Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

Aisthesis Firenze University Press

www.fupress.com/aisthesis

Intercorporeality in virtuality: the encounter


with a phantom other*
Citation: A. Battán Horenstein, M.C.
Garavito, V. Cohen (2023). Intercorporeal-
ity in virtuality: the encounter with a
phantom other. Aisthesis 16(1): 73-83. Ariela Battán Horenstein1, María Clara Garavito2, Veronica Cohen3
doi: 10.36253/Aisthesis-14362 1 Institutode Humanidades-CONICET-Universidad Nacional de Córdoba
2 Institutode Investigaciones Filosóficas-Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México
Copyright: © 2023 A. Battán Horenstein,
3 Universidad Nacional de las Artes
M.C. Garavito, V. Cohen. This is an
open access, peer-reviewed article arielabattan@gmail.com; mcgaravitog@unal.edu.co; verocohenwil@gmail.com
published by Firenze University Press
(http://www.fupress.com/aisthesis) and
distributed under the terms of the Cre- Abstract. We use phenomenology to reflect on the experience of being with others as
ative Commons Attribution License, mediated by screens through videoconferencing platforms, a phenomenon accelerated
which permits unrestricted use, distri- by the Covid-19 pandemic and social isolation measures. We explore two directions to
bution, and reproduction in any medi- explain the intersubjective experience of a videoconference. One direction introduces a
um, provided the original author and
conceptual background based on previous contributions in phenomenology, while the
source are credited.
other one is more speculative: we introduce the novel idea of a phantom other. First,
Data Availability Statement: All rel- we understand this phenomenon either as a correlate of image consciousness or as a
evant data are within the paper and its paradoxical perception. Then, we introduce the phantom other using ideas offered in
Supporting Information files. phenomenological descriptions in which the phantom limb appears as a quasi-pres-
ence. The phantom other is the same flesh and blood body with whom I co-consti-
Competing Interests: The authors
tute senses of the world. In a videoconference, the other appears as a whole body with
have declared that no competing inter-
ests exist.
which I coordinate, although she appears as a phantom other.

Keywords: intercorporeality, phantom limb, quasi-presence, lived body, virtuality.

INTRODUCTION1

The social isolation measures that were imposed by governments


across nearly the entire globe due to the COVID-19 pandemic
caused a worldwide acceleration of digital literacy and a migration

* Ariela Battán’s contribution to this research is part of the “Fenomenología


del cuerpo y experiencias de gozo”, Ministerio de Economía, Industria y Com-
petitividad”, España (PID 2021-123252 NB-100) and “Experiencia y Lenguaje”,
SECyT, Universidad Nacional de Córdoba.
Maria Clara Garavito’s contributions to this research is part of the Postdoc-
toral Fellow in the Scholarship Program at UNAM’s Institute for Philosophical
Research, advised by Dr. Edgar González Varela.
1 We want to thank Marco Dozzi for proofreading the article. Also, we would

like to express our gratitude to the reviewers for their insightful comments on
our article.

Aisthesis. Pratiche, linguaggi e saperi dell'estetico 16(1): 73-83, 2023


ISSN 2035-8466 (online) | DOI: 10.36253/Aisthesis-14362
74 Ariela Battán Horenstein, María Clara Garavito, Veronica Cohen

of a good part of our social and community life to tivize apocalyptic forecasts which predicted that
virtual environments2. With unusual speed, elder- lack of affectivity would lead to a dehumanized
ly people who had never used a cell phone were present and a future of solipsistic egos secluded
making video calls, teachers at all levels were giv- behind screens. As a result of this descriptive pro-
ing classes using online platforms, and some of us cess, we arrived at the concept of the “phantom
were taking virtual classes. other”. In what follows, we propose to explore this
As phenomenologists living under such cir- concept by proceeding in two directions. Through
cumstances (i.e.: getting accustomed to using a programmatic approach, we consider the rele-
Google Meet, Zoom, Skype, and WhatsApp for vance of conceptual and descriptive tools provided
communicating with family, friends, and stu- by phenomenological analysis to account for the
dents), countless questions and philosophical que- phenomenon of the encounter with the other in
ries arose. In this context, we began to meet vir- a virtual situation. In so doing, initially we main-
tually, thereby combining philosophical reflection tain that the intersubjective relationship mediated
and lived experience. Taking into consideration by screens seems a sort of a paradoxical percep-
the relevant aspects of this phenomenon (virtual- tion that avoids any form of reductionism. In this
ization of the meeting space, technological media- sense, the givenness of my interlocutor in a video
tion, geographical distance and temporal differ- call cannot be explained using pairs of opposites
ence, reconfiguration of affectivity, among oth- such as actual-virtual, being-appearance, or pres-
ers), we searched for phenomenological tools that ence-absence. Then, employing a more specula-
would allow us to describe and understand this tive approach, we focus on the definition of the
unexpected phenomenon. phantom other as informed by phenomenological
The phenomenal field broadened to encom- descriptions of the phantom limb (Merleau-Ponty
pass a series of new phenomena – or, more pre- [1945]; Morris [2004]; Umbelino [2019]).
cisely, old phenomena in new contexts. These
include otherness and empathy in virtuality (Fer-
encz-Flatz [2022]; Osler [2021]), extended cogni- 1. THE ENCOUNTER IN
tion, agency through technological devices (Geni- VIDEOCONFERENCING PLATFORMS:
IMAGE CONSCIOUSNESS OR PARADOXICAL
usas [2022]), screen-mediated perception, mediat-
PERCEPTION?
ed intentionality, etc. In short, we sought to apply
Merleau-Ponty’s thesis of intersubjectivity as inter-
Our point of departure is twofold: first, the
corporeality to the encounter mediated by screens
principle that «all consciousness is consciousness
through videoconferencing platforms.
of something», and second, Merleau-Ponty’s claim
Our goal was to provide a phenomenological
that consciousness is embodied and intention-
description of the experience of being with others
ally projected towards the world. According to
as mediated by digital screens. We aimed to rela-
Merleau-Ponty, «appearances are always enveloped
in me by a certain corporeal attitude» (Merleau-
2 By virtual environments, we refer to a milieu where Ponty [1945]: 356). For this reason, we do not
people interact through technological devices of audio- limit our inquiry to the domain of consciousness,
visual communication and within the framework of the but rather start from the fact of embodiment. For
screen. The setting up of a virtual milieu or environment example, when someone takes a cube and turns it
does not pre-exist the meetings stricto sensu. The milieu over in her hand, the object is perceptually given
is motivated and generated by the interaction of individu-
to her as a perspectival object, with physical char-
als and their communicational exchange. The engagement
with the virtual milieu does not imply a duplication or acteristics, values, etc. because she is an embod-
neutralization of reality. There is no conflict between vir- ied subject. However, when the interaction occurs
tuality and reality, but rather they coexist, and we dwell with human beings in flesh and blood (leibhaftig),
simultaneously in both milieus.
Intercorporeality in virtuality: the encounter with a phantom other 75

the subject identifies the other as a conscious- ly related. In image consciousness, the distinc-
ness based on their gestures and linguistic expres- tion between the material object and the image
sions. Now, if the other is seen on a screen (a fact becomes evident, whereas in perception, the
that changes the conditions of her appearance), intentional object coincides with the object that
what would be the intentional correlate of this appears. Consequently, as Álvarez Falcón holds,
consciousness in this case? In other words, what «In the image we will find a strange unreal, ficti-
would be the object toward which consciousness tious, virtual support of something that does not
is projected? Is it the computer, the screen, or the appear, because rather than being present, it is
image of the other? The myriad of possible objects represented, presentified» (Álvarez Falcón [2009]:
that are involved in this experience is only one 23-12, translation by the authors).
dimension that our analysis can address. An ade- However, to compare an image with someone
quate answer to these questions depends on ana- appearing on a screen is problematic: not only
lyzing all the aspects involved in the phenomenon. because there are remarkable differences between
We assume that during the interactions a drawing on a sheet of paper and a screen com-
through digital platforms, we meet people rather posed of pixels, but also because the other with
than a computer or a screen. Nevertheless, the whom I interact is more than an image on a
other does not appear in the same conditions and screen. Looking at the image of my grandmother
circumstances as in a face-to-face meeting. that appears on a photographic paper – a physical,
This phenomenon can be usefully approached immobile thing – is not the same experience that
by using a phenomenological conceptual frame- I have when I call her on Zoom. Something differ-
work that is based on Husserl’s reflections on ent occurs when I meet her through a videocon-
image consciousness (see Álvarez Falcón, [2009]; ference platform. Through it, we share temporality,
Boyer, [2014]). Let us briefly recall Husserl’s dis- and I resonate and interact with her movements,
tinction between intuitive presentation (percep- facial gestures, and voice.
tion) and presentification (fantasy) as it appears Even if the screen is the perceived object, the
in Phantasy, Image Consciousness, and Memory other – i.e., our interlocutor in audiovisual com-
(1980). When facing a photograph or a painting, munication – is not reducible to an object-image
it is possible to phenomenologically distinguish in Husserlian terms. Strictly speaking, the other is
three strata – or, as Husserl says, three objects: 1) not an image, but appears “in an image” by means
the physical thing or the thing-image (Bildding), of the screen. Nevertheless, it is undeniable that
2) the representative object or the object-image she is given through the pixels, and her appear-
(Bild-Objeckt) and 3) the represented object or ance does not belong to the same domain as the
subject-image (Bild-Subjekt) (Husserl [1980]: § 9, screen or the image.
64). Therefore, in the perception of a painting, for The Husserlian thematization of image con-
example, it is possible to distinguish between the sciousness can be enlightening, but it is an insuf-
picture, that is, the material object made of wood ficient tool for addressing our problem. For this
that can be hung on the wall (physical thing), the reason, we explore the possibility of considering
(pictorial) image or copy of that which is to be this perception of the other on a screen as a para-
represented (the representative object), and the doxical perception. The paradoxical perception: (i)
subject of the picture (the represented object). oscillates between the visual capture of the object
The picture (conceived as a material object) (the screen) and the perception of what appears
and the image belong to different domains. When on it (the interlocutor), (ii) is not reducible to the
the image appears, the givenness of the mate- dichotomies between actual and virtual or pres-
rial object is displaced; the object represented is ence and absence, and (iii) involves not only con-
given to consciousness as an image. Nonetheless, sciousnesses and objects but lived bodies, even if
although they are in conflict, they are intimate- they are mediated by screens.
76 Ariela Battán Horenstein, María Clara Garavito, Veronica Cohen

We rely on González-Guardiola’s (2019) phe- not corporeally present here and now, but which
nomenology of specular reflection to elucidate depends on the subject’s corporeal presence.
these three points. Relying on the Husserlian the- González-Guardiola adds:
ory of image consciousness, González-Guardiola
describes the ordinary action of looking into a What is intentionally aimed at by both objects (the
mirror. In this action, both a body in a vertical image and the reflection) supposes absolutely differ-
position and a flat, perpendicularly placed mir- ent modalities of ‘aiming’ in both cases: the image
ror are involved: «the mirror replicates the move- will continue to exist as a spatiotemporal object that
exists independently of the positionality and mobil-
ments of our body when the body is visually ori-
ity of my body and of any other body, while the
ented towards it» (González-Guardiola [2019]:
existence of the reflection depends on the position-
256, translation by the authors). Thus, it is possi-
ality and mobility of the body (González-Guardiola
ble to distinguish four components of this expe- [2019]: 261, translation by the authors).
rience: (i) the reflecting body that must comply
with the conditions of verticality and perpen- To summarize, González-Guardiola’s analy-
dicularity, (ii) the image reflected on the mirror sis offers us at least three significant elements to
or reflected body, (iii) the mirror surface, that is, understand the phenomenon of intersubjectiv-
the material thing and (iv) the intentional con- ity in virtual encounters: first, the comprehension
sciousness that carries out the synthesis of these of the particular object through which a specu-
elements in the experience. González-Guardiola lar reflection exists, i.e., as a perceptual non-real
argues that we experience the synchronization of object; second, the overcoming of the presence-
these heterogeneous aspects every morning when absence dichotomy; and third, the close link
we groom ourselves. between specular reflection and the body.
For González-Guardiola, the Husserlian Here we finally reach the central assump-
scheme of image consciousness does not explain tion that is necessary to understand what is given
the specular reflection because it is a discordant through the screen: as in specular reflection, the
phenomenon that is difficult to conceive as an body plays a crucial role in videoconferencing.
image. According to González-Guardiola, Hus- The orientation of participants’ bodies in a video
serl prefers to explain the specular reflection as call as well as their gestures, movements and bod-
an illusion-object (Illusionäre-Objekt) rather than ily intentionalities shape the entire experience.
as an image-object. The illusion-object is seen as The analysis of specular reflection shows that
the correlate of a perceptual act (instead of an act there is a close link between the body and the
of image-consciousness). This is, undoubtedly, reflective object (the mirror). The subject’s place
the most significant contribution to our work: and position determine the whole perceptual field:
«the specular reflection is constantly perceived as for instance, being in an upright position in front
a reflection (illusion-object), which means that of the mirror. In addition, the perceptual field has
it is perceived as cancelled from the surround- a privileged visual direction (from the subject to
ing world of real bodies, but at the same time it the reflected image and the mirror that reflects
is among them, it is relative to its background» her) because the body is a point of orientation.
(González-Guardiola [2019]: 260, translation by In the context of video calls, we can identify the
the authors). same components interacting in a more complex
Considering the specular reflection as an manner. During a video call, we interact with
object that dwells among real objects despite its another person (or persons) through a screen.
irreality seems more appropriate to character- Despite the fact that we can see our own image in
ize the corporeal presence of the other during a the screen as in a mirror, the intersubjective expe-
videoconference. The idea of specular reflection rience, the engagement with another person, is
alludes to the non-present – that is, to what is more than a reflection or mirroring. However, we
Intercorporeality in virtuality: the encounter with a phantom other 77

also observe that the directions of attention – far goes from the subject to the object: if we close
from being reduced to the object seen within the our eyes or put our hands at rest, the interaction
limits of the screen – are multiple and manifold. with the computer stops. Moreover, when we meet
Consequently, the perceptual directions are: from another, although we make use of the mouse or
the subject to the other through the screen and even the keyboard, these are hidden behind the
vice versa, from the subject to the screen, from expressive and communicative intention that takes
both participants looking at themselves while they place in the situation at hand. During the interac-
look at each other, from the participants to the tion with the other we watch and recognize her as
objects, landscapes or spatial horizons that stand the recipient of our voice, as an interlocutor of our
in the background of the interlocutors, etc. The ideas, as a correlate of our affectivity, as a threat to
incorporation of a screen within an intersubjec- our intimacy, etc. In the intersubjective relation-
tive experience increases the phenomenon’s com- ship mediated by screens, movements resemble
plexity. However, that is not only due to the tech- the gestures of a musician. In this sense, the com-
nological device: rather, it is a consequence of the puter is more like a musical instrument than an
fact that we are, as Merleau-Ponty says in Signs, object of technological use since it seems to elicit
«an animal of perceptions and movements called what Merleau-Ponty calls «gestures of consecra-
body» (Merleau-Ponty: [1964]: 204). It is the body tion» (Merleau-Ponty [1945]: 147). These are the
that shapes the world, and this implies that «[...] gestures that the musician performs in front of
my experience opens onto things and transcends the instrument and which, far from any automa-
itself in them because it always accomplishes itself tism, «[...] put forth affective vectors, they discover
within the framework of a certain arrangement emotional sources, and they create an expressive
with regard to the world that is the definition of space» (Merleau-Ponty [1945]: 147).
my body» (Merleau-Ponty [1945]: 317). Although the gestures and movements carried
The arrangement of my body intention- out for another in front of a screen have the same
ally projected onto the screen contributes to the anatomical or physiological constitution as those
appearance of the other as a pole, as another we carry out when writing or reading, they do not
“me” to whom I address myself and from whom I bounce off the illuminated surface of the comput-
expect a response. Just as the action of grooming er, nor do they disappear into it; rather, they seem
myself and the movement associated with it “vivi- to extend beyond it to resonate with our own
fies” the reflected image (so to speak) while syn- body. Gestures communicate, they express mean-
chronizing it with the action of the real body, the ings and embody them – which is why video calls
movement of my body through meaningful ges- were a highly effective palliative during the pan-
ticulation solicits the other, asks for a gesture from demic (to the point that health professionals used
the other: not as imitation, but as creation –as the them with patients in intensive care).
expression of an existence.
In the experience of being with others in a vir-
tual situation, we recognize a different modality 2. PHANTOM LIMB AND QUASI-PRESENCE
of attention and bodily intentionality that differs
So far, we have referred to the specific charac-
from our posture when engaged in the act of read-
teristics of the intersubjective relationship in the
ing or writing in front of a screen. When we read
virtual encounter. Through the screen, the other
or write, corporeal intentionality brings the object
appears not as a simple image, but as an embodied
into existence through habits and as an extension
subject, someone who interacts with me. However,
of my being in the world. We can lose ourselves
this relationship requires further analysis since,
in reading or feel as if the ideas that we generate
although based on a “face-to-face” encounter, the
on the screen reside in our fingers. In both cases,
body of the other is given in a peculiar way. For
however, the direction of attention irremediably
78 Ariela Battán Horenstein, María Clara Garavito, Veronica Cohen

this analysis, our premise is that intersubjectivity tions – whether they be actual, virtual – resides in
is intercorporeality; consequently, we must specify this body that is projected towards its tasks:
how the corporeal dimension of the other is given
in the virtual encounter. We start with the notion The body is the vehicle of being in the world and,
of phantom limb as it is used by Merleau-Ponty in for a living being, having a body means being unit-
Phenomenology of Perception, because we find the ed with a definite milieu, merging with certain pro-
idea of a phantom body (or part of a body) to be jects, and being perpetually engaged therein. (Mer-
leau-Ponty [1945]: 84).
illuminating for understanding intercorporeality
in videoconferencing experiences3.
So, what happens when a member of this
Merleau-Ponty turns to the phenomenon of
organized totality is immobilized or amputated?
phantom limb in his critique of the definition
Does the world mute its solicitation and things
of the body as a collection of parts mechanically
cease to be projects or tasks to be carried out for
related to each other. His review of the principles
the subject? The answer to these questions leads
of mechanistic physiology allows him to introduce
to Merleau-Ponty’s reflection on phantom limb –
the idea of a lived body. Instead of experiencing
that is to say, on the limb that refuses to withdraw
the body as a set of parts, the body is consciously
from the project, to be forgotten or to remain use-
given as a totality in which some sensitive areas
less. Furthermore, this phenomenon confirms
are predominant or retained according to the tasks
that the body is thrown into the world; or rather,
one performs and one’s intentional projection
that its existence depends on the solicitations of
towards a world that solicits them. Merleau-Ponty
the world. For Merleau-Ponty, the appearance of
states that «my body is wherever it has something
a phantom limb makes sense in the field of sedi-
to do» (Merleau-Ponty [1945]: 260) – which is to
mentations by which the world is given. Because
say that the body is intentional, thrown into the
the lived body of an amputee relied upon the
world: it constitutes the world for itself, and in
amputated limb to project itself intentionally upon
this it is itself constituted as a constitutive total-
the world prior to losing it, it continues to include
ity. Furthermore, the power both to attach instru-
the amputated limb as a part of itself. Now, what
ments to oneself (with an existential significance
does it mean, phenomenologically speaking, to say
through habit) and to mobilize oneself in situa-
that the subject continues to count on that ampu-
tated limb? If, as Merleau-Ponty says, the ampu-
3 The goal of this article is to conduct a review of the tated limb appears insofar as the world continues
“phantom” in the phenomenon of quasi-presence, as to solicit it, then a name must be found for this
analyzed by Merleau-Ponty. Notably, in light of the sig- modality of presence of the limb that has already
nificant advancements in neuroscience over the last dec- been amputated and which now appears as a
ades, a vast body of literature, particularly in the work of
phantom. What allows Merleau-Ponty to escape
Vilayanur S. Ramachandran (1996, 1998), has emerged on
this topic. Ramachandran’s research focuses on the pain
from an ontological commitment to the irreduc-
patients feel in their amputated limbs and the therapeu- ible presence-absence dichotomy is the notion of
tic discoveries he has made using a “mirror box”, which quasi-presence. As Umbelino holds, the phenom-
enables patients to “observe” their amputated arm. From a enon of phantom limb shows:
contemporary phenomenological perspective, this subject
has been approached by several authors, such as Gallagher the mistake of accepting that there is a difference in
(2005), Breyer (2012), and Gallagher and Meltzoff (1996). nature between “phantom” and “real” [...] and the
In a previous work (see Battán-Horenstein [2016]), we error of presuming that, in that aporia, the “real”
have explored this approach to the phenomenology of always has primacy over the “phantom”. In this
the pain experienced in a phantom limb. However, in this sense, there is an increased relevance of the certain-
article, we aim to address a distinct issue that is related to
ty that the phantom of the absent limb is both the
the phenomenology of the phantom limb: our perception
presence (which is not present) of the lost limb, and
of the other on the screen as a quasi-presence.
Intercorporeality in virtuality: the encounter with a phantom other 79

the immemorial presence in the body of an unbro- tual spaces. As already mentioned, and following
ken spatial and temporal continuity [...] which is the Merleau-Ponty, we conceive intersubjectivity as
pre-personal body of habit (Umbelino [2019]: 87 et intercorporeality: we experience meaning through
seq., translation by the authors). the movements, actions, language, and facial ges-
tures of expressive bodies. There is a peculiar and
Merleau-Ponty uses the notion of quasi-pres- unique style of interacting with the world that is
ence to characterize the type of experience in inherent in the perception of the other in flesh
which we still expect to see a recently deceased and blood (leibhaftig). It follows that intersubjec-
friend coming through the door, or when we hear tive and intercorporeal communication are not
his or her voice. Just like the expectation of a dead based on the givenness of the other as an object,
friend, the phantom limb enters the field of qua- but rather on ways that the other copes with and
si-presence. This means that, on the one hand, its relates to the world, as well as his or her opening
presence shares the realm of the reality of what to new and unexpected meaningful experiences.
it is here and now – that is, of physical objects – A communal world is the result of encounters
while, on the other hand, it is no longer a physical among lived bodies; it is the effect of intentional
object. projections and openings of meaning developed
Merleau-Ponty’s understanding of the phe- by embodied subjects.
nomenon of phantom limb overcomes the dichot- Intentional projections and openings of mean-
omy of the “presence of a representation” and the ing carried out by the lived body that are modu-
“absence of a limb”. In his reflections, the idea of lated by one’s situation also occur in virtual
quasi-presence emerges to the extent that the encounters. The screen does not restrict the lived
amputated limb is present, but not in the way that body and what bodily intentionality constitutes.
other parts of the body are present. This type of That is why we are not only spectators of an image
presence occurs in the field of possibilities, which projected in front of us; we are in intercorporeal
is to say that it stands in direct relation to the communication with others. Through the plat-
meanings of the world in which the body is still in form, intersubjective exchanges have the following
possession of the arm. characteristics: (i) when the image is perceived, we
What aspect of Merleau-Ponty’s notion of solicit a body with which it is possible to interact.
quasi-presence helps us to understand what hap- That means that the other’s image has the power
pens in front of a screen? Is it possible to make an to affect my own experiences of the world and he
analogy between missing our deceased friend or or she can be affected by me. (ii) On the screen,
an amputated limb and the intercorporeal relation the other’s visual and audible4 appearance is relat-
that occurs in a video conference? In what follows,
we will use the notion of phantom limb as a point 4 Sound is an important aspect in “framing” and “off-
of reference in order to develop the notion of the screen” aspects of virtuality, but it would require a pecu-
“phantom other”; in turn, this will allow us to elu- liar analysis that exceeds the framework of this paper.
cidate intercorporeal experiences mediated by vid- In this context, sound is a complex phenomenon. At
eo conferencing platforms. the same time, it is not possible to completely control
off-camera sound, and audio can be cancelled by mut-
ing the microphone. By virtual environments, we refer
3. THE PHANTOM OTHER to a milieu where people interact through technologi-
cal devices of audiovisual communication and within
Even in videoconferencing platforms, the the framework of the screen. The setting up of a virtual
intersubjective encounter presupposes lived bodies milieu or environment does not pre-exist the meetings
stricto sensu. The milieu is motivated and generated by
(Leib). In other words, intersubjectivity is not an the interaction of individuals and their communicational
encounter of pure consciousnesses; rather, all bod- exchange. The engagement with the virtual milieu does
ies project meaning into the world, even in vir- not imply a duplication or neutralization of reality. Vir-
80 Ariela Battán Horenstein, María Clara Garavito, Veronica Cohen

ed to what is “framed” and what is “off-camera”. In appearance of the other, like that of the phantom
other words, the visual and audible image evokes a limb, is solicited by the situation itself; the video-
whole situation in which the other in front of me conference evokes the presence of the other body,
is embedded: for instance, a gesture by the other a body with which I coordinate, resonate, and
can be related to another person who is invisible engage in experiences of co-constituting senses
to me but is visible to the other5. of the world (Zahavi [2001]). In a way, the other
The other appearing on the screen invites us is given as an embodied subject – is in a “pre-
to attend to the multiple and varied possibilities sent body” – which implies that she is not expe-
of corporeal-being-in-the-world. Through virtual rienced as absent. However, the presence experi-
interaction, we encounter a situated other who enced during virtual encounters is distinct from
we recognize by his or her peculiar way of dealing that of face-to-face interactions, and the analogy
with the world – however she is not given in flesh of the phantom limb is a useful way to compre-
and blood, but according to the mode of a “phan- hend that virtual experience. A patient recognizes
tom other”6. that her phantom limb is not physically present
We define the phantom other as the phenom- in the same manner as her other limbs but is still
enon of the other being given in quasi-presence. perceptibly real; the phantom limb exists in the
In the same way that one’s own body is not expe- objective world, as Anabelle Dufront (2015) has
rienced as a set of parts but as a unity of con- suggested. The phantom limb is ambiguous, as
sciousness, the other’s body, when viewed through the individual acknowledges a sense of ownership
a screen, is not experienced as a visible face or in the body schema, but simultaneously lacks the
hands, but as someone who expresses intentional same level of control over it as she does with her
projections and ways in which the world appears. physical body. The limb somehow escapes con-
Furthermore, in the encounter, we do not find trol: it cannot be moved in the same way as other
ourselves as mere spectators of a way of present- limbs, and it cannot be healed like a wound on an
ing the world that is inherent in the expressivity actual hand.
and gesturality of the other’s body; rather, we find We observe a similar ambiguity in the
ourselves affected by such intentionalities. Here, encounter with others. While the other person is
quasi-presence is the result of the body’s capacity present, the level of interaction I experience is not
for intentional projection through the screen: the equivalent to that of someone sitting beside me,
whose expressions are entirely perceivable and
located within the same physical space as my own
tuality does not dispute the field of meaning with reality,
but rather they coexist, and we dwell simultaneously in body. Furthermore, I do not possess the same
both milieus. sense of ownership over her body as I do over my
5 The situation does not necessarily evoke the body in own corporeality. Despite these restrictions, being
front of me in the image, but a body in this specific situ- in front of a screen to interact with others intro-
ation: although I may never have interacted with some duces experiences of lived space, time, and body.
particular students I meet through Zoom in person, I Interaction in a virtual context determines the
have interacted with other students in a university class-
modality of givenness in which others appear as
room. With those bodies, I have constituted the spatiality
and temporality, but also affectivity, of having the expe-
perceptions.
rience of teaching a course at a university. Those experi- As we have pointed out, the other who we are
ences have sedimented, constituting the horizon of mean- interested in interacting with in the context of vir-
ings I count on, and allow me to give the name “class” to tuality is not given as an image but is more of a
a particular videoconference. paradoxical perception. Through intercorporeal
6 We have previously elaborated the notion of “phantom
affective resonance, the phantom other is what
other” (see Battán-Horenstein, Garavito, Cohen [2021a] appears in what is moving in front of me. In oth-
and [2021b]) to help us understand intersubjective
encounters in virtuality.
er words, he or she is reborn as another who we
Intercorporeality in virtuality: the encounter with a phantom other 81

recognize and in whom an affective stream finds ested in understanding affectivity as a modal-
its correlate. But how is it possible for such affec- ity of the intentionality of consciousness instead
tive resonance to take place in a virtual exchange? of as a place of understanding the other as a fel-
According to Fuchs, affective resonance is a con- low human being – that is why we see bodies as
sequence of «the way emotions disclose the affec- expressions of intentional projections, and thus as
tive qualities or affordances of a given situation» ways that the world appears in other bodies.
(Fuchs [2020]: 77) and consists of «proprioceptive We hold that intercorporeal affective reso-
and interoceptive feelings» that are aroused in the nance also arises in virtual contexts despite the
perception of other subjects and their emotional impassable limits imposed by the screen. Unlike
states. Through the notion of resonance, we con- the case of the face-to-face encounter in which
firm Merleau-Ponty’s thesis of a primary and orig- the intersubjective situation is the effect or result
inal intercorporeality. of affective resonance, affective resonance in the
However, we disagree with the way Fuchs virtual encounter is a condition of the phantom
understands virtual encounters: for him, reso- other. In other words, because there is affective
nance seems to require a complete bodily (leib- resonance – because there is a bond developed in
haftig) mediation because intercorporeal reso- the habituality of previous encounters – the other
nance would be the consequence of a (synchro- can be given in his or her quasi-presence, that is,
nous and simultaneous) interaction of subjects a presence which is neither properly real (in flesh
through their gestures and expressions. For Fuchs, and blood) nor a mere image, but rather a phan-
we experience the rage of another through both tom.
the perception of facial gestures and our intra- Like Merleau-Ponty’s notion of phantom limb,
corporeal resonance. And this resonance, which the phantom other is sustained by the habitual
is felt deep inside of us, is limited in online inter- body. The phantom other is not a second nature,
action because we cannot access the expressive- nor is it an impostor that vicariously replaces a
ness of the whole alien body; in other words, the lived body as an avatar. The phantom other is not
gesture of rage in the face is only a part of what the product of an intellectual operation, nor is it
is an embodied and situated expressiveness. Osler reducible to an image consciousness: the other
(2021) has questioned this proposal, pointing appearing on the screen enjoys all his or her sub-
out that screen-mediated relationships can be as jectivity and his or her bodily constitution despite
empathic as offline environments. Unlike Fuchs, being given to us without depth, just as a phantom
she points out that empathy occurs in interaction limb is a quasi-presence that contributes to the
with a lived body rather than a physical body, and practical interface that constitutes the conscious-
the lived body is projected through the screen: ness of our own body.
«the assumption that empathy only occurs face-to-
face rests on an unjustified restriction of expres-
sivity to the physical body» (Osler [2021]: 4). For CONCLUSIONS
her, an encounter with the other may be techno-
In this paper, we went in two directions to
logically mediated but “still direct”.
explain the intersubjective experience of a vide-
We understand intercorporeality through the
oconference. One direction introduced a con-
screen differently: while Osler and Fuchs think
ceptual background based on previous contribu-
about the conditions of the possibility of online
tions in phenomenology, while the other one was
empathy, we are more interested in the phenom-
more speculative: we introduced the novel idea
enon of intercorporeality as a coordination of
of a phantom other. First, we asked whether this
intentionalities that project and constitute senses
phenomenon should be understood either as a
of the world. Thus, intercorporeality results in
correlate of image consciousness or as a para-
more than empathic experiences. We are inter-
82 Ariela Battán Horenstein, María Clara Garavito, Veronica Cohen

doxical perception. We recognized that a virtual We have questioned two approaches to inter-
encounter cannot be understood as a correlate of subjectivity mediated by screens: Fuchs and Osler
image-consciousness, since interaction through treat intercorporeality solely as the empathic
a video conference is not a static representation encounter with an alter ego and that is why they
of the other as absent and imagined, but rather miss an important feature of intercorporeality as
a dynamic phenomenon in which the other is co-constituted sense-making. In the end, for us,
experienced as present. Moreover, the other is the phantom other shows that affectivity is the
not a paradoxical perception (such as, for exam- key to intercorporeality because it participates in a
ple, the perception of a body’s reflection in a mir- coordination of bodies through intentional projec-
ror). In a video conference, there is no encounter tions towards the world.
of a self with its reflection, but of two subjectivi-
ties that relate intercorporeally. By attending to
the case of specular reflection, we recognized that REFERENCES
the appearance of the other through videoconfer-
Álvarez Falcón, L., 2009: La «indeterminación» de
encing platforms cannot be understood in terms
la realidad: síntesis de cumplimiento y constitu-
of dualities like actual-virtual, being-appearance,
ción objetiva de lo virtual, “Eikasía. Revista de
and presence-absence.
Filosofía” IV (24), pp. 1-17.
The second direction introduced our own
Breyer, T., 2012: Das Phantom im Spiegel: Ein
approach to what occurs in videoconferencing
phänomenologischer Versuch über somatosen-
encounters. We defined the phantom other using
sorische Plastizität und Leibgedächtnis, “Inter-
ideas offered in phenomenological descriptions
nationale Zeitschrift Für Philosophie und Psy-
of phantom limb in which that limb appeared as
chosomatik” 2, pp. 308-326.
a quasi-presence. The phantom other is the same
Boyer, E., 2014: Le Conflit des perceptions, Éditions
flesh and blood body with whom we coordinate,
MF, Paris.
resonate, and co-constitute senses of the world.
Battán-Horenstein, A. 2016: Cuerpo, espejo y el
A limb appearing as a quasi-presence means that
fenómeno del miembro fantasma en la filosofía
the lived spatiality of one’s own body cannot be
de M. Merleau-Ponty, in Catoggio, L. y Parente,
reduced to a sum of organs but is the result of
D. (ed.) Merleau-Ponty: corporalidad, política y
habitualities through which one gives meaning to
otros problemas contemporáneos, Universidad
the world. If, following Merleau-Ponty, the body
de Mar del Plata, Mar del Plata, pp. 11-32.
is a being-in-the-world, then bodily experiences
Battán-Horenstein, A., Garavito, M.C y Cohen,
are linked to forms of appearance of the world.
V., 2021a: Intercorporeality in Times of Virtual
The phantom limb is an example of how the world
Encounters: The Notion of the Phantom Other,
solicits intentional projections of the body. Quasi-
The Future as a Present Concern online inter-
presence occurs when the world solicits a bodily
national conference, British Society of Phe-
configuration that includes a non-existent body
nomenology.
part, such as when it solicits an amputated organ.
Battán-Horenstein, A., Garavito, M.C y Cohen, V.,
The phantom other extends the region in which
2021b: The Phantom Other. Video Essay. htt-
the world solicits those intentionalities: sometimes
ps://vimeo.com/537923462.
it solicits intercorporeality. In a videoconference,
Dufront, A., 2015: Esquisse d’une phénoménologie
the other does not appear as having something
des fantômes. Vers une nouvelle conception du
missing, or as a set of parts, but as a whole body
réel à partir de l’analyse merleau-pontyenne du
with which we coordinate. However, this does not
membre fantôme, “Ostium, Revue Časopis des
mean that this other appears in complete pres-
sciences humaines, L’invisible et le visible (2)”,
ence: being limited by the image, she is configured
pp. 58-76.
as a phantom other.
Intercorporeality in virtuality: the encounter with a phantom other 83

Ferencz-Flatz, C., 2022: Screened Intercorporeal-


ity. Reflections on Gestures in Videoconferences,
“Journal of the British Society for Phenom-
enology” 54 (1), pp. 56-70.
Fuchs, T., 2020: Intercorporeality and interaffectiv-
ity, in Meyer, C. (ed.) Intercorporeality: Emerg-
ing Socialities in Interaction, Oxford University
Press, Oxford, pp. 3-24.
Gallagher, S., 2005: How the body shapes the mind,
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Gallagher, S. and Meltzoff, A., 1996: The Earliest
Sense of Self and Others: Merleau-Ponty and
Recent Developmental Studies, “Philosophical
Psychology” 9 (2), pp. 211-233..
Geniusas, S., 2022: What Is Immersion? Towards a
Phenomenology of Virtual Reality, “Journal of
Phenomenological Psychology” 53, pp. 1–24.
González-Guardiola, J., 2019: Fenomenología del
reflejo especular como fundamento explicativo
de la eficacia de la Caja Espejo en el tratami-
ento del dolor del miembro fantasma, “Isegoría”
60, pp. 253-270.
Husserl, E., 1980: Phantasy, Image Consciousness,
and Memory (1898-1925), Springer, New York,
2005.
Merleau-Ponty, M., 1945: Phenomenology of Per-
ception, Routledge, New York, 2012.
Merleau-Ponty, M., 1960: Signs, Northwestern
University Press, Evanston, 1964.
Morris, D., 2004: The sense of space, State Univer-
sity of New York Press, Albany.
Osler, L., 2021: Taking empathy online, “Inquiry:
An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy”
DOI: 10.1080/0020174X.2021.1899045.
Ramachandran, R.S., 1996: Synaesthesia in phan-
tom limbs induced by mirrors, “Proceedings of
The Royal Society” 263, pp. 377-386.
Ramachandran, V. S., Blackeslee, S., 1998: Phan-
toms in the Brain, William Morrow and Co.,
New York.
Umbelino, L. A., 2019: Memorabilia: o lado espa-
cial da memória (na esteira de Merleau-Ponty),
EDITUS, Iléhus.
Zahavi, D., 2001: Beyond empathy. Phenomenologi-
cal Approaches to Intersubjectivity, “Journal of
Consciousness Studies” 8 (5-7), pp. 151-167.

You might also like