Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

Chance, Indeterminacy, Multiplicity

Branden W. Joseph

My thanks to Danielle Fosler-Lussier, Chance comes in here to give us the unknown.


who graciously commented on a much
— John Cage to Pierre Boulez, January 17, 1950
earlier version of this article, and to
Rebecca Y. Kim and David W. Patterson
who equally graciously offered com-
ments on the final version. Thanks also
to Susan Roper of The Sterling and Within the legacy of John Cage, no single concept looms as large
Francine Clark Art Institute library,
who procured the materials necessary
as that of chance. Yet, despite having been invoked regularly by
for me to complete this research. art historians for almost half a century, Cage’s ideas about chance
have remained surprisingly little explored within the discipline.
Indeed, with rare exception, art historians tend to downplay Cage’s
exploration of chance as a revival of pre-war Dadaism, a quietistic
embrace of irrationality, or the source of an unacknowledged con-
flict between the composer’s endorsement of chance operations
and the highly rigorous means by which he implemented them.
Ironically, it is the very lack of specificity with which the concept of
chance has been approached that allows for its broad, if somewhat
indiscriminate, citation within art historical literature on happen-
ings and Fluxus, since nearly every artist working in these areas
engaged with chance in some manner or another. Whether lauda-
tory or dismissive, such generalizations contrast markedly not only
1. The most detailed listing of Cage’s with the specificity of Cagean chance operations, but also with the
New School courses is found in Rebecca
myriad ways in which artists received them, particularly those who
Y. Kim, In No Uncertain Musical
Terms: The Cultural Politics of John found themselves in Cage’s courses on “Composition” and “Experi-
Cage’s Indeterminacy, PhD dissertation, mental Composition” offered at the New School for Social Research
Columbia University, Department of
Music, 2008, table 3.1, pp. 133–35. between the fall of 1956 and the summer of 1960.1
A less detailed list, with errors in the
semesters of summer and fall, 1958,
appeared in Bruce Altschuler, “The In 1961, Allan Kaprow, former Cage student and the most well-
Cage Class,” in Cornelia Lauf and Susan known practitioner of happenings, would describe “the involve-
Hapgood, (eds.), FluxAttitudes, Buffalo:
Hallwalls Contemporary Arts Center, ment in chance” as neither the most important nor as the most
1991, pp. 21–22, note 2. widespread of the qualities informing the new genre of artistic
2. Allan Kaprow, “Happenings in the
performance, but rather as the “most problematical.”2 Kaprow’s
New York Scene” (1961), in Jeff Kelley, choice of adjective is apt, given the range within which Cage’s
(ed.), Essays on the Blurring of Art
and Life, Berkeley, Ca.: University of
pupils adopted, adapted, developed, and/or rejected the composer’s
California Press, 1993, p. 19. teachings with regard to chance and indeterminacy. Although

210
Kaprow, for instance, derived much from his introduction to Cage,
he largely rejected the strictness with which Cage implemented
3. Harold Rosenberg, “The American chance operations in favor of intuition and an understanding of the
Action Painters” (1952), The Tradition
of the New, New York: McGraw-Hill,
Abstract Expressionist legacy akin to its almost existentialist recep-
1959, pp. 23–39. Kaprow’s interest in tion by art critic Harold Rosenberg.3 Aspects of Kaprow’s resistance
Abstract Expressionism is, of course,
manifest in “The Legacy of Jackson
to the Cagean paradigm can be traced as far back as 1958, when he
Pollock” (1958), in Kelley, (ed.), pp. 1–9. explained that “the freest, most spontaneous and (to this writer)
most enjoyable” approach he had yet adopted in the development
4. Allan Kaprow, “One Chapter from
‘The Principles of Modern Art’,” It Is of his happenings was “just begin[ning] to imagine things, writing
No. 4, 1958, p. 52, ellipses in original. down his parts as he goes along until he decides to stop.” Reciting
On Cage’s critique of inspiration, see,
for example, John Cage, “45’ for a (and then rejecting) Cage’s already established critique of any such
Speaker” (1954), Silence, Middletown, intuitive and improvisational procedure, Kaprow continued, “when
Conn.: Wesleyan University Press,
1961, p. 170. one is left to intuition the risk is great that one becomes too depen-
dent on ‘inspiration’ (an extremely unreliable mistress) and so falls
5. Allan Kaprow, Assemblage, Environ-
ments, and Happenings, New York: into the trap of coming up constantly with clichés and habits. But
Harry N. Abrams, 1966, p. 175. Kaprow’s then, sometimes one is lucky….”4 By 1966, Kaprow would come
move away from Cage is discussed in
Jeff Kelley, Childsplay: The Art of Allan to reject Cage’s engagement with chance operations in favor of an
Kaprow, Berkeley, Ca.: University of approach he called “change,” predicated on “the following of
California Press, 2004, pp. 20–46.
intuition and wisdom” and “dependent upon human experience.”5
6. Al Hansen’s attraction to Cage’s
sense of anarchy is mentioned in
Dick Higgins, “Postface,” Jefferson’s
Like Kaprow, fellow New School classmates and future happeners
Birthday/Postface, New York: Something Al Hansen and Dick Higgins would adhere to something of an
Else, 1964, pp. 49, 51. The notion of
anarchy would also be mentioned by
existential vision of authorial risk, taking a Rosenberg-like concep-
Kaprow in notes to “A program tion of action painting into what could be called action music or
of Happenings? Events! & Situations?
Directed by Al Hansen, an eclectic,”
action theater. Hansen, for instance, embraced the anarchic side
(May 2, 1960), repr. in Hermann Braun, of Cage’s project, which he also took in a partially anti-Cagean
(ed.), George Brecht, Notebook V
direction of improvisation within chaotic and collaborative pieces
(March 1960-November 1960), Cologne:
Walther König, 1997, p. 88. On Hansen’s like his Hall Street Happening (1961; which inadvertently involved
Hall Street Happening, see Al Hansen, a performer’s falling through a skylight).6 Higgins credited Cage’s
A Primer on Happenings and Time/
Space Art, New York: Something Else course with providing “a sense of general activity and a taste for my
Press, 1965, pp. 11–20. own direction, to which previously my own skepticism had been
7. Higgins, “Postface,” pp. 50–51; very unkind,” an observation not unlike that made by Cage’s long-
Barbara Rose, An Interview with Robert time artistic colleague, Robert Rauschenberg, who called Cage “the
Rauschenberg, New York: Vintage
Books, 1987, p. 34. only one who gave me permission to continue my own thoughts.”7
Higgins, however, declared himself at odds with much of Cage’s
8. Dick Higgins, “Boredom and Danger”
(1966), A Dialectic of Centuries: Notes perspective. Moving in his own direction, Higgins transformed
towards a Theory of the New Arts, New Cage’s interest in chance – which, in French, as Higgins pointed
York: Printed Editions, 1978, pp. 48–49.
Kaprow not dissimilarly links chance
out, is “hasard” – into the notion of hazard or, more precisely,
to “risk and fear” in “Happenings in danger, which he explored in numerous compositions such
the New York Scene,” p. 19. Higgins’s
Danger Music #17 recalls Tristan
as Danger Music No. 17 (1962), the score for which reads simply,
Tzara’s “Roar,” in Robert Motherwell, “Scream! Scream! Scream! Scream! Scream! Scream!”8
(ed.), The Dada Painters and Poets:
An Anthology, New York: Wittenborn,
Schultz, Inc., 1951, p. 96; Tzara’s “poem” According to Higgins, neither he nor Hansen had much patience for
was included as part of Hansen’s Hall
Street Happening, see Hansen, A Primer,
the more detailed articles about chance operations and indetermi-
pp. 18–19. nacy Cage explicated within the course. “Once or twice,” he noted:

211
Cage read a theoretical article… the short theoretical statements from trans/
formation 2, and a (then) unpublished article by Christian Wolff on the relations
of time and sound. Some of us, particularly Hansen and myself, couldn’t for the life
of us imagine why Cage was interested in those things. They seemed so abstract,
compared with the very concrete observations that Cage favored in connection
with the pieces played in class, and so terribly old-fashioned in their implications.
9. Dick Higgins, “[On Cage’s Classes]” Mostly they read like legal contracts.9
(1970), in Richard Kostelanetz, (ed.),
John Cage: An Anthology, New York:
Praeger, 1970, p. 123 (ellipses in origi- Among Higgins’s classmates, evidently only George Brecht, who
nal). The statements Higgins seems
to be referencing appeared in trans/
had previously written a treatise entitled Chance-Imagery, shared
formation, Vol. 1, No. 3 (1952). Cage’s more theoretical leanings:
The usual format of our sessions would be that, before the class began,
Cage and George Brecht would get into a conversation, usually about “spiritual
virtuosity,” instead of the virtuosity of technique, physique, etc. This would
continue as the people arrived, then gradually expand, until the subject matter
became hard to follow.

According to Higgins, Brecht and Cage conversed at length and in


10. Ibid., pp. 122–24. intricate detail about the implications of their aesthetic research.
“Only George Brecht,” Higgins continued,
11. Altschuler, “The Cage Class,”
pp. 17–23. …seemed to share Cage’s fascination with the various theories of imperson-
ality, anonymity and the life of pieces outside of their perceivers, makers, or anyone
12. On Cage’s notion of experimenta-
tion, see, for instance, John Cage, else. For the rest of us, the main thing was the realization of the possibilities,
“Experimental Music: Doctrine” (1955), which made it easier to use smaller scales and a greater gamut of possibilities than
Silence, p. 13: “the word ‘experimental’
is apt, providing it is understood not as
our previous experience would have led us to expect.10
descriptive of an act to be later judged
in terms of success and failure, but sim-
ply as of an act the outcome of which is
Despite the fact that Cage’s students received and resisted his
unknown.” For adaptations of the idea, teachings in a variety of ways, it is not correct to conclude, as some
see Allan Kaprow, “Experimental Art”
(1966), in Kelley, (ed.), Essays, esp.
have, that Cage’s ideas had little impact or that the import of his
pp. 68–69; and Hansen, A Primer, p. 109: class was primarily that of providing an opportunity for self-direct-
“My goal now is to involve the ideas
of all my favorite people – Artaud and
ed exploration.11 Even while necessarily developing in their own
John Cage and Ray Johnson – in a total directions, Cage’s students adopted a number of distinctly Cagean
theater project in which things which categories and concepts. Both Hansen and Kaprow, for instance,
weren’t possible before will be done.”
Cage’s idea would later be adopted would later echo Cage’s notion of “experimental actions” as the
by French philosophers Gilles Deleuze pursuit and engagement with the unforeseen.12 And, even while
and Félix Guattari in Anti-Oedipus:
Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Mark rejecting Cage’s pursuit of impersonality, Higgins would adopt
Seem, Robert Hurley, and Helen R. Lane and develop an idea of “transparency” very close to that of Cage,
(trans.), Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1983, pp. 370–71. in which the structure of an artwork or performance allowed for
incorporation of external, environmental events: “…the work,”
13. Higgins, “Blank Images” (1970),
A Dialectic of Centuries, p. 78. See also wrote Higgins, “should acquire its meaning by what you can see
Higgins, “Postface,” p. 35, where he through it and how this looks in relation to the work.”13
rightly notes the relation of transpar-
ency to the work of Marcel Duchamp.
On transparency in Cage’s work, see While understanding the different ways in which Cage’s teach-
Branden W. Joseph, “John Cage and
the Architecture of Silence,” October
ings were received is important for assessing the composer’s
No. 81, Summer 1997, pp. 80–104. impact within the visual arts, equally so is comprehending the

212
Dick Higgins performing Danger Music No. 17, 1962

degree to which his own aesthetic transformed over the course


of the decade. Indeed, according to Cage, it was partially on
account of the fact that his “musical thought was changing” that
14. John Cage, “[The New School],” he decided to begin teaching at the New School.14 Although it
in Kostelanetz, (ed.), p. 119.
would not be possible even to begin to address the full range
of Cage’s artistic reception, even on the subject of chance opera-
tions alone, it will nonetheless be worthwhile, as a necessary
first step, to approach with some specificity the development of
Cage’s techniques of employing chance up through the years in
which his New School courses were offered. The results – drawn
in part from musicology and in part from heretofore unexamined
sources and resonances in the philosophy of Henri Bergson
and Gilles Deleuze – will take us far from a simple notion of chance
to a much more complex and sophisticated engagement with
indeterminacy and multiplicity. From there we will return to
the classroom to investigate further what there was to learn at
the New School from John Cage.

213
By the time Cage offered his first New School course, he had been
associated with chance operations for half a decade. Music of
Changes, Cage’s first manifesto presentation of chance, was complet-
ed in 1951 and debuted in at the Cherry Lane Theater in New York
on New Years Day, 1952. Prior to that moment, Cage’s references
to chance were somewhat occasional. In “Forerunners of Modern
Music” of 1949, Cage mentioned the way in which using “radios as
instruments” would deliver the continuity of sound production over
15. John Cage, “Forerunners of Modern to “accident.”15 Around the same time, Cage incorporated field
Music” (1949), Silence, p. 62.
recordings from Alexander Calder’s workshop into his soundtrack
for the film Works of Calder (1949–50), explaining to Pierre Boulez
that “No synchronizing was attempted and what the final result is
16. John Cage, Letter to Pierre Boulez, rather due to a chance that was admired.”16 Previously, in composi-
May 22, 1951, in Jean-Jacques Nattiez,
(ed.), The Boulez-Cage Correspondence,
tions such as Double Music (1941), in which Cage and Lou Harrison
Cambridge: Cambridge University wrote out their parts independently and then combined them,
Press, 1993, p. 93. The epigraph to this
article also refers to Cage’s soundtrack
without alteration, into the final piece, Cage courted a different
to Works of Calder and can be found type of chance, one arising from the simultaneous performance of
in John Cage, Letter to Pierre Boulez,
January 17 [1950], in Nattiez, (ed.), p. 48.
independent work (a procedure that Cage would continue to
pursue throughout many years of collaborations with dancer Merce
17. Boulez notes the resemblance of
Double Music to cadavre exquis in
Cunningham). Although the inspiration behind Double Music came
Nattiez, (ed.), p. 29; Cage’s visit to the from Cage’s interest in the anonymity of collective production,
Bauhaus is noted in Christopher Shultis,
associated with Gothic sculpture and embraced in the early Bauhaus
“Cage and Europe,” in David Nicholls,
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to (which Cage visited in 1930 or 1931), the method of combining
John Cage, Cambridge: Cambridge two entirely separate creative endeavors resembled the Surrealist
University Press, 2002, p. 22. George
Brecht invoked cadavre exquis in regard parlor game cadavre exquis (exquisite corpse) in which a drawing or
to Cage’s “Music for Four Pianos,” poem is composed by different individuals unaware of each other’s
eighty-four independent compositions
(many composed via methods involving efforts.17 A few years later, Cage, Harrison, Henry Cowell, and
chance, although Brecht does not men- Virgil Thompson would explicitly take up the Surrealist method in
tion it), which could be played in any
combination by as many as four pianists the twenty Party Pieces they wrote together in the mid-1940s.18
at once; George Brecht, Chance-Imagery
(1957), New York: Something Else Press,
1965, p. 11.
Surprisingly absent from Cage’s earliest research is anything
akin to the technique used by Marcel Duchamp in Erratum Musical
18. These works, as Leta Miller notes,
were originally titled “Sonorous
(1913), in which vocal parts to be performed by Duchamp and
or Exquisite Corpses“: Leta E. Miller, his sisters Yvonne and Magdaleine were “composed” by picking
“Cage’s Collaborations,” in Nicholls,
(ed.), p. 154.
notes at random out of a hat. When sung by all three voices at
once, Duchamp’s libretto, a short dictionary definition of the verb
“to print,” sounded as a chaotic and cacophonous “harmony.”
19. Tristan Tzara, “Manifesto on
Duchamp’s method recalls the recipe for Dadaist poetry in Tristan
feeble love and bitter love” (1916–20), Tzara’s “Manifesto on feeble love and bitter love,” in which a
in Motherwell, p. 92.
newspaper page is cut up and its words drawn at random from a
20. Moira and William Roth, “John bag. “The poem,” Tzara noted wryly, “will be like you.”19 Cage
Cage on Marcel Duchamp,” Art
in America Vol. 61, No. 6, November–
became aware of the musical precedents in Duchamp’s oeuvre only
December 1973, p. 74; quoted in once he had begun his own investigation of chance operations
Richard Kostelanetz, (ed.), Conversing
with Cage, New York: Limelight
– to which Duchamp responded laconically, “I suppose I was fifty
Editions, 1994, p. 219. years ahead of my time.”20 Despite a superficial similarity, Cage

214
soon recognized that his compositions had far surpassed those
21. Kostelanetz, (ed.), Conversing with of Duchamp in the complexity of the processes used.21
Cage p. 219–20. At some point, Cage
came to own one of the more complex
and lesser-known of Duchamp’s chance The intricacy of Cage’s compositional procedures was evident in
compositions, La Mariée mise à nu par
Music of Changes. After having decided upon the work’s overall
ses célibataires même. Erratum Musi-
cal (1913); provenance given in Anne temporal structure, Cage divided the composition’s remaining ele-
D’Harnoncourt and Kynaston McShine, ments into twenty-six charts: eight for sounds (half of each chart
(eds.), Marcel Duchamp, New York: The
Museum of Modern Art, 1973, p. 264. reserved for silence), eight for amplitudes or dynamics, eight for
durations, one for tempi, and one for superposition (“how many
22. John Cage, “Composition:
To Describe the Process of Composition events are happening at once during a given structural space”).22
Used in Music of Changes and Each chart was configured in eight columns and eight rows (those
Imaginary Landscape No. 4,” Silence,
p. 58. containing silences or no change in value [e.g., in tempo] gener-
ally not represented) so as to conform to the sixty-four-cell chart of
hexagrams in the I Ching, the Chinese “Book of Changes,” a copy
of which Christian Wolff had given him in late 1950 or early 1951.
Following the I Ching’s method of divining hexagrams by tossing
three coins six times, Cage could locate the corresponding places
on each grid and thereby define the necessary elements for each
and every acoustical event within the final composition. As docu-
mented by the invaluable work of James Pritchett and David
Bernstein, the compositional procedure of Music of Changes was
both time-consuming and labor-intensive, every sound being the
23. James Pritchett, The Music of John product of consulting multiple charts.23
Cage. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993, pp. 78–88; and David W.
Bernstein, “Cage and High Modernism,” Neither Cage’s use of charts nor his employment of the I Ching
in Nicholls, (ed.), pp. 203–09.
began with Music of Changes. Both had been pioneered in the Con-
24. See Pritchett, pp. 60–78; and certo for Prepared Piano and Chamber Orchestra (1950–51).24 In it,
Bernstein, pp. 193–203. Additional detail Cage staged an opposition between the piano, which began the
is provided in James Pritchett, “From
Choice to Chance: John Cage’s Concerto first movement intuitively and improvisationally composed, and
for Prepared Piano,” Perspectives of the orchestra. In contrast with the first movement’s piano part,
New Music, Vol. 26, No. 1, Winter 1988,
pp. 50–81; and James Pritchett, “The freely composed in the manner of Cage’s prepared piano works of
Development of Chance Techniques in the 1940s, the orchestra part derived from a fourteen-column by
the Music of John Cage, 1950–1956,”
New York University, Department of sixteen-row chart on which all sonorities were specifically notated.
Music, 1988. My thanks to Rebecca Kim Each of the sixteen rows was weighted toward a particular instru-
for the last two references.
ment: row 1, flute; row 2, oboe; row 3, clarinet, and so on, down
though the various types of percussion: metal, wood, friction, and
a miscellaneous section that Cage described as “characterized by
25. John Cage, Letter to Pierre Boulez, mechanical means, e.g., the radio.”25 The fourteen columns in each
May 22, 1951, in Nattiez, (ed.), p. 93.
row contained different sounds or sound aggregates, each weighted
according to the instrument dominating the row. Unlike Music
of Changes, each sound within the concerto, no matter how simple
or complex, was invariant and predefined. As Cage explained to
Boulez: “Each sound is minutely described in the chart: e.g. a
particular tone, sul pont on the 2nd string of the first vn. [violin]
26. Ibid. with a particular flute tone and, for example a wood block.”26

215
For the orchestral part of the first movement, Cage derived the
sequence in which the sounds would occur by making vertical and
horizontal moves on the chart: beginning with the sound represent-
ed in one of the cells, subsequent sounds were selected by follow-
ing a simple sequence such as moving down two cells and then
27. Cage wrote to Boulez, “I then made over three.27 In composing the concerto’s second movement, Cage
moves on this chart of a ‘thematic na-
ture’ but, as you may easily see, with an retained the chart for the orchestra and added a second chart of
‘athematic’ result. This entire first move- equally detailed sonorities for the prepared piano. In this case,
ment uses only 2 moves, e.g. down 2,
over 3, up 4, etc,” in ibid. According to
however, Cage determined the sequence of the sounds by a different,
Bernstein, most moves were two-part, although equally impersonal, method that involved tracing a series
one on the vertical axis and one on the
horizontal axis. Bernstein, p. 195.
of concentric circles and squares on graph paper. For the third and
final movement, Cage employed a single chart in which he com-
bined sounds to be made by the piano, sounds to be made by the
orchestra, and a number of new sound aggregates to be made by
both piano and orchestra together, thus representing their ultimate
28. As noted by Pritchett, however, unification within a single, impersonal compositional procedure.28
Cage subjectively modified such aspects
as phrasing and rhythm. Pritchett, p. 63.
As when composing the orchestra’s part of the first movement,
Cage selected the sounds by means of simple two-part vertical and
horizontal moves on the chart. It was here that Cage first employed
the I Ching. Although the chart of piano and orchestra sounds for
the third movement consisted of the same sixteen rows and four-
teen columns he had used earlier, Cage produced two additional

216
John Cage classes at the New School for Social Research, 1958
(left to right: John Cage, George Brecht, Al Kouzel, Jackson Mac Low, John Cage,
Al Hansen, center, and Allan Kaprow, back wall)

charts, in the eight-by-eight configuration of the I Ching, which


contained arrays of simple moves interspersed with empty cells
representing silences. Cage then tossed coins to obtain the
hexagrams by which to read these additional charts in order to
determine the moves to be made on the one containing sounds.

Since the charts Cage used in composing Concerto for Prepared Piano
and Chamber Orchestra included already complete and precisely
29. As Pritchett notes, “The sounds notated sound complexes, composition essentially consisted in
of the concerto are both independent using chance operations to determine the sequencing of the sounds.
(in the way they occur in time) and
simultaneous (in the way they exist in Thus, to a certain extent, the Concerto is a linear equivalent of the
the chart).” (Pritchett, p. 75). Important- charts that, at any given moment, represent the totality of available
ly, Cage introduced means of retiring
and replacing sounds within the chart sounds.29 In this respect, Cage’s procedure had not advanced all
technique of Concerto for Prepared Piano that far beyond Duchamp’s or Tzara’s random drawing of materials
and Chamber Orchestra. Nevertheless,
at any given moment, the charts were out of a hat or bag.30 In Music of Changes, by contrast, Cage’s separa-
static and complete. See Cage’s com- tion of the sound’s various components into multiple charts – one
ments to Boulez in Nattiez, (ed.), p. 94.
containing sonorities, one containing durations, and one containing
30. The Concerto profoundly altered dynamics – allowed him to surpass the limitations of compositional
Cage’s notion of musical continuity;
nonetheless, he employed several
preconception not merely in the sequencing of the sounds, but in
means by which to produce transposi- their very identity. More than simply arranged according to the laws
tions, symmetry, and other correspon-
dences. See Bernstein, pp. 195–96
of chance, each defining parameter of every acoustical event within
and 202–3. Music of Changes was determined by chance operations.

217
Such an apparently small shift from one to multiple charts intro-
duced two important changes in Cage’s aesthetic. The first concerns
the understanding of the pool of sounds from which his composi-
tion would draw. In place of a closed set of predetermined sounds,
Cage would conceive of sound as a limitless and differentiated
“sound-space” or “field.” The second change concerns the manner
in which sounds are understood to move from this sound-space
into the composition and, from there, into the areas of performance
and audition. Both transformations will ultimately prove impor-
tant for understanding the full implications of Cage’s engagement
with chance.

The first transformation in Cage’s compositional practice hinges


on the fact that, whereas the Concerto was largely equivalent to a
diachronic realization of its charts, which represented (at any given
moment) the totality of the work’s materials in synchronic fash-
31. The exception being the first ion,31 Music of Changes derived from the coming into existence of
movement’s piano part, which was
composed without charts.
sounds that did not pre-exist, as such, within the charts at all. In
Music of Changes, the chance-driven manipulation of different com-
ponents of each sound – the transformation of the components
of the sound chart by the durations and dynamics of the others –
altered the sounds originally given into ones the composer could
not foresee. As Pritchett has demonstrated, the original, “natural”
readings of the elements Cage placed within the sound charts were
mutated in unexpected ways by the chance determination of dura-
32. Pritchett, pp. 82–83. tions and dynamics.32 Thus, although the ultimate state of each
sound could be precisely determined and notated within the score,
the totality of acoustic possibilities drawn upon in Music of Changes
was no longer preconceived. Composition thus entered the realm
of “experimentation” and became an activity without foreseen or
predetermined result.

Music of Changes, however, represented only a preliminary step in


transforming Cage’s conception of the pool of potential sounds.
The sound charts with which he began contained sound complexes
that were intentionally created, and chance-determined manipu-
lations of duration and dynamics only pushed them a relatively
short distance into the unknown. In order to begin with materials
that were not preconceived, Cage developed the “point-drawing”
technique initiated in the score for Music for Carillon I (1952),
developed in magisterial fashion in works such as Concert for Piano
and Orchestra (1957–58), and serving as the basis of scores using
transparencies such as Fontana Mix (1958), Variations I (1958),
and Variations II (1961). In point-drawing scores, Cage simply and

218
immediately notated dots on a sheet of paper by, for instance,
marking a number of imperfections found on the sheet within a
33. In Music for Carillon I, Cage used a given amount of time.33 These points could then be translated into
stencil made from crumpled paper
to determine the placement of the dots.
sounds by establishing different means of mapping by which their
In scores using transparencies, he frequency, amplitude, timbre, duration, and “morphology” (attack
used randomly arrayed dots printed and decay characteristics) could be determined independently
on paper or moveable transparencies.
of the composer’s preconceptions. No longer beginning in the mind
of the composer, the composition now drew its materials from the
entirety of an acoustical “field.” “The reason I am presently work-
ing with imperfections in paper is this,” Cage noted in 1954. “I am
thus able to designate certain aspects of sound as though they were
34. Cage, “45’ for a Speaker,” p. 157. in a field, which of course they are.”34
On the point-drawing technique,
see Pritchett, pp. 92ff.
Cage’s conception of sound as existing within a field was precipi-
tated by his interest in technology. In Cage’s estimation, the capa-
bilities of, for instance, magnetic tape allowed for the possibility
not only of reproducing any sound but, through various means of
manipulation, producing every possible sound. Sound thereby
became conceivable as a continuous expanse without gap, division,
or lacuna. As Cage explained in “Experimental Music”:
Musical habits include scales, modes, theories of counterpoint and harmo-
ny, and the study of the timbres, singly and in combination of a limited number of
sound-producing mechanisms. In mathematical terms these all concern discrete
steps. They resemble walking – in the case of pitches, on steppingstones twelve in
number. This cautious stepping is not characteristic of the possibilities of mag-
netic tape, which is revealing to us that musical action or existence can occur at any
point or along any line or curve or what have you in total sound-space; that we are,
in fact, technically equipped to transform our contemporary awareness of nature’s
35. John Cage, “Experimental Music” manner of operation into art.35
(1957), Silence, p. 9.

Although continuous and unlimited, the “total sound-space”


implied in Cage’s “field situation” was, importantly, not homoge-
36. The term “field situation” appears neous.36 Any movement or transformation in coordinates equaled
in John Cage, “Diary: How to Improve
the World (You Will Only Make Matters
a transformation in acoustic identity. Once again describing the
Worse) 1967,” A Year from Monday. effects of magnetic tape, Cage stated:
Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University
The situation made available by these means is essentially a total sound-
Press, 1967, p. 157.
space, the limits of which are ear-determined only, the position of a particular
sound in this space being the result of five determinants: frequency or pitch,
amplitude or loudness, overtone structure or timbre, duration, and morphology
(how the sound begins, goes on, and dies away). By the alteration of any one of
37. Cage, “Experimental Music,” p. 9. these determinants, the position of the sound in sound-space changes.37

38. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari,


A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Continuous, but also heterogeneous, Cage’s total sound-space is
Schizophrenia, Brian Massumi, (trans.),
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
what Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari would call a “smooth space”;
Press, 1987, p. 371. all points are reachable, but none are identical.38 “I believe, of

219
course, that what we’re doing is exploring a field,” Cage would
proclaim in 1961, “that the field is limitless and without qualitative
39. John Cage, “Where Are We Going? differentiation but with multiplicity of differences.”39
And What Are We Doing?” (1961),
Silence, pp. 204–5.

Cage’s use of the term “multiplicity” in describing the heteroge-


neous and unlimited space of all sound would not seem to
have been purely occasional. It had come up earlier within the
context of his correspondence with Boulez about Music of Changes.
Whereas Cage had contended that his earlier use of the chart tech-
nique had brought him “closer to a ‘chance’ or if you like to an
un-aesthetic choice,” the full development of the multiple chart
procedure within Music of Changes opened onto a different para-
digm: “when I send you the Changes I shall also send you the
charts I used,” he wrote to Boulez in the summer of 1951. “As I see
it, the problem is to understand thoroughly all the qualities that
40. Cage, Letter to Pierre Boulez, act to produce multiplicity.”40
December 18, 1950, in Nattiez, (ed.),
p. 78; and Cage, Letter to Pierre Boulez,
summer 1951, in Nattiez, (ed.), p. 110. The term “multiplicity” would have been particularly significant
Pritchett transcribes the word “quali-
ties,” apparently erroneously, as
for Cage at the time, for the year 1951 most likely marked his ini-
“quantities” (Pritchett, pp. 96 and 137). tial reception of vitalist French philosopher of multiplicity, Henri
Bergson. Although the majority of Cage literature rightly focuses
on the importance of his reception of Indian and East Asian phi-
losophies, as related through such figures as Ananda K. Coomaras-
wamy and Daisetz T. Suzuki, the relatively little researched link
between Cage and Bergson opens up new aspects of the compos-
er’s thinking. As I have argued elsewhere, Cage’s mature under-
standing of silence as formulated in that year can be related to (if
it did not, in fact, derive from) Bergson’s critique of nonbeing as
41. See Branden W. Joseph, Random expressed in Creative Evolution.41 According to Bergson, what an
Order: Robert Rauschenberg and
the Neo-Avant-Garde, Cambridge,
individual conceived as the absence of an object was, in actuality,
Mass.: MIT Press, 2003, p. 47–56. merely the finding of another object that he or she did not seek.42
Cage uses the term “multiplicity”
as early as 1948, although in a seem-
Similarly, after an experience within an anechoic chamber – in
ingly different con-text; John Cage, which Cage heard, not silence, but the noises made by his circula-
“A Composer’s Confessions” (1948),
in Richard Kostelanetz, (ed.), John
tory and nervous systems – Cage would come to define silence,
Cage: Writer, New York: Limelight not as the complete absence of sounds, but rather as the absence
Editions, 1993, p. 41.
only of intentional sounds and the presence of other sounds not
42. Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution, sought, i.e., unintended. From such a perspective, as Cage would
Arthur Mitchell, (trans.), New York: put it, “There is no such thing as silence.”43
Henry Holt & Co., 1911, p. 273.

43. Cage, “45’ for a Speaker,” p. 191. Where Cage quoted Bergson most explicitly, however, was on the
notion of disorder. As he stated, for instance, in a lecture delivered
at Dartmouth College in 1955, “Magnetic tape reveals to ears… that
things are in this life in a state of togetherness that is a real cause
for joy, that their disorder, if so it appears to us, is simply (as Bergson

220
44. John Cage, [“Dartmouth Spring has said) an order we had not been looking for.”44 Bergson’s
’55“], folder 10, box 12, John Cage
Papers, Collection 1000-72, Special
critique of disorder was also found in Creative Evolution and
Collections and Archives, Olin Library, proceeded in the same manner as his critique of nonbeing. As
Wesleyan University, Middletown,
alluded to in Cage’s paraphrase, Bergson considered disorder to
Conn.; cited in Kim, p. 221. Kim
also mentions Earle Brown’s citation be a pseudo-idea that arose on account of the disappointment
of Bergson, p. 97. of an individual who, searching for one kind of order, finds
another. “When I enter a room and pronounce it to be ‘in disorder,’
what do I mean?” queried Bergson:
The position of each object is explained by the automatic movements of
the person who has slept in the room, or by the efficient causes, whatever they may
be, that have caused each article of furniture, clothing, etc., to be where it is: the
order, in the second sense of the word, is perfect. But it is order of the first kind
that I am expecting, the order that a methodical person consciously puts into his
life, the willed order and not the automatic: so I call the absence of this order
“disorder.” At bottom, all there is that is real, perceived and even conceived, in
this absence of one of the two kinds of order, is the presence of the other. But the
second is indifferent to me, I am interested only in the first, and I express the pres-
ence of the second as a function of the first, instead of expressing it, so to speak,
45. Bergson, pp. 232–33. as a function of itself, by saying it is disorder.45

If one type of order was that expressed in scientific, geometric,


46. Ibid., p. 230. Around 1954, Cage mechanistic, and/or mathematical laws (an order predicated
began to echo Bergson’s notion of dura-
tion as, not an abstract or mechanical on suppressing lived duration), the second was a “vital” one that
expanse of time, but a subjectively lived existed within duration’s continual flow and was “essentially
temporality in relation to the world
around: “Time… is what we and sounds
creation.”46 To each type of order corresponded a certain type of
happen in. Whether early or late: in it. multiplicity. One form was proper to discontinuous, numerical
It is not a question of counting.” (Cage,
“45’ for a Speaker,” p. 151).
multiplicities, the other to continuous, virtual multiplicities, those
integrally related to the creative transformations of lived dura-
47. Bergson, pp. 38–40. On the different
types of multiplicity, see Gilles Deleuze,
tion.47 According to Bergson (in a connection that would not have
Bergsonism, Hugh Tomlinson and gone unnoted by Cage) the idea of chance as a form of disorder
Barbara Habberjam, (trans.), New York:
Zone Books, 1988 p. 37–41.
was prompted by the confusion of an individual who failed to
grasp the difference between these two types of order. “…in real-
48. Bergson, p. 234.
ity,” wrote Bergson, “chance merely objectifies the state of mind
49. John Cage, “Letter to Paul Henry of one who, expecting one of the two kinds of order, finds himself
Lang” (1956), in Kostelanetz, (ed.), confronted with the other. Chance and disorder are therefore
John Cage: An Anthology, p. 118. Cage
explicitly opposes the “natural” and necessarily conceived as relative.”48
“anthropomorphic” points of view in
Cage, “On Film” (1956), in Kostelanetz,
(ed.), John Cage, p. 115. For Bergson’s Like Bergson, Cage sought to think in a non-“anthropomorphic”
critique of dialectics, see, for example, manner, to grasp the “life” that, as he explained to Paul Henry
Bergson, p. 238. Cage is, as a thinker,
like Bergson in Deleuze’s description Lang, “goes on very well without me” – an order of existence that
of him: not one who ascribes to “a prop- surpasses the limitations of the human mind and the procedures
erly human wisdom and equilibrium,”
but one who attempts to “open us up to of dialectical thinking that Cage saw as derived from it.49 It was for
the inhuman and the superhuman (dura- this reason that he mobilized the idea of multiplicity (as a complex
tions which are inferior or superior to
our own), to go beyond the human con-
interaction that was in line with the actual, ontological existence
dition.” (Deleuze, Bergsonism, p. 28.) of sound) against an idea of relationships as generally understood

221
and grasped by the human mind. Relationships were seen as
inherently limited, essentially dualistic, and therefore reductive in
comparison with the multiplicity Cage was attempting to access.
Drawing upon Suzuki, Cage explained:
From a non-dualistic point of view, each thing and each being is seen at the
center, and these centers are in a state of interpenetration and non-obstruction.
From a dualistic point of view, on the other hand, each thing and each being is not
seen: relationships are seen and interferences are seen. To avoid undesired inter-
ferences and to make one’s intentions clear, a dualistic point of view requires a
50. John Cage, “Composition as Process careful integration of the opposites.50
II: Indeterminacy” (1958), Silence, p. 38.

In this, we can begin to see that Cage’s repeated insistence on the


unknowability of life, nature, or existence opened onto more than
simply mysticism. With an understanding of ontology (includ-
ing, but not limited to, “sound-space”) as an infinite expanse of
interconnections in a state of continuous mobility and temporally
accumulating growth (as it was also conceived by Bergson), totality
51. Bergson, pp. 45–47. was no longer properly cognizable as such.51 Yet, Cage’s descrip-
tions of existence as a “limitless” field filled with an ungraspable
“multiplicity of differences” did not mean that nothing could be
understood, only that existence in its totality could not be. Sound
being no longer a limited and pre-visible totality as in the charts of
the Concerto, individual sounds were to be drawn from a complex,
unpredictable, and unlimited totality. And as opposed to Music of
Changes, which drew its initial components from a set of pre-given
notated sonorities, the field of all sound was properly unknowable
for it existed only within a virtual state. This was the “change in
our heads” Cage would mention in relation to conceiving of exis-
tence as a “field phenomena.” “And about this field,” Cage con-
tended, “nothing can be said. And yet one goes on talking, in order
to make this clear” – “our business has changed from judgment
52. Cage, “Where Are We Going? And to awareness.”52
What Are We Doing?,” pp. 199, 204,
and 206. The idea of transcending the
intellect is fundamental for Bergson;
see, for example, Bergson, pp. 163–64.
If the first important change to arise from the multiple-chart tech-
nique utilized in Music of Changes concerned Cage’s understanding
of the limitless field within which all sounds existed, the second
impacted his conception of the manner in which those sounds
traveled from this pool of all potential sound – from the continuous
multiplicity that is the total sound-space – to the level of the
composition itself. Previously, in Concerto for Prepared Piano and
Chamber Orchestra the relationship of the sounds in the composi-
tion to their prior existence in the compositional charts was one of
identity. In both states the sound itself was effectively unchanged.
In Music of Changes, by contrast, the use of multiple charts began to

222
indicate a relationship between the composition’s sounds and the
material from which they were drawn that was not one of identity,
but one of difference.

The distinction that Cage will come to make is fundamental, and


in order to describe it we will have to be precise. It is from Deleuze
– whose own study of Bergson began at exactly the same historical
moment as Cage’s – that we will be able to derive the needed analyt-
53. Deleuze’s first article on Bergson, ical tools.53 First, we will have to introduce a terminological distinc-
“Bergson’s Conception of Difference”
was initially presented as a lecture
tion, for, as pointed out by Deleuze, there is in Bergson’s thought
in 1954. Gilles Deleuze, “Bergson’s an important difference between possibilities and virtualities.54
Conception of Difference,” in John
Mullarkey, (ed.), The New Bergson,
Like disorder and non-being, the idea of the possible is for Bergson
Manchester: Manchester University a false idea, a projection from reality backward into a supposedly
Press, 1999, pp. 42–65; lecture date
given in Michael Hardt, Gilles Deleuze:
prior state. Possibilities are considered to be knowable, pre-exist-
An Apprenticeship in Philosophy, ing their realization already endowed with their proper form. There
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
is, then, no difference between a possible action and a real action
Press, 1993, p. 2.
apart from the fact that a real action has come to pass and a merely
54. Deleuze, Bergsonism, pp. 42–43, possible action has not, or has not yet.
96–98.

Virtualities, by contrast, are of a different order altogether: they


do not pre-exist their coming into being in an already constituted
form. The virtual exists in a state of potentiality and is, as such,
properly unknowable. Whereas possibilities relate to static, pre-
formed, closed systems (being, in fact, backward projections from
an existent reality), virtualities are part of ongoing systems, “vital”
and “creative” systems that are infinitely evolving and temporally
accumulating. The virtual, therefore, cannot be fully conceived
until it is created.

In order to describe the manner in which Bergsonian virtuali-


ties come into being, Deleuze provides a second terminological
distinction: whereas possibilities are realized, virtualities are
actualized. Here the distinction is equally fundamental. The
relationship of possibilities to their realization is characterized
by identity and limitation. A possibility that is realized is the
same as it was in its prior state of possibility; it is identical to its
previous state, only it now seemingly has reality added to it.
In relation to the totality of possibilities available at any given
time the one that is realized is derived according to a process
of limitation, having been selected from out of all the others that
are not, or are not yet, realized. Such is the relationship of the
notes in Duchamp’s Erratum Musical to the hatful from which
they were drawn or of the notes in Cage’s Concerto for Prepared
Piano to the charts in which they were found. The role of chance
is limited to that of selecting from amongst the set of possible

223
elements available at any one given time that one element that is,
at a particular moment, to be realized.

Actualization, by contrast, takes place specifically with regard to


continuous multiplicities of the kind proper to Cage’s conception of
sound. Actualization is the manner in which one part or aspect
of such a continuous multiplicity comes into existence. In that a part
(e.g., a sound) derives from the multiplicity as a whole, the multi-
plicity can be said to divide, but such a division, Deleuze explains,
is neither a simple partition nor merely a subtraction of part from
whole, but rather a procedure of differentiation in kind. The
resulting entity is not recognizable as either a discrete section or a
particular aspect of the original multiplicity (which is, in any case,
durationally changing), but is an actualization that is, with relation
to its previous state, new. Deleuze explains:
For, in order to be actualized, the virtual cannot proceed by elimination
or limitation, but must create its own lines of actualization in positive acts. The
reason for this is simple: While the real is in the image and likeness of the possible
that it realizes, the action, on the other hand[,] does not resemble the virtuality
that it embodies. It is difference that is primary in the process of actualization
– the difference between the virtual from which we begin and the actuals at which
we arrive, and also the difference between the complementary lines according to
which actualization takes place. In short, the characteristic of virtuality is to exist in
such a way that it is actualized by being differentiated and is forced to differentiate
55. Ibid., p. 97. itself, to create its lines of differentiation in order to be actualized.55

Actualization is thus the manner in which a positive form of differ-


entiation operates, one in which difference is not based on nega-
56. Ibid., p. 103. tion but on creation and is therefore a positive force.56 It relates to
a form of difference understood to be central and internal, a form
in which the virtual multiplicity in its movement of actualization
differs first and foremost from itself.

Although all of the distinctions enumerated above – between possi-


bilities and virtualities, realization and actualization, and discrete
and continuous multiplicities – can be found in Creative Evolu-
57. See, for instance, Bergson, pp. 179, tion, they are nowhere as clearly defined in Bergson’s prose as in
181, 196–97, and 257–58. For a typical
example of the English translation, see: Deleuze’s analysis of it, a situation obscured further by the English
“But the body which is to perform translation.57 For this reason, perhaps, Cage uses the terms “pos-
[exercera] this action, the body which
marks out upon matter the design of sible” and “potential” (the translator’s preferred English term for
its eventual actions [ses actions “virtuel”) almost interchangeably. Nevertheless, it is clear from the
virtuelles] even before they are actual
[avant d’accomplir des actions réelles]…”
context of Cage’s statements that Cagean possibilities and poten-
Bergson, p. 12; original French terms tialities are by and large equivalent to Bergsonian virtualities as
within square brackets, Henri Bergson,
L’Évolution créatrice. Paris: Presses
more strictly defined by Deleuze and as they line up on the side of
Universitaires de France, 1998, p. 12. actualization, continuous multiplicity, and the unforeseen nature

224
of experimental actions. As Cage wrote about his score, Variations I
(1958), “In this situation, the universe within which the action is
to take place is not preconceived. Furthermore, as we know, sounds
are events in a field of possibilities, not only at the discrete points
58. John Cage, “Composition as Process conventions have favored.”58
I: Changes” (1958), Silence, p. 28.

By 1958, Cage consistently described his compositional proces-


ses in terms of actualization. As he noted, for instance, in
“Composition as Process I: Changes,” “With tape and music-
synthesizers, action with the overtone structure of sounds can
be less a matter of taste and more thoroughly an action in a
59. Ibid., p. 31. field of possibilities.”59 More significantly, Cage’s compositional
practice followed the general lines of actualization. This was
evident as early as 1952, in Cage’s discussion of the superposi-
tion chart in Music of Changes, where a sound was considered to
exist in a virtual state (was, in Cage’s terms, “possibly audible”),
and was only “actually audible” within certain conditions deter-
mined by coin tosses according with the I Ching. As he described
the process in the journal trans/formation (the article he later
read to his New School class):
Each one of the events (1 to 8) is worked from the beginning to the end of the
composition. For instance, the 8th one is present from beginning to end but may
sound only during a structural space that has been defined by a toss (for Superposi-
tions) of 57 to 64 [in the I-Ching]. It is then not only present but possibly audible.
It becomes actually audible if a sound is tossed (rather than a silence) and if the
duration tossed is of a length that does not carry the sound beyond the structural
60. Morton Feldman, Pierre Boulez, space open to it.60
John Cage, and Christian Wolff,
“4 Musicians at Work,” trans/formation,
Vol. 1, No. 3, 1952, p. 172; repr. as The multiple chart technique of Music of Changes, wherein individ-
“Statements by Morton Feldman,
ual musical events arise out of the combination of different charts
John Cage and Christian Wolff,” in
Nattiez, (ed.), p. 107; and as Cage, and are not fully contained within any one of them, also begins to
“Composition: To Describe the Process hint at the process of actualization.
of Composition Used in Music of
Changes and Imaginary Landscape
No. 4,” Silence, p. 59. Actualization, however, was more clearly implemented in the point-
drawing scores wherein sound was engaged or related to as a field.
As Cage describes the process in “45’ for a Speaker”:
To determine the number of imperfections in a given space, coins are tossed.
That number of spots is then potentially active. Subsequent tosses determine
which are actually active. Tables are arranged referring to tempi, the number of
superimpositions, that is to say number of things that can go on at once, sounds
61. Cage, “45’ for a Speaker,” p. 159. & silences, durations, loudnesses, accents.61

Shortly afterward, Cage associates his point-drawing technique


both with the notion of chance and with the more particularly
Bergsonian notions of life, duration, and virtuality (“potentiality”):

225
I am talking & contemporary music is changing. Like life it changes. If it were
not changing it would be dead. That is why chance enters for me so largely into
my means which are skillful. It is at the point of potentiality… I am working now to
62. Ibid., p. 181. work without charts, without any support in total space.62

For Cage, sound ontologically is a virtual multiplicity, and in this


state it is unified, it is one (a total sound-space), although hetero-
geneous and unbounded. Composition consists in devising ways
of translating the spot on the paper (a potential or virtual sound)
into an actual sound by determining – through the use of chance
operations and/or varying degrees of indeterminacy – all com-
ponents necessary to provide the identity of the sonic event. It is
through the application of these procedures that the point comes
into being as a sound. In this way, the continuous multiplicity
that is the totality of all sound is divided, but the sounds thereby
produced are not previously located or foreseen. “Spots are spots,”
as Cage put it, “and skill’s needed to turn them to the point of
63. Ibid., p. 161. Although unaware of practicality.”63
Cage’s relation to Bergson, Pritchett’s
description of Notation Y from the piano
part of Concert for Piano and Orchestra
well illustrates the process of actualiza-
tion through differentiation. (Pritchett,
With Music of Changes, Cage had succeeded in enacting a process
p. 119.) of actualization (to however limited a degree) only with regard to
the level of composition. If, for the composer, the situation was one
of having access to an unprecedented realm of sound (if not yet
entirely a total sound-space), the performer was still faced with a
more or less conventionally notated score (however complex or in-
novative). As Cage described the situation:
That the Music of Changes was composed by means of chance operations
identifies the composer with no matter what eventuality. But that its notation is in
all respects determinate does not permit the performer any such identification:
his work is specifically laid out before him. He is therefore not able to perform
64. Cage, “Composition as Process II:
Indeterminacy,” p. 36. from his own center but must identify himself insofar as possible with the center
of the work as written.64
65. See Adorno’s criticism, although
directed against advanced serialist tech-
nique, of the moment “when the sub- From this perspective, Music of Changes falls squarely within the
ject, whose freedom is the precondition
of all advanced art, is driven out; when most compromising terms of Theodor Adorno’s critique of advanc-
a violent and external totality, hardly ed music. By effectively subtracting him or herself from the compo-
different from political totalitarianism,
acquires the reins of power“; Theodor sition, the composer delivers performers over to a fixed and entirely
W. Adorno, “The Aging of the New objective contingency that lords over them, effectively placing them
Music” (1955), in Richard Leppert, (ed.),
Essays on Music, Berkeley, Ca.: Univer-
in a position of submission before it as before a social situation
sity of Califorina Press, 2002, p. 196. equally objectively and impersonally controlled.65 Levying this very
Adorno later credited Cage’s music with
acting as “a protest against the dogged
charge against himself, in an exemplary moment of self-criticism,
complicity of music with the domination Cage explained:
of nature“; Theodor W. Adorno, “Vers
The Music of Changes is an object more inhuman than human, since chance
une musique informelle,” Quasi una
fantasia, London: Verso, 1994, p. 315. operations brought it into being. The fact that these things that constitute it,

226
though only sounds, have come together to control a human being, the performer,
gives the work the alarming aspect of a Frankenstein monster. This situation is
of course characteristic of Western music, the masterpieces of which are its most
frightening examples, which when concerned with humane communication only
66. Cage, “Composition as Process II: move over from Frankenstein monster to Dictator.66
Indeterminacy,” p. 36.

For the audience, too, there was little difference between Music of
Changes and any intentionally composed work. Although Cage’s
compositional process eliminated any a priori message, it did not
interrupt the communicative process seen to operate between
composer or performer and audience. On account of the fixity of
its score, the Music of Changes could not escape a posteriori projec-
tions and analyses: it was just as open to the recovery or imputa-
67. See Adorno’s criticism that “Cage, tion of meanings as tarot cards or cups of tea leaves.67
and doubtless many of his disciples,
content themselves with abstract
negation in seances with overtones Although, in Music of Changes, Cage concentrated exclusively on
of [Rudolf] Steiner, eurythmics and
healthy-living sects.” (Adorno, “Vers
composition, he succeeded on that level in gaining insights that led
une musique informelle,” p. 315.) to the realization of his “failure” within the realms of performance
and audience reception. Seeking to move beyond the determinate
score of Music of Changes, Cage pursued indeterminacy, developing
the means by which a single point or note could be read in a variety
– eventually an unlimited variety – of ways. Hence, the majority of
Cage’s point-drawing scores (and, later, those using transparencies)
take the form of compositional puzzles for which the “answers”
– that is, the actual notes to be played – are variable or even unlim-
ited in scope and, at the outset, unknown to either composer or
performer. In this sense, the score comes into existence as a result
of the performer’s “actualization”; prior to that moment it exists
only in a state of virtuality. As Cage explained in the lecture,
“Experimental Music,” “The total field of possibilities [read ‘virtua-
lities’] may be roughly divided and the actual sounds within these
divisions may be indicated as to number but left to the performer
68. Cage, “Experimental Music,” p. 11. or to the splicer to choose.”68

Only with this final step of introducing indeterminacy into his


scores, it could be argued, did Cage succeed in the task he set
for himself “to understand thoroughly all the qualities that act
to produce multiplicity.” For in order for a composition to be
a multiplicity it is not enough that it derives from an unlimited
space of all sound or that it engages with chance operations.
For a composition to be a multiplicity, it must not be reproduced
or realized but actualized; it must proceed to performance not
by means of identity, representation, or resemblance – from out
of a limited and pre-established set of materials – but via an act
of creation. A composition acts to produce a multiplicity because,

227
and only if, it exists as a virtuality with relation to the stage of
performance that succeeds it. In this, the performer partially loses
his or her subservient position as the composer’s representative
to take on a greater share in the role of individual creator, and
the performance loses its role as a representation of the score to
69. For Cage, such a critique of repre- become a process of actualized differentiation.69
sentation was explicitly political and in
line with his developing anarchism. See,
for instance, Cage’s invocation of the The same is true of the relationship between performance and
police in “History of Experimental Music
in the United States” (1959), Silence,
audience reception. In the first place, performance becomes inde-
p. 72. terminate of audition on account of its potential unrepeatability.
The same piece at different times and performed by different
performers (each of whom has, presumably, actualized the score
for him or herself) gives rise quite literally to distinct acoustical
experiences, and this indeterminacy is augmented by Cage’s
explicitly allowing for the possibility of multiple compositions of
70. In order to make the variability his being performed simultaneously.70 In addition, the “transpar-
of indeterminate works clear, Cage
and David Tudor would often perform
ency” of Cage’s compositions, their openness to the inclusion of
multiple versions (actualizations) of ambient and unintended noises, further differentiates each perfor-
the same score within a single concert.
mance according to the acoustical circumstances encountered in
the particular time and place of presentation. (This, Brecht noted
quite specifically: “Ambient sound penetrates the intended, is
‘included’ in the music. It is relevant to the situation in which the
71. Dieter Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, music arises/relevant to the music, which is ever situational.”)71
Notebook III (April 1959–August 1959),
Cologne: Walther König, 1991, p. 125.
Moreover, the music’s being free of any traditionally expressive or
communicative message, the audience’s act of interpretation
(as the hermeneutic uncovering of meaning) gives way to what Cage
72. Cage, “45’ for a Speaker,” p. 174;
called “sensitivic responsiveness” or “response ability”: a form
and “Experimental Music,” p. 10. of reception that arises from, but is not determined by, the perfor-
Brandon LaBelle has described the man-
mance, a reception that is as constitutively dependent on each
ner in which Cage’s music reconfigures
listening particularly nicely: “By seeking audience member as on the composer or performer.72
to strip away the representational
nature of sound… sound is potentially
dislodged to float along a chain of refer- For the audience of one of Cage’s pieces, the performance is a virtu-
ence, as a ‘signifying’ agent within a ality, it is a virtual multiplicity, and the same is true of the composi-
musical event, outside the narratives
of musical argument. This signifying of tion with relation to the performance and of sound or ontology with
sound over its signification (and ulti- relation to the composition. The passage or movement from one
mate decipherability) makes possible
a shift in listening by which individual activity to the other is one of actualization, a process of differentia-
imagination is mobilized, for listening tion from one layer to the next that is a process of individuation.
reaches not for correct meaning but for
its potential.” Brandon LaBelle, Back- Acoustical aggregates are actualized in the process of composing to
ground Noise: Perspectives on Sound form small, virtual systems by which the composition functions as
Art, New York: Continuum, 2006, p. 17.
a multiplicity.73 These, in turn, are actualized into specific acousti-
73. “Given a number of actually active cal events in performance, forming in their interaction with other
points, they are an aggregate, a constel-
lation, they can move about among
sounds (both performed and ambient) a multiplicity with relation
themselves and it becomes necessary to the audience. Finally, the audience – by means of the interaction
to classify the kinds of aggregates,
say constant and again intermittent.”
of sounds with the individual’s unique emotional and cognitive
Cage, “45’ for a Speaker,” p. 163. responses – actualizes an experience that is individual.

228
Cage advocated promoting such an individualized reception by
dispersing performers and/or loudspeakers around and about the
audience (an avenue first explored in Cage’s happening-like Theater
Event #1 [1952] at Black Mountain College). Such acoustical distri-
bution fragmented the performed sound, rendering what is heard
by each audience member different from the experience of others
located at different positions throughout the hall. In this way, the
unique proximity of each listener to the various points of sound
production physically renders performance indeterminate of any
one, unique, collective experience of hearing. Cage explained:
Rehearsals have shown that this new music, whether for tape or for instru-
ments, is more clearly heard when the several loud-speakers or performers
are separated in space rather than grouped closely together. For this music is not
concerned with harmoniousness as generally understood, where the quality of
harmony results from a blending of several elements. Here we are concerned with
the coexistence of dissimilars, and the central points where fusion occurs are
74. Cage, “Experimental Music,” p. 12. many: the ears of the listeners wherever they are.74

In this context, immediately following the above quote, Cage once


again referenced Bergson’s discussion of disorder: “This dishar-
mony, to paraphrase Bergson’s statement about disorder, is simply
75. Ibíd. a harmony to which many are unaccustomed.”75

Cage’s process of moving via differentiation through the pro-


cesses of composition, performance, and audition figures as an
almost analytical model of Bergson’s ontological vision and is one
of the ways that Cage’s music could be seen to imitate nature in its
“manner of operation.” From the level of the universe as a whole
to that of human society to that of the smallest of microorganisms,
nature was described by Bergson as in a state of ongoing fluctua-
tion between the two poles of individuation and association:
So, among the dissociated individuals, one life goes on moving: everywhere
the tendency to individualize is opposed and at the same time completed by an
antagonistic and complementary tendency to associate, as if the manifold unity of
life, drawn in the direction of multiplicity, made so much the more effort to with-
draw itself on to itself. A part is no sooner detached than it tends to reunite itself,
if not to all the rest, at least to what is nearest to it. Hence, throughout the whole
76. Bergson, pp. 258–59. Bergson is realm of life, a balancing between individuation and association.76
discussing life as a virtual, continuous
multiplicity.
In Cage’s work, the same dual process is at work, as, for instance,
individual notes are actualized from the virtual totality that is all
sound to then find themselves associated with others to form a
virtual multiplicity with regard to performance, and then again
from the process of performance to the situation of hearing. Such
a dual movement of individuation and association (what Cage

229
would call, following Suzuki, “unimpededness and interpenetra-
tion”) was seen by Bergson as essential. “The evolution of life
in the double direction of individuality and association has there-
fore nothing accidental about it,” he declared, “it is due to the
77. Ibid., p. 261. On “unimpededness very nature of life.”77
and interpenetration,” see, for instance,
Cage, “Composition as Process III: Com-
munication” (1958), Silence, pp. 46–47. We are now in a better position to understand what is meant by
Cage when he famously defined the purpose of writing music as
“an affirmation of life – not an attempt to bring order out of chaos
nor to suggest improvements in creation, but simply a way of wak-
ing up to the very life we’re living, which is so excellent once one
gets one’s mind and one’s desires out of its way and lets it act of its
78. Cage, “Experimental Music,” p. 12. own accord.”78 The answer has nothing to do with the presentism
of which Cage has often been accused, the quietistic endorsement of
a purely mimetic relationship between the composition and the
actually existing state of society. Rather, the relationship of the work
of art to the ontological state of being – the relationship, in other
words, of art to life as put forward by Cage – is one of indeterminacy
in this sense: sounds (and, as we shall see shortly, other aspects of
existence as well) come into existence through a process of differen-
tiation as they pass from a state of virtuality to one of actualization.

We have found ourselves, it would seem, in rather unfamiliar art


historical territory, quite a ways from any simple notions of chance
or vague relations between “art” and “life.” Yet, if we turn back to
what Cage taught in his New School composition courses, we find
specific ideas drawn from his most advanced aesthetic researches
of the time. These are most clearly located in the work of George
Brecht, both because of the unique access Brecht’s course note-
books afford to Cage’s teaching and because, as Dick Higgins indi-
cated, Brecht seemed to follow the intricacies of Cage’s aesthetic
much more closely than his other classmates.

According to Brecht’s notes, the first idea Cage communicated to


his 1958 summer class was that of the five “dimensions” of sound
and their “trend toward Continuity.” As Cage had explained in
“Experimental Music” a year earlier, frequency, duration, ampli-
tude, timbre, and morphology had all effectively become fields
rather than discrete elements: thus, a “frequency field,” as Brecht
noted, rather than “definite tones”; a “duration field,” in place of
notations of “1/8th, 1/16th, 1/32, etc.”; an “overtone field,” instead of
79. Dieter Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, traditional “orchestration”; and so on.79 Importantly, Cage’s under-
Notebook I (June 1958–September
1958), Cologne: Walther König, 1991,
standing of sounds as existing within a field had long extended to
p. 3 (dated June 24, 1958). the idea that they interacted not only with all other sounds but with

230
all facets of existence. As Cage explained in “Experimental Music:
Doctrine” in 1955:
Urgent, unique, uninformed about history and theory, beyond the imagina-
tion, central to a sphere without surface, its [a sound’s] becoming is unimpeded,
energetically broadcast. There is no escape from its action. It does not exist as one
of a series of discrete steps, but as transmission in all directions from the field’s
center. It is inextricably synchronous with all other, sounds, non-sounds, which
80. Cage, “Experimental Music: latter, received by other sets than the ear, operate in the same manner.80
Doctrine,” p. 14.

From such a perspective, Cage’s idea of the “field” extended into


the multisensory, multimedia, and multidisciplinary realm he
termed “theater”:
Relevant action is theatrical (music [imaginary separation of hearing from
the other senses] does not exist), inclusive and intentionally purposeless. Theater
is continually becoming that it is becoming; each human being is at the best
point for reception. Relevant response (getting up in the morning and discovering
oneself musician) (action, art) can be made with any number (including none
81. Ibid. [none and number, like silence and music, are unreal]) of sounds.81

One year earlier, in “45’ for a Speaker,” Cage had specifically invok-
ed the relation of sound and vision, writing:
Music is an oversimplification of the situation we actually are in. An ear alone
82. Cage, “45’ for a Speaker,” p. 149.
is not a being; music is one part of theater. “Focus” is what aspects one’s noticing.
83. Ibid., p. 189. Cage’s invocation of Theater is all the various things going on at the same time. I have noticed that music
“theater” was doubtlessly related to
is liveliest for me when listening for instance doesn’t distract me from seeing.82
his reception of Antonin Artaud, whose
work he studied in 1951–52. See Cage’s
comments in his letter to Boulez, May
22, 1951, in Nattiez, (ed.), p. 96.
Anticipating the partial conjunction of his own discipline with
that of most of his New School students, Cage noted further,
84. The Audio Visual Group is men-
“it is theater and music disappears entirely into the realm of art
tioned in Joseph Jacobs, “Crashing New
York à la John Cage,” in Joan Marter, where it knows it belongs.”83
(ed.), Off Limits: Rutgers University
and the Avant-Garde, 1957–1963, New
Brunswick, N. J.: Rutgers University Although by no means deriving exclusively from Cage’s example,
Press, 1999, p. 73. On the notion the genres of happenings and Fluxus drew greatly upon Cage’s
of Cagean “theater,” see Branden W.
Joseph, “The Tower and the Line: extension of composition to include the visual as well as the au-
Toward a Genealogy of Minimalism,” dible, objects and environments as well as sounds. Kaprow’s first
Grey Room No. 27, spring 2007, pp.
58–81, and (a reworking of some of the happenings, Brecht’s early experiments with light, and Hansen,
same material) Beyond the Dream Higgins, and Larry Poons’s founding of the Audio Visual Group
Syndicate: Tony Conrad and the Arts
after Cage, New York: Zone Books, can all be understood as developments of Cagean “theater.”84 In
2008, esp. pp. 81–84. 1960, even as Kaprow had become the happening’s official spokes-
85. Diane De Bonneval, “New
person, the genre was received as indelibly linked to Cage’s New
School’s ‘Happenings’ Proves to be School classroom and its practitioners identified as his students.85
‘Hellzapoppin’ – Beatnik Style,”
New York World-Telegram and Sun,
Even as late as 1961, a year after Cage had stopped teaching, Brecht
May 3, 1960, in Hermann Braun, could still be found working through Cage’s theatrical paradigm.
(ed.), George Brecht, Notebook V
(March 1960–November 1960),
In the draft of an article proposed for the nascent publication,
Cologne: Walther König, 1997, p. 89. Fluxus, Brecht wrote:

231
Composers, performers and auditors of music permit sound-experiences by
arranging situations having sound as an aspect. But there are other than sound-
situations. But the theater is well lit. Situations can be of interest in any dimension.
Now consider music admitting ambient sound, for example, that of John Cage,
Christian Wolff. Why shut my eyes? And if my eyes are open, why a “sound-situation?”
Why mention sound at all. There are things to see. I have to cough; the seat creaks;
and I can feel the vibration. Since there is no distraction, why choose sound as the
86. Hermann Braun, (ed.), George common aspect?86
Brecht, Notebook VII (June 1961–
September 1962), Cologne: Walther
König, 2005, p. 115. Much in this Working within the context of Cage’s class, Brecht engaged not
passage was struck through by Brecht. only with general ideas, but with specific compositional procedures.
Hence one finds Brecht, in what seems one of his first “homework”
assignments, proposing an extension of Cage’s point-drawing
scores:
(1) A piece of wood, about 1 foot square, is painted white, and while still wet
is placed outdoors (e.g. in the woods). After it is dry, each speck represents a sound.
(2) An “interpretive matrix” (ruled areas, lines, etc. on acetate, over a frame)
87. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, Note- is placed over this piece of wood, to allow transformation into sound.87
book I, p. 24. Cage’s Music for Carillon
No. 5 (1967) would later use the grain of
a piece of plywood to determine pitches. Here, Brecht can be seen extending Cage’s point-drawing tech-
My thanks to David Patterson for this
nique in a more painterly and object-oriented direction, while liter-
connection.
alizing Cage’s relationship to nature.

Brecht’s notes indicate that Cage invoked Bergson’s discussion


88. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, of disorder on the first day of the summer 1959 class.88 Bergsonian
Notebook III, p. 57 (citation dated June
22, 1959). Although Brecht gives
ideas of virtuality and actualization seem already to have been
no indication of ever having consulted introduced into the course the year before, likely though Cage’s
Bergson’s writings directly, he could still
discussions of his own work and the article from trans/formation.
declare to Cage over six months later
that “The order-disorder distinctions Although appearing in several places, such concerns seem to have
is of great interest to me right now“; become a particular focus for Brecht toward the end of October
Hermann Braun, (ed.), George Brecht,
Notebook IV (September 1959–March in the context of his thinking through the conditions of “an aural-
1960), Cologne: Walther König, 1997, visual event.”89 As part of Brecht’s effort to expand Cagean prin-
p. 168 (dated January 27, 1960).
ciples into a more explicitly audio-visual register, he lists optical
89. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, analogues for Cage’s five-part analysis of the components of a
Notebook II, p. 33 (dated October 24,
1958). sound. The frequency of acoustical phenomena proves analogous
to the wavelength of light, while timbre becomes “spectral distri-
bution.” The attributes of amplitude, duration, and morphology
Brecht judged equally applicable to both auditory and visual events
and hence left unchanged. Once having defined his materials’
characteristics, Brecht states the general “Problem”: “To construct
situations in which it is made possible for light and sound events
of any desired characteristics (frequency/wave-length, amplitude/
brightness, duration, timbre/spectral distribution, morphology) to
occur at any points in space and time.” It is in subsequently con-
templating “the nature of the unity of space and time which occurs in

232
such situations” that Brecht will have recourse to the framework
of actualization:
If each micro-event (lighting of a light, sounding of a sound-source) is
capable of occurring in only one point of space (e.g. by the static placement of
a speaker, or light bulb), then this space “discreteness” is analogous to a time
discreteness, wherein micro-events would only be capable of occurring at certain
points in time. Of course, a “program” actually does constrain events to occur at
certain points in time.
We must, perhaps, differentiate “potentiality” and “actuality.” Universe
of possibilities. Embodiment. The above paragraph shows confusion of these two
90. Ibid., pp. 35–36 (dated October 26, [upward arrow] ideas.90
1958).

Almost immediately, on the basis of this insight, Brecht reformu-


lates his thinking about audio-visual events concisely and accord-
ing to the notion of actualization from an unlimited universe of
virtualities (though, like Cage, he uses the term “possible”): “The
event (micro), made actual, is one chosen from a universe of all
91. Ibid., p. 36. possible {lights/sounds} from all possible space points.”91

The transformation that arises within Brecht’s thinking at this


point is two-fold and follows the same contours as Cage’s had
undergone when developing his chance operations in the direction
of actualization: the first concerns the definition of the pool
from which events might derive; the second, the manner in which
such events move from that pool into the domains of performance
and perception.

Like Cage, Brecht would soon come to conceive of events as being


drawn, not from discrete sets of terms, but from an infinitely
extensive universe of virtualities. Seeking to describe the “General
Nature of a Performance,” Brecht would write in November, 1958,
“The overall event (performance) is a selection of space-time events
having specific qualities, drawn from a universe in which all possi-
ble space-time events, having all possible qualities, were available.”
Although, like Cage, Brecht again utilizes the term “possible,” the
unlimited totality to which he refers indicates that “virtual” would
apply. Accordingly, and immediately afterward, Brecht invokes the
notion of actualization:
In practice, the universe of possibilities is as follows:
All points in space within a specific room (say 1” module) are available for “activa-
92. Ibid., p. 41 (dated November 4,1958). tion,” by sounds or lights of any given qualities.92

Brecht’s reconception of what may be called the “ontology of the


event” represents a fundamental transformation in his think-
ing about chance. Formerly, in Chance-Imagery, he had conceived

233
chance not as actualizing a virtuality, but as the realization of a
limited and predetermined set of possibilities (in the strict,
Bergsonian sense of the term). This, Brecht explained precisely:
It is sometimes possible to specify only the universe of possible character-
istics which a chance event may have. For example, a toss of a normal die will be
expected to give a number from one to six. Any particular face will be expected
to turn up in about one-sixth of a great many throws. But the outcome of any one
toss remains unknown until the throw has been made. It is often useful to keep
in mind this “universe of possible results,” even when that universe is hypotheti-
cal, for this clarifies for us the nature of our chance event as a selection from a
93. Brecht, p. 2. limited universe.93

The transformation in Brecht’s thinking (the “change in his


head,” as Cage might say) that takes place with the reconceptual-
ization of chance in the direction of actualization would be
important for Brecht’s aesthetic development. Almost immedi-
ately, he likened the conception of an unlimited, virtual totality to
sources in traditional Asian philosophy (an affinity he and Cage
also shared) and to contemporary scientific conceptions of
relativity and quantum mechanics, ideas he thought to develop
in an article variously titled: “Relativity in the Work of John Cage,”
“Space, Time, and Causality in the Work of John Cage,” “The
Structure of a New Aesthetic,” or “John Cage and the Modern
94. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, World-View: Space, Time and Causality.”94 Drawing from (and, in
Notebook II, pp. 64–66.
part, contributing to) Cage’s developing polemic against
European serialism and certain works by Karlheinz Stockhausen
and Boulez, Brecht underscored the distinction between their
95. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, “closed systems” and the “open systems” that Cage pursued.95
Notebook III, p. 118 (dated July 21,
1959). On Cage’s engagement with
European multiple serialists, see In seeking to implement these transformations, Brecht proposed
Amy C. Beal, New Music, New Allies:
a switchboard for lights and sounds that operated with a series of
American Experimental Music in West
Germany from the Zero Hour to controls and that reacted differently to high and low frequencies
Reunification, Berkeley, Ca.: University (in essence, a series of band-pass filters):
of California Press, 2006, pp. 78–130;
and Kim, pp. 128–207. Kim’s splendid One sound (hi or lo freq.) can go to any speaker (whether or not it sounds on that
discussion provides a detailed reading spkr.), or to any light (whether or not it can/has sufficient energy to/light that light).
of what Cage derived from his New
School students, particularly Brecht, Also, a flux of hi/med/lo sounds on tape going to a hi-freq. spkr., will sound
at this time. only a hi-freq. etc.96
96. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, Note-
book II, p. 43 (dated November 6, 1958). Brecht worked on this proposal for some time, eventually sketching
a sort of control box for indeterminacy, which he ultimately aban-
doned on account of its complexity (“No desire to become an elec-
97. Ibid., p. 95 (dated June 14, 1959) trician“).97 To a not insignificant degree, however, Brecht’s box was
and notes to pp. 15 and 19.
to automate Cage’s process of actualization as found, for instance,
in the superimposition charts of Music of Changes. Every light or
speaker attached to Brecht’s switchboard was in a state of virtual

236
or potential activity, in the sense that it could be activated or lit,
at any moment. Any particular light or speaker would be actually
active, however, could light or emit a sound, only upon receipt
of appropriate frequency stimuli. In other cases, energy would be
passing through (would be, from the perceiver’s point of view)
98. Brecht well understood the relation- virtually there, but would not be actually perceivable.98
ship of difference, or non-resemblance,
between score and performance that
occurred in a situation of actualization: The second important transformation to Brecht’s aesthetic out-
“…the score, or program, has no
look to take place after his exposure to Cagean aesthetics involves
necessary correspondence to the light-
sound event.” (Ibid. p. 24 [dated October the role of the individual subject – composer, performer, or
14, 1958]). listener (perceiver) – within the actualization process. Early on in
Cage’s class, Brecht noted the tripartite division between compos-
er, performer, and listener, importantly understanding that each
stage in the process of composition, performance, and perception
could be the locus of “sound-structuring,” as when, in the case
of listening, the spatialization of acoustical stimuli rendered the
individual the structuring center of the multiplicity of acoustical
99. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, events.99 Brecht would think though the various relations between
Notebook III, p. 115. Brecht notes the
tripartite situation of composer,
composer, performer, and listener in great detail, eventually ex-
performance, and perception in Daniels, tending his focus to five different tiers with the addition of “nota-
(ed.), George Brecht, Notebook II,
p. 23 (dated October 10, 1958).
tion” and “sound” and graphing the results in an elegant penta-
Brecht notes the “Implications of the grammic chart.100 Brecht’s considerations encompass all possible
spatial arrangement of sound-sources”
relations – from the most determined (“playing magnetic tape”) to
in Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht,
Notebook II , p. 9 (dated October 4, the most indeterminate. However, within his discussions of inde-
1958). terminate and/or environmental music, the process of actualiza-
100. Ibid., pp. 126–27. tion, as it operated from one stage to another, is evident. As Brecht
wrote, for example, in draft notes for yet another proposed article
(on “Situational Music”):
In performing this new music (with much compositional indeterminacy) the
performer confirms his own nature, in exactly the way the composer, in composi-
tion, confirmed his. The “virtu” of virtuosity must now mean behavior out of one[’]s
life-experience; it cannot be delimited toward physical skill. The listener respond-
ing to this sound out of his own experience, adds a new element to the system:
composer/notation/performer/sound/listener, and, for himself, defines the sound
101. Ibid., p. 123. as music. For the virtuoso listener all sound may be music.101

Here, we recognize the subject of virtuosity that so impressed (and


baffled) Higgins from Brecht’s pre-class conversations with Cage.
The “virtuoso listener” is one who is able to actualize the virtual
multiplicity that is the field of all sounds – performed and environ-
mental, sound and so-called silence – within which they find them-
selves situated.

By this time, Brecht was no longer solely within Cage’s orbit


(though he would continue to grapple with the composer’s work

237
and example for years). In addition to his prior interest in
Dada and the work of Jackson Pollock, he had encountered the
work of the British experimental composer Cornelius Cardew,
which pushed him to understand perception as constituted by
the individual’s internal, visceral “environment” as much as
by their physical surrounds (“…is the food in our stomachs
102. Ibid., p. 128. It is my speculation a part of the ‘ambient situation?’”).102 And, as Julia Robinson has
that Brecht moves toward this observa-
tion under the influence of Cardew.
demonstrated elsewhere in detail, Brecht’s thinking had been
Brecht references Cornelius Cardew’s profoundly transformed by exposure, in another New School
essay “re-pulling listener’s teeth” in
Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht, Notebook
course, to German philosopher, Ernst Cassirer’s ideas about
III, p. 114. Cardew’s article, as made symbolic form.103 With works such as Time Table Music (1959)
clear by Brecht’s reference on p. 117, is
– which entailed no composition, as such, but considered all
Cornelius Cardew, “The Unity of Musical
Space,” New Departures No. 1, sum- occurrences within a given time period (chosen at random from
mer 1959, pp. 53–56. Some years later, a commuter schedule) as part of the event – Brecht situated
Brecht would participate with Cardew
in events around the Scratch Orchestra himself closer, perhaps, to the position of the virtuoso listener
in London. than to that of the multiplicitous composer that Cage largely
103. Julia E. Robinson, From Abstrac- still occupied (4’33” notwithstanding). Yet, it is not enough to
tion to Model: In the Event of George contend that Brecht simply went his own way, or merely derived
Brecht and the Conceptual Turn in Art of
the 1960s, PhD dissertation, Princeton inspiration or encouragement from Cage. Rather (like his West
University, Department of Art History Coast counterpart, La Monte Young), Brecht only came into
and Archaeology, 2008.
his own by working through the implications of Cage’s aesthetic
in its most advanced form. Only then was Brecht prepared
to transform his artistic focus from the “structure of nature”
– which, in part by following Cage, Brecht had come to see as
infinitely changing and, hence,properly unknowable – to the
104. Daniels, (ed.), George Brecht,
Notebook II , p. 107 (dated January 21,
individual’s “structure of experience,” the point at which
1958). the totality of events would be actualized.104

238

You might also like