having been embraced after reflection under con- prejudices, as we have just singled out). Nobody denies this proposition, and Locke
straint just as obedience to God does not lose its value for being reached through himself acknowledges it (cf. SL, 32, 34, 37, 61, Works , 95, 98, 101, 129), adopting
chastisement and afflictions (cf. Arg., 6, RLP, 27). Truth and obedience obtained by it as a subject of study until the end of his life, as seen in his Of the Conduct of the
force are still perfectly acceptable to God. Understanding. Therefore, Proast's greatest challenge is not to prove that people
Not only does Proast think that there is just one true religion, but he also thinks often do not seek truth with "application of mind" and "freedom of judgement" (if
it has an undeniable foundation. From his perspective, the only factor that can it were so, there would be no need for force), but to articulate this proposition with
account for a person's rejection of it is the fact that it was not duly sought. But what the much more controversial statement that nobody who seeks as he ought can fail
does 'due examination' really mean? Nowhere does Proast describe in detail the lo discover the way to salvation.
search for truth or show positively how this search should be conducted. His descrip- In order to make this articulation, as we can see from the Jong quotation above,
tion does not advance beyond the assertion that the examination must be "severe Proast mentions a passage from Scripture, Proverbs 2: 1-5, which assures the dis-
and impartial" or "serious and impartial" (Arg., 10, 26, RLP, 29, 36). In The covery of the "knowledge of God" for those who "incline" their "ear unto wisdom",
Argument, as well as in the Third Letter, Proast only mentions the motives for which "apply" their "heart to understanding" and search for it "as for hid treasures". This
scriptural basis is crucial for him, as it is through this passage that he ultimately
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™
collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In
2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was
created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project
Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your
efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the
Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-
profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the
laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by
the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal
tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax
deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and
your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500


West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact
links and up to date contact information can be found at the
Foundation’s website and official page at
www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission
of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works
that can be freely distributed in machine-readable form
accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated
equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly
important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws


regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of
the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform
and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many
fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not
solicit donations in locations where we have not received written
confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or
determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states


where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know
of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from
donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot


make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations
received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp
our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current


donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a
number of other ways including checks, online payments and
credit card donations. To donate, please visit:
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could
be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose
network of volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several


printed editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by
copyright in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus,
we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any
particular paper edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new
eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear
about new eBooks.

You might also like