Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Quarterly Journal of Speech

ISSN: 0033-5630 (Print) 1479-5779 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rqjs20

Foregrounding norms and ironic communication

David S. Kaufer & Christine M. Neuwirth

To cite this article: David S. Kaufer & Christine M. Neuwirth (1982) Foregrounding
norms and ironic communication, Quarterly Journal of Speech, 68:1, 28-36, DOI:
10.1080/00335638209383589

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00335638209383589

Published online: 05 Jun 2009.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 10

View related articles

Citing articles: 5 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rqjs20

Download by: [University of Sussex Library] Date: 30 May 2016, At: 15:39
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH,
68 (1982), 28-36

FOREGROUNDING NORMS AND IRONIC


COMMUNICATION
David S. Kaufer and Christine M. Neuwirth

R ECENT work in the pragmatics of


ironic communication has focused
primarily on classifying its interpersonal
neously "build amiable communities"
while "excluding victims." He writes,
"Even irony that does imply victims, as
uses. Theorists in literary criticism,1 in all ironic satire, is often much more
linguistic pragmatics,2 and rhetoric3 clearly directed to more affirmative
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

have noted that irony can be used in one matters."5 Perelman has also hinted at
of two ways: (1) to emphasize or rein- this double-edged character of irony,
force points before friendly audiences, noting not only that it is one species of
and (2) to attack or ridicule the opposing ridicule but also that ridicule "works
values of hostile or unsuspecting listen- toward the preservation of what is
ers. Meyers observes, "In conversational accepted."6 Kaufer has offered an analy-
use, irony serves two purposes that I can sis of this multifunctionality of ironic
ascertain from observation, one inclu- utterances by proposing that they "bi-
sive, the other exclusive. That is, some- furcate" listeners into confederates and
times irony is used to reinforce solidari- victims.7 Confederates cfosociate them-
ty, camaraderie between or among selves from the ironist's literal utterance;
members. The exclusive function serves victims associate themselves with the
to elevate the speaker's own position at literal utterance.
the expense of his hearer, via a put- Muecke pointed out that ironies can
down or a one-up ploy. It is in this latter also be used heuristically, as in Socratic
category that sarcasm belongs, as a use irony, for refuting an interlocutor's posi-
of irony for the particular purpose of tion.8 Summarizing the three principal
causing hurt." 4 communicative functions of irony,
Booth recognized that these "two Muecke notes that irony may be used as
purposes" of irony are not mutually a device to "enforce one's meaning," to
exclusive and that ironists can simulta- "attack a point of view or to expose folly,
hypocrisy, or vanity," or to "lead one's
readers to see that things are not so
Mr. Kaufer is Assistant Professor of English and
Ms. Neuwirth is a doctoral student in English, simple or certain as they seem or
Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh PA perhaps not so complex as they seem."9
15213.
These three uses of irony we call
1 Wayne C. Booth, A Rhetoric of Irony (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1974). reinforcing, ridiculing, and refutative.
2
Of course, "real world" ironies are
Alice R. Myers, "Toward a Definition of Irony," in
Studies in Language Variation, ed. R.W. Fasold multifunctional, often combining shades
(Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press), pp.
171-183. and nuances of these three functions.10
3 Chaim Perelman and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, The
5
New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation (Notre Booth, p. 28.
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1969), pp. 6 Perelman, p. 206.
205-210; David Kaufer, "Irony and Rhetorical Strate- 7 Kaufer, pp. 94-98.
gy," Philosophy and Rhetoric, 10 (1977), 90-110. 8 Douglous C. Muecke, The Compass of Irony (Lon-
4
Meyers, pp. 179-180. don: Metheun, 1969), pp. 232-233.
29
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH KAUFER AND NEUWIRTH

Although a good deal may be learned by backgrounds little girl and the event of
exploring the interaction of these ironic biting. Chafe's point is that pronominal-
functions, we shall mainly be concerned ization cannot occur unless the concept
with ironies that fall primarily into one pronominalized is foregrounded. This
category or another. One of our aims is observation, according to Chafe, ex-
to find out how ironically intended utter- plains why the third sentence is prob-
ances can be used to reinforce, ridicule, lematic: Once a concept falls out of the
or refute. We also want to know what foreground (as does little girl), it can no
properties distinguish ironies specifically longer be pronominalized without re-
tailored to one or another of these sulting in some loss of discourse coher-
different purposes. ence.
Lesgold, Roth, and Curtis13 have
I confirmed Chafe's observations in the
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

IRONY AND THE FOREGROUNDING OF laboratory by observing that subjects


NORMS take less time to understand coherent
discourses like the following fairly
Before addressing these concerns, we easily: "I am trying to find a black dog.
first must discuss a psychological process Yesterday that dog bit a little girl. She
Chafe labels "foregrounding."11 A con- was scared but wasn't hurt." Examples
cept is "foregrounded" or "in the fore- like the following cause subjects difficul-
ground" if a speaker or writer can ty: "Yesterday a black dog bit a little
assume that the audience has the concept girl. It got away and we are still trying to
actively in mind. Chafe writes, "We find it. She was scared but she wasn't
might think of what is going on in a really hurt."
discourse as if it described states and In the first discourse, a listener
events unfolding on a stage. We could evidently hears the word "she" when the
then say that at any particular point in concept little girl is foregrounded (i.e.,
the discourse there are certain things still activated in short-term memory).
which are 'on stage.' It is whatever is on Because this word-concept pairing is
stage that I am calling foregrounded."12 coreferential, the discourse is coherent.
Chafe appeals to foregrounding while In the second discourse, however, the
explaining certain semantic properties of listener hears the "she" when little girl
texts, especially pronominalization, as in is no longer "activated." The lack of a
the following text: "Yesterday I saw a foregrounded antecedent results in the
little girl get bitten by a dog. I tried to loss of some coherence—and this, appar-
catch the dog but it ran away. The little ently, inhibits processing of the second
girl was scared but she wasn't hurt." discourse.
Chafe observes that the first sentence Our interest in foregrounding, howev-
foregrounds the concepts /, little girl, er, is not tied to issues of discourse
dog, and the event of biting. The second coherence per se, but rather to the role
sentence keeps / and dog "on stage" but this process seems to play in ironic
communication. As a basis of non-ironic
9 Ibid.
10 contrast, consider that the most direct
See, for example, Booth's extended discussion of
Swift's irony in "A Modest Proposal," pp. 105-123. route to foregrounding information is to
11 Wallace Chafe, "Discourse Structure and Human
13
Knowledge," in Language Comprehension and the Alan M. Lesgold, Steven F. Roth, and Mary E.
Acquisition of Knowledge, ed. R.O. Freedle and J.B. Curtis, "Foregrounding Effects in Discourse Compre-
Carroll (New York: Winston, 1972), pp. 41-69. hension," Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
l2
Ibid., p. 50. Behavior, 18 (1979), 291-308.
30
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH FEBRUARY 1982

mention it. We notice that the dog wants evaluation. A utters "the keys are not on
to leave the house. We plan that a the table," to B in a context where both
listener near the door will open it if we know it was B's responsibility that the
can foreground this information. We keys be there. Here A's statement
utter "the dog wants to leave," and mentions neither a norm nor norm viola-
thereby foreground this information. tion but contextually implies the latter,14
Because of its conventional use as a which is a less direct and non-ironic
foregrounding strategy, let us think of route to norm foregrounding.
explicit mention as the prototypical fore- Second, then, we can identify "viola-
grounding mechanism. tive" routes in which the speaker fore-
Ironists seem to exploit a type of fore- grounds norms by violating them.
grounding strategy that is both less Suppose a librarian happens to notice a
direct and more restricted than the patron conversing in a "talking forbid-
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

prototype. Ironic foregrounding is less den" section of the library. We can


direct than explicit mention in that the expect the patron's violation to fore-
ironist implies but does not say what she ground conventional norms of silence
or he wants foregrounded. There must, which the librarian invokes when taking
of course, be some inferential link action to correct the patron's behavior.
between what the ironist says and what Ironic foregrounding of norms relies
is foregrounded. The listener's task in on a combination of both applicative and
understanding an irony is to discover violative routes: the ironist foregrounds
this link. The ironist's task is to put the norms, intending to apply them, by
listener on the right trail of discovery. pretending to violate them. Conversely,
But ironic foregrounding is also more perceiving irony requires that one rein-
restricted than explicit mention for, as terpret what initially seems a speaker's
we shall argue, the ironist can put the violation of norms as a deliberate,
listener on the right trail of discovery although indirect, application. What
only by inferentially foregrounding clues does a listener use to direct this
norms. We must parcel out nonironic reinterpretation? Two important ones
and ironic routes a speaker may take seem to be the listener's recognition that
when foregrounding norms. (1) both violating and applying norms
First, we can identify "applicative" imply their being foregrounded; and (2)
routes to norm foregrounding. These wanting the norms both foregrounded
refer to the straightforward application and applied is consistent with the speak-
of norms a speaker makes when issuing er's rhetorical purposes.
a literal evaluative utterance. A speaker For example, when Shakespeare has
tells a companion, "The movie was Antony say, "Brutus is an honorable
fantastic!" and thereby foregrounds man," the audience knows full well that
norms about good movies by issuing a Brutus has failed to meet Antony's stan-
predication which conventionally ap- dards of honorability and recognizes that
plies them. Norms are also straightfor- he is violating his own norms. But the
wardly "applied" when the evaluation is audience also recognizes that it would be
negative. A speaker says, "the weather is consistent with Antony's rhetorical pur-
miserable," and thereby applies a norm
of beautiful weather by suggesting that 14
For an insightful discussion of how seemingly "val-
the present weather fails to meet it. ue-neutral" statements can contextually imply the
application of strong evaluative norms, see William
Norms can be applied even when the Labov and David Fanshel, Therapeutic Discourse (New
surface utterance does not look like an York: Academic Press, 1977), pp. 71-110.
31
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH KAUFER AND NEUWIRTH

pose to foreground these norms to apply and transparency.15 For it may well be
them against Brutus. What Antony that ironies work more effectively within
presents as a violation of transparent tight-knit groups in which group stan-
norms can thus be reinterpreted as a dards are highly transparent than within
deliberate application of them. Hence, loosely defined social practices. It may
knowing that a speaker has a rhetorical well be that it is easier to carry out ironic
purpose consistent with foregrounding a masquerades when acting out an imper-
norm in order to apply it, a listener can sonal role standard (e.g., mimicking the
reinterpret a speaker's apparent norm President of the United States) than
violation as an unstated application. when acting in institutions, like li-
braries, where .regulations are rigidly
II enforced.
Our purpose is not to develop a
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

NORMATIVE APPLICATIONS AND


TYPES general classification of norms, but
rather a theory of how norms effectively
As just argued, the ironist's transpar- figure in the three uses of irony
ent violation of norms is only a pretense, discussed in the literature. To this end,
an ostensible violation that thinly we need only reduce the vagueness
disguises a genuine application. Yet it is enough to address two problems. First,
clear that not all actions easily submit to although we have established that norms
this kind of masquerade. Return for a can be foregrounded either through
moment to our librarian example. application or violation, we still need to
Suppose the conversing patron had understand what it is about norms that
pleaded "irony" in defense of his or her makes them contextually violable or
action. The defense might go something applicable in the first place. Second,
like this: "There is no reason to scold me while we cannot possibly survey the
for talking. My conversing, after all, was various notions (i.e., regulation, stan-
only a pretended violation of the rules. dard, etc.) that seem to divide norms by
Indeed when I was talking, I was merely type, we must nonetheless come up with
ironically ridiculing people who always an understanding of "normative type"
talk in libraries!" This defense would that is meaningful for distinguishing our
surely be unconvincing, but why? Why three ironic uses.
is it that some sorts of evaluative behav- As for the contextual applicability/
ior are more easily feigned than others, violability of norms, we follow Taylor
and thus more ripe for ironic masquer- and Toulmin's association of norms with
ade? This is far from a trivial problem, context-sensitive argumentative war-
one that would involve us in a discussion rants used to justify evaluative or
of the relative transparency and rigidity prescriptive statements.16 Suppose a
of norms across different social contexts. shopper in a fruit market says of an
A related problem concerns the vague- apple on display, "it's green," meaning
ness of the concept of norm and the
cluster of notions associated with it: 15
Bach and Harnish offer a nice preliminary effort
personal standards, social norms, social toward such a sorting. Kent Bach and Robert M.
regularities, social standards, practices, Harnish, Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts
(New York: M.I.T. Press, 1979), pp. 267-283.
rules, role standards, group standards, 16
Paul W. Taylor, Normative Discourse (Westport:
and so on. It is likely that sorting Greenwood Press, 1961), pp. 3-59; Stephen Toulmin,
through these notions would bring us to Richard Rieke, and Allan Janik, An Introduction to
Reasoning (New York: Macmillan, 1979), pp. 309-
a fuller understanding of norm rigidity 337.
32
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH FEBRUARY 1982

that the apple is unripe and not fit for As for norm types, we need only make
buying. According to Taylor, one must one division between substantive and
logically distinguish the evaluative state- formal norms. Substantive norms refer
ment ("it's green"), the attitude ex- to norms which offer positive directives
pressed (against buying the apple), and like "brush your teeth three times a
the norm used to justify the implied day," or "vote communist." Formal
attitude (one should not buy green norms, on the other hand, refer to norms
apples).17 This example typifies the which do not in themselves commit one
general relationship among norms, atti- to a substantive content but which
tudes, and evaluative statements: Evalu- instead are directives for assessing
ative statements and the pro- or con- normative and even nonnormative sys-
attitudes they imply are justified by tems. Formal norms include norms of
norms. consistency, coherence, and so on. Iron-
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

The distinction between norms and ies used to reinforce or ridicule fore-
attitudes is important because irony ground substantive norms, but in rein-
could not work as a communicative forcement the foregrounded norms are
device if it were merely the expression of shared, in ridicule they are not; refuta-
obviously insincere attitudes. If one is tive ironists, on the other hand, fore-
known to like the color blue and then ground shared formal norms.
happens to utter, "I don't like blue," it is
clear that we might recognize the
Ill
speaker as deliberately insincere, but we
FOREGROUNDING AND THREE IRONIC
would hardly recognize him or her as
USES
ironically applying the genuine attitude
(the liking of blue) to the evaluation of Now that we have some notion of the
anything. While one can avow or disa- particular foregrounding mechanism by
vow attitudes, one cannot apply them in which ironists communicate irony, we
the service of justifying an evaluation. address our second question: How can
Norms do justify evaluations, howev- this mechanism be exploited in the
er, and their applicability as justifica- service of the distinct rhetorical purposes
tions is contextually triggered. That is to associated with reinforcement, ridicule,
say, norms are generally contextually and refutation? In what follows we
enforced without explicitly being put consider the relationship of foreground-
into force. Although the ironist gives the ing to each of these purposes.
appearance of contradicting a norm, this Ironic Reinforcement: Foregrounding
appearance is invariably set against a Shared Substantive Norms. Muecke
background where there is an overriding offers the following description of how
justification to apply it. The only reinforcing ironies work: "Such irony
"pointed" information the ironist com- works by asserting a "falsehood" and
municates is that the background is of relying upon the reader's or listener's
this particular sort. Once the audience prior knowledge of the truth to contra-
understands this information, it will dict it mentally or vocally by an
know that the literal utterance is not emphatic counter-assertion, the counter-
being used to alter the background but assertion with all its emphasis being the
rather to activate the norms already in ironist's real meaning.18 In our terms,
force. the reinforcing ironist issues a norm-
17 l8
Taylor, pp. 5-15. Muecke, p. 51.
33
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH KAUFER AND NEUWIRTH

violating utterance to signal his/her ridicule are varied and complex, often
application of the norm. Of course, for involving ironically knowledgeable as
the ironist to pursue a strategy of rein- well as ironically naive listeners, we
forcement rather than simple emphasis, limit this discussion to two contrasting
she or he must make sure that the norms types of ridiculing ironists.
on which the irony will turn are shared. 1. Ironists who ridicule listeners who
Let us say that both A and B do not subscribe to but fail to conform to
want it to rain on a particular day and commonly held norms. Ironists use this
each knows the other has this preference. type of ridicule correctively—as a way of
It rains on the day in question and A correcting in-group cohorts whose be-
says to B: "Lovely day.'" B recognizes havior has lapsed from orthodox values.
A's utterance as a violation of norms. Suppose A is driving carelessly and
This recognition in turn brings into the nearly causes an accident. B, a passen-
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

foreground (for B) the norms (of beauti- ger, sarcastically utters, "Smooth move!"
ful weather) violated. But B can also If we assume that A and B both under-
recognize that it is consistent with A's stand A's driving to be reckless, there is
rhetorical purpose that A should fore- no reason to consider B as excluding A
ground these norms anyway—so as to from an "in group." Rather, B seems to
apply them at the expense of the current assume that A shares his/her standards
weather. B thus uses this information of good driving, but nonetheless ridicules
about A's rhetorical purposes to inter- A for acting like a person who does not
pret A as applying a norm by pretending hold these standards.
to violate it. In addition, A is applying How through foregrounding mecha-
B's norms as well. Because A fore- nisms does A understand B's irony as
grounds a substantive norm to which B ridicule? Much of it has to do with
agrees, A's irony has a reinforcing func- timing. Because they know one another's
tion beyond its communicative one. norms for good driving, A will under-
Ironic Ridicule: Foregrounding Non- stand B's remark as irony in the manner
Shared Substantive Norms. Ironies serve one would understand a reinforcing
a ridiculing function when made in the irony. But (A might reason), why does B
environment of listeners or third parties pick this moment to reinforce values—
who either do not subscribe or conform the monent when I have seemed to lapse
tö the norms foregrounded by the ironist. from them. The timing suggests that B's
We are less likely to find such ridiculing attempted reinforcement is not gratu-
ironies in the discussion of noncontro- itous, that B may think A needs such
versial topics (like weather) and more reinforcement. To suggest that one needs
likely to find them in the discussion of reinforcing in a value to which one is
controversies where competing value intrinsically committed can be taken as a
systems emerge. Seldom do we find ridi- form of ridicule.19 A can thus interpret
culing ironies that do not also reinforce the irony as being both reinforcing and
the values of an "in group" audience. ridiculing.
The ironist's intent will be to reinforce 2. Ironists who ridicule listeners or
the values of some listeners and ridicule
19 Labov and Fanshel describe in great detail how
the opposing values of other listeners or suggestions of this kind can be interpreted as ridiculing
third parties. However, as we see below, challenges. See Therapeutic Discourse, pp. 93-98. Note
sometimes the same listener can be ironi- that had B said something like, "Gee, you should be
more careful," the sense of ridicule would have been
cally reinforced and ridiculed. reduced. B's statement would have functioned more to
While the situations fostering ironic caution A than to question his/her norms.
34
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH FEBRUARY 1982

third parties who do not share their tive norms to which one does not whole-
values. Perelman observes, "A statement heartedly subscribe.
is ridiculous as soon as it conflicts, with- We can however further elaborate the
out justification, with an accepted opin- way ridicule is ironically conveyed by
ion."20 In this sense, ironists often delib- considering another feature associated
erately voice "ridiculous" views before with the ironic foregrounding of norms:
in-groups in an attempt to ridicule the implicit value hierarchies. Let us refer to
views of out-groups. Imagine a Demo- the values the ironist applies as the
cratic speaker quipping in a politically ironist's "applied values." Let us refer to
mixed gathering: "The Republicans the (contrary) values implied by the
really care about welfare." The listeners ironist's pretended violation as the "pre-
will fall into an assortment of groups tended values." Then the implicit value
depending upon their awareness of the hierarchy associated with the ironic fore-
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

speaker's real values as well as their grounding of norms can be stated this
political affiliations. way: An ironist presupposes that his/
The groups who do not recognize the her applied values override the pre-
irony will falsely assume that the tended ones.
speaker has avowed Republican norms This hierarchy is illustrated most
when in fact s/he has only pretended to clearly when it is uncontested. Suppose
avow them. They will react to the irony one were to say, "drink diet soda and
as if it were a sincere utterance. Of the you'll be the leanest patient on the
groups who do recognize the irony, all cancer ward." Here it is clear that the
will likely construe it as reinforcing for ironist erects a value hierarchy that
the Democrats and ridiculing for the undermines the imperative plea to drink
Republicans. The irony-sensitive listen- diet soda. The pretended values asso-
ers, further, are likely to put an addi- ciated with drinking diet soda (weight
tional subjective interpretation on the control) are obviously overridden by the
utterance depending upon whether they applied values (cancer control). When
are Republicans or Democrats. If they expecting a listener to understand an
are Democrats, they may well be irony, an ironist often assumes that these
disposed to see the utterance as a proper value rankings are obvious to the listen-
attack on the hypocrisy of Republicans er. If they were not obvious, a listener
who pay lip service to social welfare might reason, how could the speaker
programs. expect me to recover the irony?
If they are Republicans, they may be Similarly, by constructing implicit
more disposed to regard the irony as-a hierarchies that are not obvious or above
real violation of Republican norms—for, controversy, an ironist can nonetheless
these listeners may reason, Republicans convey the impression that she or he
do in fact care about social welfare. Of thinks they are. Returning then to our
course, the Republicans in the audience earlier example, should a speaker build
will still understand the irony as implicit hierarchies that presume Demo-
intended ridicule even if they readily cratic values override Republican, (i.e.,
concede that social welfare is low on social welfare overrides national de-
their list of priorities. One will under- fense), the speaker will be understood as
stand a statement as ridicule, in other ridiculing a Republican with reverse
words, merely if it foregrounds substan- value rankings. The ridicule will derive
from the speaker's mimicry of the
20
Perelman, p. 206. Republicans; but it will also derive from
35
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH KAUFER AND NEUWIRTH
the fact that in mimicking Republicans, discomfited as to recant their views—but
the speaker will be implying that the it may provoke them, and is specifically
Democratic priorities are self-evident designed to provoke them, to rethink
and need no explicit justification. their position more critically, with an
Ironic Refutation: Foregrounding eye to filling in missing premises. For
Shared Formal Norms. We have thus far instance, if the ironic refutation is
seen that to understand an irony, one competently executed, the pro-abortion-
must perceive the ironist as attempting ists may feel obliged to specify more
to apply certain norms by pretending to carefully the distinction they believe
violate them. To appreciate or agree to obtains between human and fetal life.
an irony, one must agree with the ironist Refutative ironies of this sort are
that the norms she or he applies override designed not to ridicule but to open
the pretended norms. Like the ridiculing minds and deepen understandings. Iron-
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

ironist, the refutative ironist applies ists who play by such subtle rules are
norms which she or he believes to over- often admired for loosening zealots from
ride the norms of the opponent. Unlike intransigent positions, but they are also
the ridiculing ironist, however, who feared, as the Greeks feared Socrates for
applies substantive norms to attack the loosening upstanding citizens from cul-
opponent's, the refutative ironist applies turally sanctioned values. Refutative
formal norms. ironies can also be used to investigate
Accordingly, the refutative ironist will one's own positive norms under the
try to represent the views of a positive rubric of self-reflective irony or the
system as sympathetically as possible— Socratic examination of assumptions. In
only to show that the views in question such cases, the ironist reasons about his
betray real or prima facie incompatibili- or her position from the premise that
ties. Consider such an ironist who, incompleteness and inconsistency are
speaking among pro-abortionists, par- bound to appear. Unlike reinforcing or
rots their concerns by expressing a ridiculing ironists who wish to fore-
"fear" that the anti-abortionists have not ground substantive norms for friends or
demonstrated sufficient concern for "hu- foes, refutative ironists wish to fore-
man life." The ironist may then run ground formal norms for anyone's,
down a bill of particulars on the insensi- including their own, benefit.
tivities of anti-abortionists toward the
lives of women (forced to resort to illegal
abortions) as well as toward the lives of IV
unwanted children. However, in all this, Our task has been to bridge prior
the ironist's principle aim may be just to classificational work on the functions of
foreground the norm "protection of ironic communication with a discussion
human life" as the key vantage from of general processes underlying them.
which to assess the issue. We have argued that these general
This foregrounding strategy reflects processes consist in the foregrounding of
the speaker's gamble that open-minded norms whereby a speaker applies a
advocates of abortion will not fail to see norm in a certain context by pretending
the curious position into which they fall to violate it. We have sought to account
when prompted to defend abortion for differences in a range of well-known
under the banner of protecting human ironic strategies by citing differences in
life. Even if the gamble succeeds, it is not the type and interpersonal significance
likely that the audience will be so of the norms ironically foregrounded.
36
QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF SPEECH FEBRUARY 1982

We suggested that ironies play a rein- turn. We also have a long way to go in
forcing role relative to listeners who refining the classification of ironic func-
agree with the substantive norms fore- tions, and until reinforcing, ridiculing,
grounded; a ridiculing role relative to and refutative ironies are analyzed in
listeners who dissociate themselves from more detailed and elaborate contexts
these norms; and a refutative role rela- categories will remain imprecise. There
tive to listeners who associate themselves are no doubt hundreds of subfunctions
with a positive system overridden by within these functions. Many subfunc-
formal norms ironically foregrounded. tions are so context-dependent as to
As one might glean from our review of interest only the topical critic. Others
literature, we have a long way to go may be of genuine theoretical interest,
before we can establish a systematic clas- requiring us to extend our basic concep-
sification of "ironic" contexts and the tion of how irony works as a tool of
Downloaded by [University of Sussex Library] at 15:39 30 May 2016

principles of rhetoric on which they rhetoric.

You might also like