Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

bs_bs_banner

Bioethics ISSN 0269-9702 (print); 1467-8519 (online) doi:10.1111/bioe.12044


Volume 28 Number 9 2014 pp 447–455

DEBATES IN RESEARCH ETHICS

WHEN INTUITION IS NOT ENOUGH. WHY THE PRINCIPLE OF


PROCREATIVE BENEFICENCE MUST WORK MUCH HARDER TO JUSTIFY
ITS EUGENIC VISION

REBECCA BENNETT

Keywords
Principle of Procreative ABSTRACT
Beneficence, The Principle of Procreative Beneficence (PPB) claims that we have a
non-identity problem, moral obligation, where choice is possible, to choose to create the best
eugenics, child we can. The existence of this moral obligation has been proposed by
Harris, John Harris and Julian Savulescu and has proved controversial on many
Savulescu, levels, not least that it is eugenics, asking us to produce the best children
Parfit, we can, not for the sake of that child’s welfare, but in order to make a better
intuition society. These are strong claims that require robust justification that can be
open to scrutiny and debate.
This article argues that robust justifications are currently lacking in the
work of Savulescu and Harris. The justifications provided for their conclu-
sions about this obligation to have the best child possible rely heavily on
Derek Parfit’s Non-Identity Problem and the intuitive response this provokes
in many of us. Unfortunately Harris and Savulescu do not embrace the
entirety of the Non-Identity Problem and the puzzle that it presents. The
Non-Identity Problem actually provides a refutation of PPB. In order to
establish PPB as a credible and defendable principle, Harris and Savulescu
need to find what has eluded Parfit and many others: a solution to the
Non-Identity Problem and thus an overturning of the refutation it provides for
PPB. While Harris and Savulescu do hint at possible but highly problematic
solutions to the Non-Identity Problem, these are not developed or defended.
As a result their controversial is left supported by little more than intuition.

INTRODUCTION ments or undesirable traits as possible. To choose other-


wise would be morally wrong.
The Principle of Procreative Beneficence (PPB) claims Parfit was one of the first to discuss such a possible
that we have a moral obligation, where choice is possible, obligation as part of his analysis of what he called the
to choose to create the best child we can. On this view if Non-Identity Problem.1 Harris brought these arguments
we are faced with a choice regarding, for instance, which into the bioethical and applied ethics arena2 and in 2001
in vitro fertilization (IVF) embryos we should implant,
we are morally obliged, always to choose those embryos 1
D. Parfit. 1987. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Claredon Press.
that are likely to have the best quality of life and this 2
J. Harris. 1985. The Value of Life: An Introduction to Medical Ethics.
assumes choosing the embryos with the fewest impair- London: Routledge & Kegan Paul: 146–149.

Address for correspondence: Dr. Rebecca Bennett, University of Manchester – Centre for Social Ethics and Policy, School of Law, Williamson
Building, Oxford Road, Manchester M13 9PL, UK. T 01612752489. Email: Rebecca.Bennett@manchester.ac.uk
Conflict of interest statement: No conflicts declared

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
448 Rebecca Bennett

Savulescu suggested the label ‘the Principle of Procreative X is proposed.8 This article examines their work more
Beneficence’3 (PPB) for this claim. Both Harris and Savu- closely to try to identify the possible solutions they put
lescu have consistently argued strongly for such a moral forward to the Non-Identity problem, their Theory X,
obligation. that aims to refute the Non-Identity problem allowing
This claim that there is a moral obligation to choose to them to use the Non-Identity Problem in this way. I argue
produce only the best children possible has been highly that while there are hints at a number of possible solu-
controversial and attracted a great deal of debate and tions to the problem in their work these are not developed
criticism. On a practical level determining what we mean into a robust or defended argument that will overturn the
by the ‘best’ child is highly problematic and highly sub- refutation of their views that the Non-Identity Problem
jective.4 Further, it has been argued that PPB necessarily represents. Thus, I argue that neither Harris or Savulescu
puts a lower value on those with disability and encour- have done the work needed to provide a theoretical jus-
ages infringing reproductive autonomy.5 This article, tification for their eugenic vision. Not only does this deny
however, discusses what is perhaps PPB’s and the argu- others the opportunity to engage with and scrutinize the
ments by Harris and Savulescu’s most serious weakness, basis of these controversial claims, but also, without this
their failure to provide a definite account of the theoreti- work, far from providing the theoretical foundations of
cal foundations for their positions. PPB, the Non-Identity Problem provides a clear refuta-
In posing the puzzle of the Non-Identity Problem, tion of PPB. If Harris and Savulescu wish to continue to
Parfit clearly showed that while he was very drawn to a claim the existence of a moral obligation to produce the
notion of a moral obligation to produce the best lives best child possible then this work must be done and a
possible, he was unable to find a defendable argument robust and defended solution to the Non-Identity
that enabled him to propose this obligation with any Problem must be proposed. Without this Harris and
philosophical credibility. The Non-Identity Problem Savulescu’s controversial eugenic views are left supported
appears to show that such an obligation to produce only by little more than intuition and proposing eugenics
the best lives cannot be justified. If we wish to reject this based on intuitions alone would seem dangerous and
conclusion we can only do so with any creditability by unjustifiable.
finding a problem with the structure of this argument and
developing an argument, Parfit calls it ‘Theory X’,6 that THE NON-IDENTITY PROBLEM
solves the Non-Identity Problem convincingly, that is,
that allows us to legitimately reject the conclusion either Parfit introduces the Non-Identity Problem by asking us
by showing a problem with the existing premises or by to consider examples like his ‘Risky Policy’ example. The
adding a defendable premise that has this result. Despite Risky Policy example asks us to suppose that we must
his efforts Parfit was unable to identify Theory X and, choose between two energy policies. Both of these poli-
particularly in areas of population ethics, the search for cies would be safe for at least three centuries, but one
Theory X continues to be a very fertile but ultimately would entail a small risk of radioactive contamination in
inconclusive area of inquiry.7 the further future but would increase the quality of life.
Both Harris and Savulescu use Parfitian Non-Identity We choose this Risky Policy. Centuries later an earth-
Problem examples as their main instrument to justify quake releases radiation. This causes thousands of people
their positions, an approach only acceptable if a Theory to develop an incurable disease that will cause their death
3
around the age of 40.9
Julian Savulescu. Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the
We instinctively feel that choosing the Risky Policy is
Best Children. Bioethics 2001; 15: 413–426.
4
R. Bennett & J. Harris. 2002. Are There Lives Not Worth Living? wrong. Parfit argues that the wrongness of choosing the
When is it Morally Wrong to Reproduce? In Ethical Issues in Maternal- Risky Policy cannot be explained in terms of person-
Fetal Medicine. D. Dickenson, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University affecting consequences as even small changes in a society
Press: 321–334; R. Bennett. In press 2013. There Can Be No Moral will affect the identities of who is born. Parfit bases this
Obligation to Eradicate All Disability. In From Reason to Practice in
claim on what Kavka called the ‘precariousness of my
Bioethics: An Anthology Dedicated to the Works of John Harris.
J. Coggon, S. Chan, S. Holm and T. Kushner, eds. Manchester, Man-
chester University Press; P. Herissone-Kelly, Procreative Beneficence
and the Prospective Parent. J Med Ethics 2006; 32: 166–169; M. Parker.
8
The Best Possible Child. J Med Ethics 2007; 33: 279–283. See for example J. Savulescu. Procreative Beneficence: Why We
5
R. Bennett. The Fallacy of the Principle of Procreative Beneficence. Should Select the Best Children. Bioethics 2001; 15: 413–426; J. Harris.
Bioethics 2009; 23: 265–273; Bennett & Harris. op. cit. note 4, pp. One Principle and Three Fallacies of Disability Studies. J Med Ethics
321–334; Bennett, op. cit. note 4. 2001; 27: 383–387; J. Savulescu & G. Kahane. The Moral Obligation to
6
Parfit, op. cit. note 1, p. 366. Create Children with the Best Chance of the Best Life. Bioethics 2009;
7
See for example M.A. Roberts & D.T. Wasserman. Harming Future 23: 274–290; J. Harris. Sparrows, Hedgehogs and Castrati: Reflections
Persons: Ethics, Genetics and the Nonidentity Problem. Dordrecht: on Gender and Enhancement. J Med Ethics 2011; 37: 262–266.
9
Springer. Parfit. op. cit. note 1, pp. 371–372.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
When Intuition Is Not Enough 449

origin’10 and what he calls the Time-Dependence Claim,11 like the Risky Policy and choices to conceive impaired
which is the notion that the chances of any particular rather than unimpaired lives produce in us. For many
individual being born is spectacularly unlikely, given the these examples show the conclusion to this seemingly
infinite number of variables that had to be in place for valid argument as hugely counter intuitive. Parfit intro-
this to happen. In order for any particular individual to duced the puzzle of the Non-Identity Problem to attempt
exist, that individual’s parents have to have been created identify a reason, Theory X, to explain our intuitions
in the first place, they have to meet at the right time and about allowing impaired rather than unimpaired lives to
conceive us at a particular time to enable that particular be created and try and find a reason to reject the conclu-
sperm to fuse with that particular egg. Thus, it is clear sion to the Problem a task at which he was not successful.
that all sorts of things, any change in society, will effect So, faced with this puzzle, we have two philosophically
who is born. As Parfit points out, a woman who wonders credible choices: We can ‘bite the bullet’ and accept the
who she would have been if her ‘parents married other conclusion and thus the Non-Identity Problem becomes
people’ ignores the answer which is ‘no one’.12 the Non-Identity Argument. If we do this we have to
If Parfit is convincing, then those who suffer the results accept these are not bad acts even if this doesn’t feel right
of the Risky Policy (premature death caused by radia- and we have no moral reasons to suggest these acts
tion) have not been harmed by this policy as it was this should be avoided. If however we wish to reject this con-
policy that provided the conditions (a change in the clusion we can only do so by finding what eluded Parfit,
quality of life enjoyed) that allowed for their existence. a problem with the structure of this argument and devel-
These affected people were born in the only state they oping a Theory X that solves the Non-Identity Problem
could have been born in, with worthwhile if foreshort- convincingly, that is, that allows us to legitimately reject
ened lives. Thus, if morality is restricted to what is the conclusion.
person-affecting, this leads to the conclusion that, Interestingly what Harris and Savulescu do is neither
morally, it does not matter which of these energy policies of these two credible options. We will consider their
we choose as no-one is harmed as a result. approach now.
Parfit provides further examples to illustrate this puzzle
where he considers individual decisions around reproduc-
tion rather than policy decisions. Here he asks us to THE NON-IDENTITY PROBLEM AND
consider the actions of a woman who chooses to conceive
THE PRINCIPLE OF PROCREATIVE
a child at a particular time knowing that this will result in
that child having an impairment that could have been
BENEFICENCE
avoided if conception had been deferred to another time.
What Savulescu and Harris do is use a version of the
The impairment is not such that it is likely to render the
Problem where the conclusion is replaced with a com-
life unworthwhile (dominated by suffering) but will cause
pletely contradictory one, which does not follow from the
this life to go worse than another alternative life could
premises. They do this without giving an explicit or
go.13 In such cases no child’s welfare is damaged – the
defended argument to establish a Theory X which would
impaired individual would be born in the only state he
find fault with the structure of the Non-Identity Problem
could be born in and with what is as likely as anyone
and allow them legitimately to make this bold move.
else’s to be a worthwhile life. But while this act is not ‘bad
As I will show, both Savulescu14 and Harris15 rely
for’ the child created there may be a strong feeling that a
heavily on the Parfitian Non-Identity Problem examples
woman making this decision to choose to have a impaired
to justify their views about this moral obligation to
child has behaved immorally even though no individual
produce the best children possible. They consider exam-
child is made worse off by her decision.
ples like the Risky Policy example or examples of delay-
This is the Non-Identity Problem. We appear to have
ing pregnancy to avoid producing an impaired child and
shown that no-one is harmed by the Risky Policy or by
conclude that these examples and the intuitive responses
choosing to conceive an impaired but worthwhile life. As
we have to them alone convince us that decisions to create
such it appears that as these acts are not bad for any
impaired lives rather than unimpaired ones are wrong. As
individual, these are not bad acts. This is seems to be a
we have seen Parfit shared these intuitions but resisted
valid argument. But what makes this the Non-Identity
bowing to intuition in the absence of defendable reasons
Problem and not the Non-Identity Argument is the
to justify this position. Unable to find a convincing
general feeling of unease, shared by Parfit, that examples
account of the badness of acts such as the Risky Policy,
10
G.S. Kavka. The Paradox of Future Individuals. Philos Public Aff
14
1981; 11: 93–112: 93. See for example Savulescu, op. cit. note 8, pp. 413–426; Savulescu &
11
Parfit. op. cit. note 1, p. 351. Kahane, op. cit. note 8, pp. 274–290.
12 15
Ibid. See for example Harris 2001, op. cit. note 8, pp. 383–387; Harris 2011,
13
Ibid: 358–361. op. cit. note 8, pp. 262–266.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
450 Rebecca Bennett

aside from our intuitive feelings, Parfit reluctantly accepts we have seen, this is only part of the story here. It is a
that he cannot convincingly show that such acts are in massive and completely unsupported jump from recog-
fact bad. However, this does not seem to trouble Savu- nizing these elements of the Non-Identity Puzzle to reject-
lescu and Harris. They reject the seemingly valid but ing its conclusion on the basis of intuition rather than
counter intuitive conclusion, that although these acts feel reason. Here Savulescu appears to unaware of the puzzle
bad they are not bad without justifying this rejection of the Non-Identity Problem poses and the well established
logic. need for a Theory X, using Parfit’s work simply to show
that we intuitively need to accept PPB.
APPEAL TO INTUITION In a similar vein both Savulescu and Harris use exam-
ples asking us to consider choices between IVF embryos.
What Harris and Savulescu do offer to support their In Savulescu’s example one embryo has no abnormalities
arguments is an appeal to what we already are very aware but the other shows a predisposition to asthma.20 In Har-
of with the Non-Identity Problem, what makes the Non- ris’s example we have a choice of six IVF embryos three
Identity Problem such an interesting and baffling conun- of which are shown to have ‘various genetic disorders and
drum: that the conclusion of the Non-Identity Problem is three seem healthy’.21 The question posed is, which
very counter-intuitive. Harris and Savulescu follow Par- should be implanted?
fit’s lead and use examples where a choice can be made Harris and Savulesu attempt to claim that choosing the
between bringing to birth impaired or compromised unimpaired embryo is the rational choice and thus the
human lives and lives that we assume do not have these right choice. Harris argues that we have a ‘rational pref-
foreseeable compromises. Unlike Parfit, Harris and Savu- erence’22 to choose to bring to birth the best child possible
lescu’s examples are used to show that because we feel and Savulescu argues that the unimpaired embryo
that a choice is wrong it therefore must be actually wrong ‘should (on pain of irrationality) be implanted’.23 This is
to make these choices. the main argument used in favour of their position, that
For instance, in his influential 2001 article, Savulescu when we are faced with examples we feel that we have
uses what he calls the ‘Parfitian defence of voluntary good reasons to make this choice and favour the unim-
procreative beneficence’.16 He introduces a Parfit-inspired paired. As Harris says a prospective mother ‘has reason
example of the woman deciding to delay conception until to do what she can to ensure that the individual she
after her rubella infection in order to attempt to avoid chooses is as good an individual as she can make it [. . .]
having a child affected adversely by this infection and and that will have the best possible chance of a long and
concludes simply ‘She should choose to wait until her healthy life and the best possible chance of contributing
rubella is passed17’. He then presents a version of Parfit’s positively to the world it will inhabit.’24 But without an
Risky Policy example which he calls the Nuclear Accident explanation of why it is important to choose the best child
and concludes: amongst lives of positive value, rather than simply to do
the best for the children we have, it is not clear why this is
If we object to the Nuclear Accident (which most the rational choice. On one side we have what appears to
of us would), then we must appeal to some form of be a valid argument, the Non-Identity Problem, that
harmless wrong-doing. That is, we must claim that a shows that choosing worthwhile but impaired lives harms
wrong was done, but no-one was harmed. We must no-one and is thus not less preferable. Against this it
appeal to something like the Principle of Procreative seems we only have our feelings of unease. While intui-
Beneficence.18 tions and uneasy feelings might be useful in indicating
Here Savuescu is articulating exactly what Parfit did areas that need further ethical investigation it is not
about these kind of examples. He is recognizing, as Parfit enough to rely on such feelings to supply our conclusions
did, the strong intuitive response many of us have that here, particularly where there is a strong argument that
allowing the choice of the Risky Policy or choosing to has not been refuted and indicates the opposite conclu-
conceive an impaired child is wrong. He is also recogniz- sion. This is not to say that reasons could not be provided
ing, like Parfit, that if these choices are wrong it cannot be for the conclusion reached by Savulescu and Harris
to do with person-affecting harm as no individual’s but that these reasons are not provided. But without a
welfare is damaged by these choices as these individuals refutation of the Non-Identity Problem, the examples
have the only life they could have had (as Parfit said put forward by Savulescu and Harris do not show that
‘Theory X will not take a person-affecting form’19). But as
20
Ibid: 416.
21
Harris, 2001 op. cit. note 8, pp. 383–387: 385.
16 22
Savulescu, op. cit. note 8, pp. 413–426: 417. Ibid: 383–387: 386 citing J. Harris. 1992 Wonderwoman and Super-
17
Ibid. man. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 72–73.
18 23
Ibid: 418. Savulescu, op. cit. note 8, p. 416.
19 24
Parfit. op. cit. note 1, p. 378. Harris, op.cit. note 8, p. 385.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
When Intuition Is Not Enough 451

choosing the non-impaired life is rational and thus pref- 3) We can claim that the motivation of the agent makes
erable, these examples merely show that we have a gut these acts wrong.29
feeling, an intuition, an emotional response to these 4) We can accept that the child is not harmed but claim
examples that may indicate a problem with the Non- that others are harmed by bringing this child to birth
Identity Problem or may simply be a ‘yuk’ reaction that – the parents, other siblings, society.
when examined does not indicate something morally
problematic.
WHAT WOULD HARRIS/
POSSIBLE PROBLEMS WITH THE SAVULESCU DO?
NON-IDENTITY PROBLEM
As we saw earlier the main way that Harris and Savulescu
So simply saying that such choices are rational because defend their view is using examples that appeal to the
they fit with our intuitions and ignoring the problems intuitive response we often have to such cases. They do,
with this so eloquently set out by Parfit doesn’t provide a however, hint at least two of the approaches listed above
credible foundation for an obligation to choose the best but, even with very sympathetic reading of these hints a
child possible. So what could Harris and Savulescu do in lot more work needs to be done.
order to provide a theoretical foundation to their views?
Many people have tried to solve the puzzle of the Non-
Identity Problem and come up with the Theory X that Impersonal Harm as a solution to the
shows it not to be a valid argument and that would allow Non-Identity Problem
us to reject its conclusion in a credible way. Numerous While Parfit has been unable to identify his Theory X that
solutions have been proposed but all have their short- accounts for the badness of acts such as the Risky Policy
comings. The question that has to be asked here in order he does argue that ‘We can predict that Theory X will not
to try and find this Theory X is ‘what could be wrong with take a person-affecting form’.30 For Parfit, at least, it
this argument that would allow us to reject the conclu- seems clear that no individual’s welfare is damaged by the
sion?’. There are a number of options open to us that choice to bring to birth impaired but worthwhile lives and
have been explored with this aim: thus that Theory X will not be a theory that involves
1) We can reject the notion that only it is only person- badness that affects persons or individuals. Harris and
affecting concerns that are morally important.25 Savulescu also offer a few hints that the wrongness of or
2) We can reject the claim that bringing to birth badness of the Risky Policy and similar examples might
someone can only be considered to be bad for that be explained by some kind of non-person affecting or
person if he or she has what might be termed an impersonal harm.
‘unworthwhile’ life (a life dominated by suffering). As such they are rejecting the notion that it is only
Either because person-affecting concerns that are morally important.
a) all human life is a harm and reproduction is Parfit, Harris, Savulescu and many of us share the intui-
wrong26 tion that those choosing the Risky Policy or to implant
b) impaired individuals are harmed27 impaired embryos over non-impaired embryos do some-
c) impaired individuals are wronged.28 thing wrong. In the absence of any identifiable harm to
the welfare of the person created, Parfit has tried to
25
See for example Parfit. op. cit. note 1; A. Buchanan, N. Daniels & D. explain the wrongness of such acts using a notion of
Wikler. 2000. From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice. Cambridge: impersonal harm and benefit. He suggested the ‘Imper-
Cambridge University Press; D. DeGrazia. 2005. Human identity and sonal Total Principle’31 to try and explain what is wrong
Bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; J. McMahan. 2009.
with these acts that don’t seem to be bad for any
Asymmetries in the Morality of Causing People to Exist. In Harming
Future Persons: Ethics, Genetics and the Nonidentity Problem. individual.
M.A. Roberts & D.T. Wasserman, eds. Dordrecht: Springer. 49–68. The Impersonal Total Principle says that ‘If other
26
D. Benatar. 2006. Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming things are equal, the best outcome is the one in which
into Existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. there would be the greatest quantity of whatever makes
27
See for example C. Wolf. 2009. Do Future Persons Presently Have
life worth living.’32 This principle attempts to rationalize
Alternative Possible Identities? In Harming Future Persons: Ethics,
Genetics and the Nonidentity Problem. M.A. Roberts & D.T. Wasser- the intuition we have about these seemingly bad acts by
man, eds. Dordrecht: Springer: 93–114; B. Steinbock. 2009. Wrongful
29
Life and Procreative Decisions. In Harming Future Persons: Ethics, B. Steinbock & R. McClamrock. When Is Birth Unfair to the Child?
Genetics and the Nonidentity Problem. M.A. Roberts & D.T. Wasser- Hastings Cent Rep 1994; 24: 15–21.
30
man. Dordrecht: Springer: 155–178. Parfit. op. cit. note 1, p. 378.
28 31
See for example Steinbock, op. cit. note 27, pp. 155–178; J. Wood- Ibid.
32
ward. 1986. The Non-Identity Problem. Ethics 96: 804–831. Ibid.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
452 Rebecca Bennett

claiming that it is not only person-affecting concerns that and Kahane say that ‘the child will benefit more than the
are morally important. Thus while no-one’s welfare is other would by being caused to exist’.37 But this is not a
changed or improved by a choice to bring to birth an person-affecting claim. No person is better off or benefit-
impaired but worthwhile life, the Impersonal Total of ted by this choice between these two individuals. So if
‘whatever makes life worth living’ is diminished by this there is any benefit here it must be in the sense that Parfit
choice. No individual is made worse off or indeed given and Harris talk about of free-floating benefit in the
anything to complain about in that they will have a ‘making the world a better place’ impersonal sense. So it
worthwhile life but the world is a slightly worse place seems that the grounds offered by Savulescu and Kahane
than it could have been in terms of cumulative totals of are essentially impersonal.
happiness or flourishing or whatever we think produces a We can’t do more than assume this as Savulescu and
good quality of life. If happier, more successful people Kahane refuse to be tempted into providing any further
with higher qualities of life were born (and this argument explanation of a theoretical foundation to PPB. They say:
assumes that impairments will diminish the quality of a
We do not take a stand on this difficult philosophical
life) then the cumulative impersonal total of ‘whatever
issue [of what theoretical foundation or argument
makes life worth living’ will be higher in this society than
might support PPB]. As we have tried to show, our
one that allows those with impairments and/or those with
moral intuitions about timing of conception recognize
lower quality of life to be born.
reasons to select future children. PB is an account of
Thus Parfit begins to argue that this notion of imper-
the content of these reasons, not an explanation of
sonal harm and benefit might be the solution to the Non-
what might ground them.38
Identity Problem, that is, that these acts are bad because
although they are not bad for any individuals they are So whilst they suggest that it could be supported by
bad for total cumulative sums of life quality. impersonal consideration and wide-person affecting con-
Both Harris and Savulescu allude to this notion of sideration (which ultimately reduce to impersonal consid-
impersonal harm in their work albeit in a superficial and erations), this need for a sound theoretical basis for the
fleeting way. Harris talks about ‘the wrong of bringing Principle is seen as secondary to the strong intuitive
avoidable suffering into the world’33 and that by bringing response examples such as the Risky Policy invoke. Thus,
to birth impaired or disabled individuals rather than the appeal to our ‘moral intuitions’ or the fact that PPB is
unaffected individuals we are choosing to make the world ‘implicit in commonsense morality’39 is used here rather
a worse place than it could have been even though that than any exploration of the notion of impersonal harm.
individual has not been wronged.34 Similarly Savulescu
has said that ‘we must appeal to some form of harmless
wrong-doing’35 and in a much more recent article Savu- THE PROBLEMS WITH APPEALS TO
lescu and Kahane say that PPB is:
IMPERSONAL HARM
compatible with different accounts of reasons to select
future children. It can take either a wide-person affect- It is understandable why Savulescu does not wish to ‘take
ing form or an impersonal form. According to the wide a stand on this difficult philosophical issue’40 and explore
person-affecting version, our reason to select the child impersonal harm any further than he does. This notion of
with better prospects is that that child will benefit more ‘free-floating’ impersonal harm is a very difficult concept
than the other would by being caused to exist. Accord- to take seriously for many reasons.
ing to the impersonal view, our reason is that selecting Firstly, the very intuitions that attract us to this possi-
the most advantaged child would make the outcome ble explanation also repel us from this explanation. Intui-
better, even if it is not better for the child created. It is tively we find it difficult to understand how something
possible to support PB on either view.36 can be wrong when it doesn’t affect the welfare of indi-
viduals. Do we really care about benefit or harm that
At first glance Savulescu and Kahane seem to have two
doesn’t benefit or harm anyone?
different theoretical grounds as a foundation for PPB:
On a more theoretical level the notion of impersonal
impersonal considerations and wide-person affecting
harm is complex and fraught with many difficulties.
consideration. However, it is difficult to see wide-person
While Parfit begins to argue that impersonal harm may
affecting considerations as any more than another way of
be the solution to the Non-Identity Problem and is
referring to impersonal considerations. Here Savulesu
consistent in maintaining that Theory X will not be
33
J. Harris. 1998. Clones, Genes and Immortality: Ethics and the Genetic
37
Revolution. Oxford. Oxford University Press: 111. Ibid.
34 38
Bennett & Harris, op. cit. note 4, p. 324. Ibid.
35 39
Savulescu, op. cit. note 8, p. 418. Ibid.
36 40
Savulescu & Kahane, op. cit. note 8, p. 277. Ibid.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
When Intuition Is Not Enough 453

person-affecting, he quickly shows that the concept of future.’42 Parfit feels strongly that the conclusion to the
impersonal harm is impossible to sustain convincingly. Non-Identity Problem is wrong but is unable to produce
Whilst he is hopeful that others will have the success that a convincing account of why this is so and thus is tempted
has eluded him there has not, as yet, been a convincing to throw reason aside to allow others to reach what he
solution to the fatal problem with impersonal harm Parfit feels are ‘the right conclusions’.43 This is exactly what
calls the ‘Repugnant Conclusion’. Harris and Savulescu do. They work to conceal the Non-
Identity Problem by creating a ‘Principle’ that plays to
our strong intuitions but has not been defended by
THE REPUGNANT CONCLUSION reason.
But Harris and Savulescu have to accept, as Parfit
If what matters is to increase the cumulative totals of ultimately does, that if they wish to maintain their con-
happiness or whatever makes life good in any given clusions here convincingly they cannot do so by con-
society, this leads to some rather unpalatable conclu- cealing the problems with their position. If they wish to
sions. Firstly, it creates a moral obligation to create as appeal to impersonal harm to solve these problems then
many worthwhile lives as possible as doing so will they must do more than simply hint at this solution.
increase these totals very effectively. But the notion of They must provide a convincing account of impersonal
having a moral obligation to reproduce is hugely counter harm that avoids the unpalatable conclusions identified
intuitive. Do we really do good by being obliged to bring by Parfit. There have, of course, been attempts to accept
as many worthwhile lives into the world as possible? Isn’t the notion of impersonal harm without incurring the
it likely that bringing these large numbers of lives into Repugnant conclusion.44 But these attempts are highly
being will eventually decrease the average quality of life problematic often raising more problems than they
dramatically due to overcrowding and scarcity of solve. Space does not allow me to go into these here,
resources? As Parfit puts it ‘For any possible population but if Harris and Savulescu wish to use the notion of
of at least ten billion people, all with a very high quality impersonal harm as their justification for their argu-
of life, there must be some much larger imaginable popu- ments in this area, this cannot be done by fleeting and
lation whose existence, if other things are equal, would be superficial hints at this problematic solution. If Harris
better, even though its members have lives that are barely and Savulescu mean to justify their eugenic vision on
worth living’.41 Can a huge population of people with a the existence of impersonal harm, then this approach
low but worthwhile quality of life really be morally pref- and the way that their approach deals with the problems
erable to a world with a smaller population where people faced by impersonal harm, including the Repugn-
will have a substantially higher quality of life? Cumula- ant Conclusion, must be made explicit, opening it
tive totals in the huge population will be higher but does up to scrutiny and debate. Something they do not
this make this world morally preferable? currently do.
This is what Parfit calls the Repugnant Conclusion and
what makes this conclusion repugnant is that it cares little
about what we normally regard as morally important: the
welfare of individual people. The consequence of holding We can reject the claim that bringing someone
onto the notion of impersonal harm (and benefit) is that to birth can only be considered to be bad for
in doing so you are then committed to the view that any that person if he or she has what might be
decrease in the quality of lives in a population can be termed an ‘unworthwhile’ life
compensated for by an increase in the number of lives As well as arguing for impersonal harm, Harris argues
brought to birth in this population. that bringing to birth an impaired or disabled child is
Faced with the difficult and highly counter-intuitive wrongful as it ‘causes a child to be born in a ‘harmed’
conclusions to which notions of impersonal harm lead, condition’.45 Harris accepts that the impaired child has
Parfit is unable to give reasons why we should reject the ‘no complaint because for them the alternative was non-
conclusion to the Non-Identity Problem and risks taking
a stance similar to that of Harris and Savulescu. Parfit
argues that ‘It may then be better that we conceal the 42
Ibid: 373.
Non-Identity Problem from those who will decide 43
Ibid: 373.
44
whether we increase our use of nuclear energy. It may be See for example T. Hurka. Value and Population Size. Ethics 1983;
better if these people believe falsely that such a policy 93: 496–507; G.S. Kavka. The Paradox of Future Individuals. Philos
Public Aff 1982; 11: 93–112; F. Feldman. 1997. Utilitarianism, Hedon-
may, by causing a catastrophe, be greatly against the ism, and Desert: Essays in Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
interests of some of those who will live in the distant University Press; L.S. Temkin. Intransitivity and the Mere Addition
Paradox. Philos Public Aff 1987; 16: 138–187.
41 45
Parfit. op. cit. note 1, p. 388. Bennett & Harris, op. cit. note 4, p. 325.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
454 Rebecca Bennett

existence’46 but argues that whilst this child has not been will have disease or injury’.49 Now, it is clear that we have
wronged he has been harmed unnecessarily. For Harris to a strong moral obligation to prevent preventable harm
be born with any impairment that one could have a and suffering to individuals, but what is not clear is that
rational preference to be born without is to be born in a bringing to birth an impaired life is to harm that indi-
harmed state and parents who choose to bring to birth a vidual. We need to consider what is person-affecting
disabled child are responsible for harming that child and harm and what is impersonal harm here. Of course we
causing that child to suffer from this harm. have an obligation to avoid harming individuals who will
Harris’s stance on harming challenges the notion of exist. Thus any parent who deafens their child would be
harming as something comparative – that you don’t have doing a grave moral wrong as they are directly responsi-
to be ‘worse off’ to be harmed (or better off to be ben- ble for causing harm to this individual child. However, it
efitted). He argues that bringing to birth an impaired is not clear how a woman who brings to birth a deaf child
child or a child with a foreseeably compromised life causes that particular child harm. If any harm is caused
harms the child in a non-comparative way. by this choice then it is not harm to this individual child
We are left in no doubt that Harris feels that those who as he is not deafened by his mothers’ actions but born in
are born with an impairment have been harmed and the only state he can be born in.
suffer from this harm. For instance Harris says ‘I do not Harris talks of ‘depriving it [the deaf child] of one of its
believe there is a difference between choosing a preim- senses’.50 For the analogy to be sound, the ‘deaf’ embryo
plantation deaf embryo and refusing a cure to a newborn. would have to have the option or hearing or being deaf.
Nor do I see an important difference between refusing a However the ‘deaf’ embryo does not have these options –
cure and deliberately deafening a child’.47 it can either exist deaf or not exist at all. This child is not
There are, of course, those that argue impairments denied anything he could have had, in this case the ability
such as deafness do not cause suffering in themselves but to hear, his interests and rights have not been frustrated
that any suffering that arises from an impairment such as as they have when an individual child is deliberately deaf-
deafness, only does so as a result of the attitudes of others ened. It makes perfect sense to compare the life of an
in society and the lack of provision made for those with individual child before and after he was deliberately deaf-
these conditions.48 Harris shows this stance to be implau- ened and say that he is now in a worse condition and has
sible when it is applied to person-affecting harm. He been harmed. However, attempting to compare a child’s
argues that the deaf child is harmed by a decision to life with or without an impairment, when to be without
withhold a cure and to deafen a child is to cause harm to an impairment is not an option, does not make any sense.
that child. It would be morally wrong to harm a child by Thus, while it would be wrong to deny a deaf child the
deafening that child or denying a deaf child a cure, as to possibility of hearing by denying him an effective cure, we
do so would be to harm that particular child by denying do not harm a child by bringing her to birth with an
them options they are likely to have valued. To deafen a impaired but worthwhile life, as that child has not been
child or deny him an effective cure would be to harm that denied anything by this action.
individual, to make him ‘worse off ’, not because of soci- Isn’t this just impersonal harm expressed in another
ety’s imperfections but because this child had lost some- way? We agree that the individual is not wronged by
thing of value he otherwise could have had. being born with a worthwhile life. He is born impaired
However, problems occur when he takes his analogy but with a life he is likely to value and the only life it is
further and argues that not only do we harm an indi- possible for him to have. If suffering is increased by his
vidual by making that individual ‘worse off ’ than it could birth but he is not wronged and his actual suffering is not
have been (by deafening that individual or denying him increased then it seems that this increased suffering must
an available cure for deafness), but that we also harm be impersonal and thus prone to all the problems with
individuals by bringing them to birth in an impaired impersonal harm.
state. Even if we were to be generous and suppose that we are
Harris argues that we have ‘a strong moral obligation wrong about this and that Harris could somehow con-
to prevent preventable harm and suffering and that this vince us of the idea that individuals are harmed by being
obligation applies equally to curing disease and injury born with an impairment, this simply creates new prob-
and to preventing the avoidable creation of people who lems for Harris. Harris assertion that we have ‘a strong
moral obligation to prevent preventable harm and suffer-

46
J. Harris. Is There a Coherent Social Conception of Disability? J Med
49
Ethics 2000; 26: 95–100: 97. J. Harris. 1998. Rights and Reproductive Choice. In The Future of
47
Ibid. Human Reproduction. J. Harris & S. Holm, eds. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
48
S.M. Reindal. Disability, Gene Therapy and Eugenics – a Challenge versity Press: 31.
50
to John Harris. J Med Ethics 2000; 26: 89–94. Harris, op. cit. note 46, p. 99.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


14678519, 2014, 9, Downloaded from https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12044 by Readcube (Labtiva Inc.), Wiley Online Library on [29/05/2024]. See the Terms and Conditions (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/terms-and-conditions) on Wiley Online Library for rules of use; OA articles are governed by the applicable Creative Commons License
When Intuition Is Not Enough 455

ing’51 including the creation of new lives surely commits The problem that confronts Kass – and anyone who
Harris to the view that reproduction is always immoral, wishes to cut to the chase of morality so to speak by
for we are all subject to suffering through disease, injury, finding ways to decide or to act “immediately and
limited opportunity and loss. without argument” – is to have a way of knowing when
Harris’s notion of harmed but worthwhile lives seems one’s sense of outrage, or ones “feelings” or whatever,
riddled with problems. It appears to reduce to impersonal are evidence of something morally disturbing and
harm with all the problems that concept has or leads us to when they are simply an expression of bare prejudice or
considering the immorality of reproduction per se. What simply an induced emotional response.52
Harris doesn’t do, even on the most sympathetic reading
of his work, is provide a strong argument that enables us Further Harris points out that morality and moral
to legitimately reject the conclusion of the Non-Identity principles must be backed up by reason
Problem and thus provide convincing reasons to accept And this means they must always be prepared to offer
PPB and similar arguments. a reasoned defence and justification of their morality or
elements of it. It would never be enough or indeed even
CONCLUSION respectable for the reply to be “I just felt like it”.53

Harris and Savulescu’s argument that proposes a moral If we are going to accept their claim about a moral
obligation to produce the best children possible is a obligation to produce the best child possible then Harris
strong and controversial claim. It is a claim that we have and Savulescu must provide a reasoned defence of this
an obligation to change the sort of people that will be claim in order to attempt to provide it with credible jus-
born, not because it will be better for any particular tification and to expose this justification so that it can be
person that these changes are made but that this will open to scrutiny. What is not acceptable is that this
create somehow superior society. The unsolved Non- strong vision of future generations is left justified by little
Identity Problem provides a seemingly valid argument more than an appeal to intuition and gut feeling. Harris
against this claim. As such we have strong reasons, pro- and Savulescu must take a clear and logically robust
vided by the Non-Identity Problem to reject PPB and stance on this difficult philosophical problem if they wish
similar arguments. If Harris and Savulescu wish to hold to present their arguments with credibility. They must
onto their arguments in this area with any philosophical work harder to reveal the flaw in the Non-Identity
credibility, they must do a great deal more than tell us Problem if they wish to substitute their own conclusion.
what we already know, that many of us feel intuitively Eugenics based on intuition is indefensible.
that the conclusion to the Non-Identity Problem is Rebecca Bennett is Senior Lecturer in Bioethics at the Centre for Social
wrong. They must give reasons for this wrongness rather Ethics and Policy, in the School of Law, University of Manchester.
than simply replace the conclusion of the Non-Identity Rebecca has taught bioethics for twenty years and has published widely
on diverse issues in bioethics including antenatal HIV testing, assisted
Problem simply because it just feels wrong. To justify a
reproductive technologies, genetic testing in pregnancy, arguments sur-
strong eugenic vision on the basis of intuition alone is not rounding attempts to eradicate disability, responsibility in pregnancy,
an acceptable stance. Harris himself explains this issue HIV/AIDS, cloning, stem cell research, ecotognesis, and brain dead
well when talking about Kass’s attempts to use feelings pregnancy.
rather than moral philosophy to solve bioethical issues,
52
saying: J. Harris. What It Is to Be Good. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 2012; 21:
294.
51 53
Ibid: 31. Ibid: 296.

© 2013 John Wiley & Sons Ltd

You might also like