Full Download PDF of (Ebook PDF) Bioethics: Principles, Issues, and Cases 4th Edition All Chapter

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 43

(eBook PDF) Bioethics: Principles,

Issues, and Cases 4th Edition


Go to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-bioethics-principles-issues-and-cases-4th
-edition/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Bioethics: Principles, Issues, and Cases 3rd Edition


(eBook PDF)

http://ebooksecure.com/product/bioethics-principles-issues-and-
cases-3rd-edition-ebook-pdf/

(eBook PDF) Bioethics: Principles, Issues, and Cases


3rd Edition by Lewis Vaughn

http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-bioethics-principles-
issues-and-cases-3rd-edition-by-lewis-vaughn/

(eBook PDF) Business Ethics: Contemporary Issues and


Cases

http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-business-ethics-
contemporary-issues-and-cases/

(eBook PDF) Human Heredity: Principles and Issues 11th


Edition

http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-human-heredity-
principles-and-issues-11th-edition/
Human Heredity: Principles and Issues 11th Edition
(eBook PDF)

http://ebooksecure.com/product/human-heredity-principles-and-
issues-11th-edition-ebook-pdf/

(eBook PDF) Curriculum: Foundations, Principles, and


Issues 7th Edition

http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-curriculum-foundations-
principles-and-issues-7th-edition/

Neuroethics and Bioethics: Neurodivergence and


Architecture 1st edition - eBook PDF

https://ebooksecure.com/download/neuroethics-and-bioethics-
neurodivergence-and-architecture-ebook-pdf/

(eBook PDF) Psychological Testing: Principles,


Applications, and Issues 9th Edition

http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-psychological-testing-
principles-applications-and-issues-9th-edition/

(eBook PDF) Land Law: Text, Cases & Materials (Text,


Cases, and Materials) 4th Edition

http://ebooksecure.com/product/ebook-pdf-land-law-text-cases-
materials-text-cases-and-materials-4th-edition/
Bioethics
Principles, Issues, and Cases
Fourth Edition

Lewis Vaughn

New York Oxford


OX F OR D U N I V E R SI T Y PR E S S

vau03268_fm_i-xii.indd i 05/15/19 12:27 PM


viii Contents

“Cloning Human Beings: An Assessment “Genetic Interventions and the Ethics of


of the Ethical Issues Pro and Con,” Enhancement of Human Beings,” Julian
Dan W. Brock 551 Savulescu 627
“Germ-Line Gene Therapy,” LeRoy Walters and
Julie Gage Palmer 636
Chapter 9
“What Does ‘Respect for Embryos’ Mean
genetic choices 562 in the Context of Stem Cell Research?”
Genes and Genomes 562 Bonnie Steinbock 643
Genetic Testing 563 Declaration on the Production and the Scientific
In Depth: Direct-to-Consumer Genetic Tests 566 and Therapeutic Use of Human Embryonic
Gene Therapy 570 Stem Cells, Pontifical Academy for Life 646
Fact File: Available Genetic Tests for
Cancer Risk 571 Chapter 10
Fact File: Recent Research Breakthroughs
in Gene Therapy 574 euthanasia and physician-assisted
suicide 648
Stem Cells 575
Applying Major Theories 577 Deciding Life and Death 649
Classic Case File: The Kingsburys 578 Legal Brief: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide:
Major Developments 651
Key Terms 579
In Depth: Assisted Suicide: What Do Doctors
Summary 579
Think? 652
Cases for Evaluation 579
Autonomy, Mercy, and Harm 653
Further Reading 582
In Depth: Oregon’s Death With Dignity Act 655
Notes 582
In Depth: End-of-Life Decisions in the
Netherlands 657
readings 583
Applying Major Theories 657
“Implications of Prenatal Diagnosis for the
In Depth: Physician-Assisted Suicide and Public
Human Right to Life,” Leon R. Kass 583
Opinion 658
“Genetics and Reproductive Risk: Can Having
Classic Case File: Nancy Cruzan 659
Children Be Immoral?” Laura M. Purdy 587
Key Terms 660
“The Morality of Screening for Disability,”
Summary 660
Jeff McMahan 594
Cases for Evaluation 661
“Genetic Dilemmas and the Child’s Right to an
Further Reading 664
Open Future,” Dena S. Davis 598
Notes 665
“Disowning Knowledge: Issues in Genetic
Testing,” Robert Wachbroit 608 readings 666
“The Non-Identity Problem and Genetic “Death and Dignity: A Case of Individualized
Harms—The Case of Wrongful Handicaps,” Decision Making,”
Dan W. Brock 612 Timothy E. Quill 666
“Is Gene Therapy a Form of Eugenics?” “Voluntary Active Euthanasia,” Dan W. Brock 670
John Harris 616 “When Self-Determination Runs Amok,”
“Genetic Enhancement,” Walter Glannon 622 Daniel Callahan 682

vau03268_fm_i-xii.indd viii 05/15/19 12:27 PM


Contents ix

“Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Tragic View,” The Ethics of Rationing 754


John D. Arras 687 Classic Case File: Christine deMeurers 756
“Active and Passive Euthanasia,” James Key Terms 758
Rachels 702 Summary 758
“Dying at the Right Time: Reflections on Cases for Evaluation 759
(Un)Assisted Suicide,” John Hardwig 706 Further Reading 761
“The Philosophers’ Brief,” Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Notes 762
Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, Thomas
Scanlon, and Judith Jarvis Thomson 717 readings 763
“Legalizing Assisted Dying Is Dangerous “Is There a Right to Health Care and, if So, What
for Disabled People,” Liz Carr 725 Does It Encompass?,” Norman Daniels 763
“  ‘For Now Have I My Death’: The ‘Duty to Die’ “The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health
Versus the Duty to Help the Ill Stay Alive,” Care,” Allen E. Buchanan 770
Felicia Ackerman 727 “Rights to Health Care, Social Justice, and Fairness
Vacco v. Quill, United States Supreme Court 738 in Health Care Allocations: Frustrations in the
Face of Finitude,” H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. 776
Part 4. ​Justice and Health Care “Mirror, Mirror 2017: International Comparison
Reflects Flaws and Opportunities for Better
Chapter 11 U.S. Health Care,” Eric C. Schneider, Dana O.
dividing up health care Sarnak, David Squires, et al. 784
resources 743 “Public Health Ethics: Mapping the Terrain,”
Health Care in Trouble 743 James F. Childress et al. 788
In Depth: Unequal Health Care for “Human Rights Approach to Public Health
Minorities 746 Policy,” D. Tarantola and S. Gruskin 799
Fact File: U.S. Health Care 747
Appendix 811
Theories of Justice 748
Glossary 813
In Depth: Comparing Health Care Systems:
United States, Canada, and Index 815
Germany 749
Fact File: Poll: The Public’s Views on the ACA
(“Obamacare”) 751
A Right to Health Care 752
In Depth: Public Health and Bioethics 753

vau03268_fm_i-xii.indd ix 05/15/19 01:53 PM


P R E FAC E

This fourth edition of Bioethics embodies all the features filling out the discussions with background on the
that have made it a best-selling textbook and includes all latest medical, legal, and social developments. The
the most important changes and improvements that main issues include paternalism and patient auton-
dozens of teachers have asked for recently and over the omy, truth-telling, confidentiality, informed consent,
years. The book is, therefore, better than ever. And if it research ethics, clinical trials, abortion, assisted re-
isn’t, let even more good teachers say so and let the cor- production, surrogacy, cloning, genetic testing, gene
rections and enhancements continue. And may the book therapy, stem cells, euthanasia, physician-assisted
remain, as so many teachers have said, exactly suitable to suicide, and the just allocation of health care.
their teaching approach. Every issues chapter contains five to twelve read-
Bioethics provides in-depth discussions of the ings, with each selection prefaced by a brief s­ ummary.
philosophical, medical, scientific, social, and legal The a­ rticles—old standards as well as new ones—
aspects of controversial bioethical issues and reflect the major arguments and latest thinking in
combines this material with a varied collection of each debate. They present a diversity of perspectives
thought-provoking readings. But on this foundation on each topic, with pro and con positions well rep-
are laid elements that other texts sometimes forgo: resented. In most cases, the relevant court rulings
are also included.
1. An extensive introduction to ethics, bioethics,
moral principles, critical thinking, and moral
reasoning special features
2. Full coverage of influential moral theories, A two-chapter introduction to bioethics, moral
including criteria and guidelines for evaluat- reasoning, moral theories, and critical thinking.
ing them (the focus is on utilitarianism, These chapters are designed not only to introduce
­Kantian ethics, natural law theory, Rawls’ the subject matter of bioethics but also to add co-
contract theory, virtue ethics, the ethics of herence to subsequent chapter material and to
care, and feminist ethics) provide the student with a framework for thinking
3. Detailed examinations of the classic cases critically about issues and cases. Chapter 1 is an in­
that have helped shape debate in major issues troduction to basic ethical concepts, the field of
4. Collections of current, news-making cases for bioethics, moral principles and judgments, moral
evaluation reasoning and arguments, the challenges of rela-
5. Many pedagogical features to engage students tivism, and the relationship between ethics and
and reinforce lessons in the main text both religion and the law. Chapter 2 explores moral
6. Writing that strives hard for clarity and conci- theory, shows how theories relate to moral princi-
sion to convey both the excitement and com- ples and judgments, examines influential theories
plexity of issues without sacrificing accuracy (including virtue ethics, the ethics of care, and
feminist ethics), and demonstrates how they can be
topics and readings applied to moral problems. It also explains how to
Nine chapters cover many of the most controversial evaluate moral theories using plausible criteria of
issues in bioethics, detailing the main arguments and adequacy.

vau03268_fm_i-xii.indd x 05/15/19 12:27 PM


Preface xi

Helpful chapter elements. Each issues chapter • Annette C. Baier, “The Need for More Than
contains: Justice”
• Ezekiel J. Emanuel and Linda L. Emanuel,
1. Analyses of the most important arguments
“Four Models of the Physician-Patient
offered by the various parties to the debate.
Relationship”
They reinforce and illustrate the lessons on
• Dax Cowart and Robert Burt, “Confronting
moral reasoning in Chapter 1.
Death: Who Chooses, Who Controls? A Di-
2. A section called “Applying Major Theories”
alogue Between Dax Cowart and Robert
showing how the moral theories can be ­applied
Burt”
to the issues. It ties the discussions of moral
• Harriet Hall, “Paternalism Revisited”
theories in Chapter 2 to the moral problems and
• Angus Chen, “Is It Time to Stop Using Race
illustrates the theories’ relevance.
in Medical Research?”
3. A section labeled “Classic Case File” that
• Liz Carr, “Legalizing Assisted Dying Is
­examines in detail a famous bioethics case. The
Dangerous for Disabled People”
stories covered in these sections include those
• Felicia Ackerman, “‘For Now I Have My
of Elizabeth Bouvia, Jerry Canterbury, Nancy
Death’: The ‘Duty to Die’ Versus the Duty to
Klein, Baby M, Nancy Cruzan, the Kingsburys,
Help the Ill Stay Alive”
Christine deMeurers, and the UCLA Schizo-
• Eric C. Schneider, Dana O. Sarnak, David
phrenia Study. These are in ­addition to many
Squires, et al., “Mirror, Mirror 2017: Interna-
other controversial cases covered elsewhere in
tional Comparison Reflects Flaws and Op-
the book—for example, the Terri Schiavo con-
portunities for Better U.S. Health Care”
troversy, the Tuskegee tragedy, the Willow-
Clarifications and Further Discussions
brook experiments, and the U.S. government’s
• Principlism and prima facie principles
human radiation studies.
• Feminist ethics
4. A bank of “Cases for Evaluation” at the end
• Abortion and Judaism
of each chapter. These are recent news stories
• Research on euthanasia in Oregon and the
followed by discussion questions. They give stu-
Netherlands
dents the chance to test their moral ­reasoning
• End-of-life decisions in the Netherlands
on challenging new scenarios that range across
(statistics)
a broad spectrum of current topics.
• Advance directives
A diverse package of pedagogical aids. Each Updates
issues chapter contains a chapter summary, sugges- • Important informed consent cases
tions for further reading, and a variety of text boxes. • U.S. abortion (statistics)
The boxes are mainly of three types: • Abortion and public opinion (survey)
• Recent breakthroughs in gene therapy
1. “In Depth”—additional information, illustra-
• Euthanasia and assisted suicide: major
tions, or analyses of matters touched on in
developments
the main text.
• Assisted suicide: What do doctors think?
2. “Fact File”—statistics on the social, medical,
(survey)
and scientific aspects of the chapter’s topic.
• Public opinion: physician-assisted suicide
3. “Legal Brief”—summaries of important court rul-
(survey)
ings or updates on the status of legislation.
• Health care: the uninsured, per capita
spending, U.S. health care quality
new to this edition
• Comparing health care systems: U.S.,
Ten New Readings Canada, Germany
• Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Books I and II • Public opinion: views on the ACA
• Nel Noddings, “Caring” (“Obamacare”)

vau03268_fm_i-xii.indd xi 05/16/19 02:47 PM


xii Preface

ancillaries Leslie P. Francis, University of Utah


The Oxford University Press Ancillary Resource Center Devin Frank, University of Missouri–Columbia
(ARC) at www.oup-arc.com/vaughn-bioethics-4e Kathryn M. Ganske, Shenandoah University
houses an Instructor’s Manual with Test Bank and Martin Gunderson, Macalester College
PowerPoint Lecture Outlines for instructor use. Stu- Helen Habermann, University of Arizona
dent resources are available on the companion website Stephen Hanson, University of Louisville
at www.oup.com/us/vaughn and include self-quizzes, Karey Harwood, North Carolina State
flashcards, and helpful web links. University
Sheila R. Hollander, University of Memphis
Scott James, University of North Carolina,
acknowledgments
Wilmington
This edition of the text is measurably better than
James Joiner, Northern Arizona University
the first thanks to the good people at Oxford Uni-
William P. Kabasenche, Washington State
versity Press—especially my editor Robert Miller
University
and assistant editor Alyssa Palazzo—and many
Susan Levin, Smith College
reviewers:
Margaret Levvis, Central Connecticut State
Keith Abney, Polytechnic State University University
at San Luis Obispo Burden S. Lundgren, Old Dominion University
Kim Amer, DePaul University Joan McGregor, Arizona State University
Jami L. Anderson, University of Michigan Tristram McPherson, Virginia Tech
Carol Isaacson Barash, Boston University Jonathan K. Miles, Bowling Green State
Deb Bennett-Woods, Regis University University
Don Berkich, Texas A&M University James Lindemann Nelson, Michigan State
Stephan Blatti, University of Memphis University
William Bondeson, University of Missouri, Thomas Nenon, University of Memphis
Columbia Laura Newhart, Eastern Kentucky University
Lori Brown, Eastern Michigan University Steve Odmark, Century College
David W. Concepción, Ball State University Assya Pascalev, Howard University
Catherine Coverston, Brigham Young Viorel Pâslaru, University of Dayton
University David J. Paul, Western Michigan University
Russell DiSilvestro, Assistant Professor, Anthony Preus, Binghamton University
­California State University, Sacramento Susan M. Purviance, University of Toledo
John Doris, Washington University in St. Louis Sara Schuman, Washtenaw Community College
Denise Dudzinski, University of Washington David Schwan, Bowling Green State University
School of Medicine Anita Silvers, San Francisco State University
Craig Duncan, Ithaca College M. Josephine Snider, University of Florida
Anne Edwards, Austin Peay State University Joseph Wellbank, Northeastern University
John Elia, University of Georgia Gladys B. White, Georgetown University
Christy Flanagan-Feddon, Regis University David Yount, Mesa Community College
Jacqueline Fox, University of South Carolina
School of Law

vau03268_fm_i-xii.indd xii 05/15/19 12:27 PM


Principles and Theories
1

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 1 05/02/19 07:36 PM


vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 2 05/02/19 07:36 PM
CHAP TER 1

Moral Reasoning in Bioethics


Any serious and rewarding exploration of bio- Second, it would be difficult to imagine moral
ethics is bound to be a challenging journey. issues more important—​more closely gathered
What makes the trip worthwhile? As you might around the line between life and death, health
expect, this entire text is a long answer to that and illness, pain and relief, hope and despair—​
question. You therefore may not fully appreciate than those addressed by bioethics. Whatever
the trek until you have already hiked far along our view of these questions, there is little doubt
the trail. The short answer comes in three parts. that they matter immensely. Whatever answers
First, bioethics—​like ethics, its parent disci- we give will surely have weight, however they fall.
pline—​is about morality, and morality is about Third, as a systematic study of such ques-
life. Morality is part of the unavoidable, bitter- tions, bioethics holds out the possibility of an-
sweet drama of being persons who think and feel swers. The answers may or may not be to our
and choose. Morality concerns beliefs regarding liking; they may confirm or confute our precon-
morally right and wrong actions and morally ceived notions; they may take us far or not far
good and bad persons or character. Whether we enough. But, as the following pages will show,
like it or not, we seem confronted continually the trail has more light than shadow—​ and
with the necessity to deliberate about right and thinking critically and carefully about the prob-
wrong, to judge someone morally good or bad, lems can help us see our way forward.
to agree or disagree with the moral pronounce-
ments of others, to accept or reject the moral ethics and bioethics
outlook of our culture or community, and
even to doubt or affirm the existence or nature Morality is about people’s moral judgments,
of moral concepts themselves. Moral issues are principles, rules, standards, and theories—​a ll of
thus inescapable—​including (or especially) those which help direct conduct, mark out moral prac­
that are the focus of bioethics. In the twenty-first tices, and provide the yardsticks for measuring
century, few can remain entirely untouched by moral worth. We use morality to refer gener-
the pressing moral questions of fair distribution ally to these aspects of our lives (as in “Morality
of health care resources, abortion and infanti- is essential”) or more specifically to the beliefs
cide, euthanasia and assisted suicide, exploitative or practices of particular groups or persons (as
research on children and populations in devel- in “American morality” or “Kant’s morality”).
oping countries, human cloning and genetic en- Moral, of course, pertains to morality as just
gineering, assisted reproduction and surrogate ­defined, though it is also sometimes employed
parenting, prevention and treatment of HIV/ as a synonym for right or good, just as immoral
AIDS, the confidentiality and consent of patients, is often meant to be equivalent to wrong or bad.
the refusal of medical treatment on religious Ethics, as used in this text, is not synonymous with
grounds, experimentation on human embryos morality. Ethics is the study of morality using the
and fetuses, and the just allocation of scarce life- tools and methods of philosophy. Philosophy is
saving organs. a discipline that systematically examines life’s

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 3 05/02/19 07:36 PM


4 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

big questions through critical reasoning, logical some or all of these as proper guides for our ac-
argument, and careful reflection. Thus ethics—​ tions and judgments. In normative ethics, we
also known as moral philosophy—​is a reasoned ask questions like these: What moral principles,
way of delving into the meaning and import of if any, should inform our moral judgments?
moral concepts and issues and of evaluating the What role should virtues play in our lives? Is the
merits of moral judgments and standards. (As principle of autonomy justified? Are there any
with morality and moral, we may use ethics to exceptions to the moral principle of “do not
say such things as “Kant’s ethics” or may use kill”? How should we resolve conflicts between
ethical or unethical to mean right or wrong, moral norms? Is contractarianism a good moral
good or bad.) Ethics seeks to know whether an theory? Is utilitarianism a better theory?
action is right or wrong, what moral standards A branch that deals with much deeper ethical
should guide our conduct, whether moral prin- issues is metaethics. Metaethics is the study of
ciples can be justified, what moral virtues are the meaning and justification of basic moral be-
worth cultivating and why, what ultimate ends liefs. In normative ethics we might ask whether
people should pursue in life, whether there are an action is right or whether a person is good,
good reasons for accepting a particular moral but in metaethics we would more likely ask what
theory, and what the meaning is of such notions it means for an action to be right or for a person
as right, wrong, good, and bad. Whenever we try to be good. For example, does right mean has the
to reason carefully about such things, we enter best consequences, or produces the most happi-
the realm of ethics: We do ethics. ness, or commanded by God? It is the business of
Science offers another way to study morality, metaethics to explore these and other equally
and we must carefully distinguish this approach fundamental questions: What, if anything, is
from that of moral philosophy. Descriptive the difference between moral and nonmoral be-
ethics is the study of morality using the meth- liefs? Are there such things as moral facts? If so,
odology of science. Its purpose is to investigate what sort of things are they, and how can they
the empirical facts of morality—​the actual be- be known? Can moral statements be true or
liefs, behaviors, and practices that constitute false—​or are they just expressions of emotions
people’s moral experience. Those who carry out or attitudes without any truth value? Can moral
these inquiries (usually anthropologists, sociol- norms be justified or proven?
ogists, historians, and psychologists) want to The third main branch is applied ethics, the
know, among other things, what moral beliefs a use of moral norms and concepts to resolve
person or group has, what caused the subjects to practical moral issues. Here, the usual challenge
have them, and how the beliefs influence behav- is to employ moral principles, theories, argu-
ior or social interaction. Very generally, the dif- ments, or analyses to try to answer moral ques-
ference between ethics and descriptive ethics is tions that confront people every day. Many such
this: In ethics we ask, as Socrates did, How ought questions relate to a particular professional field
we to live? In descriptive ethics we ask, How do such as law, business, or journalism, so we have
we in fact live? specialized subfields of applied ethics like legal
Ethics is a big subject, so we should not be ethics, business ethics, and journalistic ethics.
surprised that it has three main branches, each Probably the largest and most energetic subfield
dealing with more or less separate but related is bioethics.
sets of ethical questions. Normative ethics is the Bioethics is applied ethics focused on health
search for, and justification of, moral standards, care, medical science, and medical technology.
or norms. Most often the standards are moral (Biomedical ethics is often used as a synonym,
principles, rules, virtues, and theories, and the and medical ethics is a related but narrower term
lofty aim of this branch is to establish rationally used most often to refer to ethical problems in

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 4 05/02/19 07:36 PM


Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 5

medical practice.) Ranging far and wide, bio- about art; norms of etiquette about polite social
ethics seeks answers to a vast array of tough behavior; grammatical norms about correct use
ethical questions: Is abortion ever morally per- of language; prudential norms about what is in
missible? Is a woman justified in having an abor- one’s interests; and legal norms about lawful and
tion if prenatal genetic testing reveals that her unlawful acts. But moral norms differ from these
fetus has a developmental defect? Should people nonmoral kinds. Some of the features they are
be allowed to select embryos by the embryos’ sex thought to possess include the following.
or other genetic characteristics? Should human
embryos be used in medical research? Should Normative Dominance. In our moral practice,
human cloning be prohibited? Should physicians, moral norms are presumed to dominate other
nurses, physicians’ assistants, and other health kinds of norms, to take precedence over them.
care professionals always be truthful with patients Philosophers call this characteristic of moral
whatever the consequences? Should severely im- norms overridingness because moral consider-
paired newborns be given life-prolonging treat- ations so often seem to override other factors.
ment or be allowed to die? Should people in A maxim of prudence, for example, may suggest
persistent vegetative states be removed from life that you should steal if you can avoid getting
support? Should physicians help terminally ill caught, but a moral prohibition against stealing
­patients commit suicide? Is it morally right to con­ would overrule such a principle. An aesthetic (or
duct medical research on patients without their pragmatic) norm implying that homeless people
consent if the research would save lives? Should should be thrown in jail for blocking the view of
human stem-cell research be banned? How a beautiful public mural would have to yield to
should we decide who gets life-saving organ trans­ moral principles demanding more humane treat-
plants when usable organs are scarce and many ment of the homeless. A law mandating brutal
patients who do not get transplants will die? actions against a minority group would conflict
Should animals be used in biomedical research? with moral principles of justice and would there-
The ethical and technical scope of bioethics is fore be deemed illegitimate. We usually think
wide. Bioethical questions and deliberations that immoral laws are defective, that they need to
now fall to nonexpert and expert alike—​to pa- be changed, or that, in rare cases, they should be
tients, families, and others as well as to philoso- defied through acts of civil disobedience.
phers, health care professionals, lawyers, judges,
scientists, clergy, and public policy specialists. Universality. Moral norms (but not exclusively
Though the heart of bioethics is moral philoso- moral norms) have universality: Moral princi-
phy, fully informed bioethics cannot be done ples or judgments apply in all relevantly similar
without a good understanding of the relevant situations. If it is wrong for you to tell a lie in
nonmoral facts and issues, especially the medi- a particular circumstance, then it is wrong for
cal, scientific, technological, and legal ones. everyone in relevantly similar circumstances to
tell a lie. Logic demands this sort of consistency.
It makes no sense to say that Maria’s doing
ethics and the moral life
action A in circumstances C is morally wrong,
Morality then is a normative, or evaluative, enter- but John’s doing A in circumstances relevantly
prise. It concerns moral norms or standards that similar to C is morally right. Universality, how-
help us decide the rightness of actions, judge the ever, is not unique to moral norms; it’s a charac-
goodness of persons or character, and prescribe the teristic of all normative spheres.
form of moral conduct. There are, of course, other
sorts of norms we apply in life—​nonmoral norms. Impartiality. Implicit in moral norms is the
Aesthetic norms help us make value judg­ments notion of impartiality—​the idea that everyone

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 5 05/02/19 07:36 PM


6 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

should be considered equal, that everyone’s inter- the moral life—​is to do moral reasoning. If our
ests should count the same. From the perspective moral judgments are to have any weight at all, if
of morality, no person is any better than any they are to be anything more than mere per-
other. Everyone should be treated the same unless sonal taste or knee-jerk emotional response,
there is a morally relevant difference between they must be backed by the best of reasons. They
persons. We probably would be completely baf- must be the result of careful reflection in which
fled if someone seriously said something like we arrive at good reasons for accepting them,
“murder is wrong . . . except when committed by reasons that could be acknowledged as such by
myself,” when there was no morally relevant dif- any other reasoning persons.
ference between that person and the rest of the Both logic and our commonsense moral ex-
world. If we took such a statement seriously at all, perience demand that the thorough sifting of
we would likely not only reject it but also would reasons constitutes the main work of our moral
not even consider it a bona fide moral statement. deliberations—​regardless of our particular moral
The requirement of moral impartiality pro- outlook or theory. We would think it odd, per-
hibits discrimination against people merely be- haps even perverse, if someone asserted that
cause they are different—​different in ways that physician-assisted suicide is always morally
are not morally relevant. Two people can be dif- wrong—​and then said she has no reasons at all for
ferent in many ways: skin color, weight, gender, believing such a judgment but just does. What-
income, age, occupation, and so forth. But these ever our views on physician-assisted suicide, we
are not differences relevant to the way they would be justified in ignoring her judgment, for
should be treated as persons. On the other hand, we would have no way to distinguish it from
if there are morally relevant differences between personal whim or wishful thinking. Likewise she
people, then we may have good reasons to treat herself (if she genuinely had no good reasons for
them differently, and this treatment would not her assertion) would be in the same boat, adrift
be a violation of impartiality. This is how phi- with a firm opinion moored to nothing solid.
losopher James Rachels explains the point: Our feelings, of course, are also part of our
moral experience. When we ponder a moral
The requirement of impartiality, then, is at issue we care about (abortion, for example), we
bottom nothing more than a proscription against may feel anger, sadness, disgust, fear, irritation,
arbitrariness in dealing with people. It is a rule or sympathy. Such strong emotions are normal
that forbids us from treating one person differ- and often useful, helping us empathize with
ently from another when there is no good reason others, deepening our understanding of human
to do so. But if this explains what is wrong with suffering, and sharpening our insight into the
racism, it also explains why, in some special consequences of our moral decisions. But our
kinds of cases, it is not racist to treat people dif- feelings can mislead us by reflecting not moral
ferently. Suppose a film director was making a truth but our own psychological needs, our own
movie about the life of Martin Luther King, Jr. personal or cultural biases, or our concern for
He would have a perfectly good reason for ruling personal advantage. Throughout history, some
out Tom Cruise for the starring role. Obviously, people’s feelings led them to conclude that
such casting would make no sense. Because there women should be burned for witchcraft, that
would be a good reason for it, the director’s “dis- whole races should be exterminated, that black
crimination” would not be arbitrary and so men should be lynched, and that adherents of a
would not be open to criticism.1 different religion were evil. Critical reasoning
can help restrain such terrible impulses. It can
Reasonableness. To participate in morality—​to help us put our feelings in proper perspective
engage in the essential, unavoidable practices of and achieve a measure of impartiality. Most of

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 6 05/02/19 07:36 PM


Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 7

or economic. Thus murder and embezzlement are


I N D E P TH both immoral and illegal, backed by social disapproval
and severe sanctions imposed by law. Controversy
MORALITY AND THE LAW
often arises when an action is not obviously or seri-
ously harmful but is considered immoral by some who
want the practice prohibited by law. The conten-
Some people confuse morality with the law, or iden-
tious notion at work is that something may be made
tify the one with the other, but the two are distinct
illegal solely on the grounds that it is immoral, re-
though they may often coincide. Laws are norms
gardless of any physical or economic harm involved.
enacted or enforced by the state to protect or pro-
This view of the law is known as legal moralism, and
mote the public good. They specify which actions
it sometimes underlies debates about the legalization
are legally right or wrong. But these same actions
of abortion, euthanasia, reproductive technology,
can also be judged morally right or wrong, and these
con­traception, and other practices.
two kinds of judgments will not necessarily agree.
Many issues in bioethics have both a moral and
Lying to a friend about a personal matter, deliberately
legal dimension, and it is important not to confuse
trying to destroy yourself through reckless living, or
the two. Sometimes the question at hand is a moral
failing to save a drowning child (when you easily
one (whether, for example, euthanasia is ever morally
could have) may be immoral—​but not illegal. Racial
permissible); whether a practice should be legal or
bias, discrimination based on gender or sexual orien-
illegal then is beside the point. Sometimes the ques-
tation, slavery, spousal rape, and unequal treatment
tion is about legality. And sometimes the discussion
of minority groups are immoral—​but, depending on
concerns both. A person may consider physician-
the society, they may not be illegal.
assisted suicide morally acceptable but argue that it
Much of the time, however, morality and the law
should nevertheless be illegal because allowing the
overlap. Often what is immoral also turns out to be
practice to become widespread would harm both
illegal. This is usually the case when immoral actions
patients and the medical profession.
cause substantial harm to others, whether physical

all, it can guide us to moral judgments that are purports to explain right actions, or make judg-
trustworthy because they are supported by the ments about right or wrong actions.
best of reasons. Moral values, on the other hand, generally
The moral life, then, is about grappling with a concern those things that we judge to be morally
distinctive class of norms marked by normative good, bad, praiseworthy, or blameworthy. Nor-
dominance, universality, impartiality, and rea- mally we use such words to describe persons (as
sonableness. As we saw earlier, these norms can in “He is a good person” or “She is to blame for
include moral principles, rules, theories, and hurting them”), their character (“He is virtu-
judgments. We should notice that we commonly ous”; “She is honest”), or their motives (“She did
apply these norms to two distinct spheres of our wrong but did not mean to”). Note that we also
moral experience—​ to both moral obligations attribute nonmoral value to things. If we say that
and moral values. a book or bicycle or vacation is good, we mean
Moral obligations concern our duty, what we good in a nonmoral sense. Such things in them-
are obligated to do. That is, obligations are about selves cannot have moral value.
conduct, how we ought or ought not to behave. Strictly speaking, only actions are morally
In this sphere, we talk primarily about actions. right or wrong, but persons are morally good or
We may look to moral principles or rules to bad (or some degree of goodness or badness).
guide our actions, or study a moral theory that With this distinction we can acknowledge a

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 7 05/02/19 07:36 PM


8 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

simple fact of the moral life: A good person can We can see appeals to moral principles in
do something wrong, and a bad person can do countless cases. Confronted by a pain-racked,
something right. A Gandhi can tell a lie, and a terminally ill patient who demands to have his
Hitler can save a drowning man. life ended, his physician refuses to comply, rely-
In addition, we may judge an action right or ing on the principle that “it is wrong to inten-
wrong depending on the motive behind it. If tionally take a life.” Another physician makes a
John knocks a stranger down in the street to pre- different choice in similar circumstances, insist-
vent her from being hit by a car, we would deem ing that the relevant principle is “ending the suf-
his action right (and might judge him a good fering of a hopelessly ill patient is morally
person). But if he knocks her down because he permissible.” An infant is born anencephalic
dislikes the color of her skin, we would believe (without a brain); it will never have a conscious
his action wrong (and likely think him evil). life and will die in a few days. The parents decide
The general meaning of right and wrong seems to donate the infant’s organs to other children
clear to just about everyone. But we should be so they might live, which involves taking the
careful to differentiate degrees of meaning in organs right away before they deteriorate. A
these moral terms. Right can mean either “obliga- critic of the parents’ decision argues that “it is
tory” or “permissible.” An obligatory action is one unethical to kill in order to save.” But someone
that would be wrong not to perform. We are obli- else appeals to the principle “save as many chil-
gated or required to do it. A permissible action is dren as possible.”2 In such ways moral principles
one that is permitted. It is not wrong to perform it. help guide our actions and inform our judg-
Wrong means “prohibited.” A prohibited action is ments about right and wrong, good and evil.
one that would be wrong to perform. We are obli- As discussed in Chapter 2, moral principles
gated or required not to do it. A supererogatory are often drawn from a moral theory, which is a
action is one that is “above and beyond” our duty. moral standard on the most general level. The
It is praiseworthy—​a good thing to do—​but not principles are derived from or supported by the
required. Giving all your possessions to the poor theory. Many times we simply appeal directly to
is generally considered a supererogatory act. a plausible moral principle without thinking
much about its theoretical underpinnings.
Philosophers make a distinction between ab-
moral principles in bioethics
solute and prima facie principles (or duties). An
As noted earlier, the main work of bioethics is absolute principle applies without exceptions.
trying to solve bioethical problems using the An absolute principle that we should not lie de-
potent resources and methods of moral phi- mands that we never lie regardless of the cir-
losophy, which include, at a minimum, critical cumstances or the consequences. In contrast, a
­reasoning, logical argument, and conceptual prima facie principle applies in all cases unless
analysis. Many, perhaps most, moral philoso- an exception is warranted. Exceptions are justi-
phers would be quick to point out that beyond fied when the principle conflicts with other
these tools of reason we also have the consider- principles and is thereby overridden. W. D. Ross
able help of moral principles. (The same could be is given credit for drawing this distinction in his
said about moral theories, which we explore in 1930 book The Right and the Good.3 It is essen-
the next chapter.) Certainly to be useful, moral tial to his account of ethics, which has a core of
principles must be interpreted, often filled out several moral principles or duties, any of which
with specifics, and balanced with other moral might come into conflict.
concerns. But both in everyday life and in bio- Physicians have a prima facie duty to be truth­
ethics, moral principles are widely thought to be ful to their patients as well as a prima facie duty
indispensable to moral decision-making. to promote their welfare. But if these duties come

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 8 05/02/19 07:36 PM


Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 9

in conflict—​if, for example, telling a patient the their consent, treating competent patients against
truth about his condition would somehow result their will, physically restraining or confining pa-
in his death—​a physician might decide that the tients for no medical reason—​such practices con-
duty of truthfulness should yield to the weight- stitute obvious violations of personal autonomy.
ier duty to do good for the patient. Not all restrictions on autonomy, however,
Moral principles are many and varied, but in are of the physical kind. Autonomy involves the
bioethics the following have traditionally been capacity to make personal choices, but choices
extremely influential and particularly relevant cannot be considered entirely autonomous unless
to the kinds of moral issues that arise in health they are fully informed. When we make decisions
care, medical research, and biotechnology. In in ignorance—​without relevant information or
fact, many—​perhaps most—​of the thorniest issues blinded by misinformation—​our autonomy is
in bioethics arise from conflicts among these diminished just as surely as if someone physi-
basic principles. In one formulation or another, cally manipulated us. If this is correct, then we
each one has been integral to major moral have a plausible explanation of why lying is
theories, providing evidence that the principles generally prohibited: Lying is wrong because it
capture something essential in our moral expe- undermines personal autonomy. Enshrined in
rience. The principles are (1) autonomy, (2) non­ bioethics and in the law, then, is the precept of
maleficence, (3) beneficence, (4) utility, and informed consent, which demands that patients
(5) justice.4 be allowed to freely consent to or decline treat-
ments and that they receive the information they
Autonomy need to make informed judgments about them.
Autonomy refers to a person’s rational capacity In many ways, autonomy is a delicate thing,
for self-governance or self-determination—​ the easily compromised and readily thwarted. Often
ability to direct one’s own life and choose for a person’s autonomy is severely undermined not
­oneself. The principle of autonomy insists on full by other people but by nature, nurture, or his or
­respect for autonomy. One way to express the prin- her own actions. Some drug addicts and alcohol-
ciple is: Autonomous persons should be allowed ics, people with serious psychiatric illness, and
to exercise their capacity for self-determination. those with severe mental impairment are thought
According to one major ethical tradition, autono- to have drastically diminished autonomy (or to
mous persons have intrinsic worth precisely be essentially nonautonomous). Bioethical ques-
because they have the power to make rational tions then arise about what is permissible to do
decisions and moral choices. They therefore must to them and who will represent their interests or
be treated with respect, which means not violating make decisions regarding their care. Infants and
their autonomy by ignoring or thwarting their children are also not fully autonomous, and the
ability to choose their own paths and make their same sorts of questions are forced on parents,
own judgments. guardians, and health care workers.
The principle of respect for autonomy places Like all the other major principles discussed
severe restraints on what can be done to an here, respect for autonomy is thought to be
autonomous person. There are exceptions, but in prima facie. It can sometimes be overridden by
general we are not permitted to violate people’s considerations that seem more important or
autonomy just because we disagree with their compelling—​ considerations that philosophers
decisions, or because society might benefit, or and other thinkers have formulated as princi-
because the violation is for their own good. We ples of autonomy restriction. The principles are
cannot legitimately impair someone’s autonomy articulated in various ways, are applied widely
without strong justification for doing so. Con- to all sorts of social and moral issues, and are
ducting medical experiments on patients without themselves the subject of debate. Chief among

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 9 05/02/19 07:36 PM


10 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

these is the harm principle: a person’s autonomy A health care professional violates this prin-
may be curtailed to prevent harm to others. To ciple if he or she deliberately performs an action
prevent people from being victimized by thieves that harms or injures a patient. If a physician
and murderers, we have a justice system that intentionally administers a drug that she knows
prosecutes and imprisons the perpetrators. To will induce a heart attack in a patient, she obvi-
discourage hospitals and health care workers ously violates the principle—she clearly does
from hurting patients through carelessness or something that is morally (and legally) wrong.
fraud, laws and regulations limit what they can But she also violates it if she injures a patient
do to people in their care. To stop someone from through recklessness, negligence, or inexcusable
spreading a deadly, contagious disease, health ignorance. She may not intend to hurt anyone,
officials may quarantine him against his will. but she is guilty of the violation just the same.
Another principle of autonomy restriction is Implicit in the principle of nonmaleficence is
paternalism. Paternalism is the overriding of a the notion that health professionals must exer-
person’s actions or decision-making for her own cise “due care.” The possibility of causing some
good. Some cases of paternalism (sometimes pain, suffering, or injury is inherent in the care
called weak paternalism) seem permissible to and treatment of patients, so we cannot realisti-
many people—​when, for example, seriously de- cally expect health professionals never to harm
pressed or psychotic patients are temporarily anyone. But we do expect them to use due care—
restrained to prevent them from injuring or kill- to act reasonably and responsibly to minimize
ing themselves. Other cases are more controver- the harm or the chances of causing harm. If a
sial. Researchers hoping to develop a life-saving physician must cause patients some harm to
treatment give an experimental drug to some- effect a cure, we expect her to try to produce the
one without his knowledge or consent. Or a least amount of harm possible to achieve the re-
physician tries to spare the feelings of a compe- sults. And even if her treatments cause no actual
tent, terminally ill patient by telling her that she pain or injury in a particular instance, we expect
will eventually get better, even though she in- her not to use treatments that have a higher
sists on being told the truth. The paternalism in chance of causing harm than necessary. By the
such scenarios (known as strong paternalism) is lights of the nonmaleficence principle, subjecting
usually thought to be morally objectionable. patients to unnecessary risks is wrong even if no
Many controversies in bioethics center on the damage is done.
morality of strong paternalism.
Beneficence
Nonmaleficence The principle of beneficence has seemed to many
The principle of nonmaleficence asks us not to to constitute the very soul of morality—​or very
intentionally or unintentionally inflict harm on close to it. In its most general form, it says that
others. In bioethics, nonmaleficence is the most we should do good to others. (Benevolence is dif-
widely recognized moral principle. Its aphoris- ferent, referring more to an attitude of goodwill
tic expression has been embraced by practitio- toward others than to a principle of right action.)
ners of medicine for centuries: “Above all, do no Beneficence enjoins us to advance the welfare of
harm.” A more precise formulation of the prin- others and prevent or remove harm to them.
ciple is: We should not cause unnecessary injury Beneficence demands that we do more than
or harm to those in our care. In whatever form, just avoid inflicting pain and suffering. It says
nonmaleficence is the bedrock precept of count- that we should actively promote the well-being of
less codes of professional conduct, institutional others and prevent or remove harm to them. In
regulations, and governmental rules and laws bioethics, there is little doubt that physicians,
designed to protect the welfare of patients. nurses, researchers, and other professionals have

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 10 05/02/19 07:36 PM


Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 11

such a duty. After all, helping others, promoting possible benefits of the treatment outweigh its
their good, is a large part of what these profes- risks by an acceptable margin. Suppose a man’s
sionals are obliged to do. clogged artery can be successfully treated with
But not everyone thinks that we all have a open-heart surgery, a procedure that carries a
duty of active beneficence. Some argue that considerable risk of injury and death. But imag-
though there is a general (applicable to all) duty ine that the artery can also be successfully
not to harm others, there is no general duty to opened with a regimen of cholesterol-lowering
help others. They say we are not obligated to aid drugs and a low-fat diet, both of which have a
the poor, feed the hungry, or tend to the sick. much lower chance of serious complications.
Such acts are not required, but are supererogatory, The principle of utility seems to suggest that the
beyond the call of duty. Others contend that latter course is best and that the former is mor-
though we do not have a general duty of active ally impermissible.
beneficence, we are at least sometimes obligated The principle also plays a major role in the
to look to the welfare of people we care about creation and evaluation of the health policies of
most—​such as our parents, children, spouses, institutions and society. In these large arenas,
and friends. In any case, it is clear that in cer- most people aspire to fulfill the requirements of
tain professions—​particularly medicine, law, and beneficence and maleficence, but they recognize
nursing—​benefiting others is often not just that perfect beneficence or maleficence is im-
supererogatory but obligatory and basic. possible: Trade-offs and compromises must be
made, scarce resources must be allotted, help and
Utility harm must be balanced, life and death must be
The principle of utility says that we should pro- weighed—​tasks almost always informed by the
duce the most favorable balance of good over bad principle of utility.
(or benefit over harm) for all concerned. The prin- Suppose, for example, we want to mandate
ciple acknowledges that in the real world, we the immunization of all schoolchildren to pre-
cannot always just benefit others or just avoid vent the spread of deadly communicable dis-
harming them. Often we cannot do good for eases. The cost in time and money will be great,
people without also bringing them some harm, but such a program could save many lives.
or we cannot help everyone who needs to be There is a down side, however: A small number
helped, or we cannot help some without also of children—​perhaps as many as 2 for every
hurting or neglecting others. In such situations, 400,000 immunizations—​w ill die because of a
the principle says, we should do what yields the rare allergic reaction to the vaccine. It is impos-
best overall outcome—​the maximum good and sible to predict who will have such a reaction
minimum evil, everyone considered. The utility (and impossible to prevent it), but it is almost
principle, then, is a supplement to, not a substi- certain to occur in a few cases. If our goal is social
tute for, the principles of autonomy, beneficence, beneficence, what should we do? Children are
and justice. likely to die whether we institute the program
In ethics this maxim comes into play in sev- or not. Guided by the principle of utility (as well
eral ways. Most famously it is the defining pre- as other principles), we may decide to proceed
cept of the moral theory known as utilitarianism with the program since many more lives would
(discussed in Chapter 2). But it is also a stand- likely be saved by it than lost because of its
alone moral principle applied everywhere in implementation.
bio­ethics to help resolve the kind of dilemmas Again, suppose governmental health agencies
just mentioned. A physician, for example, must have enough knowledge and resources to de-
decide whether a treatment is right for a patient, velop fully a cure for only one disease—​either a
and that decision often hinges on whether the rare heart disorder or a common form of skin

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 11 05/02/19 07:36 PM


12 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

cancer. Trying to split resources between these justify the properties, or traits, of just distribu-
two is sure to prevent development of any cure tions. A basic precept of most of these theories is
at all. The heart disorder kills 200 adults each what may plausibly be regarded as the core of
year; the cancer occurs in thousands of people, the principle of justice: Equals should be treated
causing them great pain and distress, but is equally. (Recall that this is one of the defining
rarely fatal. How best to maximize the good? On elements of ethics itself, impartiality.) The idea
which disease should the government spend its is that people should be treated the same unless
time and treasure? Answering this question there is a morally relevant reason for treating
(and others like it) requires trying to apply the them differently. We would think it unjust for
utility principle—​a job often involving complex a physician or nurse to treat his white diabetic
calculations of costs and benefits and frequently patients more carefully than he does his black
generating controversy. diabetic patients—​and to do so without a sound
medical reason. We would think it unfair to
Justice award the only available kidney to the trans-
In its broadest sense, justice refers to people get- plant candidate who belongs to the “right” po-
ting what is fair or what is their due. In practice, litical party or has the best personal relationship
most of us seem to have a rough idea of what with hospital administrators.
justice entails in many situations, even if we The principle of justice has been at the heart
cannot articulate exactly what it is. We know, of debates about just distribution of benefits and
for example, that it is unjust for a bus driver to burdens (including health care) for society as a
make a woman sit in the back of the bus because whole. The disagreements have generally not been
of her religious beliefs, or for a judicial system to about the legitimacy of the principle, but about
arbitrarily treat one group of citizens more how it should be interpreted. Different theories
harshly than others, or for a doctor to care for of justice try to explain in what respects equals
some patients but refuse to treat others just be- should be treated equally.
cause he dislikes them. Libertarian theories emphasize personal free-
Questions of justice arise in different spheres doms and the right to pursue one’s own social
of human endeavor. Retributive justice, for ex- and economic well-being in a free market with-
ample, concerns the fair meting out of punish- out interference from others. Ideally the role
ment for wrongdoing. On this matter, some of government is limited to night-watchman
argue that justice is served only when people are functions—​ the protection of society and free
punished for past wrongs, when they get their economic systems from coercion and fraud. All
just deserts. Others insist that justice demands other social or economic benefits are the respon-
that people be punished not because they de- sibility of individuals. Government should not
serve punishment, but because the punishment be in the business of helping the socially or eco-
will deter further unacceptable behavior. Dis- nomically disadvantaged, for that would require
tributive justice concerns the fair distribution violating people’s liberty by taking resources
of society’s advantages and disadvantages—​for from the haves to give to the have-nots. So uni-
example, jobs, income, welfare aid, health care, versal health care is out of the question. For the
rights, taxes, and public service. Distributive jus- libertarian, then, people have equal intrinsic
tice is a major issue in bioethics, where many of worth, but this does not entitle them to an equal
the most intensely debated questions are about distribution of economic advantages. Individu-
who gets health care, what or how much they als are entitled only to what they can acquire
should get, and who should pay for it. through their own hard work and ingenuity.
Distributive justice is a vast topic, and many Egalitarian theories maintain that a just dis-
theories have been proposed to identify and tribution is an equal distribution. Ideally, social

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 12 05/02/19 07:36 PM


Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 13

benefits—​whether jobs, food, health care, or But moral objectivism is directly challenged
some­thing else—​should be allotted so that every- by a doctrine that some find extremely appeal-
one has an equal share. Treating people equally ing and that, if true, would undermine ethics
means making sure everyone has equal access to itself: ethical relativism. According to this view,
certain minimal goods and services. To achieve moral standards are not objective but are rela-
this level of equality, individual liberties will tive to what individuals or cultures believe.
have to be restricted, measures that libertari- There simply are no objective moral truths, only
ans would never countenance. In a pure egali- relative ones. An action is morally right if en-
tarian society, universal health care would be dorsed by a person or culture and morally wrong
guaranteed. if condemned by a person or culture. So eutha-
Between strict libertarian and egalitarian views nasia is right for person A if he approves of it but
of justice lie some theories that try to achieve a wrong for person B if she disapproves of it, and
plausible fusion of both perspectives. With a the same would go for cultures with similarly
nod toward libertarianism, these theories may diverging views on the subject. In this way, moral
exhibit a healthy respect for individual liberty norms are not discovered but made; the indi-
and limit governmental interference in econo­ vidual or culture makes right and wrong. Ethi-
mic enterprises. But leaning toward egalitarian- cal relativism pertaining to individuals is known
ism, they may also mandate that the basic needs as subjective relativism, more precisely stated as
of the least well-off citizens be met. the view that right actions are those sanctioned
In bioethics, the principle of justice and the by a person. Ethical relativism regarding cultures
theories used to explain it are constantly being is called cultural relativism, the view that right
marshaled to support or reject health care poli- actions are those sanctioned by one’s culture.
cies of all kinds. They are frequently used—​along In some ways, subjective relativism is a com-
with other moral principles—​to evaluate, design, forting position. It relieves individuals of the
and challenge a wide range of health care pro- burden of serious critical reasoning about mo-
grams and strategies. They are, in other words, rality. After all, determining right and wrong is
far from being merely academic. a matter of inventorying one’s beliefs, and any
sincerely held beliefs will do. Morality is essen-
tially a matter of personal taste, which is an ex-
ethical relativism
tremely easy thing to establish. Determining
The commonsense view of morality and moral what one’s moral views are may indeed involve
standards is this: There are moral norms or deliberation and analysis—but neither of these
principles that are valid or true for everyone. is a necessary requirement for the job. Subjective
This claim is known as moral objectivism, the relativism also helps people short-circuit the un-
idea that at least some moral standards are ob- pleasantness of moral debate. The subjective
jective. Moral objectivism, however, is distinct relativist’s familiar refrain—“That may be your
from moral absolutism, the belief that objective truth, but it’s not my truth”—has a way of stop-
moral principles allow no exceptions or must be ping conversations and putting an end to rea-
applied the same way in all cases and cultures. A soned arguments.
moral objectivist can be absolutist about moral The doctrine, however, is difficult to maintain
principles, or she can avoid absolutism by ac- consistently. On issues that the relativist cares
cepting that moral principles are prima facie. In little about (the moral rightness of gambling,
any case, most people probably assume some say), she may be content to point out that moral
form of moral objectivism and would not take norms are relative to each individual and that
seriously any claim implying that valid moral “to each his own.” But on more momentous
norms can be whatever we want them to be. topics (such as genocide in Africa or the Middle

vau03268_ch01_001-033.indd 13 05/02/19 07:36 PM


Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
washing fluids pass through the soil and not around it. This form of apparatus
reduces the labor to a minimum and permits many determinations to be carried
on at once.
This form of apparatus was only lately devised and has only been used long
enough to test it and to show its advantages. The reported results were obtained
by the ordinary methods of washing.
In all the work reported, five grams were used, as the soils contained so much
humus that this amount gave enough humus for good work in the final
weighings. The results obtained so far appear in the following tables:
Table I.

Comparison of Method of Grandeau with Huston’s Modification and of Influence of Strength of


Ammonia Solution. Time of Digestion in Modified Method Thirty-Six Hours.

Two per cent NH₃. Four per cent NH₃. Seven per cent NH₃. Eight per cent NH₃.
Grandeau. Huston. Grandeau. Huston. Grandeau. Huston. Grandeau. Huston.
1. Peat soil, 16.40 20.06
Bogus „ 13.98 20.80
„„ 17.43

Mean 15.94 20.43

2. Peat 13.98 19.38


subsoil,
Bogus „ 13.85 20.30

Mean 13.92 19.84

3. Peat soil, 9.05 15.60 14.71 21.24 19.77 21.70 16.05 21.42
Good „ 10.27 15.88 15.34 20.20 19.85 21.90 15.40 21.80

Mean 9.61 15.74 15.03 20.72 19.81 21.80 15.73 21.61

4. Peat 16.75 24.34


subsoil,
Good „ 18.60 23.52

Mean 17.68 23.93

5. Black soil, A 3.90 6.90 (1.86) 7.42


„„„ (1.67) 6.98
„„B 3.88 7.00 4.42
„„„ 4.20

Mean 3.99 6.95 (3.05) 7.20


„ 4.31

6. Clay loam, 1.86 4.20 2.40 4.26 2.14 4.02 1.85 4.12
West side, A 4.28
„„B 1.76 4.36 2.48 (3.40) 2.13 4.48 1.90 4.40
„„„ (3.10)

Mean 1.81 4.28 2.44 (3.76) 2.14 4.25 1.88 4.26


„ 4.27

7. Clay loam, 1.90 4.12 (1.60) (4.59)


A
Lysimeter 1.61 4.22 (1.41) (4.58)
soil, B
„„C 1.80 4.12
„„D 1.95 4.04
„„E 1.92 3.85
„„F 1.95 4.08
„„G 1.90 3.93
„„H 1.90 3.80

Mean 1.76 4.17 (1.80) (4.12)


„ 1.90 3.97

Note.—Numbers in parentheses indicate results, generally the earliest ones, which the authors
do not consider strictly comparable with the rest of the work. They are given solely for the
purpose of exhibiting all the work that has been done to date. When a mean is included in
parentheses it indicates that it is calculated from all the results obtained, including those not
considered strictly comparable. Bogus is a name given to a peaty soil which is very sterile.

Table II.

Influence of Time of Digestion. Four Per Cent of Ammonia Used


Throughout. Huston’s Method.

Thirty-six Forty-eight Sixty-eight Ninety-eight


hours. hours. hours. hours.
Peat 21.24 22.28 24.04
Soil,
Good „ 20.20 21.70 23.94

Mean 20.72 21.99 23.99

Clay 4.28 4.00 4.40


loam,
„ 4.26 4.01 4.85
West (3.40)
side
„„ (3.05)

Mean 4.27 4.01 4.63


Table III.

Influence of Time of Extraction. Time, Ten Days. Grandeau’s Method, Four


Per Cent Ammonia. Peat Soil.

A. B. Mean. Remarks.
Per Per Per
cent. cent. cent.
1st 750 16.90 18.96 17.93
extraction, cc
2nd „ 250 2.80 2.38 2.59

3rd „ 250 1.77 1.10 1.44

4th „ 250 1.34 1.30 1.32 Stood over night.

5th „ 250 0.89 0.85 0.87

6th „ 250 1.41 1.65 1.53 Stood overnight.

7th „ 250 2.10 1.80 1.95 Washed again with HCl for Ca. Trace found.
„ HCl washed out, but trace of chlorids found
in ash. Probably HCl absorbed from air as
humus showed small quantity of a white
volatile solid on evaporation.
8th „ 250 0.67 0.65 0.66

9th „ 250 0.57 0.50 0.53

Total 2750 28.45 29.19 28.82


313. Summary of Results.—1. The modified method gives much higher


results than the original method of Grandeau.
2. In the Grandeau method marked irregularities follow a change in the
strength of the ammonia solution. These differences in results bear no relation
to the strength of the solution used. They seem to be errors due to the difficulty
of securing uniform and complete washing of the soil by the ammonia solution.
In the modified method the change in the strength of the ammonia solution
makes practically no difference in the amount of humus extracted, except in the
case of the peat soil where two per cent ammonia failed to extract all the humus.
But the results show no considerable increase when the strength is increased to
over four per cent.
3. The factor of time has not been fully investigated, but the results so far
obtained indicate that the time exerts less influence in the modified than in the
Grandeau method.
4. Table III shows that considerable quantities of the peat soil are still passing
into solution in the Grandeau method at the end of ten days. With ordinary soils
this is not true; but in the case of soil No. 5, a black soil, the solutions were
colored at the end of a week. On the peat soil the modified method extracted
from ten to fifty per cent more than the Grandeau, and on the ordinary soil from
two to three times as much humus.
5. In comparing duplicate results by both methods it is found that with soil
No. 3, peat soil, the following differences appear calculated to percentage of the
total amount involved in the determination:

Per cent. Per cent. Per cent. Per cent.


Strength of ammonia 2. 4. 7. 8.
Modified 1.7 5. 1.0 1.8
Grandeau 13.0 4.3 0.5 3.4

Special attention was paid to this point in case of soil No. 7, an ordinary soil;
taking all results into consideration the greatest difference in percentage of total
amount involved was, by the modified method, nineteen per cent, and by the
Grandeau, thirty per cent. In the set of six special determinations made by both
methods to test this point and which are strictly comparable with each other, the
maximum range was by the modified method 7.8 per cent and by the Grandeau
8.3 per cent of the total amount involved in the determination. From which it
appears that the modified method is on the whole capable of yielding rather
more concordant results than the Grandeau.
314. Estimation of Free Humic Acids.—This process, due to Müntz[201] is
essentially that of Huston and McBride. Twenty grams of the soil are reduced to
a fine powder and saturated with fifty cubic centimeters of concentrated
ammonia and allowed to digest two or three days in a warm place. The volume is
then made up to one liter with water, well shaken, and set aside for one day in
order to permit the subsidence of the solid matter. At the end of this time 500
cubic centimeters of the supernatant liquor are taken and acidified with
hydrochloric acid in order to precipitate the humic bodies. The humus is
collected on a filter, dried and weighed. It is then ignited and the weight of ash
deducted from the first weight thus giving the actual weight of the humus
obtained, free from mineral matter. This process gives the free humic acids. By
previous treatment of the sample with hydrochloric acid as in the process of
Huston and McBride, the total humus is obtained. The estimation of the free
humic acids is of importance in determining the quantity of lime or marl which
should be added to acid lands.
315. Humus Method of Von Bemmelén.[202]—Von Bemmelén obtains the
content of humus by the multiplication of the content of carbon in the soil by the
factor of Wolff; viz., 1.724. The estimation of carbon, water, and of the loss on
ignition is conducted in combustion tubes in a current of oxygen. The nitrogen
estimation is carried on according to the method of Dumas.
In soils containing calcium carbonate the carbon content is derived from the
carbon dioxid taken up by the potash bulbs during combustion (a); from other
carbonates not decomposed on ignition and which are subsequently determined
in the residue by treatment with hydrochloric acid in a carbon dioxid apparatus,
(b) and the total carbon dioxid derived from the carbonates in the soil (c).
For each estimation from three to five grams of the soil are taken, because
with smaller quantities the errors of analysis too strongly influence the results.
The carbon is then calculated according to the formula:
Carbon = ³⁄₁₁ (a + b − c).
The Carbon Dioxid of Carbonates.—It is necessary to expel the carbon dioxid
at ordinary temperatures, because on heating to boiling, carbon dioxid would be
formed from the humus. In a flask, as small as possible, the soil is treated at
ordinary temperature, with dilute sulfuric or citric acid, the escaping gas dried
over sulfuric acid and taken up with soda-lime. Behind the soda-lime is a small
tube filled with pieces of glass and moistened with sulfuric acid, which retains
any moisture taken out of the soda-lime. A stream of about one liter of air, free
from carbon dioxid, is sufficient to drive out all of the carbon dioxid when the
estimation is made at ordinary temperatures.
A volcanic earth from Deli, which contained five per cent of humus, gave, at a
temperature plus or minus 15°, 0.01 per cent CO₂. At boiling temperature two
analyses gave 0.54 and 0.56 CO₂. This soil contained no carbonate, and the
carbon dioxid found at the boiling temperature, must have come from the
humus substances under the influence of the dilute acids.
A heavy clay containing 6.9 per cent of humus gave, at plus or minus 15°, 3.60
per cent CO₂; at 100° without boiling, it gave an additional 0.53 per cent, and
with boiling an additional 0.11 per cent, or a total of 4.24 per cent CO₂. A light
clay containing 3.2 per cent of humus, gave, at 15°, 5.09 per cent CO₂; at a
boiling temperature an additional 0.43 per cent, and by continued boiling an
additional 0.27 per cent.
316. Estimation of Humus by the German Method.—The German
experiment stations follow the method of Loges,[203] depending on the oxidation
of the humic bodies with copper oxid after evaporation of the sample with
phosphoric acid. The object of the preliminary evaporation is to set the humic
acids free in order that they may be better and more easily oxidized than when
burned in the combined state.
The sample of soil is placed in a Hoffmeister dish (Schälchen), moistened with
dilute phosphoric acid and evaporated to complete dryness. The dish and its
contents are rubbed up with pulverized copper oxid and placed in a combustion
tube of sixty centimeters in length, open at both ends. There is then placed in the
tube, and held in place by asbestos plugs, granular copper oxid to a length of
twenty centimeters.
The combustion tube is placed in a proper furnace and one end connected
with two washing-flasks, the first containing potash lye, and the other a solution
of barium hydroxid. These flasks are to free the aspirated air from carbon dioxid.
The other end of the combustion tube is connected with an appropriate
apparatus for absorbing the carbon dioxid. Loges recommends the Pettenkofer
absorption tube and a Fresenius drying cylinder.
Between the absorption apparatus and the aspirator, is also placed a washing-
flask containing barium hydroxid solution, serving to detect any unabsorbed
carbon dioxid. The layer of granular copper oxid is first heated, the air being
slowly aspirated through the apparatus meanwhile, but not through the
absorption bulbs. All the carbon dioxid is thus removed from the apparatus.
The absorption system being connected, the tube is heated slowly from the
front, backwards, and after the tube is well heated a slow current of air is drawn
through and continued until the combustion is complete, which is usually in
about three-quarters of an hour.
After the tube is cool the powdered copper oxid and residue of combustion are
removed, and for this reason the tube is stopped with a cork at both ends instead
of being drawn out and sealed at one end. The tube can thus be refilled without
disturbing the granular layer of copper oxid.
The drying cylinder used between the combustion tube and the absorption
system has its upper part filled with cotton to avoid the deleterious effects of the
nitric oxid produced in the combustion. With this arrangement the use of
metallic copper in the combustion tube to reduce the nitric oxid can be
dispensed with, the moist cotton holding back the acid fumes. The per cent of
humus is obtained by multiplying the per cent of carbon found by 1.724.
317. Method of Raulin for the Estimation of Humus.[204]—The
volumetric estimation of humus in soil by a solution of potassium permanganate
would be convenient and practical if the combustion of the organic matter were
complete, and if the browning of the liquor did not render the end of the reaction
uncertain. The process of Schmidt, modified as below, has given satisfactory
results.
In a small flask, with flat bottom, containing about 250 cubic centimeters, are
introduced ten cubic centimeters of a solution of manganese sulfate containing
sixteen grams of the anhydrous salt per liter, and ten cubic centimeters of a ten
per cent solution of potassium permanganate. The solution is heated for a few
minutes, the liquor is decolorized and manganese bronze is precipitated. One
hundred cubic centimeters of water are added, and four cubic centimeters of
sulfuric acid containing 150 cubic centimeters of monohydrated acid per liter.
There is now added an exactly measured volume of the humic liquid properly
prepared, so that in oxidizing completely it destroys at most only half of the
manganese dioxid. The mixture is submitted to gentle ebullition for eight hours,
the water being kept at a constant volume. The excess of manganese dioxid
remaining is dissolved hot by a measured portion of decinormal oxalic acid in
slight excess, and the excess of oxalic acid is removed by a solution of potassium
permanganate containing one gram per liter. The volume of oxalic acid not
destroyed by manganese dioxid is calculated from the amount of permanganate
consumed. The volume of oxalic acid, which corresponds to the same quantity of
dioxid as the introduced humus, is also calculated by taking the difference
between the volume of oxalic acid necessary to destroy all the dioxid formed by
ten cubic centimeters of the ten per cent permanganate solution, and the volume
of the oxalic acid which has destroyed the dioxid remaining after the action of
the humus. The first volume of oxalic acid, that is to say, that which destroys the
dioxid formed by ten cubic centimeters of ten per cent permanganate is
determined in a preliminary titration.
In regard to the humic liquor, it is prepared by treating ten grams of earth
with soda solution in the usual manner. It will be easy to calculate the volume of
the oxalic solution equivalent to the total volume of the humic solution, of which
a determined fraction has been assayed, and consequently the volume of oxalic
solution equivalent to the humus in ten grams of the dry earth. This number of
cubic centimeters of the decinormal oxalic solution multiplied by 0.8 will
express in milligrams the weight of oxygen necessary to burn the humus from
ten grams of dry earth. Humus not being a definite compound, but a residue of
complex organic matters partially oxidized, it will require as much more oxygen
to complete the combustion as the previous oxidation has been less pronounced.
This weight of oxygen necessary to burn the humus from ten grams of dry earth
may serve to detect the total value as well as the weight of the humus itself.
However, if we wish to have directly the weight of the humus, resource can be
had to a table which, without being rigorous, can be regarded as sufficiently
exact when the variability of the constitution of humus is taken into account.
Volume of decinormal oxalic acid for ten Corresponding humus, directly
grams of earth. determined.
Cubic centimeters. Milligrams.
50 80
100 150
200 280
300 400
400 510
500 610
600 705
700 790
800 885
900 975
1,000 1,060
1,200 1,225
1,400 1,390
1,600 1,560
1,800 1,720
2,000 1,890
2,500 2,315
3,000 2,735
3,500 3,170
4,000 3,605
4,500 4,035
5,000 4,460
5,500 4,890
6,000 5,310
6,500 5,745

318. Pasturel’s Method.—According to Pasturel[205] the process of Raulin


does not furnish figures that are rigorously exact only with soil of which the
humus contains forty-five per cent of carbon. When the richness in organic
carbon is less, the results of the estimation are too high. Pasturel modifies the
process as follows:
Manganese Sulfate.—Dissolve sixteen grams of the pure anhydrous
manganese sulfate in distilled water and make the solution up to one liter.
Potassium Permanganate.—Make a solution of ten grams of potassium
permanganate in one liter of water; 100 cubic centimeters of the liquor just
mentioned are diluted to one liter and constitute the potassium permanganate
solution one to ten.
Oxalic and Sulfuric Acids.—A solution of oxalic acid is prepared containing
6.3 grams of the acid in one liter of water, and a dilute solution of sulfuric acid,
by dissolving 150 grams of the monohydrated acid in one liter of water.
Humus Solution.—The solution of humus is prepared by the following
process: Ten grams of fine earth are freed from all their carbonates by dilute
hydrochloric acid. After washing, the filter is broken and the dirt is washed into
a small flask. Not more than twenty or thirty cubic centimeters of water should
be employed for this purpose. Twenty cubic centimeters of a liquor containing
two grams of caustic soda are added, and the flask is placed upon a sand-bath
and maintained at a boiling temperature for six hours. It is then diluted with
water, filtered and washed as long as the waters are colored. The liquor is treated
with dilute sulfuric acid until almost the whole of the soda is saturated. It is
indispensable, however, to maintain a slight alkalinity in order that the organic
matter may rest totally dissolved. The precipitation of silica which is almost
always produced is without inconvenience. Afterward the volume is completed
to 500 cubic centimeters and the humus solution is then ready for use.
Estimation of the Humus.—Ten cubic centimeters of the manganese sulfate
are placed in a flask and ten cubic centimeters of the permanganate added, and
the whole is then slightly heated, and afterward 100 cubic centimeters of water
and four cubic centimeters of sulfuric acid are added. The humic liquor is now
introduced in such proportion that the humus which it contains dissolves at the
greatest, a half of the precipitated manganese and the rest of the process is
continued as described by Raulin.
319. Estimation of Carbonates in Arable Soil.—The principle of the
determination depends on the liberation of the carbon dioxid from its
compounds in the soil by acting on them with strong acid, and the desiccation,
absorption, and weighing of the evolved gas. Any of the ordinary forms of
apparatus for estimating carbon dioxid may be used in this determination.
The apparatus of Knorr[206] has been used with satisfaction for many years in
the laboratory of the Department of Agriculture.
Figure 65.

Knorr’s Apparatus for the Determination of Carbon Dioxid.

The apparatus consists of a flask A, Fig. 65, in which the carbon dioxid in the
soil is liberated. A condenser, D, fits by means of a ground-glass joint into the
neck of the flask in which the liberated gas, together with any air or aqueous
vapor which may be carried forward, is cooled. This prevents any excess of vapor
of water from entering the absorbing bulbs, which could easily happen at the end
of the experiments when the contents of A are raised to the boiling point. The
bulb B contains the acid, usually hydrochloric, which is employed for
decomposing the carbonates. It is provided with a guard bulb-tube, C, which
serves to absorb any carbon dioxid which might enter the apparatus with the air
during aspiration at the close of the determination. The carbon dioxid is dried in
the bulb-tube, E, in oil of vitriol, and absorbed in the potash solution in F. It is
advisable to aspirate a slow current of air through the apparatus by means of the
tube G during the whole of the operation. The quantity of the sample to be taken
depends on its richness in carbonates. Many soils are so poor in carbonates as to
render any attempt at exact determination nugatory. On the other hand, a
comparatively small sample of marls will be sufficient. A preliminary qualitative
test will indicate, in a general way, the quantity of the sample to be taken. The
sample of soil, five to fifty grams, having been transferred to A, which should be
perfectly dry, is made into a batter with freshly boiled distilled water. When all
the parts of the apparatus are properly connected gas-tight, the cock between B
and A is slowly opened and the hydrochloric (nitric) acid in B allowed to flow
into A at such a rate as will secure a moderate evolution of gas.
When the carbonate is entirely decomposed, a lamp is brought under A and its
contents gradually raised to the boiling point. The aspiration of air, free from
carbon dioxid, is meanwhile continued until all the liberated gas has been
absorbed in F. Usually about fifteen minutes will be sufficient to accomplish this
purpose.
320. Bernard’s Calcimeter.—For a rapid and approximately accurate
method of determining the amount of carbonate in the soil, estimated as calcium
carbonate, Bernard makes use of the well-known method of the volumetric
estimation of carbon dioxid. The sample to be examined should not be powdered
in any way. The sample in a natural state, but well air-dried, is gently broken up
by the fingers and passed through a sieve having ten meshes to the centimeter.
Of the fine earth thus obtained, one gram is taken, for the determination. If the
percentage of carbonate in the soil exceeds fifty then only half a gram is taken.
The apparatus employed is one well known. The small
erlenmeyer C is fitted with a rubber stopper carrying an
exit tube for the gas and a small thermometer. This flask is
connected by means of a rubber tube and small glass tube
to the measuring burette B. This burette is graduated from
0 to 100 cubic centimeters. Below, by means of a rubber
tube, it is connected with the open bulb A, which, by
means of a cord about its neck, can be suspended by the
hook as shown in the figure. The measuring tube is filled
with water through A until the level of the liquid in B is
slightly above the zero mark. Meanwhile the one gram of
earth has been placed in C, together with the tube D three-
fourths filled with an equal mixture of water and strong
hydrochloric acid. The greatest care must be taken that no
part of the acid be spilled.
The rubber stopper is now forced into C until the level of
the water in B is just at the zero mark. Grasping C in the
right hand and A in the left, the operator inclines C until
the contents of D are emptied. Meanwhile as the gas is
Figure 66.
evolved, A is lowered at such a rate as to always keep the
Bernard’s Calcimeter. level of the water in B and A on the same plane. In a few
moments the evolution of gas is complete, and the volume
given off is read at once without correction. This volume
multiplied by 0.4 gives the percentage of carbonate in the sample examined. It is
understood that the determination is made at ordinary temperatures; viz., 17° to
22°. Example:
One gram of a soil treated as above, gave of carbon dioxid (uncorrected) 65 cubic centimeters.
65 × 0.4 = 26.00 = per cent calcium carbonate in sample.

The above method is useful in the classification of soils and in determining


approximately the quantity of calcium carbonate which they contain. The
practical use of this method is of great value in determining the character of
fertilizer to be applied. It is well to know the percentage of carbonate in selecting
mineral fertilizers.
321. Soils Deficient in Carbonates.—When a soil contains but a small
quantity of carbonates, Müller[207] has called attention to the fact that the carbon
dioxid absorbed by the water in which the soil is rubbed up may vitiate the
result. Instead of water a titrated solution of sodium carbonate is employed. The
apparatus is composed of a flask containing the mixture of the sodium carbonate
and the soil on which the hydrochloric acid is to act. The hydrochloric acid is
contained in a small tube, as in Scheibler’s apparatus. The gas is received in a
rubber tube 1.5 meters long and three to four millimeters interior diameter, and
connected with a burette, the open mouth of which dips into the water of a
cylinder of proper length. The volume of gas is read when the burette is raised or
lowered in the cylinder until the liquid within and without stands at the same
level.
During the action of the acid on the carbonates the flask is constantly shaken.
Several readings of the volume of gas are made, the evolution flask being
vigorously shaken before each one. Finally, in order to allow for the variations in
temperature and pressure of the exterior air which may take place between the
beginning and the end of the reaction, a second flask containing air is placed by
the side of the evolution flask and communicating with a narrow ᥩ tube half
filled with water. Any variations in the volume of the air in the flask will be
shown by variations in the height of the liquid in the two arms of the ᥩ tube, and
the volume of the variation can be easily determined by having the ᥩ tube
calibrated.
If now a equals the volume per cent of carbon dioxid in the atmosphere of the
evolution flask at the end of the reaction, v the volume of gas disengaged, and V
the volume of the atmosphere in the evolution flask, the per cent of carbon
dioxid contained in a given length of the rubber tube will be equal to a2. This
arises from the fact that the first gas which passes into the rubber tube is
composed solely of air, while the last contains a per cent of carbon dioxid. By
reason of the shaking of the flask the mean richness of the contents of the tube in
carbon dioxid, will be sensibly a2.
From the above data the following equations are derived:
1. va2 + Va = v.
If the weight of the carbon dioxid dissolved in V′ cubic centimeters of the
liquid in the evolution flask be represented by q, the coefficient of the solubility
of pure carbon dioxid in this liquid will be, according to the law of the solubility
q
of a gas, equal to k = V′a
The volume of k has been determined for various strengths of the sodium
carbonate solution, using five cubic centimeters of hydrochloric acid containing
1.6 grams pure hydrochloric acid. For solutions disengaging from five to fifty
milligrams of carbon dioxid, the mean value of k was found to be 1.8 milligrams
in the absence of calcium chlorid. When calcium chlorid was present in
quantities varying from 0.03 to 0.07 gram per cubic centimeter of liquid in the
evolution flask, the value of k was 1.4 milligrams.
By adopting, according to circumstances, the one or the other of the above
numbers and multiplying it by Va, as determined by experiment, results are
obtained differing only 0.2 to 0.3 milligram from those secured by direct
weighing of the evolved gas.
Dietrich[208] has called attention to the necessity of adding the volume of the
dissolved gas to the measured volume in such determinations, and this volume
or weight is easily determined by the above formulas.
322. Belgian Method.—The method pursued at the Gembloux Station[209]
consists in taking from five to fifty grams of the sample of soil, according to its
content in carbonate, rubbing it up in a porcelain dish with distilled water in
order to make a thin paste. The mass is worked to drive out all the air, the whole
washed into a flask of 300 cubic centimeters capacity, and the amount of carbon
dioxid estimated by setting free with an acid, and collecting the carbon dioxid
evolved in potash bulbs.
DIGESTION OF SOILS WITH SOLVENTS.
323. General Considerations.—There are two points in connection with
the determination of mineral matters in the soil which must always be kept in
view; viz., first, the estimation of the total quantities of material in the soil, and
second, the study of those materials which are more easily brought into solution
and thus made available for the food of plants.
It is well understood that the soil particles do not give up entirely to the plant
the food materials which they contain. The practical value therefore of an
analysis of a soil depends more upon the exact determination of the plant food
available than upon its total quantity. From a mineral and geological point of
view, on the other hand, an idea of the total composition of the soil is the object
to be attained.
For the determination of the available plant food, various solvents have been
proposed, none of which, perhaps, imitates very accurately the natural solvent
action of organic life and moisture on the soil materials. A description of the
standard methods of preparing soil extracts will be the subject of a few
succeeding paragraphs.
324. Estimation of the Quantity of Materials Soluble in Water.[210]—
Five hundred grams of the air-dried soil are treated in a flask with 1,500 cubic
centimeters of water, less the quantity of water already contained in the air-
dried soil, which is volatile at 125°. The mass is frequently shaken and, after
seventy-two hours, 750 cubic centimeters of the liquid filtered. The filtrate is
evaporated to dryness in a platinum dish, dried at 120° and weighed. This is then
incinerated and, after treatment with ammonium carbonate and gentle ignition,
is again weighed. The further examination of the residue for acids and bases is
made by some of the methods hereafter described.
325. Treatment with Water Saturated with Carbon Dioxid.—Two
thousand five hundred grams of the air-dried soil are treated with 8000 cubic
centimeters of distilled, and afterwards with 2000 cubic centimeters of water,
which have previously, at room temperature, been saturated with carbon dioxid.
The mixture is left in a closed flask for seven days, frequently shaken, after
which 7,500 cubic centimeters of the liquid are filtered. The clear filtrate, after
treatment with a little hydrochloric acid and a few drops of nitric acid, is
evaporated to dryness. After the separation of the silica the traces of iron,
alumina, lime, sulfuric acid, magnesia, potash, and soda, are estimated in the
liquid in the manner hereinafter to be described. Phosphoric acid is always
present in such a case, in such small quantities as to make its estimation
unnecessary.
326. Treatment with Water Containing Ammonium Chlorid.—In the
flask containing the residue from the last experiment; viz., the soil with 2,500
cubic centimeters of liquid, are added 1,500 cubic centimeters of water saturated
with carbon dioxid, and 8,000 cubic centimeters of pure water in which five
grams of ammonium chlorid are dissolved. The mixture is then left for seven
days, with frequent shaking, and 7,500 cubic centimeters of the liquid are then
filtered, and the substances dissolved, determined in the filtrate. In addition to
the usual quantities of lime and magnesia, from two to four times as much alkali
is dissolved by this treatment as is found in the solution from the water
containing carbon dioxid alone.
327. Treatment with Water Containing Acetic Acid.—The acetic acid
should be of such a strength that after it has fully acted on the soil it should still
contain twenty per cent of free acid. 1000 grams of the soil dried at 100° are
taken and the acid added in proper proportions and treated in the manner to be
described for determining the solvent action of hydrochloric acid.
328. Treatment with Citric Acid Solution.—In ascertaining the
quantities of soil materials soluble in a solution of citric acid, Dyer[211]
recommends the use of a carefully prepared citric acid solution. The digestion is
carried on as follows: Place in a flask or bottle, holding about three liters, 200
grams of air-dried soil and two liters of distilled water, in which are dissolved
twenty grams of pure citric acid. The soil is left, at room temperature, in contact
with the one per cent acid for seven days, with thorough shaking several times a
day. At the end of the digestion the solution is filtered and 500 cubic centimeters
of the filtrate, corresponding to fifty grams of the soil, are taken for analysis for
each ingredient to be determined.
The digestion in citric acid is especially recommended by Dyer because of its
supposed near resemblance to the methods of solution of plant food practiced by
the rootlets of plants. It is evident, however, that this process is in no sense an
imitation of natural methods. The solution is to be used exclusively for the
estimation of potash and phosphoric acid. Dyer concludes, from a comparison of
the action of a solution of citric acid on soils of known fertility, that when as little
as 0.01 per cent of phosphoric acid is dissolved from a soil by this treatment it is
justifiable to assume that it stands in immediate need of phosphatic manure.
The methods used by Dyer to determine the phosphoric acid and potash in the
citric acid solution will be given in their appropriate place.
329. Treatment with Hydrochloric Acid.—The solutions of soils usually
subjected to chemical analysis are those obtained by long treatment with hot
mineral acids, among which the most common is hydrochloric.
It has long been assumed by soil analysts, perhaps not with justness, that such
treatment removed from the soil, all those elements of plant food which could
possibly be available for the needs of the growing crop. In this connection,
however, the analyst must not forget that nature, in a series of years, with her
own methods may easily accomplish what he in five days, even with the help of a
hot mineral acid, may not be able to secure. Since, however, this method of
solution has been so long practiced it is not the place here to throw doubt on its
effectiveness without being able to suggest a better way. Of the mineral acids
available no one possesses solvent powers for soils in a higher degree than
hydrochloric. A somewhat detailed description will therefore be given of the
methods of its use.
330. Strength of Acid to be Employed.—The fact that hydrochloric acid
of nearly constant strength; viz., specific gravity 1.115, equivalent to 22.9 per
cent hydrochloric acid, may be obtained by distillation, led Owen to use acid of
this density in his classic work on soil analysis. Hilgard has lately reviewed the
conditions of constant strength in the solvent with results confirming the
statements of Owen.[212] He evaporated on a steam-bath, to one-half its bulk, fifty
cubic centimeters of hydrochloric acid, specific gravity 1.116, obtained by using
the distillate from a stronger acid after rejecting the first third. The same
operation was conducted with similar acid diluted with ten per cent of water.
The acid used contained 22.96 per cent hydrochloric acid. The residual acid
contained 21.49 per cent hydrochloric acid. These results lead Hilgard to believe
that the changes arising from evaporation in hydrochloric acid during soil
digestion are insignificant, compared with those due to its action on the soluble
matters, and that evaporation during digestion is effective in maintaining a
definite strength in the solvent. For this reason it is contended that evaporation
in a porcelain beaker covered by a watch-glass is more effective in constancy of
conditions than digestion in a closed flask under pressure.
331. Influence of Time of Digestion and Strength of Acid.—
Loughridge has made an interesting study of the influence of the strength of acid
and time of digestion on the extraction of soils.[213] The method of preparing the
soil for the determination of the above points is as follows:
The soil, having been passed through the appropriate number of sieves to
obtain the fine earth is pulverized with a wooden pestle and thoroughly mixed.
The hygroscopic moisture is determined, after exposing it in a place saturated
with vapor, in a layer not exceeding one millimeter in thickness for twelve hours,
and subsequently drying at 200° in a paraffin-bath. Of this dried substance,
from two to three grams are used in the general analysis, the methods employed
being in general those adopted by Peter.[214]
The quantities of materials dissolved by acids of different densities are shown
below. The determinations were made by methods hereafter to be described.
Specific gravity of acid.
Ingredients. 1.00 1.115 1.160
Insoluble residue 71.88 70.53 74.15
Soluble silica 11.38 12.30 9.42
Potash 0.60 0.63 0.48
Soda 0.13 0.09 0.35
Lime 0.27 0.27 0.23
Magnesia 0.45 0.45 0.45
Manganese oxid 0.06 0.06 0.06
Ferric oxid 5.15 5.11 5.04
Alumina 6.84 8.09 6.22
Sulfuric acid 0.02 0.02 0.02
Volatile matter 3.14 3.14 3.14

Total 100.02 100.69 99.29

Amount of soluble matter 24.00 27.02 22.27


„ „ „ bases 13.50 14.70 12.83

From the above table it is seen that the strongest acid exerts the least soluble
effect upon the substances present in the soil, while the greatest degree of
solution was obtained by the acid of 1.115 specific gravity. This result indicates
that while lime and magnesia are probably present chiefly as carbonates, potash
as well as alumina, and to some extent lime, are present as silicates, and for that
reason are not as fully extracted by acid of low strength as by that of medium
concentration.
In regard to the influence of the time of digestion, the acid of specific gravity
1.115 being used, the data obtained are given in the following table:
Number of days digested.
Ingredients. 1. 3. 4. 5. 10.

Insoluble residue 76.97 72.66 71.86 70.53 71.79


Soluble silica 8.60 11.18 11.64 12.30 10.96
Potash 0.35 0.44 0.57 0.63 0.62
Soda 0.06 0.06 0.03 0.09 0.28
Lime 0.26 0.29 0.28 0.27 0.27
Magnesia 0.42 0.44 0.47 0.45 0.44
Manganese oxid 0.04 .06 0.06 0.06 0.06
Ferric oxid 4.77 5.01 5.43 5.11 4.85
Alumina 5.15 7.38 7.07 7.88 7.16
Phosphoric acid 0.21 0.21
Sulfuric acid 0.02 0.02 0.02 0.02 0.02
Volatile matter 3.14 3.14 3.14 3.14 3.14

Total 99.63 100.68 100.55 100.69 99.80

Amount of soluble matter 19.67 24.88 25.57 27.02 24.87


„ „ „ bases 11.05 13.68 13.91 14.49 13.68

From this table it appears that the amount of dissolved ingredients increases
up to the fifth day, the increase becoming, however, very slow as that limit is
approached. It is also found that the ingredients offering the greatest resistance
to this action are the same as those whose amounts were sensibly affected by the
strength of the acid; namely, silica, potash, and alumina.
In regard to lime and magnesia, one day’s digestion not being sufficient for
full extraction, it is evident that they do not exist in the soil as carbonates or
hydric oxids only, as has been supposed, but also as silicates. A comparison of
the results of the five and ten days’ digestion shows that the solvent action of the
acid has substantially ceased at the end of five days, there being no further
increase of the amount of dissolved matter.
332. Digestion Vessels.—Hilgard prescribes that the digestion of the
sample of soil with acid be conducted in a small porcelain beaker covered with a
watch-glass.[215] Kedzie, however, prefers beakers of bohemian glass, and shows
that hydrochloric acid attacks the porcelain with greater energy than the glass.
[216]
Platinum would be the ideal material for the digestive vessels, but its great
cost would exclude its general use. In most cases it will be found that the error
introduced into the analysis by the use of porcelain or bohemian glass beakers is
quite small and not likely to affect the quantitative estimation of soluble soil
ingredients to any extent.
In this laboratory some comparative tests made by Mr. W. D. Bigelow have
shown that vessels of hard glass of special manufacture are less soluble in hot
hydrochloric acid of 1.115 specific gravity than porcelain, thus confirming the
observation of Kedzie. Following are the data showing the weights of material
dissolved in fifty hours:

Berlin porcelain 2.8 milligrams


Bohemian glass 1.7 „
Kaehler and Martini glass 1.2 „

In each case twenty-five cubic centimeters of the acid were used. The vessels
all had approximately a capacity of 200 cubic centimeters.
333. Processes Employed—Hilgard’s Method.—The sample of soil
sifted through a 0.5 millimeter mesh sieve and thoroughly air-dried, is
conveniently preserved in weighing tubes. The actual content of hygroscopic and
combined moisture may be previously made on a separate sample of soil.
In determining the amount of material to be employed for the general analysis
regard must be had to the nature of the soil. This is necessary because of the
impracticability of handling successfully such large precipitates of alumina as
would result from the employment of as much as five grams in the case of
calcareous clay soils; while in the case of very sandy soils even that quantity
might require to be doubled in order to obtain weighable amounts of certain
ingredients. For soils in which the insoluble portion ranges from sixty to eighty
per cent, two and a half to three grams are about the right measure for general
analysis, while for the phosphoric acid determination not less than three grams
should be employed in any case. It has been alleged that larger quantities must
be taken for analysis in order to secure average results. It is difficult to see why
this should be true for soils and not for ores, in which the results affect directly
the money value, while in the case of soils the interpretation of results allows
much wider limits in the percentages. Correct sampling must be presupposed to
make any analysis useful; but with modern balances and methods it is difficult to
see why five grams should be employed instead of half that amount, which in
some cases is still too much for convenient manipulation of certain precipitates.
The weighed quantity, usually of two to two and a half grams, is brought into a
small porcelain beaker, covered with a watch-glass, treated with eight to ten
times its bulk of hydrochloric acid of 1.115 specific gravity, and two or three
drops of nitric acid, and digested for five days over the laboratory steam-bath. At
the end of this time it is evaporated to dryness, first on the water-bath and then
on the sand-bath. By this treatment all the silica set free is rendered insoluble.
334. Provisional Method of the Official Agricultural Chemists.—
Place ten grams of the air-dried soil in a round bottom 150 to 200 cubic
centimeter bohemian flask, add 100 cubic centimeters of pure hydrochloric acid
of specific gravity 1.115, insert the stopper, wire it securely, place in a steam-
bath, and digest for thirty-six hours at the temperature of boiling water. Pour the

You might also like